Situational Ethics Or Situation Ethics Takes Into Account the Particular

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Situational Ethics Or Situation Ethics Takes Into Account the Particular Situational ethics or situation ethics takes into account the particular context of an act when evaluating it ethically, rather than judging it according to absolute moral standards. With the intent to have a fair basis for judgments or action, one looks to personal ideals of what is appropriate to guide them, rather than an unchanging universal code of conduct, such as Biblical law under divine command theory or the Kantian categorical imperative.[1] Proponents of situational approaches to ethics include existentialist philosophers Kierkegaard, Sartre, de Beauvoir, Jaspers, and Heidegger.[2] Specifically Christian forms of situational ethics placing love above all particular principles or rules were proposed in the first half of the twentieth century by liberal theologians Rudolf Bultmann, John A. T. Robinson, and Joseph Fletcher.[3] These theologians point specifically to agapē, or unconditional love, as the highest end. Other theologians who advocated situational ethics include Josef Fuchs, Reinhold Niebuhr, Karl Barth, Emil Brunner, Dietrich Bonhoeffer, and Paul Tillich.[4]:33 Tillich, for example, declared that "Love is the ultimate law."[5] Fletcher, who became prominently associated with this approach in the English-speaking world due to his book (Situation Ethics), stated that "all laws and rules and principles and ideals and norms, are only contingent, only valid if they happen to serve love" in the particular situation,[4]:30 and thus may be broken or ignored if another course of action would achieve a more loving outcome. Fletcher has sometimes been identified as the founder of situation ethics, but he himself refers his readers to the active debate over the theme that preceded his own work.[4]:33–34 Contents 1 Ethical classification and origin of term 2 Fletcher 2.1 The four working principles 2.2 The six fundamental principles (propositions) 2.3 Examples 2.3.1 Himself Might his Quietus Make 2.3.2 Special Bombing Mission No. 13 2.3.3 Christian Cloak and Dagger 3 See also 4 References 5 External links Ethical classification and origin of term[edit] Situational ethics is a form of consequentialism, though distinct from utilitarianism in that the latter's aim is "the greatest good for the greatest number", while situational ethics focuses on creating the greatest amount of love. Situational ethics can also be classed under the ethical theory genre of "proportionalism" which says that "It is never right to go against a principle unless there is a proportionate reason which would justify it."[6] J. A. T. Robinson, a situational ethicist, considered the approach to be a form of ethical relativism. Source: Wikipedia – M.Naveenkumar, AP/Mech/SNSCT There was an active debate in the mid-twentieth century around situational ethics, which was being promoted by a number of primarily Protestant theologians. The English term "situation ethics" was taken from the German Situationsethik. It is unclear who first coined the term either in German or in its English variant. Fletcher[edit] Fletcher proposed that in forming an ethical system based on love, he was best expressing the notion of "love thy neighbor," which Jesus Christ taught in the Gospels of the New Testament of the Bible. Through situational ethics, Fletcher was attempting to find a "middle road" between legalistic and antinomian ethics. Fletcher developed his theory of situational ethics in his books: The Classic Treatment and Situation Ethics. Situational ethics is thus a teleological or consequential theory, in that it is primarily concerned with the outcome or consequences of an action; the end. Fletcher proposed that loving ends justify any means.[4] Fletcher outlined his theory in four "working principles" and six "fundamental principles". The four working principles[edit] The following are presuppositions Fletcher makes before setting out the situational ethics theory: Pragmatism: An action someone makes should be judged according to the love influenced in it, so the user must always ask: what is the most loving thing to do? For example, war may not – to a situationist – be considered the most 'loving' thing and so many are quick to deem it as morally wrong. Relativism: Approaching every situation with a relative mindset and thus opposing legalistic approaches – avoid words such as 'never', 'complete' and 'perfect'. Positivism: The most important choice of all in the teachings in 1 John 4:7-12 is "let us love one another because love is from God". Personalism: Whereas the legalist thinks people should work to laws, the situational ethicist believes that laws benefit the people. This forces the user to ask 'who is to be helped?' instead of 'what is the law', stressing the