Trials and Tribulations: Science in the Law Susan Haack University of Miami School of Law, [email protected]

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Trials and Tribulations: Science in the Law Susan Haack University of Miami School of Law, Shaack@Law.Miami.Edu University of Miami Law School University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository Articles Faculty and Deans 2003 Trials and Tribulations: Science in the Law Susan Haack University of Miami School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.miami.edu/fac_articles Part of the Evidence Commons, and the Law and Society Commons Recommended Citation Susan Haack, Trials and Tribulations: Science in the Law, Fall Daedalus 54 (2003). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty and Deans at University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by an authorized administrator of University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Susan Haack Trials & tribulations: science in the courts “I should like to know” [asked Mr. Chi- mining factual truth, in both criminal chely] “how a coroner is to judge of evi- and civil cases, courts very often need dence if he has not had a legal training?” to call on scientists: on toxicologists and “In my opinion,” said Lydgate, “legal tool-mark examiners, epidemiologists training only makes a man more incompe- and engineers, serologists and psychia- tent in questions that require knowledge trists, experts on pcbs and experts on of another kind. People talk about evi- paternity, experts on rape trauma syn- dence as if it could really be weighed in drome and experts on respiratory disor- scales by a blind Justice. No man can judge ders, experts on blood, on bugs, on bul- what is good evidence on any particular lets, on battered women, etc. For, as sci- subject unless he knows that subject well. ence has grown, so too has the legal A lawyer is no better than an old woman system’s dependence on scienti½c evi- at a post-mortem examination. How is he dence; it has been estimated that by 1990 to know the action of a poison? You might around 70 percent of cases in the United as well say that scanning verse will teach States involved expert testimony, most you to scan the potato crops.” of it scienti½c. Such testimony can be a powerful tool for justice; but it can also –George Eliot, Middlemarch (1872) be a powerful source of confusion–not to mention opportunities for oppor- Justice requires just laws, of course, and tunism. just administration of those laws; but it Who could have imagined, when dna also requires factual truth. And in deter- was ½rst identi½ed as the genetic materi- al half a century ago, that dna analysis Susan Haack is Cooper Senior Scholar in Arts and would by now have come to play so large Sciences, professor of philosophy, and professor of a role in the criminal justice system, and law at the University of Miami. Internationally in the public perception of the law? known for her work in philosophy of logic, episte- Even twenty years ago, forensic scien- mology, pragmatism, philosophy of science, and tists could tell only whether a blood the law of scienti½c testimony, Haack is the author sample was animal or human, male or of several books, most recently “Manifesto of a female, and, if human, of what type (the Passionate Moderate” (1998) and “Defending least common blood type being found in Science–Within Reason: Between Scientism and 3 percent, and the commonest in 43 per- Cynicism” (2003). cent, of the U.S. population). Then, in the mid-1980s, dna ‘½ngerprinting’ © 2003 by Susan Haack made vastly more accurate identi½cation 54 Dædalus Fall 2003 possible, to probabilities of the order of on the reliability of memory, perception, Science in a billion to one; and by now new tech- and eyewitness testimony, that less the courts niques have made it possible to amplify than half a century later psychological and test the tiniest samples. evidence would play a signi½cant role At ½rst, such evidence was strenuously in such landmark constitutional cases contested in court; but as its solidity, as Brown v. Board of Education (1954), or and its power to enable justice, became that by now it would have come to play unmistakable, the ‘dna wars’ gradually so large a role in the criminal justice sys- died down. By the spring of 2002, dna tem–or that it would be the focus of testing had exonerated more than a hun- seemingly endless controversy? For dred prisoners, including a signi½cant while the work of experimental psy- number on death row, and helped con- chologists on eyewitnesses, memory, vict numerous rapists and murderers. In etc., has indeed proved useful, clinical at least one instance, it both exonerated psychologists’ and psychiatrists’ diag- and convicted the same person: after noses of this syndrome and that, and es- serving nearly eleven years of a twenty- pecially their theories about the repres- ½ve-to-½fty-year sentence for rape, Kerry sion and recovery of traumatic memo- Kotler was