The Theory of the Foundations of Mathematics - 1870 to 1940

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Theory of the Foundations of Mathematics - 1870 to 1940 The theory of the foundations of mathematics - 1870 to 1940 - Mark Scheffer (Version 1.0) 2 3 . Mark Scheffer, id. 415968, e-mail: [email protected]. Last changes: March 22, 2002. This report is part of a practical component of the Com- puting Science study at the Eindhoven University of Technology. 4 To work on the foundations of mathematics, two things are needed: Love and Blood. - Anonymous quote, 2001. Contents 1 Introduction 9 2 Cantor’s paradise 13 2.1Thebeginningofset-theory................... 13 2.2Basicconcepts........................... 15 3 Mathematical constructs in set-theory 21 3.1Somemathematicalconcepts................... 21 3.2Relations.............................. 23 3.3Functions............................. 29 3.4 Induction Methods . 32 3.4.1 Induction . 32 3.4.2 Deduction......................... 33 3.4.3 The principle of induction . 34 3.5Realnumbers........................... 45 3.5.1 Dedekind’scuts...................... 46 3.5.2 Cantor’schainsofsegments............... 47 3.5.3 Cauchy-sequences..................... 48 3.5.4 Propertiesofthethreedefinitions............ 50 3.6Infinitesets............................ 51 3.7TheContinuumHypothesis................... 60 3.8 Cardinal and Ordinal numbers and Paradoxes . 63 3.8.1 Cardinal numbers and Cantor’s Paradox . 63 3.8.2 Ordinal numbers and Burali-Forti’s Paradox . 65 4 Peano and Frege 71 4.1Peano’sarithmetic........................ 71 4.2Frege’swork............................ 74 5 6 CONTENTS 5 Russell 79 5.1 Russell’s paradox . 82 5.2Consequencesandphilosophies................. 88 5.3ZermeloFraenkel......................... 92 5.3.1 Axiomatic set theory . 92 5.3.2 Zermelo Fraenkel (ZF) Axioms . 93 6 Hilbert 99 6.1Hilbert’sprooftheory.......................101 6.2Hilbert’s23problems.......................110 7 Types 113 7.1 Russell and Whitehead’s Principia Mathematica . 113 7.2Ramsey,HilbertandAckermann.................119 7.3Quine...............................121 8G¨odel 123 8.1 Informally: G¨odel’s incompleteness theorems . 123 8.2 Formally: G¨odel’sIncompletenessTheorems..........127 8.2.1 On formally undecidable propositions . 127 8.2.2 The impossibility of an ‘internal’ proof of consistency . 130 8.2.3 G¨odel numbering and a concrete proof of G1, G2 and G3 131 8.3 G¨odel’s theorem and Peano Arithmetic . 132 8.4Consequences...........................134 8.5 Neumann-Bernays-G¨odelaxioms.................135 9 Church and Turing 141 9.1TuringandTuringMachine...................141 9.2ChurchandtheLambdaCalculus................153 9.3TheChurch-Turingthesis....................166 10 Conclusion 169 A Timeline and Images 181 CONTENTS 7 Mathematical Notations Many different notations have been developed for set theory and logic. Most notations that we have used are standard today; other notations that we have used are introduced in the text. Mathematical Logic symbol meaning also described as ∧ conjuction and ∨ disjunction (inclusive) or ¬ negation not ϕ(x) propositional function → implication if ... then ↔ bi-implication if and only if, iff ≡ equivalence is equivalent to ∀ universal quantifier for all ∃ existential quantifier exists ∃! one-element existential quantifier exists a unique In most places we have chosen to use the following notation1 to denote quantifications: (relation : range : term) denotes the relationship over a set of termsrangingoverrange Consider a general pattern (Qx : ϕ(x0,...,xn):t(x0,...,xn)), with Q aquantifier,ϕ a boolean expression in terms of the dummies x0, ..., xn, and t(x0,...,xn) the term of the quantification. The quantification is the accumulation of values t(x0,...,xn) using an operator or relation indicated by Q, over all values (x0,...,xn) for which ϕ(x0,...,xn)holds. 1Notation originally due to E.W. Dijkstra. 8 CONTENTS This notation is suitable for formal manipulation and unambiguous in the sense that it explicitly indicates the quantifier Q, the dummies and the range of the dummies that is indicated by the boolean expression ϕ (i.e. it exactly determines the domain of the quantification). This allows us to reason about general properties of quantifications, in a way in which the (scopes of the) bound variables are clearly identified. Note that this type of quantification is only suitable for binary operations that are symmetric and associative. Example: ( x :0≤ x ≤ 5:x2) = 02 +12 +22 +32 +42 +52 = 5 x2 x=0 Example: (∃x : x ∈ N : x3 − x2 =18) ≡ ‘there exists a natural number x such that x3 − x2 =18’ If the term ranges over all possible values of the variable (here : x), or if it is clear what the range of a variable is, we can omit it. Example: (∀x : true : x ∈ A → x ∈ B) ≡ (∀x :: x ∈ A → x ∈ B) ≡ ‘all elements of A are also elements of B’ Chapter 1 Introduction Pure mathematics is, in its way, the poetry of logical ideas. - Albert Einstein This report covers the most important developments and theory of the foundations of mathematics in the period of 1870 to 1940. The tale of the foundations is fairly familiar in general terms and for its philosophical con- tent; here the main emphasis is laid on the mathematical theory. The history of the foundations of mathematics is complicated and is a many-sided story; with this article I do not aim to give a definitive or complete version, but to capture what I consider the essence of the theoretical developments, and to present them in a clear and modern setting. Some basic mathematical knowledge on set-theory and logics are presupposed. By the middle of the nineteenth century, certain logical problems (for example paradoxes around the notions of infinity, the infinitesimal and con- tinuity) at the heart of mathematics had inspired a movement, led by German mathematicians, to provide mathematics with more rigorous foundations. This is where the theory of this report begins, with the emergence of set theory by the German mathematician Cantor. In section 2.1 we informally describe how work on a problem concerning trigonometric series gradually led Cantor to his theory of sets (section 2.2). As a result of the work of Weierstrass, Dedekind and Cantor, pure mathematics had been provided with much more sophisticated foundations. The notion of infinitesimal had been banished, ‘real’ numbers had been provided with a logically consistent 9 10 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION definition (section 3.5), continuity had been redefined and, more controver- sially, a whole new branch of arithmetic had been invented which addressed itself to the problems (e.g. paradoxes) of infinity (sections 3.6, 3.7). In 1895 Cantor discovered a paradox (section 3.8.1) that he did not publish but communicated to Hilbert in 1896. In 1897 it was rediscovered in a slightly different form by Burali-Forti (section 3.8.2). Cantor and Burali-Forti could not resolve this paradox, but it was not taken so seriously, partly because the paradoxes appeared in a rather technical region. The Italian mathematician Peano (section 4.1) was able to show that the whole of arithmetic could be founded upon a system that uses three basic notions and five initial axioms. At the same time the German mathematician Frege (section 4.2) worked on developing a logical basis for mathematics. Just as Peano, Frege wanted to put mathematics on firm grounds. But Frege’s grounds were strictly logic; he followed a development later called logicism, also known as the development of so-called mathematical logic. The British mathematician Russell noted Peano’s work and later that of Frege. Soon thereafter he showed (section 5.1) how finite descriptions like ‘set of all sets’ could be self-contradictory (i.e. paradoxical) and pointed out the difficulties that arose with self-referential terms. This paradox that Russell found existed not only in specific technical regions but in all of the axiomatic systems underlying mathematics at the same time (section 5.1). But since the paradoxes could be avoided in most practical applications of set theory, the belief in set theory as a proper foundation of mathematics remained. Axiomatic set theory (section 5.3.1) was an attempt to come to a theory without paradoxes. Various responses to the paradox (section 5.2) led to new sets of axioms for set theory. The two main approaches are by the German mathematicians Zermelo and Fraenkel (section 5.3), and by the Hun- garian von Neumann, the Hungarian-Austrian G¨odel and the Briton Bernays (section 8.5). It also led to the emergence of the ‘intuitionistic’ philosophy of mathematics by the Dutch mathematician Brouwer (not covered here) and to a theory of types, proposed by Russell himself with the help of his for- mer teacher, the English mathematician Whitehead. Despite of the paradox Russell and Whitehead still claimed that all mathematics could be founded on a mathematical logic; this believe was given a definite presentation in their work ‘Principia Mathematica’ (section 7.1). Various consequences fol- lowed (section 7.3) and new conceptions of logic arose (by Wittgenstein and 11 Ramsey, see section 7.2). At the turn of the century, the German mathematician David Hilbert listed certain important problems concerning the foundations of mathema- tics and mathematics in general (section 6.2. To overcome paradoxes and other