Epigenetics , Paleontology, and Evolution Abstract

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Epigenetics , Paleontology, and Evolution Abstract EPIGENETICS , PALEONTOLOGY, ANDEVOLUTI ON S tan P . Ra cho o t i n and Kei t h S t e war t Thoms on Pe abo dy Museum of Na tura l Hi s t ory , Yale University , New Hav en , Connecticut 0 6511 , U. S .A . ABSTRACT 'Three requirements of evolution are persistence with chang e, internally cohes ive individua l s of limit ed dura t ion, and interaction with environment. We recast th es e proper t i es in megaevolutionary terms. Harologous structures persist over geological t ime as they evo lve in form and funct ion. Spec ies, which arise through a greater or lesser genetic r evolution, behave as individuals. The interact ion of genes and envi­ ronments- -development- -under lies both the origin of species and the continuity of haro­ logies. The properties of epigenetics- -self assemb ly, feedback, alternative pathways to the sane devel opmental end, canpensati on for the inevitable irregularities of devel­ opment--allow a redefinition of genet ic revolution in terms of the establishment of new, stable developmental patterns : a typological r esult produced in ac ceptably popu­ l ati ona l ways . Harologues, s imi larly, are the products of evo lving epigenetic sub-sys­ tems. Al though developmental systems retain ancestral potentials that renain unex ­ pressed for tens of millions of years, such potentials are so burdened with other devel­ opmental pathways built upon them that they hold little promise for evolutionary change. But where a recent developmental change has occurred, no such "buf fering" exists . As errors occur, sane will be ep igenetically acconm:>dated and , if adaptive, genet i cally assimilated. These are the quanta of evolution. If a r ecent adaptive breakthrough has occurred, i t wi ll be "suppor t ed" at first by interacting ep igenetic sub-systems. The poorly canalized epigenetic system roost; closely associated with the new adaptation will be under intense selection to build up an epigenetic environment that assures the pre­ dictable expression of the new trait. Until this happens, further "exper iments" along the l ines of t he initial change can occur and be assimilated. Depend ing on eco logical milieu, t his i s the stuff of adaptive r adiation , evo l ut i onary trends, or allanetri c change. Speciation, which can occur without any adaptive change, is th e result of anal­ ogous changes in the epigenetic systems responsible for mate r ecognition . We accept the neo-Darwinian reliance on natural selection acting in populations. But we choose to concentrate on i ts action on developmental processes, rather than on traits , the obvious and experimentally tractable end -products of such processes. The normal features of epi­ genet ics fortuitousl y l ay down the lines of l ea st r esistance to evo l utionary change. We find ourselves l ooking a t an intrinsic and emergent s i de to evolution, a view that in the past was held, on similar gener al grounds, by Bateson, Goldschnidt, and Waddington . The story of evolution i s perhaps less the warfare of selfish genes than the YX>rking out of the potentials of selfless epigenes. I NTRODUCTION bution i s seen as a na tural offshoot from the syn thet ic stock. But though the syn­ The title of our paper, "Epi genetics, thetic theory has provided many answers , Paleontology, and Evolution", i s de liber­ i t has not adequately framed a l l the ques­ ately chosen to r eca ll the title of the tions. llich renains to be explained, es­ conference that was held at Princeton Univ ­ pecially when we take the long paleontolo­ ersi ty in 1947 on "Genetics , Paleontology, gical per sp ective . The answers to these and Evol ut i on" (Jepsen et al . 1949). I t questions are, we think, t o be found in a included not only th e subjects of gene tics , considera t i on of the evolutionary implica­ speciation, and paleontology, but canpara­ t ions of development and the developmental tive anatany, ecology, and systematics as impl i cations of evo l ution, topics that were well. The synthetic theory that came of notably l acking in the 1947 conference . age with that symposium ha s been the nota­ ble success of organ isrnal biology of thi.s Our goa l in t his paper i s to set in a century. In a day when theories in o ther developmental con text the problems of mega­ parts of biology change wi th the seasons, evo lution: the nature of adaptation, the it i s astonishing to f ind that 33 years tempos and nodes of evol ution, the framing later the study of evolution is no l es s of us eful general izati ons about the origin vigorous for having r emained in the sane and diversification of major groups . As node . We =uld be pleased if our contri - we go about this , we find ourselves r ein- G.G . E. Sc udd er & J . L. Rev e a l (eds .) I EVOLUTION TODAY, Proce edings of t he Second Inter ­ na tio na l Congress o f Systematic a nd Evoluti onary Bi olo g y, pp . 