released in 1992 when newly ries, have been the subject of heated bat- conducted dna tests established his in- tles in the courtroom, in the press, and nocence; less than three years after his in the academy. release, he was charged with another In the mid-1980s, testimony of alleg- rape, and this time convicted on the ba- edly repressed and recovered mem- sis of dna analysis identifying him as ories came to public attention in the the perpetrator. McMartin Preschool case–the longest Even so, dna evidence can present U.S. criminal trial ever (six years), and problems of its own: police of½cers and one of the most expensive (around $15 forensic technicians make mistakes– million). But in 1990 the seven defen- and have been known deliberately to fal- dants were acquitted of the ritual sexual sify or misrepresent evidence; juries may abuse that, under the influence of thera- misconstrue the signi½cance of expert pists, numerous children at the school testimony about the probability of a ran- had claimed to remember. George dom match with the defendant, or of in- Franklin spent nearly seven years in formation about the likelihood that a prison for the murder of nine-year-old sample was mishandled–and attorneys Susan Nason, convicted on his daugh- have been known to contribute to such ter’s supposed memory of the event, misunderstandings; criminals devise recovered under hypnosis twenty years devious ways to circumvent dna iden- afterward; he was released in 1996, after ti½cation–and at least one prisoner, ap- his daughter also ‘remembered’ his com- parently hoping to exploit the potential mitting two other murders, with respect for confusion, has petitioned for a dna to one of which he could be unambigu- test that, as he must have anticipated, ously ruled out. (Franklin later sued con½rmed his guilt. prosecutors and the experts who testi- And who could have imagined, when ½ed against him for wrongful prosecu- Hugo Münsterberg urged in his On the tion and violation of his civil rights.) By Witness Stand: Essays on Psychology and the late 1990s, it began to seem that crit- Crime (1908) that the law avail itself of ics such as experimental psychologist the work of experimental psychologists Elizabeth Loftus, who had maintained Dædalus Fall 2003 55 Susan all along that supposedly repressed and atric and clinical testimony, experimen- Haack on recovered ‘memories’ could be the result tal psychologist Margaret Hagen writes science of therapists’ suggestive questioning, of “charlatans and greedy frauds.” were vindicated. But recently the ‘mem- But other scientists–like Eliot’s Dr. ory wars’ have flared up all over again, Lydgate–think the real problem is, rath- this time in legal claims ½led against er, that jurors, attorneys, and judges are Catholic priests accused of sexual abuse too illiterate scienti½cally to discrimi- of children and young people. nate sound science from charlatanism. Norman Levitt, for example, comment- Why has the legal system found scien- ing in Prometheus Bedeviled (1999) on the ti½c testimony hard to handle? Ever “noisome travesty” of the O. J. Simpson since there have been scienti½c witness- trial, complains that “the basic princi- es, lawyers and legal scholars–like ples of statistical inference were opaque Eliot’s Mr. Chichely–have had their to all concerned except the witnesses doubts about them. The commonest themselves. The lawyers . , the judge, complaint has been that venal scientists the dozens of commentators . , and brought in by unscrupulous attorneys certainly the woozy public–all seemed will testify to just about anything a case utterly ignorant as to what . statistical demands. In 1858, the Supreme Court independence might mean . All the observed that “experience has shown other scienti½c issues encountered the that the opposite opinions of persons same combination of neglect and eva- professing to be experts may be ob- sion.” tained in any amount”; in 1874, John Or- There surely are venal and incompe- dronaux wrote in the American Journal of tent scienti½c witnesses, and there surely Insanity that “If Science, for a consider- are scienti½cally ignorant and credulous ation, can be induced to prove anything jurors, attorneys, and judges; but the fa- which a litigant needs in order to sustain miliar complaints gloss over many com- his side of an issue, then Science is fairly plexities. Scienti½c testimony may be open to the charge of venality and per- flawed by outright fraud, or, more often, jury, rendered the more base by the dis- by the overemphatic presentation of guise of natural truth in which she robes scanty or weak evidence; it may be solid herself.” More than a century later, in science misapplied by a poorly run labo- Galileo’s Revenge (1991), Peter Huber was ratory, or serious but highly speculative sounding a similar theme: junk science and controversial science, or sloppily –“data dredging, wishful thinking, truc- conducted scienti½c work, or pseudo- ulent dogmatism, and, now and again, scienti½c mumbo jumbo.
