The Concept of Affectivity in Early Modern Philosophy ------Gábor Gábor of of in in B Affe Oros E the the Arly Modern P Hi

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Concept of Affectivity in Early Modern Philosophy ------Gábor Gábor of of in in B Affe Oros E the the Arly Modern P Hi --------- --------- LOSOPHY There is no need to argue for the relevance of affectivity in HI early modern philosophy. When doing research and concep- P (eds) tualizing affectivity in this period, we hope to attain a basic H interpretive framework for philosophy in general, one that is T independent of and cutting across such unfruitful divisions as the time-honored interpretive distinction between “rationalists” N TÓ and “empiricists”, which we consider untenable when applied to VÁ T 17th-century thinkers. S I Y MODERN Y MODERN Our volume consists of papers based on the contributions RL to the First Budapest Seminar in Early Modern Philosophy, VÉR A LI held on 14–15 October 2016 at Eötvös Loránd University, E O . Budapest. When composing this volume, our aim was not I to present a systematic survey of affectivity in early mod- A L Y IN ern philosophy. Rather, our more modest goal was to foster A T Z I S collaboration among researchers working in different coun- T tries and different traditions. Many of the papers published IV here are already in implicit or explicit dialogue with others. ct JUDI We hope that they will generate more of an exchange of ide- . as in the broader field of early modern scholarship. OROS B F AFFE O T GÁBOR EP THE CONCEPT C BTK OF AFFEctIVITY in Early Modern ISBN 978-963-284-820-4 THE CON Philosophy GÁBOR BOROS . JUDIT SZALAI . OLIVÉR ISTVÁN TÓTH (eds) boros_borito.indd 1 2017.10.20. 11:48:40 --------- --------- The Concept of Affectivity in Early Modern Philosophy Gábor Boros – Judit Szalai – Olivér István Tóth (eds) The Concept of Affectivity in Early Modern Philosophy budapest • 2017 © Authors, 2017 © Editors, 2017 ISBN 978-963-284-820-4 [online] www.eotvoskiado.hu Executive Publisher: The Dean of the Faculty of Humanities of Eötvös Loránd University Cover: Ildikó Csele Kmotrik Layout: Manzana Bt. Table of contents Introduction . 7 I Ádám Smrcz: A Neo-Stoic Theory of Natural and Unnatural Affections . 11 II Maximillian Kiener: The Compulsion to Believe Something: On Affectivity of Indubitable, Clear and Distinct Perceptions in Descartes .............................................. 24 III Jan Forsman: Descartes on Will and Suspension of Judgment: Affectivity of the Reason for Doubt ............................ 38 IV Hanna Vandenbussche: Descartes and Pascal on Imagining Love and Imaginary Love ........................................ 59 V Judit Szalai: Medicine, Emotion Management and Mind-Body Interaction in the Later Descartes and Early Cartesianism . 75 VI Davide Monaco: A New Account of the Objective-Formal Distinction in Spinoza’s Parallelism Theory . 89 VII Filip Buyse: A New Reading of Spinoza’s Letter 32 to Oldenburg: Spinoza and the Agreement between Bodies in the Universe ......... 104 VIII Keith Green: Spinoza on Reflexive Affects and the Imitation of Affects ................................................ 124 IX Gábor Boros: Life as Death in Spinoza . 142 X Olivér István Tóth: Is Spinoza’s Theory of Finite Mind Coherent? – Death, Affectivity and Epistemology in the Ethics . 159 XI Brian Glenney: Spinoza on Passionate Misperception . 174 XII Christopher Davidson: An Affective Aesthetics in Spinoza and Its Political Implications ....................................... 185 XIII Zsolt Bagi: Emancipation of the Body in Spinoza’s Political Philosophy. The Affective Integration .................................... 207 XIV Dávid Bartha: The Human Passions and the Purely Active Will of God: An Introduction to Berkeley’s Theory of Emotion ................. 221 XV Dan O’Brien: Hume, Sympathy and Belief . 240 XVI Hans D. Muller: Hume on Sympathy, Pity and Impartiality ......... 257 XVII Csaba Olay: Alienation in Rousseau . 271 Contributors ..................................................... 284 Index of Names ................................................... 