18 1- 19 3 . 19 81 . 182 EVOLUTION TODAY Rachootin & Thomson terpreting sane of the ftmdarnental con­ "Intrinsi c" and "extrinsi c" bear close cepts of evolut ion, including variation, relation to the distinction that Mayr has spec ies, and what i t i s that selection drawn between typological and population­ acts upon . These reinterpretations cane al thinking . Throughout the paper, we out of a series of generally accepted will be contrasting a populational, or , premises about development , which, how­ rrore generally, an extrinsic approach ever, have unexpected impl ications when with a complementary intrinsic approach viewed over the time scale familiar to the that is developmental and typological. paleontologist. Our paper is an outline Note that both approaches are ways of of a way of ret:hinking what everyone knows t:hinking, not hypotheses about nature. about evolution. We ask you to rearrange The mind has a hard time holding = com­ your mental furniture and consider sane pletely different views of the worId si­ changes that we think are suitable for mul taneously, but it is our guess that sane circurnstances .Al though the rear­ having two ways and switching when i t rangement is new, the pieces are not. seems appropriate i s better than having Those that look unfamiliar we have only one way that we always be lieve to be right, brought down from the attic. and another, which we seem to fall into, but which we have decided is always wrong. In the broadest terms. we ask what me­ ga -evolution ought to require of theories Development is studied in a typological at the level of genetics and development, m:xIe. Development shows directedness; in and also at the level of speciation. We an experimental manipulation, the embryo expect that nothing at the l evel of mega­ " tri es" , if you will, to develop normally, evolution contradicts what happens at according to type, in spite of the insult. these l ower levels, but that we will not Results in a devel opment al experiment turn fully understand these l ower l evel s un til on the behaviour of particular, crucial we actively search them for phenCID2I1a that embryos. This is a far cry from popula­ may seem peripheral to the population bio­ tion thinking. The dichotomy is apparent logist, but which are required to explain in the 1947 symposium, which neglected de­ the data of the paleontologist and the velopmental biology, but not because there roorphologist. We trace the emergent mega­ were no evolutionists interested in it. evolutionary phenanena down to their hid­ Indeed, embryology dominated evolutionary den roots, which we find to be developmen­ studies in the last century, and was the tal, and then ask what this mega-evolution­ guiding light to such twentieth century ary view of development suggests about the vorkers as William Bateson, Richard Gold ­ nature of species and speciation. schmidt, and C. H. Waddington. The prob­ lem was that the typological and the pop­ We also ask you to allow us to break one t l at i ona l could not be fused into a sin­ other convention of evolutionary theory, gle approach. How, for instance, could concerning intrinsic and extrinsic factors Goldschmidt's macro-evolution, which took in evolution. Extrinsic factors are the developmental saltations as the means of relations of an organism to the external getting from one major group to another, environnent- -adaptations to local condi­ be reconciled with the gradual, popula­ tions, the sorting-out of congeners in tional approach that was then being fash­ sympatry by character displacement, and ioned, an approach that accounted for me­ such chance effects as the genetic sample ga -evolution by an aCCl.IIllllation of micro~ borne by the traditional gravid female com­ evo lutionary events? The r esolution on pared to the population from which she de­ the part of those who formulated and pop­ rives, or the effect of a river changing ularized the synthetic view--Mayr, Dob­ its course and cutting off a population. zhansky, Simpson, Stebbins--was to take We accept such extrinsic factors as the population t:hinking as right, true, and carrron property of all m:xIem evolution­ rrodern, and typological thinking as wrong, ists. But although we all believe in such false and old-fashioned. A sympathet i c factors, they are remarkably difficult to treatment of evolutionary development was demonstrate in anyone case.