Recommended publications
  • Susan Haack SERIOUS PHILOSOPHY1
    Susan Haack SERIOUS PHILOSOPHY1 Abstract What is serious philosophy? What does it demand of us? And is it true, as some suppose, that a philosopher can’t be serious about his work unless he is solemn and humorless? Calling on ideas from C.S. Peirce, Haack argues first that philosophy is a serious form of inquiry, requiring real commitment and real intellectual effort, and then that playfulness and humor may actually be of help in such inquiry, while solemnity and self-importance will, for sure, impede it .“The serious philosopher,” she concludes “must indeed work in earnest – but not in grim earnest.” “… the spirit … is the most essential thing – the motive…” (C.S. Peirce)2 At dinner the night before I was to give a talk in her department, a young professor solemnly told me that there’s no place for humor in serious philosophy. Since the paper on the relation of science and literature I was to present the next day was full of playful literary allusions and verbal jokes this was, to say the least, an awkward moment.3 Nonetheless, my paper was a serious piece of work – jokes and all. Now, thanks to Spazio filosofico’s imaginative choice of theme, at last I have my opportunity to explore what’s wrong with the idea that, to be serious, philosophical work must be humorless. It’s been a long time coming; but, as the saying goes, better late than never. “Serious,” of course, has a whole raft of uses, and many subtly-interrelated meanings. We laugh about the apocryphal billionaire who complains that household expenses are skyrocketing – “a million here, a million there, and pretty soon you’re talking serious money”; meaning real money, a significant sum of money.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientism and Its Discontents Susan Haack
    SCIENTISM AND ITS DISCONTENTS SUSAN HAACK University College, Dublin, September 2016 2 PART II: SCIENTISTIC PHILOSOPHY, NO; SCIENTFIC PHILOSOPHY, YES 3 “The kind of philosophy that interests me and must, I think, interest everybody, is that philosophy which uses the most rational methods it can devise, for finding out the little that can as yet be found out about the universe of mind and matter from those observations which every person can make in every hour of his waking life. It will not include matters which are more conveniently studied by students of special sciences such as psychology…” 4 “It is true that philosophy is in a lamentably crude condition at present; that very little is really established about it; while most philosophers set up a pretension of knowing all there is to know---a pretension calculated to disgust anybody who is at home in any real science. But all we have to do is turn our backs upon all such vicious conduct, and we shall find ourselves enjoying the advantages of having an almost virgin soil to till…”---C. S. Peirce, “Scientific Philosophy,” c.1905 5 Peirce urged that philosophy be undertaken in the same spirit as the best work of the sciences, and that it should rely on experience as well as reason---though not recondite experience 6 today’s cultural landscape is very different • & philosophy today very different than in Peirce’s day • it is no longer dominated by theologians (given to “sham reasoning” according to Peirce) • & by now the threat from “lawless rovers of the sea of literature” is receding
    [Show full text]
  • Susan Haack: Putting Philosophy to Work. Inquiry and Its Place in Culture
    Susan Haack: Putting Philosophy to Work. Inquiry and Its Place in Culture. Essays on Science, Religion, Law, Literature, and Life, Expanded Edition, New York, Prometheus Books, 2013 Reviewed by Teodor Dima In the preface to the expanded edition of the volume reviewed here, Susan Haack, Distinguished Professor in the Humanities, Cooper Senior Scholar in Arts and Sciences, professor of philosophy, and professor of law at the University of Miami, explains its genesis as follows: “... after the publication of my Evidence and Inquiry (1993), Manifesto of a Passionate Moderate (1998), and Defending Science— Within Reason (2003), I received such a variety of intriguing invitations – from people in the natural, the medieval, and the social sciences, from scholars in literature and scholars in law, from humanists and theologians, even from professors of architecture and the editors of an avant-garde art magazine – asking me to write or speak about the bearing of my work on their concerns” (p. 12). At the same time, these invitations were challenges to new research topics and answers regarding the epistemological significance of several concepts always debated in specialized literature: “truth; evidence; fact; objectivity; bias; self- deception; reason and the emotions; the demands of rationality and the limits of formalism; the ways in which unbiased inquiry differs from advocacy research, and inquiry in the sciences from inquiry in other fields; the threats to the integrity of the scientific enterprise posed by pressures from political and commercial interests; the difficulties our legal system has had in handling the scientific (and quasi-scientific) testimony so often crucial to the reduction of key factual issues; the tensions between science and religion; the possibility of learning true things from works of fiction; and even what gives human lives meaning” (p.