problems that arose in existing systems, Hilbert developed a theory of axiomatic systems (section 6.1). He then stimulated his student Zermelo in using this axiomatic method to develop as first a set of axioms for set theory (section 5.3.2). Hilbert had since then made more precise demands on any proposed set of axioms for mathematics (section 6.1) in terms of consistency, completeness and decidability. In 1931 G¨odel had shown that consistency and completeness could not both be attained (chapter 8). G¨odel’s work left outstanding Hilbert’s ques- tion of decidability. The English mathematician Turing proved in 1936 that there are undecidable problems, by giving the so-called halting problem that cannot be solved by any algorithm (section 9.1), after formalizing the no- tion of algorithm with his concept of the Turing Machine. The American mathematician Church (independently) obtained the same result but with another formalization of the notion of an algorithm, using his computational model of lambda calculus (section 9.2).
Recommended publications
  • “The Church-Turing “Thesis” As a Special Corollary of Gödel's
    “The Church-Turing “Thesis” as a Special Corollary of Gödel’s Completeness Theorem,” in Computability: Turing, Gödel, Church, and Beyond, B. J. Copeland, C. Posy, and O. Shagrir (eds.), MIT Press (Cambridge), 2013, pp. 77-104. Saul A. Kripke This is the published version of the book chapter indicated above, which can be obtained from the publisher at https://mitpress.mit.edu/books/computability. It is reproduced here by permission of the publisher who holds the copyright. © The MIT Press The Church-Turing “ Thesis ” as a Special Corollary of G ö del ’ s 4 Completeness Theorem 1 Saul A. Kripke Traditionally, many writers, following Kleene (1952) , thought of the Church-Turing thesis as unprovable by its nature but having various strong arguments in its favor, including Turing ’ s analysis of human computation. More recently, the beauty, power, and obvious fundamental importance of this analysis — what Turing (1936) calls “ argument I ” — has led some writers to give an almost exclusive emphasis on this argument as the unique justification for the Church-Turing thesis. In this chapter I advocate an alternative justification, essentially presupposed by Turing himself in what he calls “ argument II. ” The idea is that computation is a special form of math- ematical deduction. Assuming the steps of the deduction can be stated in a first- order language, the Church-Turing thesis follows as a special case of G ö del ’ s completeness theorem (first-order algorithm theorem). I propose this idea as an alternative foundation for the Church-Turing thesis, both for human and machine computation. Clearly the relevant assumptions are justified for computations pres- ently known.
    [Show full text]
  • Weyl's Predicative Classical Mathematics As a Logic-Enriched
    Weyl’s Predicative Classical Mathematics as a Logic-Enriched Type Theory? Robin Adams and Zhaohui Luo Dept of Computer Science, Royal Holloway, Univ of London {robin,zhaohui}@cs.rhul.ac.uk Abstract. In Das Kontinuum, Weyl showed how a large body of clas- sical mathematics could be developed on a purely predicative founda- tion. We present a logic-enriched type theory that corresponds to Weyl’s foundational system. A large part of the mathematics in Weyl’s book — including Weyl’s definition of the cardinality of a set and several re- sults from real analysis — has been formalised, using the proof assistant Plastic that implements a logical framework. This case study shows how type theory can be used to represent a non-constructive foundation for mathematics. Key words: logic-enriched type theory, predicativism, formalisation 1 Introduction Type theories have proven themselves remarkably successful in the formalisation of mathematical proofs. There are several features of type theory that are of particular benefit in such formalisations, including the fact that each object carries a type which gives information about that object, and the fact that the type theory itself has an inbuilt notion of computation. These applications of type theory have proven particularly successful for the formalisation of intuitionistic, or constructive, proofs. The correspondence between terms of a type theory and intuitionistic proofs has been well studied. The degree to which type theory can be used for the formalisation of other notions of proof has been investigated to a much lesser degree. There have been several formalisations of classical proofs by adapting a proof checker intended for intuitionistic mathematics, say by adding the principle of excluded middle as an axiom (such as [Gon05]).
