Introduction to Cognitive Science. Behaviorism Jesse Harris February 11, 2013

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction to Cognitive Science. Behaviorism Jesse Harris February 11, 2013 LCS 11: Introduction to Cognitive Science. Behaviorism Jesse Harris February 11, 2013 Background to behaviorism Much of philosophy has addressed what is sometimes known as ‘Plato’s problem’ – how do we come to know so much about the world, given our limited experience? Two important, though not necessarily mutually exclusive, strands of response are rationalism, with privileges reason over experience, and empiricism, which favors experience over reason.1 Rationalism How do we know so much about the world given our limited experi- ence? The rationalists propose that knowledge is deductive, in that we 1 In the Meno, Plato adopts a rationalist approach, ar- may glean knowledge from principles independent of experience. guing that knowledge is innately given and that the soul relies on experience Rationalism and reason to recollect that knowledge. His argument is illustrated by getting Knowledge is to be gained primarily through reason alone. a slave to “recollect” how to determine the areas of embedded squares like those above. With respect to questions of mind, rationalism is often associated with René Descartes, who modeled his method on geometric proofs from Euclid.2 Descartes wished to determine an incontrovertible 2 Euclid’s highly influential The Elements foundation of knowledge which was free of the possibility of illusion deduces Euclidean geometry from a limited set of axioms. Descartes and from the senses and which supported the immortality of the soul. others seemed to consider the axiomatic Descartes famously settled on a foundation of knowledge through method developed by Euclid to be the ideal form of scientific inquiry. the idea that, even if illusory, a thought must have a thinker: the very act of doubt verified some aspect of his existence! In other words, cognito ergo sum. There are three important methodological assump- tions that Descartes made: 1. Knowledge can be determined independently of the senses; 2. Ideas are transparent to conscious introspection; 3. We should privilege that which could be established by pure thought, e.g., mathematical truths, over the sense data of experi- ence Substance dualism The mind (soul) is a immaterial, immortal substance which exists independently of the body. lcs 11: introduction to cognitive science. behaviorism 2 Despite deeply ingrained problems with this view, substance dualism remains a popular view.3 An alternate, and just as venerable, view 3 Three prevalent considerations are as is known as empiricism, which treats the acquisition of knowledge as follows (see Cunningham, 2000, ch. 1) inductive. 1. Reliance on introspection 2. Causal separation 3. Development of mind Empiricism In contrast to rationalists, empiricists largely reject the assumption that ideas are innate. Instead, mental contents are derived from two factors. 1. Sensations – events with external causes. 2. Reflection – mental operations that associate external or internal states with other internal states. Together, these factors yield Ideas, mental contents likened to pictures or images, linked to what they are about. “Let us then suppose the mind to be, Empiricism as we say, white paper, void of all Knowledge is to be gained primarily through sense experience. character, without any ideas. How comes it to be furnished? . I answer, in one word, experience. In that, all our A prominent proponent of empiricism was John Locke, who devised knowledge is founded, and from that it ultimately derives itself.” a scheme for mental mechanics in which ideas come to be associated with one another. Through this kind of associationism, as it was called, Essay Concerning Human Understanding John Locke (1689) simple ideas compose to form more complex ones. Introspectionism Interestingly enough, the earliest experimental psychologists adopted elements, from both traditions. For example, Wilhelm Wundt and his student E. B. Titchener4 developed a method known as introspec- 4 tion, in which the contents of experience were reflected on during conscious investigation and reported back. In an attempt to make this process more scientific, participants were trained in introspec- tion through many trials, reporting their subjective experience.5 In particular, participants were instructed to decompose the process into discrete stages: perception of stimulus, a search for a response, Wilhelm Wundt E. B. Titchener identification of response, production of response, and so on. (1832–1920) (1867–1927) Exercise: Try this for yourself. View this 5 “The first order of the psychologist . is to ascertain the nature and num- swatch of red and reflect on the experience, ber of mental elements. He takes up attempting to break down the experience into mental experience, bit by bit, dividing as many components as you can. and subdividing, until the division can go no further. When that point is reached, he has found a conscious element.” An Outline of Psychology (Titchener, 1896) lcs 11: introduction to cognitive science. behaviorism 3 Behaviorism