Recommended publications
  • Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B
    Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B. M ü ller, G ü nter P. Wagner, and Werner Callebaut, editors The Evolution of Cognition , edited by Cecilia Heyes and Ludwig Huber, 2000 Origination of Organismal Form: Beyond the Gene in Development and Evolutionary Biology , edited by Gerd B. M ü ller and Stuart A. Newman, 2003 Environment, Development, and Evolution: Toward a Synthesis , edited by Brian K. Hall, Roy D. Pearson, and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2004 Evolution of Communication Systems: A Comparative Approach , edited by D. Kimbrough Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2004 Modularity: Understanding the Development and Evolution of Natural Complex Systems , edited by Werner Callebaut and Diego Rasskin-Gutman, 2005 Compositional Evolution: The Impact of Sex, Symbiosis, and Modularity on the Gradualist Framework of Evolution , by Richard A. Watson, 2006 Biological Emergences: Evolution by Natural Experiment , by Robert G. B. Reid, 2007 Modeling Biology: Structure, Behaviors, Evolution , edited by Manfred D. Laubichler and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2007 Evolution of Communicative Flexibility: Complexity, Creativity, and Adaptability in Human and Animal Communication , edited by Kimbrough D. Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2008 Functions in Biological and Artifi cial Worlds: Comparative Philosophical Perspectives , edited by Ulrich Krohs and Peter Kroes, 2009 Cognitive Biology: Evolutionary and Developmental Perspectives on Mind, Brain, and Behavior , edited by Luca Tommasi, Mary A. Peterson, and Lynn Nadel, 2009 Innovation in Cultural Systems: Contributions from Evolutionary Anthropology , edited by Michael J. O ’ Brien and Stephen J. Shennan, 2010 The Major Transitions in Evolution Revisited , edited by Brett Calcott and Kim Sterelny, 2011 Transformations of Lamarckism: From Subtle Fluids to Molecular Biology , edited by Snait B.
    [Show full text]
  • Richard Goldschmidt and the Crossing-Over Controversy Michael Dietrich Dartmouth College
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Dartmouth Digital Commons (Dartmouth College) Dartmouth College Dartmouth Digital Commons Dartmouth Faculty Open Access Articles Open Dartmouth: Faculty Open Access 1-1-2000 Richard Goldschmidt and the Crossing-Over Controversy Michael Dietrich Dartmouth College Marsha Richmond Wayne State University Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.dartmouth.edu/facoa Part of the Biology Commons Recommended Citation Dietrich, Michael and Richmond, Marsha, "Richard Goldschmidt and the Crossing-Over Controversy" (2000). Dartmouth Faculty Open Access Articles. 24. http://digitalcommons.dartmouth.edu/facoa/24 This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Open Dartmouth: Faculty Open Access at Dartmouth Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dartmouth Faculty Open Access Articles by an authorized administrator of Dartmouth Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Copyright 2002 by the Genetics Society of America Perspectives Anecdotal, Historical and Critical Commentaries on Genetics Edited by James F. Crow and William F. Dove Richard Goldschmidt and the Crossing-Over Controversy Marsha L. Richmond* and Michael R. Dietrich†,1 *Interdisciplinary Studies Program, Wayne State University, Detroit, Michigan 48202 and †Department of Biological Sciences, Dartmouth College, Hanover, New Hampshire 03755 NE of the basic tenets linking the Mendelian laws
    [Show full text]
  • Phenotypic Plasticity & Evolution
    Innovation and 9 Diversification Via Plasticity-Led Evolution Nicholas A. Levis Indiana University David W. Pfennig University of North Carolina CONTENTS 9.1 Introduction .................................................................................................. 211 9.2 Plasticity-Led Evolution: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives ......... 212 9.3 How Plasticity-Led Evolution Promotes Innovation and Diversification ..... 215 9.3.1 Plasticity-Led Evolution and Innovation .......................................... 215 9.3.2 Plasticity-Led Evolution and Diversification .................................... 218 9.4 Evaluating Plasticity-Led Evolution ............................................................. 221 9.5 Plasticity-Led Evolution: Consensus, Controversy, and Challenges ............222 9.5.1 Plasticity-Led Evolution: Where Is the Consensus? .........................223 9.5.2 Plasticity-Led Evolution: Where Is the Controversy? .......................228 9.5.3 Plasticity-Led Evolution: Where Are the Challenges? .....................229 9.6 Conclusions ................................................................................................... 231 Acknowledgments .................................................................................................. 232 References .............................................................................................................. 233 9.1 INTRODUCTION Biodiversity requires explanation. Why are there so many different kinds of living things, and where do their