    [Show full text]
  • Redalyc.Sets and Pluralities
    Red de Revistas Científicas de América Latina, el Caribe, España y Portugal Sistema de Información Científica Gustavo Fernández Díez Sets and Pluralities Revista Colombiana de Filosofía de la Ciencia, vol. IX, núm. 19, 2009, pp. 5-22, Universidad El Bosque Colombia Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=41418349001 Revista Colombiana de Filosofía de la Ciencia, ISSN (Printed Version): 0124-4620 [email protected] Universidad El Bosque Colombia How to cite Complete issue More information about this article Journal's homepage www.redalyc.org Non-Profit Academic Project, developed under the Open Acces Initiative Sets and Pluralities1 Gustavo Fernández Díez2 Resumen En este artículo estudio el trasfondo filosófico del sistema de lógica conocido como “lógica plural”, o “lógica de cuantificadores plurales”, de aparición relativamente reciente (y en alza notable en los últimos años). En particular, comparo la noción de “conjunto” emanada de la teoría axiomática de conjuntos, con la noción de “plura- lidad” que se encuentra detrás de este nuevo sistema. Mi conclusión es que los dos son completamente diferentes en su alcance y sus límites, y que la diferencia proviene de las diferentes motivaciones que han dado lugar a cada uno. Mientras que la teoría de conjuntos es una teoría genuinamente matemática, que tiene el interés matemático como ingrediente principal, la lógica plural ha aparecido como respuesta a considera- ciones lingüísticas, relacionadas con la estructura lógica de los enunciados plurales del inglés y el resto de los lenguajes naturales. Palabras clave: conjunto, teoría de conjuntos, pluralidad, cuantificación plural, lógica plural. Abstract In this paper I study the philosophical background of the relatively recent (and in the last few years increasingly flourishing) system of logic called “plural logic”, or “logic of plural quantifiers”.
    [Show full text]
  • The Iterative Conception of Set Author(S): George Boolos Reviewed Work(S): Source: the Journal of Philosophy, Vol
    Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Iterative Conception of Set Author(s): George Boolos Reviewed work(s): Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 68, No. 8, Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics (Apr. 22, 1971), pp. 215-231 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2025204 . Accessed: 12/01/2013 10:53 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded on Sat, 12 Jan 2013 10:53:17 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE JOURNALOF PHILOSOPHY VOLUME LXVIII, NO. 8, APRIL 22, I97I _ ~ ~~~~~~- ~ '- ' THE ITERATIVE CONCEPTION OF SET A SET, accordingto Cantor,is "any collection.., intoa whole of definite,well-distinguished objects... of our intuitionor thought.'1Cantor alo sdefineda set as a "many, whichcan be thoughtof as one, i.e., a totalityof definiteelements that can be combinedinto a whole by a law.'2 One mightobject to the firstdefi- nitionon the groundsthat it uses the conceptsof collectionand whole, which are notionsno betterunderstood than that of set,that there ought to be sets of objects that are not objects of our thought,that 'intuition'is a termladen with a theoryof knowledgethat no one should believe, that any object is "definite,"that there should be sets of ill-distinguishedobjects, such as waves and trains,etc., etc.