Frustration and disillusionment with introspection as a method of gaining entry into mental processes quickly mounted.6 John Wat- 6 “Take the case of sensation. A sensa- son and, later, B. F. Skinner,7 led the charge against the subjectivity tion is defined in terms of its attributes. One psychologist will state with readi- 8 seemingly inherent to the introspective method. They proposed a ness that the attributes of a visual purely behavioristic approach to studying the cognition, concerned sensation are quality, extension, dura- tion and intensity. Another will add in no small measure with the prediction and control of behavior. clearness. Still another that of order. I As discussed in Cunningham (2000), multiple kinds of behaviorism doubt if any one psychologist can draw resulted, notably, Methodological and Metaphysical Behaviorism. up a set of statements describing what he means by sensation which will be agreed to by three other psychologists Methodological behaviorism of different training.“ A scientific study of mind should eschew talk of the mind in favor Psychology as the Behaviorist Views It of a description of behavior, since only behavior provides publicly (Watson, 1913) observable, hence potentially verifiable, data. 7 Metaphysical behaviorism Mental events are reducible in kind to behavior: there is no substance or thing corresponding to what we call ‘mind.’ Influenced by the Vienna Circle’s circumscribed view of science,9 John B. Watson B.F. Skinner (1904–1990) behaviorism seeks to align, to various extents, the study of mind with (1878–1958) the study of behavior. That is, instead of worrying about the con- 8 “Psychology as the behaviorist views nection between mind and body, we focus on what we can observe: it is a purely objective experimental responses to external stimuli. Among the vocabulary central to Skin- branch of natural science. Its theoretical goal is the prediction and control ner’s behaviorism was operant conditioning, in which modification of of behavior. Introspection forms no behavior is voluntary. Skinner developed the so-called “Skinner box” essential part of its methods, nor is the to control an animal’s environment, typically a pigeon or white rat, scientific value of its data dependent upon the readiness of with which they starve them to create a “drive,” and then wait for animal to discover lend themselves to interpretation in a relation between the environment, e.g., a lever, and a reward, e.g., a terms of consciousness. The behaviorist . recognizes no dividing line between food pellet. Soon enough, the behavior is associated with the reward. man and brute.” Ibid. 9 The Vienna Circle refers to a group of philosophers and scientists in Vi- enna in the early 1920s who sought to eliminate what they deemed logical mistakes from philosophical questions. They thought that ambiguous language had radically misled scientific and philosophical inquiry, and proposed a unified science built on the foun- 10 In addition, Skinner placed animals on a schedule of reinforcement. dation of symbolic logic and publicly If a pigeon is fed at regular intervals regardless of its behavior, it will observable sense experience. adopt essentially arbitrary patterns of behavior which it has associ- 10 Skinner, B. F. (1948). ‘Superstition’ ated with the reward, such as spinning, pecking, etc. The efficacy of in the pigeon. Journal of Experimental the association could be manipulated by varying the rate of reward: Psychology 38, 168–272 lcs 11: introduction to cognitive science. behaviorism 4 fixed and random reinforcement. The strongest type was random re- inforcement, in which the animal is rewarded at random intervals. Indeed, it sometimes happened that although feeding device was dis- mantled, the pigeon indefinitely continued to perform the behavior that was associated with the reward. Thus, the behaviorist was able to account for admitedly simple behavior without recourse to unsightly mentalistic terms like desire, belief, and so forth. That is, the psychologist needn’t speculate about what the bird was feeling; she only needed to report its behavior. Encouraged by the success with pigeons and rats, Skinner and col- leagues proposed that the basic mechanism of association between a stimulus and response was the central, or even sole, mechanism driv- ing all behavior, even in human beings. Skinner even claimed that language learning was simply an instance of operant reinforcement, albeit complex in nature. For example, a child might be rewarded by her parents to cry out Papa in the presence of her father, thereby associating the word with the figure. In a devasting review by Noam Chomsky,11 it soon became apparent that Skinner’s science of behav- 11 Chomsky, N. (1959). Verbal Behavior. ior was simply not rich enough to account for more complex forms of By B. F. Skinner. Language 35, 26–58 speech or human behavior. Chomsky’s review is Indeed, even once committed behaviorists like Keller and Mar- widely regarded as the death knoll for 12 ian Breland observed that instinctive behaviors not driven by the behaviorism, mak- external environment were a powerful determinant of an animal’s ing commonsense, mentalistic talk once action.