    [Show full text]
  • Speciation and Macroevolution Anya Plutynski Blackwell's Companion
    Speciation and Macroevolution Anya Plutynski Blackwell’s Companion 1.0 Introduction Speciation is the process by which one or more species arises from a common ancestor, and “macroevolution” refers to patterns and processes at and above the species level – or, transitions in higher taxa, such as new families, phyla or genera. “Macroevolution” is contrasted with “microevolution,”1 evolutionary change within populations, due to migration, assortative mating, selection, mutation and drift.2 In the evolutionary synthesis of the 1930’s and 40’s, Haldane (1932), Dobzhansky (1937), Mayr (1942), and Simpson (1944) argued that the origin of species and higher taxa were, given the right environmental conditions and sufficient time, the product of the same microevolutionary factors yielding change within populations. Dobzhansky reviewed the evidence from genetics, and argued, “nothing in the known macroevolutionary phenomena would require other than the known genetic principles for causal explanation” (Dobzhansky, 1951, 17). In sum, genetic variation between species was not different in kind from the genetic variation within species. Dobzhansky concluded that one may “reluctantly put an equal sign” between micro- and macroevolution. This view was not accepted by all, however. Richard Goldschmidt, for instance, argued that microevolution does not, by the sheer accumulation of small, adaptive 1 The terms were coined in 1927 by the Russian entomologist Iuri’i Filipchenko in Variabilität und Variation (according to Bowler 1983). 2 West-Eberhard (2005) discusses what she sees as two competing definitions of macrevolution in the literature, which has, she claims confused discussion of the issues. This essay will retain the definition of change at and above the species barrier.
    [Show full text]
  • Generating and Filtering Major Phenotypic Novelties: Neogoldschmidtian Saltation Revisited
    Chapter 7 Generating and filtering major phenotypic novelties: neoGoldschmidtian saltation revisited Richard N\. Bateman and William A. D/M/che/e ABSTRACT Further developing a controversial neoGoldschmidtian paradigm that we first pub- lished in 1994, we here narrowly define saltational evolution as a genetic modifica- tion that is expressed as a profound phenotypic change across a single generation and results in a potentially independent evolutionary lineage termed a prospecies (the 'hopeful monster' of Richard Goldschmidt). Of several saltational and parasaltational mechanisms previously discussed by us, the most directly relevant to evolutionary-developmental genetics is dichotomous saltation, which is driven by mutation within a single ancestral Uneage. It can result not only in instantaneous speciation but also in the simultaneous origin of a profound phenotypic novelty more likely to be treated as a new supraspecific taxon. Saltational events form unusually long branches on morphological phylogenies, which follow a punctuated equilibrium pattern, but at the time of origin they typically form zero length branches on the contrastingly gradualistic molecular phylogenies. Our chosen case- studies of heterotopy (including homeosis) and heterochrony in fossil seed-ferns and extant orchids indicate that vast numbers of prospecies are continuously generated by mutation of key developmental genes that control morphogenesis. First principles suggest that, although higher plant mutants are more likely to become established than higher animals, the fitness of even plant prospecies is in at least most cases too low to survive competition-mediated selection. The establishment of prospecies is most Hkely under temporary release from selection in environments of low biotic competition for resources, followed by honing to competitive fitness by gradual rein- troduction to neoDarwinian selection.