    [Show full text]
  • Evidence Matters
    Book Reviews EVIDENCE MATTERS: SCIENCE, we later seek to gather more facts and clarity I’ll mention just one of the many hotly PROOF, AND TRUTH on the subject, this 90 percent figure serves contested issues at the trial. Two police IN THE LAW as our “prior.” officers testified that they saw Sacco put BY SUSAN HAACK Now, in this population (P), bike owner- his hand under his coat when they arrived Cambridge University Press, New York, NY, 2014. ship is much less prevalent than automobile to arrest him. They interpreted this gesture 432 pages, $34.99. ownership. We will say that among those in as his effort to draw his revolver. The pros- P who own an automobile, 10 percent also ecution suggested to the jury that this was Reviewed by Christopher C. Faille own a bike. Among those in P who don’t own evidence of consciousness of guilt. an automobile, 20 percent own a bike. These Let’s fast forward to the 1990s. Joseph B. Susan Haack, an Englishwoman who figures, in decimal form, .10 or .20, are “con- Kadane and David A. Schum, two prominent studied philosophy at both Oxford and ditional” probabilities. We do some checking academic statisticians with Bayesian philo- Cambridge, and who now teaches it at the and learn something new about Jones. He sophical inclinations, wrote A Probabilistic University of Miami, has produced this book owns a bike. Analysis of the Sacco and Vanzetti on the philosophy of law or, more strictly, Can we say anything more about the Evidence. In the book, Kadane and Schum on the philosophy behind the tasks that law probability that Jones owns a car, using both don‘t seek to resolve the case, but they do assigns to its finders of fact.
    [Show full text]
  • Science As Social? - Yes and No'
    SUSAN HAACK SCIENCE AS SOCIAL? - YES AND NO' Ours is an age in which partial truths are tirelessly transformed into total falsehoods and then acclaimed as revolutionary revelations [Thomas Szasz j.2 INTRODUCTION Some feminist philosophers of science claim the insight that science is social. It is true that the co-operative and competitive engagement of many people, within and across generations, in the enterprise of scientific inquiry, contributes to its success. It is false that social values are inseparable from scientific inquiry; false that the purpose of science is the achievement of social goals; false that knowledge is nothing but the product of negotiation among members of the scientific com­ munity; false that knowledge, facts, reality are nothing more than social con­ structions; false that science should be more democratic; false that the physical sciences are subordinate to the social sciences. I shall first offer an account of what is epistemologically distinctive about scientific inquiry in which the proposition that science is social, in its true inter­ pretation, plays a significant part. Next, I shall argue that in its other interpretations - the inevitability or desirability of politicized inquiry, social constructivism, "de­ mocratic epistemology," and the rest - the proposition that science is social is false. And then, turning to the question, what, if anything, all this has to do with femi­ nism, I shall argue that "science as social" is either a genuine insight, but not a feminist one, or else is no insight at all; and, in conclusion, that feminism has taken a wrong direction in pursuing the project of a feminist epistemology of science - a project that is neither sound epistemology nor sound feminism.
    [Show full text]
  • Proteus Rebound Reconsidering the “Torture of Nature” Author(S): Peter Pesic Source: Isis, Vol
    Proteus Rebound Reconsidering the “Torture of Nature” Author(s): Peter Pesic Source: Isis, Vol. 99, No. 2 (June 2008), pp. 304-317 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of The History of Science Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/588627 Accessed: 24-03-2018 04:29 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms The History of Science Society, The University of Chicago Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Isis This content downloaded from 142.58.129.109 on Sat, 24 Mar 2018 04:29:39 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms CRITIQUES AND CONTENTIONS Proteus Rebound Reconsidering the “Torture of Nature” By Peter Pesic* ABSTRACT Though Carolyn Merchant has agreed that Francis Bacon did not advocate the “torture of nature,” she still maintains that “the very essence of the experimental method arose out of human torture transferred onto nature.” Her arguments do not address serious problems of logic, context, and contrary evidence. Her particular insistence on the influence of the torture of witches ignores Bacon’s skepticism about witchcraft as superstitious or imag- inary.
    [Show full text]
  • Rafts, Boats, and Cruise Ships Verhaegh, Sander
    University of Groningen Rafts, Boats, and Cruise Ships Verhaegh, Sander IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from it. Please check the document version below. Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Publication date: 2015 Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database Citation for published version (APA): Verhaegh, S. (2015). Rafts, Boats, and Cruise Ships: Naturalism and holism in Quine’s philosophy. University of Groningen. Copyright Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). The publication may also be distributed here under the terms of Article 25fa of the Dutch Copyright Act, indicated by the “Taverne” license. More information can be found on the University of Groningen website: https://www.rug.nl/library/open-access/self-archiving-pure/taverne- amendment. Take-down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum. Download date: 02-10-2021 RAFTS, BOATS, AND CRUISE SHIPS Naturalism and Holism in Quine’s Philosophy SANDER VERHAEGH RAFTS,BOATS,ANDCRUISESHIPS © Sander Verhaegh, Groningen, 2015 Cover design: Anne Jansen.