importance of people before laws. The six fundamental principles (propositions)[edit] First proposition Only one thing is intrinsically good; namely love: nothing else at all. Fletcher (1966, p. 56) – an action is good only in so far as it brings about agape. Second proposition The ruling norm of Christian decision is love: nothing else. Fletcher (1966, p. 69) – the most important commandment is to love God and "love thy neighbour". Third proposition Source: Wikipedia – M.Naveenkumar, AP/Mech/SNSCT Love and Justice are the same, for justice is love distributed, nothing else. Fletcher (1966, p. 87) – asks that one must always have an eye on the intention of an action. Justice is Christian love using its head, calculating its duties, obligations, opportunities, resources... Justice is love coping with situations where distribution is called for. Fletcher (1966, p. 95) Fourth proposition Love wills the neighbour's good, whether we like him or not. Fletcher (1966, p. 103) – illustrates that agape is not an emotion as it sometimes involves sacrifice, we must thus love not expecting anything in return. Fifth proposition Only the end justifies the means, nothing else. Actions only acquire moral status as a means to an end; for Fletcher, the end must be the most loving result. When measuring a situation, one must consider the desired end, the means available, the motive for acting and the foreseeable consequences. Fletcher (1966, p. 120) – thus, you must recognise that anything may be done if it brings about the most loving outcome. Sixth proposition Love's decisions are made situationally, not prescriptively. Fletcher (1966, p. 134) Examples[edit] Fletcher proposed various examples of situations in which the established moral laws might need to be put on hold in order to achieve the greater amount of love. These were based upon real situations. Himself Might his Quietus Make[edit] “ I dropped in on a patient at the hospital who explained that he only had a set time to live. The doctors could give him some pills (that would cost $40 every three days) that would keep him alive for the next three years, but if he didn't take the pills, he’d be dead within six months. Now he was insured for $100,000, double indemnity and that was all the insurance he had. But if he took the pills and lived past next October when the insurance was up for renewal, they were bound to refuse the renewal, and his insurance would be canceled. So he told me that he was thinking that if he didn't take the pills, then his family would get left with some security, and asked my advice on the situation. ” Pragmatism, positivism, relativism and personalism are the four working principles which mean to be reasonably sure the act you take will work and provide the most loving consequence, accepting Situational Ethics as a matter of faith and not reason, each situation must be relative to love and bring about the most loving result and finally the needs of people come first rather than a set of rules. Special Bombing Mission No. 13[edit] Source: Wikipedia – M.Naveenkumar, AP/Mech/SNSCT “ When the atomic bomb was dropped on Hiroshima, the plane crew were silent. Captain Lewis uttered six words, "My God, what have we done?" Three days later another one fell on Nagasaki. About 152,000 were killed, many times more were wounded and burned, to die later. The next day Japan sued for peace. When deciding whether to use "the most terrible weapon ever known" the US President appointed an Interim Committee made up of distinguished and responsible people in the government. Most but not all of its military advisors favoured using it. Top-level scientists said they could find no acceptable alternative to using it, but they were opposed by equally able scientists. After lengthy discussions, the committee decided that the lives saved by ending the war swiftly by using this weapon outweighed the lives destroyed by using it and thought that the best course of action. ” Christian Cloak and Dagger[edit] “ I was reading "Biblical Faith and Social Ethics",[7] Clinton Gardner's book on a shuttle plane to New York. Next to me sat a young woman of about twenty-eight or so, attractive and well turned out in expensive clothes of good taste. She showed some interest in my book, and I asked if she'd like to look at it. "No", she said, "I'd rather talk." What about? "Me." I knew this meant good-bye to the reading. "I have a problem I'm confused about. You might help me to decide," she explained... There was a war going on that her government believed could be stopped by some clever use of espionage and blackmail. However, this meant she had to seduce and sleep with an enemy spy in order to lure him into blackmail. Now this went against her morals, but if it brought the war to an end, saving thousands of lives, would it be worth breaking those standards? ” These situations were criticised as being extreme.