    [Show full text]
  • Richard Goldschmidt's Monster
    Countering the critics no change for millions of years, followed by the relatively Richard sudden (in conventional geological terms) appearance of new species. The leading proponents of this version of evolution (known generally as Punctuated Equilibrium) Goldschmidt’s include such notable figures as Niles Eldredge, Steven Stanley and Stephen Jay Gould.2 monster This division within the transformist (evolutionist) camp must be kept in mind as we examine the Goldschmidt case. A.W. (Bill) Mehlert Both groups insist that the fossil record supports their views and discredits the opposing party’s case. Neo-Darwinism th Fifty years ago one of the leading evolutionist has generally ruled from the early 20 century to 1972, authorities of the day, geneticist Richard when Eldredge and Gould published their important work, Goldschmidt, recognized internal inconsistencies Punctuated Equilibrium, An Alternative to Phyletic in the evolutionary paradigm, inconsistencies that Gradualism, which was based on observation of the fossil remain unresolved today. Goldschmidt put forward record. Speaking in evolutionary terms, the rocks show two major objections. Firstly, that virtually ‘all known that the new species almost always appear abruptly, and orders and families appear suddenly and without any replace previous forms. apparent transitions’ in the fossil record. Secondly, Goldschmidt’s case that the mechanism for evolution is fundamentally flawed: according to neo‑Darwinism, the evolutionary process works ‘uphill’, i.e. higher taxa (families to Despite being an ardent evolutionist himself, by 1952 phyla) are created from lower taxa (species and Goldschmidt had become increasingly disillusioned by genera) by speciation events; but based on the the failure of science to present a credible mechanism fossil record, it works ‘downhill’, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Reinventing Richard Goldschmidt: Reputation, Memory, and Biography
    Dartmouth College Dartmouth Digital Commons Dartmouth Scholarship Faculty Work 1-1-2011 Reinventing Richard Goldschmidt: Reputation, Memory, and Biography Michael Dietrich Dartmouth College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.dartmouth.edu/facoa Part of the Biology Commons Dartmouth Digital Commons Citation Dietrich, Michael, "Reinventing Richard Goldschmidt: Reputation, Memory, and Biography" (2011). Dartmouth Scholarship. 8. https://digitalcommons.dartmouth.edu/facoa/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Work at Dartmouth Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dartmouth Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Dartmouth Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Journal of the History of Biology Ó Springer 2011 DOI 10.1007/s10739-011-9271-y Reinventing Richard Goldschmidt: Reputation, Memory, and Biography MICHAEL R. DIETRICH Department of Biological Sciences Dartmouth College Hanover, NH 03755 USA E-mail: [email protected] Abstract. Richard Goldschmidt was one of the most controversial biologists of the mid-twentieth century. Rather than fade from view, Goldschmidt’s work and reputation has persisted in the biological community long after he has. Goldschmidt’s longevity is due in large part to how he was represented by Stephen J. Gould. When viewed from the perspective of the biographer, Gould’s revival of Goldschmidt as an evolutionary heretic in the 1970s and 1980s represents a selective reinvention of Goldschmidt that provides a contrast to other kinds of biographical commemorations by scientists. Keywords: Richard Goldschmidt, hopeful monsters, evolutionary synthesis, Stephen J. Gould, punctuated equilibrium, biography Richard Goldschmidt is one of the most controversial and enigmatic figures in twentieth century biology.