    [Show full text]
  • [The PROOF of FERMAT's LAST THEOREM] and [OTHER MATHEMATICAL MYSTERIES] the World's Most Famous Math Problem the World's Most Famous Math Problem
    0Eft- [The PROOF of FERMAT'S LAST THEOREM] and [OTHER MATHEMATICAL MYSTERIES] The World's Most Famous Math Problem The World's Most Famous Math Problem [ THE PROOF OF FERMAT'S LAST THEOREM AND OTHER MATHEMATICAL MYSTERIES I Marilyn vos Savant ST. MARTIN'S PRESS NEW YORK For permission to reprint copyrighted material, grateful acknowledgement is made to the following sources: The American Association for the Advancement of Science: Excerpts from Science, Volume 261, July 2, 1993, C 1993 by the AAAS. Reprinted by permission. Birkhauser Boston: Excerpts from The Mathematical Experience by Philip J. Davis and Reuben Hersh © 1981 Birkhauser Boston. Reprinted by permission of Birkhau- ser Boston and the authors. The Chronicleof Higher Education: Excerpts from The Chronicle of Higher Education, July 7, 1993, C) 1993 Chronicle of HigherEducation. Reprinted by permission. The New York Times: Excerpts from The New York Times, June 24, 1993, X) 1993 The New York Times. Reprinted by permission. Excerpts from The New York Times, June 29, 1993, © 1993 The New York Times. Reprinted by permission. Cody Pfanstieh/ The poem on the subject of Fermat's last theorem is reprinted cour- tesy of Cody Pfanstiehl. Karl Rubin, Ph.D.: The sketch of Dr. Wiles's proof of Fermat's Last Theorem in- cluded in the Appendix is reprinted courtesy of Karl Rubin, Ph.D. Wesley Salmon, Ph.D.: Excerpts from Zeno's Paradoxes by Wesley Salmon, editor © 1970. Reprinted by permission of the editor. Scientific American: Excerpts from "Turing Machines," by John E. Hopcroft, Scientific American, May 1984, (D 1984 Scientific American, Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • Some First-Order Probability Logics
    Theoretical Computer Science 247 (2000) 191–212 www.elsevier.com/locate/tcs View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Some ÿrst-order probability logics provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Zoran Ognjanovic a;∗, Miodrag RaÄskovic b a MatematickiÄ institut, Kneza Mihaila 35, 11000 Beograd, Yugoslavia b Prirodno-matematickiÄ fakultet, R. Domanovicaà 12, 34000 Kragujevac, Yugoslavia Received June 1998 Communicated by M. Nivat Abstract We present some ÿrst-order probability logics. The logics allow making statements such as P¿s , with the intended meaning “the probability of truthfulness of is greater than or equal to s”. We describe the corresponding probability models. We give a sound and complete inÿnitary axiomatic system for the most general of our logics, while for some restrictions of this logic we provide ÿnitary axiomatic systems. We study the decidability of our logics. We discuss some of the related papers. c 2000 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: First order logic; Probability; Possible worlds; Completeness 1. Introduction In recent years there is a growing interest in uncertainty reasoning. A part of inves- tigation concerns its formal framework – probability logics [1, 2, 5, 6, 9, 13, 15, 17–20]. Probability languages are obtained by adding probability operators of the form (in our notation) P¿s to classical languages. The probability logics allow making formulas such as P¿s , with the intended meaning “the probability of truthfulness of is greater than or equal to s”. Probability models similar to Kripke models are used to give semantics to the probability formulas so that interpreted formulas are either true or false.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cyber Entscheidungsproblem: Or Why Cyber Can’T Be Secured and What Military Forces Should Do About It