Recommended publications
  • Below the Belt: Situational Ethics for Uniethical Situations
    The Journal of Sociology & Social Welfare Volume 7 Issue 4 July Article 2 July 1980 Below the Belt: Situational Ethics for Uniethical Situations Gale Goldberg University of Louisville Joy Elliott University of Louisville Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wmich.edu/jssw Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, and the Social Work Commons Recommended Citation Goldberg, Gale and Elliott, Joy (1980) "Below the Belt: Situational Ethics for Uniethical Situations," The Journal of Sociology & Social Welfare: Vol. 7 : Iss. 4 , Article 2. Available at: https://scholarworks.wmich.edu/jssw/vol7/iss4/2 This Article is brought to you by the Western Michigan University School of Social Work. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BELOW THE BELT: SITUATIONAL ETHICS FOR UNIETHICAL SITUATIONS Gale Goldberg, Ed.D. Jqy Elliott, M.S.S.Uj. Associate Professor Assistant Professor Kent School of Social Work Kent School of Social Work University of Louisville University of Louisville Louisville, Kentucky 40208 Louisville, Kentucky 40208 The word "politics" generally conjures up images of smoke- filled, back rooms where unscrupulous men in shirt sleeves chew their cigars and make shady deals that serve partisan interests. But politics is neither inherently shady nor specific to back rooms. In fact, as long as society is differentiated along ethnic, sex and social class lines, politics pervades all of social life. You are involved in politics and so is your mother. A statement or decision is political when either the content of the issue is viewed differently by. people from different social groups, e.g. race, sex, age, or the decision has different con- sequences for different social groups, or both.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relevance of Joseph Fletcher's Situation Ethics for Animal Experimentation in Clinical Studies
    and M cal e ni d li ic C a Monday, J Clin Med Sci 2018, 2:2 l f S o c Journal of Clinical and Medical l i e a n n r c u e o s J Sciences Review Article Open Access The Relevance of Joseph Fletcher's Situation Ethics for Animal Experimentation in Clinical Studies Osebor Ikechukwu Monday* Department of General Studies (Arts and Humanities), Delta State Polytechnic Ogwashi-Uku, Ogwashi-Uku, Nigeria Received: July 25, 2018; Accepted: August 27, 2018; Published: August 31, 2018 *Corresponding author: Monday OI, Department of General Studies (Arts and Humanities), Delta State Polytechnic Ogwashi-Uku, Ogwashi-Uku, Nigeria, Tel: +2348037911701; E-mail: [email protected] Copyright: © 2018 Monday OI. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the creative commons attribution license, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. Abstract The need for continual progress in medical research is one among the challenges today facing humankind. On- going, necessary medical research involving animal subjects will be defended from a Utilitarian standpoint. Animal experimentation can be conducted in such a way that injury and suffering to the animal subjects can be minimized. Clinical studies have been necessary for the eradication of many diseases, such as smallpox and polio and promise similar results for other medical conditions in the future. The ethical and emotional demands placed upon the experimenter during clinical trials, as well as the suffering of the animal subjects, presents us with an ethical dilemma concerning the moral justification of animal experimentation for clinical studies.
    [Show full text]
  • The Challenge of Ethics
    The Challenge of Ethics A Center for Continuing Education 1465 Northside Drive, Suite 213 Atlanta, Georgia 30318 (404) 355-1921 – (800) 344-1921 Fax: (404) 355-1292 THE CHALLENGE OF ETHICS TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter 1 -- The Foundation of Ethics 1 Defining Ethics 1 The History of Ethics 1 Greek Ethics 2 Roman Ethics 3 Christian-Based Ethics 3 Truth 3 Modern Day Ethics 5 The Interpretation of Ethics 5 The Philosophies of Ethics 5 Deontological Ethics 6 Virtue Ethics 7 Normative Ethics 8 Analytic Ethics (Metaethics) 8 Situational Ethics 9 Descriptive Ethics 10 Consequentialist Ethics 10 Dominant Ethical Philosophies 11 Ethical Relativism 11 The Duty of Ethics 13 The Duty of Social Virtue 14 The Duty of Responsibility 14 The Behavior of Ethics 15 Summary 16 Chapter 2 -- The Development of Personal Ethics 17 Personal Ethics 17 Developing Personal Ethics 17 Influence From Family 18 Influence of Culture 18 Influence of Religious Beliefs 19 Influence of Habits 19 Principles of Personal Ethics 20 Creating a Personal Code of Ethics 21 Chapter Three -- Business Ethics 23 Understanding Professional Ethics 23 The Importance of Ethics in Professionalism 24 Approaches To Ethical Standards 25 Common Good Approach 25 Fairness or Justice Approach 26 Moral Rights Approach 26 Utilitarian Approach 26 Universalism Approach 27 Virtue Approach 28 Steps in Ethical Decision Making 28 Identifying the Situation 28 Determine Who’ll be Affected by The Decision 28 Assess Relevant Aspects Of The Situation 29 Relevant Formal Ethical Standards Review 29 Review Relevant