    [Show full text]
  • Racial Purity, Stable Genes, and Sex Difference: Gender in the Making of Genetic Concepts by Richard Goldschmidt and Fritz Lenz
    Repositorium für die Geschlechterforschung Racial Purity, Stable Genes, and Sex Difference: Gender in the Making of Genetic Concepts by Richard Goldschmidt and Fritz Lenz, 1916-1936 Satzinger, Helga 2009 https://doi.org/10.25595/242 Veröffentlichungsversion / published version Sammelbandbeitrag / collection article Empfohlene Zitierung / Suggested Citation: Satzinger, Helga: Racial Purity, Stable Genes, and Sex Difference: Gender in the Making of Genetic Concepts by Richard Goldschmidt and Fritz Lenz, 1916-1936, in: Heim, Susanne; Sachse, Carola; Walker, Mark (Hrsg.): The Kaiser Wilhelm Society under National Socialism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 145-170. DOI: https://doi.org/10.25595/242. Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Dieser Text wird unter einer CC BY 4.0 Lizenz (Namensnennung) This document is made available under a CC BY 4.0 License zur Verfügung gestellt. Nähere Auskünfte zu dieser Lizenz finden (Attribution). For more information see: Sie hier: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/deed.en https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/deed.de www.genderopen.de 7 Racial Purity, Stahle Genes, and Sex Difference: The Kaiser Wilhelm Society under Gender in the Making of Genetic Concepts by Richard National Socialism Goldschmidt and Fritz Lenz, 1916 to 1936 Helga Satzinger SUSANNE HEIM Institute for Contemporary History, Munich/Berlin In 1936, the geneticist Richard Goldschmidt (1878-1958) was forced to CAROLA SACHSE relinquish his position as director at the Kaiser Wilhelm Institute (KWI) University of Vierma for Biology in Berlin Dahlem due to National Socialist anti-Semitism. His emigration to the United States at the age of nearly fifty-eight meant leaving MARK WALKER behind excellent working conditions, his editorship of important journals, and a highly influential position in German-languag~ genetics.
    [Show full text]
  • Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Making Mutations
    MAX-PLANCK-INSTITUT FÜR WISSENSCHAFTSGESCHICHTE Max Planck Institute for the History of Science 2010 PREPRINT 393 Luis Campos and Alexander von Schwerin (eds.) Making Mutations: Objects, Practices, Contexts Table of Contents The Making of “Making Mutations”.........................................................................................3 Alexander von Schwerin & Luis Campos Identifying Mutation Women in Mutation Studies: The Role of Gender in the Methods, Practices, and Results of Early Twentieth-Century Genetics ......................................................................................11 Marsha L. Richmond Mutant Sexuality: The Private Life of a Plant.........................................................................49 Luis Campos Generating Plants and Women: Intersecting Conceptions of Biological and Social Mutations in Susan Glaspell's “The Verge” (1921)................................................................71 Jörg Thomas Richter Non-Evolutionary Mutants? A Note on the Castorrex Rabbit ................................................85 Thierry Hoquet Organisms Tracing the Totsuzen in Tanaka's Silkworms: An Exploration of the Establishment of Bombyx Mori Mutant Stocks................................................................................................ 109 Lisa A. Onaga Supporting the Balance View: Dobzhansky’s Construction of Drosophila pseudoobscura ...................................................................................................................... 119 Matt Dunn The First
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 10 Speciation and Macroevolution Anya Plutynski
    Chapter 10 Speciation and Macroevolution anya plutynski 1. Introduction Speciation is the process by which one or more species1 arises from a common ancestor, and “macroevolution” refers to patterns and processes at and above the species level – or, transitions in higher taxa, such as new families, phyla, or genera. “Macroevolution” is contrasted with “microevolution,”2 evolutionary change within populations, due to migration, selection, mutation, and drift. During the 1930s and 40s, Haldane (1932), Dobzhansky (1937), Mayr (1942), and Simpson (1944) argued that the origin of species and higher taxa were, given the right environmental conditions and suffi cient time, the product of the same microevolutionary factors causing change within populations. Dobzhansky reviewed the evidence from genetics, and argued, “nothing in the known macroevolutionary phenomena would require other than the known genetic principles for causal explanation” (Dobzhansky, 1951, p.17). In sum, genetic variation between species was not different in kind from the genetic variation within species. Dobzhansky concluded that one may “reluctantly put an equal sign” between micro- and macroevolution. This view was not accepted by all, however. Richard Goldschmidt, for instance, argued that microevolution does not, by the sheer accumulation of small, adaptive changes, lead to novel species. In his words, “the facts of microevolution do not suffi ce for macroevolution” (Goldschmidt, 1940, p.8). Goldschmidt’s position was regarded by many during the synthesis as implausible. However, similar arguments, questioning the suffi ciency of microevolutionary pro- cesses for macroevolutionary change, were offered up at different stages subsequent to the 1940s. In this same vein but based on very different arguments, Gould and Eldredge (1977) argued that there are causal processes operating at and above the species level which are not reducible to, or explainable in terms of, change within populations.