288 Gábor Boros – Judit Szalai – Olivér István Tóth Introduction There is scarcely any need to argue for the relevance of the concept of affectivity in early modern philosophy. Theories of emotion in this period have been one of the focal topics our research group, centered around Eötvös Loránd University, Budapest (ELTE), has in- vestigated in the past decades. The research group has taken several forms in the past and is now supported by the National Research, Development and Innovation Office (Hungary) in the frame of a research project on theories of emotions (K120375, “Self-Interpretation, Emotions, Narrativity”) and a research project on Descartes (K125012, “The Cartesian Mind between Cognition and Extension”). We work on various areas within early modern philosophy, with minimally one shared goal: deconstructing the time-honored interpretive distinction between “rationalists” and “empiricists”, which we consider untenable when ap- plied to 17th-century thinkers. Conceptualizing affectivity in this period provides us with an interpretive frame independent of and cutting across such unfruitful divisions. This was the main motivation behind our decision to commence the series of Budapest Seminars in Early Modern Philosophy with the topic of affectivity, inviting prospective participants to reinforce or to reject our conviction concerning the fruitfulness of this basic concept. In our view, the participants’ general response to this concealed expectation was illumi- natingly positive. We are proudly presenting the volume composed of papers based on the contributions presented at the conference. Besides NRDIO, we are grateful to Eötvös University, Budapest for supporting both the event (held in October 2016 at ELTE) and the preparation of the present volume. Special thanks to the Philosophy Department of the National Association of PhD Students for their support of the seminar. The aim of this volume is not to present a systematic survey of affectivity in early mod- ern philosophy, but rather to foster collaboration among researchers working in different countries and different traditions. Many of the papers published here are already in implicit or explicit dialogue with others. We hope that they will generate more exchange of ideas in the broader early modern scholarship. Introduction 7 Ádám Smrcz discusses the influence of Stoic authors on Justus Lipsius’ philosophy in general, and on his theory of affections in particular. He presents the intricacies of Lipsius’ attempt to Christianize this ancient philosophical school in a way that was adjusted both to his ever-changing religious affiliations and to the rigor of philosophical reasoning. Lipsius’ solution was distinguishing natural and unnatural affections and combatting an emerging prejudice concerning Stoic ethics. Kiener and Forsman both discuss Descartes’ concept of dubitability and indubitability. Maximillian Kiener takes a fresh look at the age-old problem of the Cartesian circle in Descartes’ Meditations. In his view, while most commentators have considered certainty, dubitability and compulsion to believe as psychological phenomena, they should rather be treated as epistemic concepts that might have bearings on psychological notions such as emotions and affectivity. Thus, he urges us to revise our understanding of early modern affectivity from an epistemic point of view. He also presents a new interpretation of the indubitability of clear and distinct ideas. Jan Forsman defends an indirect doxatic vol- untarist reading of Descartes against direct doxatic voluntarist interpretations. He argues that on Descartes’ view we are not capable of rejecting, accepting or suspending judgments based on our volitions; rather, our free will can choose to focus on particular reasons for forming a judgment. This view allows Forsman not to attribute to Descartes the seemingly counter-intuitive view that we can willfully doubt logical truths and accept judgments against all reasons. Hanna Vandenbussche compares Descartes’ and Pascal’s discussions of love. She shows that while both distinguished imaginary love from intellectual love, they had dif- ferent views on the role of the imagination. For Descartes it is one faculty of the soul, while for Pascal it is a source of moral corruption. Still, both saw imagination as a source of distortion, and especially as a source of a distorted image of oneself. Surprisingly, this does not prevent them from including the imagination in their accounts of the love of God. Judit Szalai focuses on the philosophical and physical descriptions of the operation of the emotions in the later Descartes and early Cartesians. She argues that contrary to the current mainstream interpretation, Descartes’ correspondence with Elizabeth does not represent a break within the Cartesian corpus, but rather shows one aspect of his theory more prominently. She then presents the way in which Descartes’ philosophical and physi- cal views map onto the medical practice of the 17th-century. Davide Monaco provides a new interpretation of the formal-objective distinction in Spinoza. By tracing back the history of the distinction to the Timaeus via Descartes and Suarez, he argues that Spinoza in his mature works does not simply accept the Scholastic or Cartesian version of the distinction. He argues that Spinoza’s parallelism doctrine implies the replacement of the objective being of ideas with the formal being of ideas, thus turning the formal-objective distinction into a formal-formal distinction. Both Buyse and Green discuss the consequences of Spinoza’s conatus doctrine for his theory of affects.Filip Buyse focuses on Spinoza’s Letter 32 to Oldenburg, in which he an- swers