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics for A-Level for AQA Philosophy and OCR Religious Studies
    Ethics for A-Level For AQA Philosophy and OCR Religious Studies MARK DIMMOCK AND ANDREW FISHER To access digital resources including: blog posts videos online appendices and to purchase copies of this book in: hardback paperback ebook editions Go to: https://www.openbookpublishers.com/product/639 Open Book Publishers is a non-profit independent initiative. We rely on sales and donations to continue publishing high-quality academic works. Ethics for A-Level Mark Dimmock and Andrew Fisher https://www.openbookpublishers.com © 2017 Mark Dimmock and Andrew Fisher This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International license (CC BY 4.0). This license allows you to share, copy, distribute and transmit the work; to adapt the work and to make commercial use of the work providing attribution is made to the authors (but not in any way that suggests that they endorse you or your use of the work). Attribution should include the following information: Mark Dimmock and Andrew Fisher, Ethics for A-Level. Cambridge, UK: Open Book Publishers, 2017, https:// doi.org/10.11647/OBP.0125 In order to access detailed and updated information on the license, please visit https://www. openbookpublishers.com/product/639#copyright Further details about CC BY licenses are available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ All external links were active at the time of publication unless otherwise stated and have been archived via the Internet Archive Wayback Machine at https://archive.org/web Digital material and resources associated with this volume are available at https://www.openbookpublishers. com/product/639#resources ISBN Paperback: 978-1-78374-388-9 ISBN Hardback: 978-1-78374-389-6 ISBN Digital (PDF): 978-1-78374-390-2 ISBN Digital ebook (epub): 978-1-78374-391-9 ISBN Digital ebook (mobi): 978-1-78374-392-6 DOI: 10.11647/OBP.0125 Cover image: Malaysia from the Sky, photo by Ishan @seefromthesky.
    [Show full text]
  • Studies in Situation Ethics Charles Allen Hampton Ouachita Baptist University
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Ouachita Baptist University Ouachita Baptist University Scholarly Commons @ Ouachita Honors Theses Carl Goodson Honors Program 1968 Studies in Situation Ethics Charles Allen Hampton Ouachita Baptist University Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarlycommons.obu.edu/honors_theses Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Hampton, Charles Allen, "Studies in Situation Ethics" (1968). Honors Theses. 301. http://scholarlycommons.obu.edu/honors_theses/301 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Carl Goodson Honors Program at Scholarly Commons @ Ouachita. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons @ Ouachita. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STUDIES IN SITUATION ETHICS An Honors Paper Presented to. Dr. James Berryman Ouachita Baptist University In Fulfillment of the Requirements for Special Studies Philosophy H 290 I by Charles Allen Hampton May, l9q8 -· I I. I I I General Evaluation:: This study is a very fine survey of the situational approach to Christian ethics. This study has all the weakne~ses of a survey. Specific C:t•iticisms: Outline-"Bultmann" misspelled. p. 1, line -·1o:.:.••my'' should be eliminated as well as _all· personal pronaums (lst and 2nd person) in formal writing. P• l; line 13.:..ur think''-saae as line 10 p. 1, line 14-Better style--"The generalization is best illustrated, or can be illustrat.ed by relating •• •'' p~ 1~ line 1~--Better style--usome ministerial students •••" p~ 2,; line 1-"talked with the writer.•tt p~ 2; line 1--"my''..;._same as p.
    [Show full text]
  • Christian Ethics ETHC 5300
    1 Introduction to Christian Ethics ETHC 5300 Dr. Steve W. Lemke New Orleans Baptist Theological Seminary Spring 2018 Course Description In this introduction to the study and practice of Christian ethics, the student will examine philosophical and theological backgrounds for ethics, the role of biblical authority, and the historical relation between church and culture in order to develop a valid method of moral decision making, examine the importance of ministerial ethics, evaluate ethical issues, and lead the church in applying the gospel to life. Contacting the Instructor Dr. Lemke may be contacted through any of the following means: Office: HSC 270 Telephone: (504)-816-8150 E-mail: [email protected] Facebook: Steve Lemke Mission Statement, Core Values, and Key Competencies The NOBTS Mission Statement is to equip leaders to fulfill the Great Commission and the Great Commandments through the local church and its ministries. The NOBTS core value for the 2017-2018 academic year is Servant Leadership. This course teaches an ethic of servanthood and humility. This course also addresses the core values of Doctrinal Integrity and Spiritual Vitality. As part of the larger Seminary goal of equipping effective leaders of healthy churches, this course addresses the key competency of spiritual and character formation in the Seminary’s curriculum. 2 Student Learning Outcomes In order to provide moral leadership by modeling and mentoring Christian character and devotion, by the end of the course successful students should be able to: Apply their knowledge and comprehension of the following concepts to the process of providing moral leadership by modeling and mentoring Christian character and devotion: o A biblical Christian ethic.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Relativism by Matt Slick by CARM (Christian Apologetics & Research Ministry)