    THE CYBER ENTSCHEIDUNGSPROBLEM: OR WHY CYBER CAN’T BE SECURED AND WHAT MILITARY FORCES SHOULD DO ABOUT IT Maj F.J.A. Lauzier JCSP 41 PCEMI 41 Exercise Solo Flight Exercice Solo Flight Disclaimer Avertissement Opinions expressed remain those of the author and Les opinons exprimées n’engagent que leurs auteurs do not represent Department of National Defence or et ne reflètent aucunement des politiques du Canadian Forces policy. This paper may not be used Ministère de la Défense nationale ou des Forces without written permission. canadiennes. Ce papier ne peut être reproduit sans autorisation écrite. © Her Majesty the Queen in Right of Canada, as © Sa Majesté la Reine du Chef du Canada, représentée par represented by the Minister of National Defence, 2015. le ministre de la Défense nationale, 2015. CANADIAN FORCES COLLEGE – COLLÈGE DES FORCES CANADIENNES JCSP 41 – PCEMI 41 2014 – 2015 EXERCISE SOLO FLIGHT – EXERCICE SOLO FLIGHT THE CYBER ENTSCHEIDUNGSPROBLEM: OR WHY CYBER CAN’T BE SECURED AND WHAT MILITARY FORCES SHOULD DO ABOUT IT Maj F.J.A. Lauzier “This paper was written by a student “La présente étude a été rédigée par un attending the Canadian Forces College stagiaire du Collège des Forces in fulfilment of one of the requirements canadiennes pour satisfaire à l'une des of the Course of Studies. The paper is a exigences du cours. L'étude est un scholastic document, and thus contains document qui se rapporte au cours et facts and opinions, which the author contient donc des faits et des opinions alone considered appropriate and que seul l'auteur considère appropriés et correct for the subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Finding an Interpretation Under Which Axiom 2 of Aristotelian Syllogistic Is
    Finding an interpretation under which Axiom 2 of Aristotelian syllogistic is False and the other axioms True (ignoring Axiom 3, which is derivable from the other axioms). This will require a domain of at least two objects. In the domain {0,1} there are four ordered pairs: <0,0>, <0,1>, <1,0>, and <1,1>. Note first that Axiom 6 demands that any member of the domain not in the set assigned to E must be in the set assigned to I. Thus if the set {<0,0>} is assigned to E, then the set {<0,1>, <1,0>, <1,1>} must be assigned to I. Similarly for Axiom 7. Note secondly that Axiom 3 demands that <m,n> be a member of the set assigned to E if <n,m> is. Thus if <1,0> is a member of the set assigned to E, than <0,1> must also be a member. Similarly Axiom 5 demands that <m,n> be a member of the set assigned to I if <n,m> is a member of the set assigned to A (but not conversely). Thus if <1,0> is a member of the set assigned to A, than <0,1> must be a member of the set assigned to I. The problem now is to make Axiom 2 False without falsifying Axiom 1 as well. The solution requires some experimentation. Here is one interpretation (call it I) under which all the Axioms except Axiom 2 are True: Domain: {0,1} A: {<1,0>} E: {<0,0>, <1,1>} I: {<0,1>, <1,0>} O: {<0,0>, <0,1>, <1,1>} It’s easy to see that Axioms 4 through 7 are True under I.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hilbert's Contributions to Logical Theory
    David Hilbert’s contributions to logical theory CURTIS FRANKS 1. A mathematician’s cast of mind Charles Sanders Peirce famously declared that “no two things could be more directly opposite than the cast of mind of the logician and that of the mathematician” (Peirce 1976, p. 595), and one who would take his word for it could only ascribe to David Hilbert that mindset opposed to the thought of his contemporaries, Frege, Gentzen, Godel,¨ Heyting, Łukasiewicz, and Skolem. They were the logicians par excellence of a generation that saw Hilbert seated at the helm of German mathematical research. Of Hilbert’s numerous scientific achievements, not one properly belongs to the domain of logic. In fact several of the great logical discoveries of the 20th century revealed deep errors in Hilbert’s intuitions—exemplifying, one might say, Peirce’s bald generalization. Yet to Peirce’s addendum that “[i]t is almost inconceivable that a man should be great in both ways” (Ibid.), Hilbert stands as perhaps history’s principle counter-example. It is to Hilbert that we owe the fundamental ideas and goals (indeed, even the name) of proof theory, the first systematic development and application of the methods (even if the field would be named only half a century later) of model theory, and the statement of the first definitive problem in recursion theory. And he did more. Beyond giving shape to the various sub-disciplines of modern logic, Hilbert brought them each under the umbrella of mainstream mathematical activity, so that for the first time in history teams of researchers shared a common sense of logic’s open problems, key concepts, and central techniques.