Recommended publications
  • Concepts As Correlates of Lexical Labels. a Cognitivist Perspective
    This is a submitted manuscript version. The publisher should be contacted for permission to re-use or reprint the material in any form. Final published version, copyright Peter Lang: https://doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-05287-9 Sławomir Wacewicz Concepts as Correlates of Lexical Labels. A Cognitivist Perspective. This is a submitted manuscript version. The publisher should be contacted for permission to re-use or reprint the material in any form. Final published version, copyright Peter Lang: https://doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-05287-9 CONTENTS Introduction………………………………………………………………... 6 PART I INTERNALISTIC PERSPECTIVE ON LANGUAGE IN COGNITIVE SCIENCE Preliminary remarks………………………………………………………… 17 1. History and profile of Cognitive Science……………………………….. 18 1.1. Introduction…………………………………………………………. 18 1.2. Cognitive Science: definitions and basic assumptions ……………. 19 1.3. Basic tenets of Cognitive 22 Science…………………………………… 1.3.1. Cognition……………………………………………………... 23 1.3.2. Representationism and presentationism…………………….... 25 1.3.3. Naturalism and physical character of mind…………………... 28 1.3.4. Levels of description…………………………………………. 30 1.3.5. Internalism (Individualism) ………………………………….. 31 1.4. History……………………………………………………………... 34 1.4.1. Prehistory…………………………………………………….. 35 1.4.2. Germination…………………………………………………... 36 1.4.3. Beginnings……………………………………………………. 37 1.4.4. Early and classical Cognitive Science………………………… 40 1.4.5. Contemporary Cognitive Science……………………………... 42 1.4.6. Methodological notes on interdisciplinarity………………….. 52 1.5. Summary…………………………………………………………. 59 2. Intrasystemic and extrasystemic principles of concept individuation 60 2.1. Existential status of concepts ……………………………………… 60 2 This is a submitted manuscript version. The publisher should be contacted for permission to re-use or reprint the material in any form. Final published version, copyright Peter Lang: https://doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-05287-9 2.1.1.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive and Neuroscience Research on Learning And
    The 11th International Conference on Education Research New Educational Paradigm for Learning and Instruction September 29 – October 1, 2010 Cognitive and Neuroscience Research on Learning and Instruction: Recent insights about the impact of non-conscious knowledge on problem solving, higher order thinking skills 12 and interactive cyber-learning environments. Richard E. Clark University of Southern California, USA Abstract There are as least three powerful insights from recent studies of the brain that support cognitive science research findings: First, our brains learn and process two very different types of knowledge; non conscious, automated knowledge and conscious, controllable, declarative knowledge. Evidence also suggests that we believe we control our own learning by conscious choice when in fact nearly all mental operations are highly automated, including learning and problem solving; Second, human beings have a very limited capacity to think during learning and problem solving and when that capacity is exceeded, thinking and learning stop without us being aware. Thus instruction and self managed learning must strive to avoid cognitive overload; and Third, nearly all of our instructional design and cyber learning theories and models fail to account for the influence of non-conscious cognitive processes and therefore are inadequate to deal with complex learning and performance. Evidence for these points will be described and their implications for instruction and the learning of problem solving and higher order thinking skills will be discussed. Models of learning and instruction that appear to help overcome some of these biological and cognitive barriers will be described. In addition, suggestions for new research questions on interactive learning environments that take account of the three insights will also be described.