    Ethical Relativism by Matt Slick By CARM (Christian Apologetics & Research Ministry) Ethical relativism is the position that there are no moral absolutes, no moral right and wrongs. Instead, right and wrong are based on social norms. Such could be the case with "situational ethics," which is a category of ethical relativism. At any rate, ethical relativism would mean that our morals have evolved, that they have changed over time, and that they are not absolute. One advantage of ethical relativism is that it allows for a wide variety of cultures and practices. It also allows people to adapt ethically as the culture, knowledge, and technology change in society. This is a good and valid form of relativism. The disadvantage of ethical relativism is that truth, right and wrong, and justice are all relative. Just because a group of people think that something is right does not make it so. Slavery is a good example of this. Two hundred years ago in America, slavery was the norm and morally acceptable. Now it is not. Relativism also does not allow for the existence of an absolute set of ethics. Logically, if there are no absolute ethics, then there can be no Divine Absolute Ethics Giver. Requiring an absolute set of ethics implies an Absolute Ethics Giver, which can easily be extrapolated as being God. This would be opposed to ethical relativism. Therefore, ethical relativism would not support the idea of an absolute God, and it would exclude religious systems based upon absolute morals; that is, it would be absolute in its condemnation of absolute ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception in Aristotle's Ethics
    Perception in Aristotle's Ethics Author: Sharon Eve Rabinoff Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/3323 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2013 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Philosophy PERCEPTION IN ARISTOTLE’S ETHICS A Dissertation By SHARON EVE RABINOFF Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2013 © Copyright by SHARON EVE RABINOFF 2013 Perception in Aristotle’s Ethics Dissertation by Eve Rabinoff Under the Supervision of Dr. Marina McCoy Abstract The project of this dissertation is to examine the role that perception plays in Aristotle’s ethics. Aristotle is famous for offering what might be called a situational ethics: discerning what one ought to do is not derivable from universal laws, but must be assessed with respect to the particulars that make up the situation in which one must act. Aristotle argues that what virtue calls for is acting and feeling in an appropriate manner, i.e. at the right time, to the right degree, in the right manner, with respect to the right people, and so on (Nicomachean Ethics 1106b21-24). Moreover, because of the situational specificity of right action, one must also have the right character in order to discern what virtue calls for—only the virtuous person sees what is truly good. If one has a faulty character, the particulars will appear in a distorted manner, just as the wine tastes bitter to those who are ill (1113a25-29).
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Ethics and Politics
    Eastern Review Volume 8 Article 12 December 2019 Kant on ethics and politics Sabrina P. Ramet Norwegian University of Science and Technology, Trondheim, Norway, Department of Sociology and Political Science, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digijournals.uni.lodz.pl/easternreview Recommended Citation Ramet, Sabrina P. (2019) "Kant on ethics and politics," Eastern Review: Vol. 8 , Article 12. DOI: 10.18778/1427-9657.08.08 Available at: https://digijournals.uni.lodz.pl/easternreview/vol8/iss1/12 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Social Sciences Journals at University of Lodz Research Online. It has been accepted for inclusion in Eastern Review by an authorized editor of University of Lodz Research Online. For more information, please contact [email protected]. http://dx .doi .org/10 .18778/1427-9657 .08 .08 EASTERN REVIEW 2019, T. 8 Sabrina P. Ramet https://orcid .org/0000-0003-2843-3898 Norwegian University of Science and Technology Trondheim, Norway Department of Sociology and Political Science e-mail: sabrina .ramet@ntnu .no Kant on ethics and politics Abstract. Best known for his ethical works, Immanuel Kant was part of the liberal Enlightenment and addressed most of the principal political issues of his day . Several of his major works were written in the wake of the storming of the Bastille in Paris, while Europe was engaged in the French Revolutionary Wars . His rejection of revolution but endorsement of the principles for which the French revolutionaries were fighting, as well as his plea for a federation of European states that would settle disputes peacefully, reflected his engagement with the controversies raised by the Revolution.