    [Show full text]
  • Foundherentism: Basic Concepts and Distinctions 1
    Philosophy 3340 - Epistemology Susan Haack's Foundherentist Theory of Empirical Justification 1. Foundherentism: Basic Concepts and Distinctions 1. S-beliefs versus C-beliefs: "A's S-belief that p": A mental state of A's that is A's believing that p. "A's C-belief that p": The content of A's S-belief that P - namely, the proposition that p. 2. Evidence for p can be divided into S-evidence and C-evidence: A's S-evidence with respect to p consists of the "set of states of A causally related to his S-belief that p." A's C-evidence with respect to p consists of "a set of propositions capable of standing in logical or quasi-logical relations to the C-belief that p." 3. Not just any type of state can be part of a person's S-evidence: "'A's S-evidence with respect to p' will refer to those experiential and belief-states of A's which belong, at the time in question, to the causal nexus of A's S-belief that p." (421) 4. Haack divides S-evidence with respect to p up into two components: (1) A's S-reasons with respect to p is that part of A's S-evidence with respect to p that consists of other beliefs. (2) A's experiential S-evidence with respect to p is that part of A's S-evidence with respect to p that consists of A's "perceptions, his introspective awareness of his own mental goings-on, and memory traces of his earlier perceptual and introspective states." (421) 5.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of P. F. Strawson, with Replies 23
    TABLE OF CONTENTS FRONTISPIECE IV GENERAL INTRODUCTION TO THE LIBRARY OF LIVING PHILOSOPHERS Vll FOUNDER'S GENERAL INTRODUCTION TO THE LIBRARY OF LIVING PHILOSOPHERS IX ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Xll PREFACE XV PART ONE: INTELLECTUAL AUTOBIOGRAPHY OF P.F. STRAWSON 1 FACSIMILE OF STRAWSON'S HANDWRITING 2 INTELLECTUAL AUTOBIOGRAPHY OF P. F. STRAWSON 3 PART TWO: DESCRIPTIVE AND CRITICAL ESSAYS ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF P. F. STRAWSON, WITH REPLIES 23 1. RUTH GARRETT MILLIKAN: Proper Function and Convention in Speech Acts 25 REPLY TO RUTH GARRETT MILLIKAN 44 2. SUSAN HAACK: Between the Scylla of Scientism and the Charybdis of Apriorism 49 REPLY TO SUSAN HAACK 64 3. E. M. ADAMS: On the Possibility of a Unified World View 69 REPLY TO E. M. ADAMS 86 4. PAN AYOT BUTCHVAROV: The Relativity of Reallys 91 REPLY TO PAN AYOT BUTCHVAROV 106 XIV TABLE OF CONTENTS 5. RICHARD BEHLING: Two Kinds of Logic? III REPLY TO RICHARD BEHLING 127 6. JOHN McDoWELL: Referring to Oneself 129 REPLY TO JOHN McDoWELL 146 7. SIMON BLACKBURN: Relativization and Truth 151 REPLY TO SIMON BLACKBURN 168 8. T ADEUSZ SZUBKA: Strawson and Antirealism 175 REPLY TO T ADEUSZ SZUBKA 192 9. DAVID FREDERICK HAIGHT: Reference and Reality 199 REPLY TO DAVID FREDERICK HAIGHT 214 10. JOSEPH S. Wu: P. F. Strawson's Criticism of Formal Logic 217 REPLY TO JOSEPH S. Wu 224 11. ANDREW G. BLACK: Naturalism and Cartesian Skepticism 227 REPLY TO ANDREW G. BLACK 242 12. DA VID PEARS: Strawson on Freedom and Resentment 245 REPLY TO DAVID PEARS 259 13. ROBERT BOYD: Strawson on Induction 263 REPLY TO ROBERT BOYD 272 14.
