Laboratory Primate Newsletter

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Laboratory Primate Newsletter LABORATORY PRIMATE NEWSLETTER Vol. 47, No. 4 October 2008 JUDITH E. SCHRIER, EDITOR JAMES S. HARPER, GORDON J. HANKINSON AND LARRY HULSEBOS, ASSOCIATE EDITORS MORRIS L. POVAR, CONSULTING EDITOR ELVA MATHIESEN, ASSISTANT EDITOR ALLAN M. SCHRIER, FOUNDING EDITOR, 1962-1987 Published Quarterly by the Schrier Research Laboratory Psychology Department, Brown University Providence, Rhode Island ISSN 0023-6861 POLICY STATEMENT The Laboratory Primate Newsletter provides a central source of information about nonhuman primates and re- lated matters to scientists who use these animals in their research and those whose work supports such research. The Newsletter (1) provides information on care and breeding of nonhuman primates for laboratory research, (2) dis- seminates general information and news about the world of primate research (such as announcements of meetings, research projects, sources of information, nomenclature changes), (3) helps meet the special research needs of indi- vidual investigators by publishing requests for research material or for information related to specific research prob- lems, and (4) serves the cause of conservation of nonhuman primates by publishing information on that topic. As a rule, research articles or summaries accepted for the Newsletter have some practical implications or provide general information likely to be of interest to investigators in a variety of areas of primate research. However, special con- sideration will be given to articles containing data on primates not conveniently publishable elsewhere. General descriptions of current research projects on primates will also be welcome. The Newsletter appears quarterly and is intended primarily for persons doing research with nonhuman primates. Back issues may be purchased for $10.00 each. We are no longer printing paper issues, except those we will send to subscribers who have paid in advance. We will not accept future subscriptions, unless subscribers are willing to pay $100/year. (Please make checks payable to the Brown University Psychology Department.) Readers with ac- cess to electronic mail may receive a notice when a new issue is put on the Website by sending the message sub- scribe LPN-WARN your-own-name to [email protected]. (Send the message subscribe LPN-PDF to receive PDF files by e-mail; or the message subscribe LPN-L to receive the nongraphic contents of each issue.) Current and back issues of the Newsletter are available on the World Wide Web at <http://www.brown.edu/primate>. Persons who have absolutely no access to the Web, or to the electronic mail- ing, may ask to have paper copies sent to them. The publication lag is typically no longer than the three months between issues and can be as short as a few weeks. The deadline for inclusion of a note or article in any given issue of the Newsletter has in practice been somewhat flexible, but is technically the tenth of December, March, June, or September, depending on which issue is scheduled to appear next. Reprints will not be supplied under any circumstances, but authors may reproduce their own articles in any quantity. PREPARATION OF ARTICLES FOR THE NEWSLETTER. – Articles, notes, and announcements may be submitted by mail, e-mail, or computer disk, but a printed copy of manuscripts of any length or complexity should also be sent by regular mail.. Articles in the References section should be referred to in the text by author(s) and date of publication, e.g., Smith (1960) or (Smith & Jones, 1962). Names of journals should be spelled out com- pletely in the References section. Latin names of primates should be indicated at least once in each note and article. In general, to avoid inconsistencies within the Newsletter, the Latin names used will be those in Mammal Species of The World: A Taxonomic and Geographic Reference, 2nd Ed. D. E. Wilson & D. M. Reeder (Eds.). Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1993. For an introduction to and review of primate nomenclature see the chapter by Maryeva Terry in A. M. Schrier (Ed.), Behavioral Primatology: Advances in Research and Theory (Vol. 1). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1977. All correspondence concerning the Newsletter should be addressed to: Judith E. Schrier, Psychology Department, Box 1853, Brown University Providence, Rhode Island 02912 [401-863-2511; FAX: 401-863-1300] e-mail address: [email protected] Current and back issues of the Newsletter are available on the World Wide Web at http://brown.edu/primate ACKNOWLEDGMENTS The Newsletter is supported by Brown University Cover photograph of a Douc Langur (Pygathrix nemaeus), taken at the San Diego Zoo by Paul G. Wilde, June 1997 Copyright © 2008 by Brown University Creating Housing to Meet the Behavioral Needs of Long-tailed Macaques C. D. Waitt1, Paul E. Honess1, and Moshe Bushmitz2 1Dept of Veterinary Services, University of Oxford, Oxford, U.K.; and 2BFC, Mazor, Tel Aviv, Israel