    [Show full text]
  • The Science of Psychology 1
    PSY_C01.qxd 1/2/05 3:17 pm Page 2 The Science of Psychology 1 CHAPTER OUTLINE LEARNING OBJECTIVES INTRODUCTION PINNING DOWN PSYCHOLOGY PSYCHOLOGY AND COMMON SENSE: THE GRANDMOTHER CHALLENGE Putting common sense to the test Explaining human behaviour THE BEGINNINGS OF MODERN PSYCHOLOGY Philosophical influences Physiological influences PSYCHOLOGY TODAY Structuralism: mental chemistry Functionalism: mental accomplishment Behaviourism: a totally objective psychology Gestalt psychology: making connections Out of school: the independents The cognitive revolution FINAL THOUGHTS SUMMARY REVISION QUESTIONS FURTHER READING PSY_C01.qxd 1/2/05 3:17 pm Page 3 Learning Objectives By the end of this chapter you should appreciate that: n psychology is much more than ‘common sense’; n psychological knowledge can be usefully applied in many different professions and walks of life; n psychology emerged as a distinct discipline around 150 years ago, from its roots in physiology, physics and philosophy; n there are fundamental differences between different schools of thought in psychology; n psychology is the science of mental life and behaviour, and different schools of thought within psychology place differing degrees of emphasis on understanding these different elements of psychology; n most academic departments in the English-speaking world focus on the teaching of experimental psychology, in which scientific evidence about the structure and function of the mind and behaviour accumulates through the execution of empirical investigations; n in the history of psychology many different metaphors have been used for thinking about the workings of the human mind, and since the Second World War the most influential of these metaphors has been another complex information-processing device – the computer.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rise of Cognitive Science in the 20Th Century
    The Rise of Cognitive Science in the 20th Century Carrie Figdor (forthcoming in Kind, A., ed., Philosophy of Mind in the 20th and 21st Centuries: Routledge) Penultimate Draft Abstract. This chapter describes the conceptual foundations of cognitive science during its establishment as a science in the 20th century. It is organized around the core ideas of individual agency as its basic explanans and information-processing as its basic explanandum. The latter consists of a package of ideas that provide a mathematico- engineering framework for the philosophical theory of materialism. Keywords: cognitive science; psychology; linguistics; computer science; neuroscience; behaviorism; artificial intelligence; computationalism; connectionism Part I. Introduction. Cognitive science is the study of individual agency: its nature, scope, mechanisms, and patterns. It studies what agents are and how they function. This definition is modified from one provided by Bechtel, Abrahamson, and Graham (1998), where cognitive science is defined as “the multidisciplinary scientific study of cognition and its role in intelligent agency.” Several points motivate the modification. First (and least consequential), the multidisciplinarity of cognitive science is an accident of academic history, not a fact about its subject matter (a point also pressed in Gardner 1985). Second, the label “intelligent” is often used as a term of normative assessment, when cognitive science is concerned with behavior by entities (including possibly groups, as individual or collective agents) that are not considered intelligent, as well as unintelligent behavior of intelligent agents, for any intuitive definition of “intelligent”.1 Third and most importantly, the term “cognition” is omitted from the definiens to help emphasize a position of neutrality on a number of contemporary debates.