Recommended publications
  • Stoicism and Political Thought from Lipsius to Rousseau
    Philosophic Pride Brooke.indb 1 1/17/2012 12:09:47 PM This page intentionally left blank Brooke.indb 2 1/17/2012 12:09:47 PM Philosophic Pride stoicism and political thought from lipsius to rousseau Christopher Brooke princeton university press Princeton and Oxford Brooke.indb 3 1/17/2012 12:09:47 PM Copyright © 2012 by Princeton University Press Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street, Princeton, New Jersey 08540 In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, 6 Oxford Street, Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1TW press.princeton.edu Jacket illustration: The Four Philosophers, c. 1611–12 (oil on panel), by Peter Paul Rubens (1577–1640); Palazzo Pitti, Florence, Italy. Reproduced courtesy of The Bridgeman Art Library; photo copyright Alinari All Rights Reserved Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Brooke, Christopher, 1973– Philosophic pride : Stoicism and political thought from Lipsius to Rousseau / Christopher Brooke. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references (p. 253) and index. ISBN 978-0-691-15208-0 (hardcover : alk. paper) 1. Political science—Philosophy— History. I. Title. JA71.B757 2012 320.01—dc23 2011034498 This book has been composed in Sabon LT Std Printed on acid-free paper. ∞ Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 00 Brooke FM i-xxiv.indd 4 1/24/2012 3:05:14 PM For Josephine Brooke.indb 5 1/17/2012 12:09:47 PM This page intentionally left blank The Stoic last in philosophic pride, By him called virtue, and his virtuous man, Wise, perfect in himself, and all possessing, Equal to God, oft shames not to prefer, As fearing God nor man, contemning all Wealth, pleasure, pain or torment, death and life— Which, when he lists, he leaves, or boasts he can; For all his tedious talk is but vain boast, Or subtle shifts conviction to evade.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoic Enlightenments
    Copyright © 2011 Margaret Felice Wald All rights reserved STOIC ENLIGHTENMENTS By MARGARET FELICE WALD A Dissertation submitted to the Graduate School-New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in English written under the direction of Michael McKeon and approved by ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ New Brunswick, New Jersey October 2011 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Stoic Enlightenments By MARGARET FELICE WALD Dissertation Director: Michael McKeon Stoic ideals infused seventeenth- and eighteenth-century thought, not only in the figure of the ascetic sage who grins and bears all, but also in a myriad of other constructions, shaping the way the period imagined ethical, political, linguistic, epistemological, and social reform. My dissertation examines the literary manifestation of Stoicism’s legacy, in particular regarding the institution and danger of autonomy, the foundation and limitation of virtue, the nature of the passions, the difference between good and evil, and the referentiality of language. Alongside the standard satirical responses to the ancient creed’s rigor and rationalism, seventeenth- and eighteenth-century poetry, drama, and prose developed Stoic formulations that made the most demanding of philosophical ideals tenable within the framework of common experience. Instead of serving as hallmarks for hypocrisy, the literary stoics I investigate uphold a brand of stoicism fit for the post-regicidal, post- Protestant Reformation, post-scientific revolutionary world. My project reveals how writers used Stoicism to determine the viability of philosophical precept and establish ways of compensating for human fallibility. The ambivalent status of the Stoic sage, staged and restaged in countless texts, exemplified the period’s anxiety about measuring up to its ideals, its efforts to discover the plenitude of ii natural laws and to live by them.