Introduction Long-tailed macaques (Macaca fascicularis) are one sanctuaries, particularly as a result of rescue from illegal of the most widespread primates found in captivity. and private trade, but also due to retirement from research Though uncommon in zoos (ISIS database, 2008), long- and breeding facilities (C.W., P.H., & M.B., pers. obs.). tailed macaques are found in large numbers in breeding Despite their large numbers in captivity, little information centers and research facilities around the world (Carlsson has been dedicated to providing environments that meet et al., 2004; Hagelin, 2004). They also are found in many their species-typical behavioral needs. Figure 1: External view of the two-story housing system. Designing for Behavioral Needs When designing captive environments to meet ani- most of their time at heights of 12 m (39.4 ft) or less in mals’ behavioral needs, we should use the choices and the lower canopy and understory, though they also go preferences that animals make in both the wild and cap- down to the ground to forage (Ungar, 1996). Research on tivity (Dawkins, 2003). In their natural habitat, long- captive long-tailed macaques informs us that they have tailed macaques live in a variety of tropical forested re- strong preferences for higher parts of their enclosures gions throughout Southeast Asia (Rowe, 1996; Supriatna (Watson & Shively, 1996). Preferences for height are et al., 1996). They use a variety of substrates, spending most likely linked to feelings of safety, as long-tailed ma- caques exhibit a vertical flight response when frightened in the wild (van Schaik et al., 1983) and captivity (C.W., Second author’s address: Dept of Veterinary Services, Univ. of P.H., & M.B., pers. obs). Not providing adequate vertical Oxford, Oxford, U.K. [e-mail: [email protected]]. 1 flight space may lead animals to feeling trapped and can cealment from frightening stimuli, as hiding is a common cause stress and anxiety-related behaviors. For example, strategy employed by wild long-tailed macaques when long-tailed macaques housed in taller cages were found to threatened by predators, including humans (van Schaik et exhibit less self-directed stereotypies than those in shorter al., 1983). Captive environments should also allow for cages (Watson & Shively, 1996). this by incorporating visual barriers within the enclosure design. This allows animals to increase or decrease visual Not only should long-tailed macaques be provided contact with each other as they choose, as well as hide with enclosures that are tall, but it is also important to from caretakers or visitors and divide into sub-groupings. maximize the use of space. As long-tailed macaques Various studies have demonstrated the benefits of visual choose to exploit a variety of heights and substrates in the barriers in reducing aggression and related injuries in wild, the captive environment should also allow for this. other macaque species (e.g., McCormack & Megna, 2001; This can be achieved through the careful placement of Maninger et al., 1998; Westergaard et al., 1999). Visual plenty of perches at different heights. Providing an ade- quate amount of well-spaced perching is important for avoiding agonism in primates (Nakamichi & Asanuma, 1998; Neveu & Deputte, 1996), as it allows animals to space themselves as they desire and reduces risk of ag- gressive competition. Figure 3: Multi-level perching around enclosure walls and in the center allows animals to space themselves as they desire and avoids competition over space. barriers can even be effective for pair-housed macaques, Figure 2: Pop-holes in mezzanine floor allowing access be- where they have been demonstrated to promote affiliation tween the two stories. (Reinhardt & Reinhardt, 1991). Many primate species, including long-tailed ma- Two-story Housing Concept and Design caques, which live in multi-male groups in the wild, are The two-story housing system we describe here was kept in small, single-male groups in captivity. Long- designed to specifically address the macaques’ behavioral tailed macaques naturally form mixed-sex groups ranging needs and is currently used to house multi-male, multi- in size from 6 to 58 individuals; when numbers are large, female groups of long-tailed macaques at BFC, a breeding long-tailed macaque groups split up into smaller foraging facility in Israel. The concept is to create an environment parties based on social rank to avoid feeding competition that resembles the situation in the wild, where animals can (Wheatley, 1980; van Noordwijk & van Schaik, 1987; van occupy different arboreal levels, while also being able to Schaik & van Noordwijk, 1988). Many facility managers exploit the ground. The height is 4 m, and while the and caretakers argue that males of these species are too footprint is 36 m2, there is a total floor area of 72 m2 due aggressive to keep together (C.W., P.H., & M.B., pers. to the presence of a wooden mezzanine floor at 2 m obs.). This is likely to be due in large part to the fact that (Figure 1).