    [Show full text]
  • The Moral Philosophy of Simone De Beauvoir Advantages of Ambiguity
    THE MORAL PHILOSOPHY OF SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR ADVANTAGES OF AMBIGUITY: THE MORAL PHILOSOPHY OF SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR By AMY LEASK, B.A. HONS A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts McMaster University ©Copyright by Amy Leask, April 1999 MASTER OF ARTS (1999) McMaster University (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: Advantages of Ambiguity: The Moral Philosophy of Simone de Beauvoir AUTHOR: Amy Leask, B.A. Hons (McMaster University) SUPERVISOR: Dr. S. M. Najm, Dr. E. Boetzkes NUMBER OF PAGES: vi, lO2 ii Abstract Simone de Beauvoir is known as a prolific novelist, a passionate political activist for the women's movement, and the long-time companion to the existential philosopher, Jean Paul Sartre. Her ideas as a philosopher, however, are often overshadowed by these alternate identities. The aim of this thesis is to reaffirm the value of de Beauvoir's philosophical contributions, in particular, those which pertain to moral philosophy. In order to achieve this, I will first attempt to distinguish de Beauvoir's philosophy from that of Sartre. From a moral standpoint, de Beauvoir presents a more explicitly moral version of existentialism, one which takes as its focus the self-other tension left unresolved in Sartrean ontology. Second, and more importantly, I will discuss the broad scope of de Beauvoir's moral theory. Her own application of this theory to the situation of women may be complimented by possible applications to racial, environmental and other moral issues. Perhaps the most significant contribution of this particular thesis lies in its methodological approach.
    [Show full text]
  • The Existential Phenomenology of Hazel E. Barnes: Toward a Theory of Existential Leadership Jen Jones
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Spring 2014 The Existential Phenomenology of Hazel E. Barnes: Toward a Theory of Existential Leadership Jen Jones Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Jones, J. (2014). The Existential Phenomenology of Hazel E. Barnes: Toward a Theory of Existential Leadership (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/710 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE EXISTENTIAL PHENOMENOLOGY OF HAZEL E. BARNES: TOWARD A THEORY OF EXISTENTIAL LEADERSHIP A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Jen Jones May 2014 Copyright by Jen Jones 2014 THE EXISTENTIAL PHENOMENOLOGY OF HAZEL E. BARNES: TOWARD A THEORY OF EXISTENTIAL LEADERSHIP By Jen Jones Approved February 28, 2014 ________________________________ ________________________________ Dr. Janie Harden Fritz Dr. Ronald C. Arnett Professor of Communication & Rhetorical Professor and Chair of Communication Studies and Rhetorical Studies (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ________________________________ Dr. Erik Garrett Associate Professor of Communication and Rhetorical Studies (Committee Member) ________________________________ ________________________________ Dr. James C. Swindal Dr. Ronald C. Arnett Dean, McAnulty College of Liberal Arts Chair, Department of Communication and Rhetorical Studies iii ABSTRACT THE EXISTENTIAL PHENOMENOLOGY OF HAZEL E. BARNES: TOWARD A THEORY OF EXISTENTIAL LEADERSHIP By Jen Jones May 2014 Dissertation supervised by Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Choosing Normativity After the “Death of God”
    Studia Philosophiae Christianae ETHICS – POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY UKSW 56(2020) Special Issue 2 ANDRZEJ KOBYLIŃSKI WHAT NORMATIVITY AFTER THE “DEATH OF GOD”? ETHICAL IMPLICATIONS OF WEAK THOUGHT* Abstract. The article aims to analyse the concept of normativity in the philosophy of weak thought developed by Gianni Vattimo. Weak thought refers to the theory of a weakening of being in an era of the end of metaphysics, as well as a challenge to the Cartesian concept of the subject. Such a philosophical theory does not entirely abandon normativity in the moral dimension. Vattimo proposes a weak notion of normativity, i.e. persuasion, without claims to universal applicability. Weak normativity derives from dialogue and respect for tradition, it recommends compliance with specific moral principles, but it does not acknowledge universal ethical obligations. This version of normativity is grounded in cultural heritage, agreement and social contract. Keywords: weak thought; strong thought; human nature; morality; nihilism; freedom; natural law; cultural heritage; post-metaphysical ethics 1. Introduction. 2. From the “death of God” to weak thought. 3. Negation of the concept of nature. 4. Cultural heritage as a source of morality. 5. Conclusions. 1. INTRODUCTION In the 1960s a renaissance of Friedrich Nietzsche’s thought began in many countries. Nietzsche-Renaissance had a profound impact on philosophy as it was practiced both in Italy and beyond. In the country on the Tiber, it was not easy to speak and write positively about the author of Thus Spoke Zarathustra immediately after World War II, due to his association with the birth of fascism and na- tional socialism.
    [Show full text]