    [Show full text]
  • Mastery This Emphasis Is Not Exclusive of Social Responsibility and Concern
    University of Alberta Stoicism, Moral Education and Material Goods by David Patrick Burns A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Theoretical, Cultural and International Studies in Education Department of Educational Policy Studies ©David Patrick Burns Spring 2011 Edmonton, Alberta Permission is hereby granted to the University of Alberta Libraries to reproduce single copies of this thesis and to lend or sell such copies for private, scholarly or scientific research purposes only. Where the thesis is converted to, or otherwise made available in digital form, the University of Alberta will advise potential users of the thesis of these terms. The author reserves all other publication and other rights in association with the copyright in the thesis and, except as herein before provided, neither the thesis nor any substantial portion thereof may be printed or otherwise reproduced in any material form whatsoever without the author's prior written permission. To my loving wife, thank you. ABSTRACT Material goods play an important role in ethical life and moral education. Judging which goods are preferable to which − and which are therefore worth pursuing over which − is an ethically crucial process. The currently dominant paradigms of moral education (virtue education, cognitive developmentalism and care theory) do not satisfactorily contribute to this important topic. I argue that the resultant lacuna may be resolved by attending to the insight of the classical Stoics and their modern day neo‐Stoic interpreters. Stoicism, I argue, provides a unique set of philosophical resources that fosters critical deliberation and reflection regarding the attribution of value to material goods.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoic Psychotherapy in Descartes and Spinoza
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 11 Issue 4 Article 4 10-1-1994 Stoic Psychotherapy in Descartes and Spinoza Derk Pereboom Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Pereboom, Derk (1994) "Stoic Psychotherapy in Descartes and Spinoza," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 11 : Iss. 4 , Article 4. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol11/iss4/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. STOIC PSYCHOTHERAPY IN DESCARTES AND SPINOZA1 Derk Pereboom The psychotherapeutic theories of Descartes and Spinoza are heavily influ­ enced by Stoicism. Stoic psychotherapy has two central features. First, we have a remarkable degree of voluntary control over our passions, and we can and should exercise this control to keep ourselves from having any irrational passiom: at all. Second, the universe is determined by the providential divine will, and in any situation we can and should align ourselves with this divine will in order to achieve equanimity. Whereas Descartes largely endorses the Stoic picture, Spinoza develops a distinctive, intellectualized version of this view. Although the influence of the Stoic outlook on sixteenth and seventeenth century European culture has been well-documented, it is seldom recalled how, in particular, Stoicism affects the views of the early modern European philosophers.2 The works of Descartes and Spinoza supply remarkable illus­ trations of this impact.
    [Show full text]
  • Part 1 Anger Management in Early Modern Philosophical Discourses
    Part 1 Anger Management in Early Modern Philosophical Discourses ∵ Chapter 3 Neo-Stoicism as an Antidote to Public Violence before Lipsius’s De constantia: Johann Weyer’s (Wier’s) Anger Therapy, De ira morbo (1577) Karl A.E. Enenkel Among the works of Johann Weyer (Wier, Piscinarius; 1515/1516–1588), court physician to Wilhelm the Rich, 5th Duke of Cleve, Jülich, and Berg,1 occurs a most intriguing treatise, De ira morbo, eiusdem curatione philosophica, medic- ina et theologica—On the Disease (Kranckheit) of Anger, and its Philosophical, Medical, and Theological Therapy, which appeared in 1577.2 Weyer intended to 1 Johann Weyer served Wilhelm the Rich as court physician from 1555 onward until his well- deserved retirement in 1578. For Weyer’s biography cf. Hoorens V., Een ketterse arts voor de heksen. Jan Wier (1515–1588) (Amsterdam: 2011); Binz C., Doctor Johann Weyer, ein rheinischer Arzt, der erste Bekämpfer des Hexenwahns (1st ed. Bonn: 1885 [Zeitschrift des Bergischen Geschichtsvereins 21]; 2nd ed. Berlin: 1896; reprint of the 2nd ed. Wiesbaden: 1969, and New York: 1975); Meyer Th., “Weyer, Johann”, Biographisch-Bibliographisches Kirchenlexikon 20 (2002) cols. 1537–1544. Thus far, Weyer has become known in scholarly discussions almost exclusively with respect to his treatise on witches (De praestigiis daemonum [. .] [ed. pr. Basel, Johannes Oporinus: 1563); cf., inter alia, the above-quoted works, and Nahl R. van, Zauberglaube und Hexenwahn im Gebiet von Rhein und Maas. Spätmittelalterlicher Volksglaube im Werk Johan Weyers (1515–1588) (Bonn: 1983); Mora G. et al., Witches, Devils, and Doctors in the Renaissance: Johann Weyer, “De praestigiis daemonum”, Medieval & Renaissance Texts & Studies 73 (Binghamton, N.Y.: 1991); Cobben J.J., Duivelse bezetenheid, beschreven door dok- ter Johannes Wier, 1515–1588 (Rotterdam: 2002); Gunnoe Ch.D., “The Debate between Johann Weyer and Thomas Erastus on the Punishment of Witches”, in Van Horn Melton J.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism in Early Christianity