Recommended publications
  • Cruel Nature: Harmfulness As an Important, Overlooked Dimension in Judgments of Moral Standing ⇑ Jared Piazza , Justin F
    Cognition 131 (2014) 108–124 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Cognition journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT Cruel nature: Harmfulness as an important, overlooked dimension in judgments of moral standing ⇑ Jared Piazza , Justin F. Landy, Geoffrey P. Goodwin Department of Psychology, University of Pennsylvania, USA article info abstract Article history: Entities that possess moral standing can be wronged and deserve our moral consideration. Received 8 October 2013 Past perspectives on the folk psychology of moral standing have focused exclusively on the Revised 24 December 2013 role of ‘‘patiency’’ (the capacity to experience pain or pleasure) and ‘‘agency’’ (usually Accepted 27 December 2013 defined and operationalized in terms of intelligence or cognitive ability). We contend that harmfulness (i.e., having a harmful vs. benevolent disposition) is an equally if not more important determinant of moral standing. We provide support for this hypothesis across Keywords: four studies using non-human animals as targets. We show that the effect of harmfulness Moral standing on attributions of moral standing is independent from patiency and intelligence (Studies Harmfulness Patiency 1–2), that this effect pertains specifically to an animal’s harmful disposition rather than Agency its capacity to act upon this disposition (Study 3), and that it primarily reflects a parochial Intelligence concern for human welfare in particular (Study 4). Our findings highlight an important, Animals overlooked dimension in the psychology of moral standing that has implications for real-world decisions that affect non-human animals. Our findings also help clarify the con- ditions under which people perceive patiency and agency as related versus truly indepen- dent dimensions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Great Ape Project — and Beyond*
    The Great Ape Project — and Beyond* PAOLA CAVALIERI & PETER SINGER Why the Project? Aristotle refers to human slaves as 'animated property'. The phrase exactly describes the current status of nonhuman animals. Human slavery therefore presents an enlightening parallel to this situation. We shall explore this parallel in order to single out a past response to human slavery that may suggest a suitable way of responding to present-day animal slavery. Not long ago such a parallel would have been considered outrageous. Recently, however, there has been growing recognition of the claim that a sound ethic must be free of bias or arbitrary discrimination based in favour of our own species. This recognition makes possible a more impartial appraisal of the exploitative practices that mark our civilisation. Slavery in the ancient world has been the subject of a lively debate among historians. How did it arise? Why did it end? Was there a characteristic 'slave mode of production'? We do not need to go into all these disputes. We shall focus instead on the distinctive element of slavery: the fact that the human being becomes property in the strict sense of the term. This is sometimes referred to as 'chattel slavery' - a term that stresses the parallel between the human institution, and the ownership of animals, for the term 'cattle' is derived from 'chattel'. Slave societies are those societies of which chattel slavery is a major feature. They are relatively rare in human history. The best known examples existed in the ancient world, and in North and Central America after European colonisation.
    [Show full text]
  • An Assessment of Recent Trade Law Developments from an Animal Law Perspective: Trade Law As the Sheep in Wolf's Clothing?
    AN ASSESSMENT OF RECENT TRADE LAW DEVELOPMENTS FROM AN ANIMAL LAW PERSPECTIVE: TRADE LAW AS THE SHEEP IN WOLF’S CLOTHING? By Charlotte Blattner* Further development within the field of animal law seems to be at an impasse, lost among the potential paths presented by its traditional influ- ences: international treaty law, domestic animal welfare regulations, and trade law. First, classical elements of global animal treaty law are limited to preservationist aspirations, insusceptible to the questions of how animals are treated or how they cope with their environment. Second, animal welfare regulation is understood as a matter confined to national territories. In cross-border dialogue, animal matters have been reduced to allegations of imperialism, which is not conducive to furthering animal interests. Third, animals are regarded as commodities in international trade law, rendering their regulation an undesirable barrier to trade. These present deficiencies deprive global animal law of its significance as a dynamic instrument re- sponsive to global challenges, be they ethical, environmental, economic, technological, or social in nature. The objective of this paper is to demonstrate future ways out of this impasse. Recent developments in trade law, as demonstrated by four exam- ples found within the World Trade Organization’s (WTO) ‘case law,’ mark an important development for animal law. State objectives expressed through trade law are slowly moving away from anthropocentric considera- tions (i.e., geared to preserve a fraction of animals for human interests) to- wards sentiocentric animal welfare (i.e., aimed at minimizing animal suffering and focusing on animal interests). Thereby, the quality of animal law that developed on the international scene through trade law exceeded the status quo of global animal treaty law.