    [Show full text]
  • The Association of Strategy Use and Concrete-Operational Thinking in Primary School
    ORIGINAL RESEARCH published: 23 May 2018 doi: 10.3389/feduc.2018.00038 The Association of Strategy Use and Concrete-Operational Thinking in Primary School Moritz Börnert-Ringleb* and Jürgen Wilbert Department of Inclusive Education, University of Potsdam, Potsdam, Germany Concrete-operational thinking depicts an important aspect of cognitive development. A promising approach in promoting these skills is the instruction of strategies. The construction of such instructional programs requires insights into the mental operations involved in problem-solving. In the present paper, we address the question to which extent variations of the effect of isolated and combined mental operations (strategies) on correct solution of concrete-operational concepts can be observed. Therefore, a cross-sectional design was applied. The use of mental operations was measured by thinking-aloud reports from 80 first- and second-graders (N = 80) while solving tasks depicting concrete-operational thinking. Concrete-operational thinking was assessed Edited by: using the subscales conservation of numbers, classification and sequences of the TEKO. Michael S. Dempsey, Boston University, United States The verbal reports were transcribed and coded with regard to the mental operations Reviewed by: applied per task. Data analyses focused on tasks level, resulting in the analyses of Sharinaz Hassan, N = 240 tasks per subscale. Differences regarding the contribution of isolated and Curtin University, Australia Niels A. Taatgen, combined mental operations (strategies) to correct solution were observed. Thereby, University of Groningen, Netherlands the results indicate the necessity of selection and integration of appropriate mental *Correspondence: operations as strategies. The results offer insights in involved mental operations while Moritz Börnert-Ringleb solving concrete-operational tasks and depict a contribution to the construction of [email protected] instructional programs.
    [Show full text]
  • A Comprehension of Spinoza's God
    A Comprehension of Spinoza's God Through the Dichotomy of Labels Tania Norell LUNDS UNIVERSITET | CENTRUM FÖR TEOLOGI OCH RELIGIONSVETENSKAP TLVM77 Philosophy of Religion Master Thesis 30 credits Supervisor: Jayne Svenungsson, Professor of Systematic Theology Examiner: Jesper Svartvik, Professor of Theology of Religions Autumn term 2015 Lund University Sweden Lund University Tania Norell Abstract: The 17 th century philosopher Spinoza is known for his concept of God as One Substance, God or Nature and therefore considered as a monist and categorized as a naturalist. He has been labeled an atheist and God-intoxicated man, as well as a determinist and pantheist, which I perceive to be dichotomies. The problem, as I see it, is that Spinoza’s philosophy and concept of God has mainly been interpreted through a dualistic mind-set, traditional to philosophers and theologians of the West, but Spinoza has a monistic worldview, and this has consequences in regards to the comprehension of what Spinoza’s concept of God entails and what a relationship “with” God implies . The labels panentheist and necessitarianist are discussed and the label of theologian argued. The thesis methodology is constructive because the purpose is to provide a theoretical foundation that has the potential to be applied in dialogues about God between the vast varieties of believers and non-believers alike, as well as across boundaries of contradicting worldviews and academic disciplines, and this focus on functionalism is inspired by a theory that calls for the furthering of inter-disciplinary dialogue between the subject areas philosophy of religion and theology specifically. My personal worldview is that there might well be One Substance, God or Nature, but that does not necessarily mean that there is one truth that is valid, but rather that all truth claims may be of value.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This Is a Story About Philosophy. Or About Science
    Chapter 1: An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This is a story about philosophy. Or about science. Or about philosophy transforming into science. Or about science and philosophy, and how they are related. Or were, in a particular time and place. At least, that is the general area that the following narrative will explore, I hope with sufficient subtlety. The matter is rendered non-transparent by the fact that that the conclusions one draws with regard to such questions are, in part, matters of discretionary perspective – as I will try to demonstrate. My specific historical focus will be on the propagation of a complex intellectual tradition concerned with human sensation, perception, and mental function in early nineteenth century Britain. Not only philosophical opinion, but all aspects of British intellectual – and practical – life, were in the process of significant transformation during this time. This cultural flux further confuses recovery of the situated significance of the intellectual tradition I am investigating. The study of the mind not only was influenced by a set of broad social shifts, but it also participated in them fully as both stimulus to and recipient of changing conditions. One indication of this is simply the variety of terms used to identify the ‘philosophy of mind’ as an intellectual enterprise in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.1 But the issue goes far deeper into the fluid constitutive features of the enterprise - including associated conceptual systems, methods, intentions of practitioners, and institutional affiliations. In order to understand philosophy of mind in its time, we must put all these factors into play.