    STOICISM IN EARLY CHRISTIANITY Edited by Tuomas Rasimus, Troels Engberg-Pedersen, and Ismo Dunderberg K Tuomas Rasimus, Troels Engberg-Pedersen and Ismo Dunderberg, Stoicism in Early Christianity Baker Academic, a division of Baker Publishing Group, © 2010. Used by permission. _Rasimus_Stoicism_BB_djm.indd 3 9/29/10 3:29 PM © 2010 by Tuomas Rasimus, Troels Engberg-Pedersen, and Ismo Dunderberg Published by Baker Academic a division of Baker Publishing Group P.O. Box 6287, Grand Rapids, MI 49516-6287 www.bakeracademic.com Printed in the United States of America All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Stoicism in early Christianity / edited by Tuomas Rasimus, Troels Engberg- Pedersen, and Ismo Dunderberg. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and indexes. ISBN 978-0-8010-3951-5 (alk. paper) 1. Stoics. 2. Philosophy and religion—Rome. 3. Church history—Primitive and early church, ca. 30–600. 4. Bible. N.T.—Philosophy. I. Rasimus, Tuomas. II. Engberg-Pedersen, Troels. III. Dunderberg, Ismo. BR128.A2.S76 2010 261.2—dc22 2010021683 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Tuomas Rasimus, Troels Engberg-Pedersen and Ismo Dunderberg, Stoicism in Early Christianity Baker Academic, a division of Baker Publishing Group, © 2010. Used by permission. _Rasimus_Stoicism_BB_djm.indd 4 9/29/10 3:29 PM Contents Preface vii Abbreviations ix 1. Setting the Scene: Stoicism and Platonism in the Transitional Period in Ancient Philosophy 1 Troels Engberg-Pedersen 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Henry More As Reader SELLARS Accepted12march2017 GREEN
    King’s Research Portal DOI: 10.1080/09608788.2017.1306772 Document Version Peer reviewed version Link to publication record in King's Research Portal Citation for published version (APA): Sellars, J. (2017). Henry More as Reader of Marcus Aurelius. British Journal for the History of Philosophy . https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2017.1306772 Citing this paper Please note that where the full-text provided on King's Research Portal is the Author Accepted Manuscript or Post-Print version this may differ from the final Published version. If citing, it is advised that you check and use the publisher's definitive version for pagination, volume/issue, and date of publication details. And where the final published version is provided on the Research Portal, if citing you are again advised to check the publisher's website for any subsequent corrections. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Research Portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognize and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. •Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the Research Portal for the purpose of private study or research. •You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain •You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the Research Portal Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim.
    [Show full text]
  • Literaturverzeichnis"
    553 Literaturverzeichnis" I Antike Primärtexte Alexander von Aphrodisias, De anima liber cum Mantissa (=De anima liber alter), in: Supplementum Aristototelicum 11,1, ed. Ivo Bruns, Berlin 1887. ders., Über das Schicksal, übers. u. komm. v. Andreas Zierl, Berlin 1995. Ancius Manlius Torquatus Severinus Boethius, De Institutione arithmetica libri duo, De Institutione musica libri quinque, ed. Godofredus Friedlein, Leipzig 1867 (=ND Frankfurt a. M. 1966). ders., Fünf Bücher über die Musik, aus dem lat. in die dt. Sprache übertr. u. erkl. v. Oscar Paul, 2. ND. der Ausg. Leipzig 1872, Hildesheim (u.a.) 1985. Aristoteles, Analytica Priora et Posteriora, ree. William D. Ross (praefatione et ap- pendice auxit L. Minio-Paluello), Oxford, 1964. ders., Categoriae et liber De Interpretatione, rec. L. Minio-Paluello, Oxford, 1949. ders., De anima, rec. William D. Ross, Oxford, 1956. ders., De arte poetica liber, ree. Rudolf Kassel, Oxford 1965. ders., Metaphysica, ree. Werner Jaeger, Oxford, 1957. ders., Physica, rec. William D. Ross, Oxford, 1950. Aurelio Agostino. Musica. Introduzione, traduzione, note e apparati di Maria Bette­ tini, Mailand 1997. Cicero, Marcus Tullius, De divinatione (enthält außerdem: De fato u. Timaeus), ect. Remo Giomini, Leipzig 1975. ders., Academicorum Reliquiae cum Lucullo, ree. Otto Plasberg, Stuttgart 1961. ders., De re publica, ree. Konrad Ziegler, Leipzig 71969 (=Stuttgart (u. a.) 1992). ders., De re publica (lat./dt.), Vom Staatswesen, übers. u. hg. v. Karl Büchner, ND Stuttgart 1995. ders., De finibus bonorum et malorum. Über das höchste Gut und das größte Übel, (lat./dt.), übers. u. hg. v. Harald Merklin, Stuttgart1989. Diogenes Laertius, De vitis cIarorum philosophorum, (griech./ d1.), übersetzt von Otto Apelt, hg.