    [Show full text]
  • Connexion: a Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates
    Dalhousie Law Journal Volume 40 Issue 2 Article 5 10-1-2017 Connexion: A Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates John Enman-Beech Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.schulichlaw.dal.ca/dlj Part of the Animal Law Commons Recommended Citation John Enman-Beech, "Connexion: A Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates" (2017) 40:2 Dal LJ 545. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Schulich Law Scholars. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dalhousie Law Journal by an authorized editor of Schulich Law Scholars. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Enman-Beech* Connexion: A Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates Effective animal advocacy requires human-animal connexion. I apply a relational approach to unfold this insight into a praxis for animal advocates. Connexion grounds the affective relationships that so often motivate animal advocates. More importantly, it enables animal agency, the ability of animals to act and communicate in ways humans can experience and respond to. With connexion in mind, some weaknesses of previous reform efforts become apparent. I join these in the slogan "abolitionismas disconnexion." In so far as abolitionism draws humans and animals apart, it undermines the movement's social basis, limits its imaginative resources, and deprives animals of a deeper freedom. I evaluate political theories of animals and find that only some can frame a picture of humans and animals living together in connexion. I close by noting the limitations of the connexion lens-we cannot simply create connexions without also evaluating whether they are oppressive-and some practical policy measures that can be taken today to further the goods of connexion Pour 6tre efficace, /a defense des animaux exige une connexion entre /'homme et /'animal.
    [Show full text]
  • The First Step in the Case for Great Ape Equality: the Argument for Other Minds
    WellBeing International WBI Studies Repository 8-1996 The First Step in the Case for Great Ape Equality: The Argument for Other Minds Kristin Andrews York University Follow this and additional works at: https://www.wellbeingintlstudiesrepository.org/psycho Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Behavior and Ethology Commons, and the Comparative Psychology Commons Recommended Citation Andrews, K. (1996). The first step in the case for great ape equality: the argument for other minds. Etica ed Animali, 8, 131ss. This material is brought to you for free and open access by WellBeing International. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The First Step in the Case for Great Ape Equality: The Argument for Other Minds Kristin Andrews A defense of equality for great apes must begin with an understanding of the opposition and an acknowledgement of the most basic point of disagreement. For great apes to gain status as persons in our community, we must begin by determining what the multitude of different definitions of "person" have in common. Finding that great apes fulfill the requirements of any one specific theory of personhood is insufficient, for these theories are highly controversial, and a critique of the theory will undermine the status of great apes as persons. Instead, the first step in the argument for ape equality must be a defense of their self-consciousness. This notion is one thing all plausible theories of personhood have in common. Contrary to most people's common conceptions, many philosophers have argued that great apes, as well as all nonhuman animals, lack consciousness.1 This notion must be demolished before any argument for the equality of great apes can be fully defended.
    [Show full text]
  • A Conspiracy of Life: a Posthumanist Critique of Appoaches to Animal Rights in the Law Barnaby E
    University of Massachusetts Law Review Volume 14 | Issue 1 Article 3 A Conspiracy of Life: A Posthumanist Critique of Appoaches to Animal Rights in the Law Barnaby E. McLaughlin Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umassd.edu/umlr Part of the Animal Law Commons Recommended Citation McLaughlin, Barnaby E. () "A Conspiracy of Life: A Posthumanist Critique of Appoaches to Animal Rights in the Law," University of Massachusetts aL w Review: Vol. 14 : Iss. 1 , Article 3. Available at: https://scholarship.law.umassd.edu/umlr/vol14/iss1/3 This Note is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship Repository @ University of Massachusetts chooS l of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Massachusetts Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarship Repository @ University of Massachusetts chooS l of Law. A Conspiracy of Life: A Posthumanist Critique of Approaches to Animal Rights in the Law Barnaby E. McLaughlin 14 U. MASS. L. REV. 150 ABSTRACT Near the end of his life, Jacques Derrida, one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century, turned his attention from the traditional focus of philosophy, humans and humanity, to an emerging field of philosophical concern, animals. Interestingly, Derrida claimed in an address entitled The Animal That Therefore I Am that, since I began writing, in fact, I believe I have dedicated [my work] to the question of the living and of the living animal. For me that will always have been the most important and decisive question. I have addressed it a thousand times, either directly or obliquely, by means of readings of all the philosophers I have taken an interest in.