    [Show full text]
  • Einstein and Hilbert: the Creation of General Relativity
    EINSTEIN AND HILBERT: THE CREATION OF GENERAL RELATIVITY ∗ Ivan T. Todorov Institut f¨ur Theoretische Physik, Universit¨at G¨ottingen, Friedrich-Hund-Platz 1 D-37077 G¨ottingen, Germany; e-mail: [email protected] and Institute for Nuclear Research and Nuclear Energy, Bulgarian Academy of Sciences Tsarigradsko Chaussee 72, BG-1784 Sofia, Bulgaria;∗∗e-mail: [email protected] ABSTRACT It took eight years after Einstein announced the basic physical ideas behind the relativistic gravity theory before the proper mathematical formulation of general relativity was mastered. The efforts of the greatest physicist and of the greatest mathematician of the time were involved and reached a breathtaking concentration during the last month of the work. Recent controversy, raised by a much publicized 1997 reading of Hilbert’s proof- sheets of his article of November 1915, is also discussed. arXiv:physics/0504179v1 [physics.hist-ph] 25 Apr 2005 ∗ Expanded version of a Colloquium lecture held at the International Centre for Theoretical Physics, Trieste, 9 December 1992 and (updated) at the International University Bremen, 15 March 2005. ∗∗ Permanent address. Introduction Since the supergravity fashion and especially since the birth of superstrings a new science emerged which may be called “high energy mathematical physics”. One fad changes the other each going further away from accessible experiments and into mathe- matical models, ending up, at best, with the solution of an interesting problem in pure mathematics. The realization of the grand original design seems to be, decades later, nowhere in sight. For quite some time, though, the temptation for mathematical physi- cists (including leading mathematicians) was hard to resist.
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor's Paradise Regained: Constructive Mathematics From
    Cantor's Paradise Regained: Constructive Mathematics from Brouwer to Kolmogorov to Gelfond Vladik Kreinovich Department of Computer Science University of Texas at El Paso El Paso, TX 79968 USA [email protected] Abstract. Constructive mathematics, mathematics in which the exis- tence of an object means that that we can actually construct this object, started as a heavily restricted version of mathematics, a version in which many commonly used mathematical techniques (like the Law of Excluded Middle) were forbidden to maintain constructivity. Eventually, it turned out that not only constructive mathematics is not a weakened version of the classical one { as it was originally perceived { but that, vice versa, classical mathematics can be viewed as a particular (thus, weaker) case of the constructive one. Crucial results in this direction were obtained by M. Gelfond in the 1970s. In this paper, we mention the history of these results, and show how these results affected constructive mathematics, how they led to new algorithms, and how they affected the current ac- tivity in logic programming-related research. Keywords: constructive mathematics; logic programming; algorithms Science and engineering: a brief reminder. One of the main objectives of science is to find out how the world operates, to be able to predict what will happen in the future. Science predicts the future positions of celestial bodies, the future location of a spaceship, etc. From the practical viewpoint, it is important not only to passively predict what will happen, but also to decide what to do in order to achieve certain goals. Roughly speaking, decisions of this type correspond not to science but to engineering.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice and Its Implications
    THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND ITS IMPLICATIONS KEVIN BARNUM Abstract. In this paper we will look at the Axiom of Choice and some of the various implications it has. These implications include a number of equivalent statements, and also some less accepted ideas. The proofs discussed will give us an idea of why the Axiom of Choice is so powerful, but also so controversial. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. The Axiom of Choice and Its Equivalents 1 2.1. The Axiom of Choice and its Well-known Equivalents 1 2.2. Some Other Less Well-known Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice 3 3. Applications of the Axiom of Choice 5 3.1. Equivalence Between The Axiom of Choice and the Claim that Every Vector Space has a Basis 5 3.2. Some More Applications of the Axiom of Choice 6 4. Controversial Results 10 Acknowledgments 11 References 11 1. Introduction The Axiom of Choice states that for any family of nonempty disjoint sets, there exists a set that consists of exactly one element from each element of the family. It seems strange at first that such an innocuous sounding idea can be so powerful and controversial, but it certainly is both. To understand why, we will start by looking at some statements that are equivalent to the axiom of choice. Many of these equivalences are very useful, and we devote much time to one, namely, that every vector space has a basis. We go on from there to see a few more applications of the Axiom of Choice and its equivalents, and finish by looking at some of the reasons why the Axiom of Choice is so controversial.
    [Show full text]