    [Show full text]
  • Presberg LS Jacket
    dventures in aradox PENN STATE STUDIES in ROMANCE LITERATURES Editors Frederick A. de Armas Norris Lacy Allan Stoekl Refiguring the Hero: Medieval Spanish Epic: From Peasant to Noble in Mythic Roots and Ritual Language Lope de Vega and Calderón by Thomas Montgomery by Dian Fox Unfinished Revolutions: Don Juan and the Point of Honor: Legacies of Upheaval in Seduction, Patriarchal Society, Modern French Culture and Literary Tradition edited by Robert T. Denommé and by James Mandrell Roland H. Simon Narratives of Desire: Nineteenth-Century Spanish Stages of Desire: Fiction by Women The Mythological Tradition in Classical by Lou Charnon-Deutsch and Contemporary Spanish Theater by Michael Kidd Garcilaso de la Vega and the Italian Renaissance Fictions of the Feminine in the by Daniel L. Heiple Nineteenth-Century Spanish Press by Lou Charnon-Deutsch Allegories of Kingship: Calderón and the Anti-Machiavellian Tradition The Novels and Plays of by Stephen Rupp Eduardo Manet: An Adventure in Multiculturalism Acts of Fiction: by Phyllis Zatlin Resistance and Resolution from Sade to Baudelaire Fernando de Rojas and the by Scott Carpenter Renaissance Vision: Phantasm, Melancholy, and Didacticism in Grotesque Purgatory: Celestina by Ricardo Castells A Study of Cervantes’s Don Quixote, Part II by Henry W. Sullivan The Poetics of Empire in the Indies: Spanish Comedies and Historical Prophecy and Imitation in Contexts in the 1620s La Araucana and Os Lucíadas by William R. Blue by James Nicolopulos The Cultural Politics of Tel Quel: Literature and the Left in the Mariá de Zayas Tells Baroque Tales of Love Wake of Engagement and the Cruelty of Men by Danielle Marx-Scouras Margaret Greer Madrid 1900: Vision, the Gaze, and the Function of the The Capital as Cradle of Senses in Celestina Literature and Culture James F.
    [Show full text]
  • Henry More As Reader of Marcus Aurelius
    Henry More as Reader of Marcus Aurelius JOHN SELLARS ABSTRACT: I examine Henry More’s engagement with Stoicism in general, and Marcus Aurelius in particular, in his Enchiridion Ethicum. More quotes from Marcus’s Meditations throughout the Enchiridion, leading one commentator to note that More ‘mined the Meditations’ when writing his book. Yet More’s general attitude towards Stoicism is more often than not critical, especially when it comes to the passions. I shall argue that while More was clearly an avid reader of the Meditations he read Marcus not as a Stoic but as a ‘non-denominational’ ancient moralist who confirms a range of doctrines that More finds elsewhere in ancient philosophy. In this sense More continues the Neoplatonic practice of downplaying doctrinal differences between ancient philosophers in order to construct a single ancient philosophical tradition. This is quite different from the approach of his contemporary and fellow Cambridge Platonist, Ralph Cudworth, who was keen to highlight doctrinal differences between ancient philosophers. Henry More’s Enchiridion Ethicum, first published in 1668 and translated into English as An Account of Virtue in 1690,1 is rich in references to ancient philosophical authors. Among these Aristotle is probably the most prominent, but a casual reader of the work cannot help be struck by the frequency with which More quotes from or refers to the Meditations of Marcus Aurelius. Indeed, the frequency led one recent commentator to claim that More ‘mined the Meditations’ when writing the work.2 More was by no means alone in being captivated by the Meditations during this period.