    [Show full text]
  • BIOLOGICAL CONTINUITY and GREAT APE RIGHTS .By MARK A
    BIOLOGICAL CONTINUITY AND GREAT APE RIGHTS .By MARK A. KRAuse* Finding the best approach to ensure that great apes will not succumb to the senseless destruction that humans inflict upon them, which could ultimately lead to their extinction, is an imposing task. Deforestation, poaching, and draining wild ape populations for the purposes of economic gain, personal gratification, and laboratory research have been ongoing' problems spanning several decades. Over the past ten years, maintaining captive populations has been of great concern as well. One exigent con- cern is the large number of chimpanzees who are used in biomedical re- search; that number is estimated at nearly two thousand individuals in the U.S.' Efforts are underway that we hope will sensitize the public to what is happening in many laboratories. Federal health, sanitation, and enrich- ment standards leave a lot to be desired, as does the compliance with these standards by laboratories housing hundreds of chimpanzees. Attempts to extend legal rights across the species barrier have begun. Granting great apes--chimpanzees, bonobos, gorillas, and orangutans- certain basic rights to life will prevent much of the exploitation that they currently endure. The main thrust of this essay is to approach the legal rights issue with an argument based on biological relatedness. What I hope emerges from this is an awareness that differences in kind between our species and our fellow animals are an illusion maintained by human arrogance. This reality is reflected in the continuity that exists between ourselves and apes. Even though the angle taken here is from the great ape side, the great apes are not the only species deserving of legal protec- tion.
    [Show full text]
  • The Meaning of the Great Ape Project
    POLITICS AND ANIMALS ISSUE 1 I FALL I 2015 The Meaning of the Great Ape Project PAOLA CAVALIERI Independent Researcher It is now more than two decades since the Great Ape Project was launched. How does such a cultural Keywords: and political initiative fit in the ongoing construction of a politics of animal liberation, and in the larger egalitarianism; contemporary moral and social landscape? An albeit tentative answer to this question will be possible nonhuman great apes; only in the context of an illustration of what the Great Ape project is—of its starting point, its articula- personhood; tion, and the objections it elicited. liberation THE PREMISES community may be arranged on the basis of extensive, super-scientific explanations of things (M. Warnock, Should the deeper sense of the idea of equality, 1990, p. 105)—that, in other words, individuals can be on which human rights is based, demand that we treated according to their alleged place within grand gen- provide for the interests and needs of humans eral worldviews built to explain the universe. While in but allow discrimination against the interests and pre-modern philosophy metaphysics predominated over needs of nonhuman beings? Wouldn’t it be ethics, and ethics was based on values which were deter- strange if the same idea contains the claim for mined by particular conceptions of Being, starting at equality and the permission for discrimination least from Henry Sidgwick (1981, B. I, Chapter 3, B. IV, too? (Anstötz, 1993, p. 169) Conclusion) a consensus slowly emerged that in ethics We live in egalitarian times.
    [Show full text]
  • Born Free and Equal? on the Ethical Consistency of Animal Equality
    Born free and equal? On the ethical consistency of animal equality Stijn Bruers Proefschrift voorgelegd tot het bekomen van de graad van Doctor in de Moraalwetenschappen Promotor: Prof. dr. Johan Braeckman Promotor Prof. dr. Johan Braeckman Vakgroep Wijsbegeerte en Moraalwetenschap Decaan Prof. dr. Marc Boone Rector Prof. dr. Anne De Paepe Nederlandse vertaling: Vrij en gelijk geboren? Over ethische consistentie en dierenrechten Faculteit Letteren & Wijsbegeerte Stijn Bruers Born free and equal? On the ethical consistency of animal equality Proefschrift voorgelegd tot het behalen van de graad van Doctor in de moraalwetenschappen 2014 Acknowledgements First of all, I would like to thank my supervisor Prof. Dr. Johan Braeckman. He allowed me to explore many new paths in ethics and philosophy and he took time to guide me through the research. His assistance and advice were precious. Second, I owe gratitude to Prof. Dr. Tom Claes and Tim De Smet for comments and Dianne Scatrine and Scott Bell for proofreading. Thanks to Gitte for helping me with the lay-out and cover. Thanks to the University of Ghent for giving opportunities, knowledge and assistance. From all philosophers I know, perhaps Floris van den Berg has ethical ideas closest to mine. I enjoyed our collaboration and meetings with him. Also the many discussions with animal rights activists of Bite Back, with the participants at the International Animal Rights Conferences and Gatherings and with the many meat eaters I encountered during the years allowed me to refine my theories. Furthermore, I am grateful to anonymous reviewers for some useful comments on my research papers.