    [Show full text]
  • Neo-Darwinism and Evo-Devo: an Argument for Theoretical Pluralism in Evolutionary Biology
    Neo-Darwinism and Evo-Devo: An Argument for Theoretical Pluralism in Evolutionary Biology Lindsay R. Craig Temple University There is an ongoing debate over the relationship between so-called neo-Darwinism and evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo) that is motivated in part by the possibility of a theoretical synthesis of the two (e.g., Amundson 2005; Brigandt and Love 2010; Laubichler 2010; Minelli 2010; Pigliucci and Müller 2010). Through analysis of the terms and arguments employed in this debate, I argue that an alternative line of argument has been missed. Specifically, I use the terms of this debate to argue that a relative significance issue (Beatty 1995, 1997) exists and reflects a theoretical pluralism that is likely to remain. 1. Introduction The relatively new field of evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo) continues to attract considerable attention from biologists, philosophers, and historians, in part, because work in this field demonstrates that impor- tant changes are underway within biology (e.g., Gilbert, Opitz and Raff 1996; Love 2003; Amundson 2005; Burian 2005a; Müller and Newman 2005; Laubichler 2007, 2010; Müller 2007; Pigliucci 2007, 2009; Minelli 2010). Though studies of development and evolution were closely connected during the 19th century, continued work in genetics fostered a general split between the two during the first decades of the twentieth century (e.g., Allen 1978; Gilbert 1978; Mayr and Provine 1980; Gilbert, Opitz and Raff 1996). Consequently, embryology and developmental biology did not play a significant role in the development of so-called neo-Darwinism1 during the Thanks to Richard Burian, Michael Dietrich, and Robert Richardson for comments on earlier versions of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • RICHARD BENEDICT GOLDSCHMIDT April 12,1878-April 24,1958
    NATIONAL ACADEMY OF SCIENCES R I C H A R D B E N E D I C T G OLDSCHMIDT 1878—1958 A Biographical Memoir by C U R T S TERN Any opinions expressed in this memoir are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Academy of Sciences. Biographical Memoir COPYRIGHT 1967 NATIONAL ACADEMY OF SCIENCES WASHINGTON D.C. RICHARD BENEDICT GOLDSCHMIDT April 12,1878-April 24,1958 BY CURT STERN ICHARD GOLDSCHMIDT left not only a published record of R, nearly sixty years of scientific activities but also a full autobiography and a detailed sketch of his life written in fulfill- ment of the traditional request of the National Academy of Sciences. In addition, he preserved many letters which he had received from colleagues all over the world and deposited them in the archives of the Library of the University of California at Berkeley. It would be possible to reconstruct a large part of the development of the biological sciences in the twentieth cen- tury on the basis of Goldschmidt's publications and their in- teraction with his contemporaries. It would also be possible to explore in depth the personality of the man as it was formed through the impact of his time. These may be worth-while tasks for future historians. The present Memoir can present only a selection out of the multitude of his activities. Richard Goldschmidt was born on April 12, 1878, in Frank- furt am Main, Germany. He died in Berkeley, California, on April 24, 1958.
    [Show full text]