    [Show full text]
  • Shakespeare's Moral Compass
    SHAKESPEARE’S MORAL COMPASS 55829_Parvini.indd829_Parvini.indd i 003/08/183/08/18 111:511:51 AAMM EDINBURGH CRITICAL STUDIES IN SHAKESPEARE AND PHILOSOPHY Series Editor: Kevin Curran Edinburgh Critical Studies in Shakespeare and Philosophy takes seriously the speculative and world-making properties of Shakespeare’s art. Maintaining a broad view of ‘philosophy’ that accommodates fi rst-order questions of metaphysics, ethics, politics and aesthetics, the series also expands our understanding of philosophy to include the unique kinds of theoretical work carried out by performance and poetry itself. These scholarly monographs will reinvigorate Shakespeare studies by opening new interdisciplinary conversations among scholars, artists and students. Editorial Board Members Ewan Fernie, Shakespeare Institute, University of Birmingham James Kearney, University of California, Santa Barbara Julia Reinhard Lupton, University of California, Irvine Madhavi Menon, Ashoka University Simon Palfrey, Oxford University Tiffany Stern, Shakespeare Institute, University of Birmingham Henry Turner, Rutgers University Michael Witmore, The Folger Shakespeare Library Paul Yachnin, McGill University Published Titles Rethinking Shakespeare’s Political Philosophy: From Lear to Leviathan Alex Schulman Shakespeare in Hindsight: Counterfactual Thinking and Shakespearean Tragedy Amir Khan Second Death: Theatricalities of the Soul in Shakespeare’s Drama Donovan Sherman Shakespeare’s Fugitive Politics Thomas P. Anderson Is Shylock Jewish?: Citing Scripture and the Moral
    [Show full text]
  • MARCUS AURELIUS MARCUS Department at the University of Cologne
    BLACKWELL BLACKWELL COMPANIONS TO THE ANCIENT WORLD COMPANIONS TO THE ANCIENT WORLD t h e e d i t o r A COMPANION TO A COMPANION TO Marcel van Ackeren is Associated Professor/ A COMPANION TO Senior Research Fellow in the Philosophy MARCUS AURELIUS MARCUS Department at the University of Cologne. He is the author of Das Wissen vom Guten. Bedeutung Contributors to this volume: AURELIUS und Kontinuität des Tugendwissens in den Dialogen MARCUS AURELIUS Platons (2003), Heraklit (2005), Understanding E D I T E D B Y Marcel van Ackeren, Martin Beckmann, Anthony R. Birley, Ancient Philosophy (edited with Jörn Müller, EDITED BY VAN ACKEREN marcus MARCEL VAN ACKEREN 2006), The Political Identity of the West. Platonism Lukas de Blois, Susanne Börner, Dietrich Boschung, Julia Bruch, A COMPANION TO in the Dialogue of Cultures (edited with Orrin F. Matteo Ceporina, Werner Eck, Mark J. Edwards, Michael Erler, Considered the last of the “Five Good Emperors,” Summerell, 2006), Die Philosophie Marc Aurels, 2 Thomas Fischer, Pascale Fleury, Angelo Giavatto, Christopher Gill, Marcus Aurelius ruled the Roman Empire vols. (2011), and Meditations and Representations. Jean-Baptiste Gourinat, Olivier Hekster, Katrin Herrmann, aurelius from ad 161 until his death in 180 – yet his Marcus Aurelius in Interdisciplinary Light (edited Leofranc Holford-Strevens, Péter Kovács, Jill Kraye, Anthony A. Long, influence on philosophy continues to resonate with Jan Opsomer, 2012). Irmgard Männlein-Robert, Gretchen Reydams-Schils, Amy Richlin, EDITED BY Marcel van ackeren in the modern age through his Meditations. A David Sedley, John Sellars, Peter Stewart Companion to Marcus Aurelius presents the first comprehensive collection of essays to explore all essential facets relating to contemporary ALSO AVAILABLE IN THIS SERIES: Marcus Aurelius studies.
    [Show full text]