    [Show full text]
  • CEFP FINAL Susan Haack Sun Yong Interview 7 5 2010 Version 2
    1 PRAGMATISM, THEN AND NOW: 1 Sun Yong 2 Interviews Susan Haack 3 SY: Professor Haack, thank you for accepting my interview request. You are well known in philosophy circles in China, not only for your books Philosophy of Logics 4 and Evidence and Inquiry 5 but also for your research on pragmatism and your anthology Meaning and Action: Selected Writings on Pragmatism Old and New. 6 It is six years since Professor Chen Bo interviewed you in World Philosophy ;7 and I’m hoping that in this interview I can learn more about your views both on the classical pragmatist tradition and on pragmatism today. SH: I’m happy to talk with you, and grateful for the opportunity to clarify some issues for Chinese readers. May I suggest that we begin with the classical pragmatist tradition, and then move on, through developments in pragmatism and neo-pragmatism during the twentieth century, to the present and even prospects for the future? SY: Yes, let me begin, as you suggest, by asking you to clarify some issues about the history of pragmatism. In his Contemporary Theories of Knowledge 8 (a book which has had considerable influence in China), Thomas English Hill tell us that Peirce declined the 1 © 2010 Sun Yong/Susan Haack. All rights reserved. This interview has been presented (by Prof. Haack) at the Peirce Edition Project, Indianapolis University/Purdue University; the LOGOS Group, Universitat de Barcelona, Spain; and the meeting of the Central European Pragmatist Forum held at Comenius University, Bratislava, Slovak Republic. 2 Professor of Philosophy, Shanghai Financial University, P.R.
    [Show full text]
  • LW&CSP Scholarship
    To appear in I. Angelelli y M. Cerezo, eds., Studies on the History of Logic. Proceedings of the III Symposium on History of Logic, Gruyter, Berlin, 1996, 281-294. SCHOLARSHIP ON THE RELATIONS BETWEEN LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN AND CHARLES S. PEIRCE* Jaime NUBIOLA University of Navarra, Spain It is now over thirty years since Richard Rorty pointed out the similarities between Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations (1953) and the philosophical framework of Charles S. Peirce (1839-1914), the American logician who was the founder of pragmatism. The view put forward by Rorty is that Peirce had envisaged and repudiated positivist empiricism fifty years earlier, and had developed a set of insights and a philosophical mood very similar to those of contemporary philosophers working under the influence of the later Wittgenstein. The affinity between Peirce's philosophy and the more recent tendency born of the rejection of the Tractatus and the positivism of the Vienna Circle, gave rise to an expectation that the study of Peircean pragmatism and the writings of the later Wittgenstein in ever closer comparison would shed increasing light on both philosophers' work (Rorty 1961). Similarly, on a more recent occasion Christopher Hookway emphasised that the best approach for understanding Peirce is to see him as an analytic philosopher avant la lettre. It is well known that Karl-Otto Apel identified Peirce's thought as the milestone in the process of semiotic transformation from transcendental philosophy into analytic philosophy (Apel 1981). Many of the distinctive features of analytic philosophy are already present in Peirce, and many of the problems which concerned Peirce most are central to contemporary philosophical debate.
    [Show full text]
  • Six Signs of Scientism: Part 1 “Scientism” Refers to a Too Uncritically Deferential Attitude Toward Science
    Six Signs of Scientism: Part 1 “Scientism” refers to a too uncritically deferential attitude toward science. In this first part of her two-part article, Professor Haack identifies the first three of six signs of scientism: using words like “science,” “scientific,” etc., honorifically; adopting scientific trappings purely decoratively; and preoccupation with the “problem of demarcation.” SUSAN HAACK A man must be downright crazy to deny that science has made to avoid both underestimating the value many true discoveries. of science and overestimating it. What —C.S. Peirce (1903)1 I meant by “cynicism” in this context was a kind of jaundiced and uncriti- Scientism . employs the prestige of science for disguise and cally critical attitude toward science, an protection. 2 inability to see or an unwillingness to —A.H. Hobbs (1953) acknowledge its remarkable intellectual achievements, or to recognize the real cience is a good thing. As Francis Bacon foresaw cen- benefits it has made possible. What I turies ago, when what we now call “modern science” meant by “scientism” was the opposite was in its infancy, the work of the sciences has brought failure: a kind of over-enthusiastic and S uncritically deferential attitude toward both light, an ever-growing body of knowledge of the world science, an inability to see or an unwill- and how it works, and fruit, the ability to predict and control ingness to acknowledge its fallibility, its limitations, and its potential dangers. the world in ways that have both extended and improved One side too hastily dismisses science; our lives. But, as William Harvey complained, Bacon really the other too hastily defers to it.
    [Show full text]