    [Show full text]
  • It Has Been Over Thirty Years Since Peter Singer Introduced
    kari weil A Report on the Animal Turn It has been over thirty years since Peter Singer introduced the term speciesism into philosophical parlance and wrote eloquently against a form of discrimination that went largely unnoticed both inside and outside academia. But while Singer has had enormous influence over the years in the area of animal rights, his effort to put the discrimination against non- human species on par with the prejudicial treatment and injustices caused by sexism or racism has had less success; the fight against speciesism has not had the same force in the academy, perhaps until now. In the past few years there has been an explosion of conferences, books, and discussion networks around the question of the animal. On the online discussion network H-Net Animal, a lively and heated discussion took place on the questions of what animal studies is, whether it is already or should become a new discipline, and if so, whether it should model itself on women’s stud- ies or ethnic studies. Such questions are both pertinent and misconceived. Women’s studies and ethnic studies programs demanded that the academy acknowledge and address the underrepresentation and misrepresentation of groups of people under the forces of sexism and racism. This redress was Volume 21, Number 2 doi 10.1215/10407391-2010-001 © 2010 by Brown University and differences: A Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies Downloaded from http://read.dukeupress.edu/differences/article-pdf/21/2/1/374367/diff212_01Weil.pdf by guest on 24 September 2021 2 A Report on the Animal Turn to be done not only by focusing on gaps and misrepresentations but also, and more important, by bringing the voices of women and minorities into the academy to write and represent themselves.
    [Show full text]
  • Abstract the Wrongness of Killing
    Copyright Rainer Ebert May 2016 Abstract The Wrongness of Killing by Rainer Ebert There are few moral convictions that enjoy the same intuitive plausibility and level of acceptance both within and across nations, cultures, and traditions as the conviction that, normally, it is morally wrong to kill people. Attempts to provide a philosophical explanation of why that is so broadly fall into three groups: Consequentialists argue that killing is morally wrong, when it is wrong, because of the harm it inflicts on society in general, or the victim in particular, whereas personhood and human dignity accounts see the wrongness of killing people in its typically involving a failure to show due respect for the victim and his or her intrinsic moral worth. I argue that none of these attempts to explain the wrongness of killing is successful. Consequentialism generates too many moral reasons to kill, cannot account for deeply felt and widely shared intuitions about the comparative wrongness of killing, and gives the wrong kind of explanation of the wrongness of killing. Personhood and human dignity accounts each draw a line that is arbitrary and entirely unremarkable in terms of empirical reality, and hence ill-suited to carry the moral weight of the difference in moral status between the individuals below and above it. Paying close attention to the different ways in which existing accounts fail to convince, I identify a number of conditions that any plausible account of the wrongness of killing must meet. I then go on to propose an account that does. iv I suggest that the reason that typically makes killing normal human adults wrong equally applies to atypical human beings and a wide range of non-human animals, and hence challenge the idea that killing a non-human animal is normally easier to justify than killing a human being.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Purgatory: Why Some Animals Are Neither Persons Nor Property
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects CUNY Graduate Center 2-2021 Legal Purgatory: Why Some Animals are Neither Persons nor Property Sharisse Kanet The Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/4114 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] LEGAL PURGATORY: WHY SOME ANIMALS ARE NEITHER PERSONS NOR PROPERTY by Sharisse Kanet A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2021 ©2020 SHARISSE KANET ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii Legal Purgatory: Why Some Animals are Neither Persons nor Property by Sharisse Kanet This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. 09/06/2019 Steven Ross Chair of Examining Committee 09/06/2019 Nickolas Pappas Executive Officer Supervisory Committee: Steven Ross Jesse Prinz Peter Godfrey-Smith Lori Gruen THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii ABSTRACT Legal Purgatory: Why Some Animals are Neither Persons nor Property by Sharisse Kanet Advisor: Steven Ross All animals with non-borderline sentience are deserving of certain legal considerations independent of their use and relationship to human beings. That is, all sentient beings should have some rights. Given the current organization of the U.S.
    [Show full text]