    [Show full text]
  • Wundt's "New Psychology"
    Wundt's "New Psychology" Wilhelm Wundt(1832-1920) was the first professional to call himself a psychologist. He founded one of the first psychological laboratories in Leipzig, Germany, in 1879. Wundt believed the "only certain reality is immediate experience" (Blumenthal, 1975). If psychology were to be a science, then psychologists would have to collect data about experience. To do this, Wundt used procedures similar to those developed by the psychophysicists. He arranged controlled laboratory settings. He carefully administered stimulation such as sounds and sights. He gathered information about how quickly people responded to a stimulus (reaction time) and what they experienced. Wundt believed these experiments would lead to a consensus or agreement among scientists about the nature of experience. Wilhelm Wundt Wundt's approach was not unreasonable. It resembled the way most natural sciences developed in the 1800s. Science like botany and zoology began with careful observation and an effort to arrive at consensual validation (agreement among different observers). For example, biologists began with careful descriptions of plants and animals before trying to classify them. Wundt believed the same approach would work in psychology. Careful scientific observers could simply look inside themselves to see the mind in action, and they should be able to agree on the basic phenomena of psychology. After agreeing about basic observations, they could do a deeper analysis of what they had found. The technique of "looking inside" to gather data about the mind is called introspection . The problem with Wundt's program is fairly obvious to those of us in the modern world, where differences between people are taken for granted.
    [Show full text]
  • Coordination of Component Mental Operations in Sequences of Discrete Responses
    Coordination of Component Mental Operations in Sequences of Discrete Responses Shu-Chieh Wu ([email protected] ) Roger W. Remington ([email protected]) NASA Ames Research Center, Mail Stop 262-4 Moffett Field, CA 94035 USA Harold Pashler ([email protected]) Department of Psychology, University of California, San Diego La Jolla, CA 92093 USA Abstract distributed across different resources, interleaving upcoming operations in the slack time created by queued bottleneck In daily life we often perform sequences of actions, which processes, and allowing operations from different resources with practice are accomplished by overlapping mental to proceed concurrently. The success of this approach operations for successive actions. Is it possible to derive depends on the underlying assumption that component performance predictions for such sequences from a mental operations inferred from discrete task performance characterization of the mental operations for a single do not function differently in extended task environments. stimulus-response pair? We explore this by examining the joint timing of eye movements and manual responses in a This assumption has yet to be tested. Also, success has been typing-like task following Pashler (1994). Participants made achieved for tasks that are largely perceptual-motor, with separate choice responses to a series of five stimuli spread good fits obtaining after about 100 contiguous trials (e.g., over a wide viewing area. Replicating Pashler’s results, John et al., 2002). responses to the first stimulus (RT1) were elevated, with The goal of the present research is to investigate the inter-response intervals (IRI) for subsequent items rapid and coordination of component mental operations in extended flat across items.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 11: Behaviorism
    Chapter 11: Behaviorism Megan Davis, Nicole Pelley and Stephanie Quinlan Behaviorism (1892-1956) ● Psychology has been the study of the mind since the Greeks ○ The definition of the mind has been debated extensively ○ 20th century: Shift from what the mind was to what it did ■ Mind causes behavior ● New field of research ○ Psychology was redefined with help from animal psychology ○ People started believing humans evolved from animal forms ○ Had to rethink Descartes’ definition of the mind New Directions in Animal Psychology New Directions in Animal Psychology Animal psychology as Romanes begun it, used 2 methods: 1. Anecdotal Method → Collect data 2. Method of Inference → Interpret data Close examination in late 19th, early 20th century. Anecdote → Experiment From Anecdote to Experiment ● Experiment replaced anecdotes and informal, naturalistic experiments ● Aim of animal psychology - produce natural science and anecdote not the path to science ● Two important research programs: ○ Thorndike ○ Pavlov From Anecdote to Experiment Edward Lee Thorndike (1874-1949): ● Initially wanted to study children ● Not many readily available, took up animals ● Studied with William James ● Developed “connectionism” ○ Methodological and theoretical approach to animal learning ○ Formulation of an S-R psychology he called “connectionism” ○ Anecdotal method overestimated animal intelligence From Anecdote to Experiment Thorndike’s Puzzle Boxes ● Trap cat inside box ● Each box opened by cat in different way ● Rewarded with salmon for escaping ○ Ex. of instrumental
    [Show full text]
  • Addressing Metacognitive Capacity for Self Reflection in the Psychotherapy for Schizophrenia
    58 The British Psychological Psychology and Psychotherapy: Theory, Research and Practice (2011), 84, 58–69 Society C 2010 The British Psychological Society www.wileyonlinelibrary.com Addressing metacognitive capacity for self reflection in the psychotherapy for schizophrenia: A conceptual model of the key tasks and processes ∗ , Paul H. Lysaker1,2 , Kelly D. Buck1 3, Antonino Carcione4, Michelle Procacci4, Giampaolo Salvatore4, Guiseppe Nicolo` 4 and Giancarlo Dimaggio4 1Roudebush VA Medical Center, Indianapolis, Indiana, USA 2Department of Psychiatry, Indiana University School of Medicine, Indianapolis, Indiana, USA 3Purdue University School of Nursing, Indianapolis, Indiana, USA 4Terzo Centro di Psicoterapia Cognitiva, Associazione di Psicologia Cognitiva, Rome, Italy Purpose. Recognition that recovery from schizophrenia may involve a deepening of the experience of being in the world has led to the possibility that psychotherapy may play a key role in treatment by enhancing metacognition, or the capacity to think about thinking. While the potential of psychotherapy to enhance metacognition in non- psychotic disorders has been discussed in depth, little has been written about how psychotherapy may systematically address metacognition in schizophrenia. Accordingly, the current paper formulates a model of how psychotherapy might address one specific element of metacognition, namely self-reflectivity. Methods. Procedures are outlined for assessing clients’ capacity for self-reflectivity within narrative contexts during psychotherapy. Results. Targeted interventions are identified which are tailored to clients’ capacities in the moment and which assist clients to think about their own thinking at the level of which they are capable. This may lead clients over time to develop a greater ability to engage in acts of increasingly complex self-reflectivity.
    [Show full text]
  • Functional Imaging in Behavioral Neurology and Cognitive Neuropsychology
    Functional Imaging in Behavioral Neurology and Cognitive Neuropsychology Geoffrey Karl Aguirre From: T. E. Feinberg & M. J. Farah (Eds.), Behavioral Neurology and Cognitive Neuropsychology . (in press). New York: McGraw Hill. Introduction What can we hope to learn of the physical operation of the central nervous system and the mental processes that result? The fields of behavioral neurology and cognitive neuropsychology survey this relationship, and have at their disposal powerful intellectual and methodological tools. While the terrain of possible models of brain and behavior interaction seems boundless, particular tests of these models may exist beyond the reach of particular methods. These methods fall into two broad categories, and have been around for several centuries. The first category includes manipulations of the neural substrate itself. Such an intervention might inactivate a brain area, perhaps through a lesion, with Paul Broca’s 1861 observation of the link between language and left frontal lobe damage providing a prototypical example. The effects of stimulation of brain areas can also be studied, as Harvey Cushing did with the human sensory cortex in the early 20th century. In contrast, observation techniques relate a measure of neural function to behavior. Hans Berger’s work in the 1920s on the human electroencephalographic response is a good starting point. Impressive refinements and additions to both of these categories have taken place over the last century. For example, beyond the static lesions of “nature’s accidents” that have been the mainstay of cognitive neuropsychology for many years, it is now possible to temporarily and reversibly inactivate areas of human cortex using transcranial magnetic stimulation (see chapter X for additional details).
    [Show full text]