Changing Minds with Style∗

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Changing Minds with Style∗ Changing Minds With Style∗ Carolina Flores April 2021 Abstract People often respond to evidence in ways we don’t anticipate. This causes trouble for understanding those who respond to evidence in ways that differ from our own and for our ability to rationally engage with them. I argue that we can address these problems by seeing others’ ways of interacting with evidence in terms of epistemic style. I offer an analysis of epistemic styles as ways of respond- ing to evidence which express epistemic character, that is, a recognizable way of being an epistemic agent. I argue that we have reason to think that people take up epistemic styles in robust, though context-dependent, ways. This allows us to use models of others’ epistemic styles to predict their responses to evidence in relevant contexts, enabling us to select evidence that they are likely to find persuasive. More importantly, sensitivity to epistemic styles gives us a way of understanding those whose epistemic behavior is at odds with our own, instead of seeing their behavior as the result of irredeemable irrationality. 1 Introduction People interact with evidence in a wide range of ways. For example, evidence that persuaded you might leave others cold, or make them retrench. What to one person obviously indicates nefarious intentions, to another suggests bumbling incompetence. Where one person briskly rules out alternative explanations, another keeps them live, refusing to make up their mind. This variation in way of interacting with evidence compromises our ability toun- derstand one another, often leading us to think that others’ responses to evidence respond are due to deep irrationality. And it poses an under-noticed problem for at- tempts at rational persuasion. How are we to select evidence, and more generally, carve out a strategy of persuasion, without knowing how our interlocutors will inter- act with evidence? And how can we come to acquire this knowledge in the face of the diversity of responses we encounter? Troublingly, such problems for understanding ∗Acknowledgements: Thanks to Laura Callahan, Elisabeth Camp, Danny Forman, Alex Guerrero, Tyler John, Kelsey Laity D’Agostino, Ting-An Li, Matt McGrath, James McIntyre, Thi Nguyen, Jill North, Dee Payton, Susanna Schellenberg, Ernest Sosa, Caroline Von Klemperer, Christopher Willard-Kyle, and Elise Woodard for helpful comments on previous drafts. Thanks also to participants in the Rutgers Aesthetics Graduate Seminar for helpful discussion. 1 and rational persuasion compromise our ability to rationally deliberate, and therefore constitude a threat to central democratic practices. To address these problems, I introduce the notion of epistemic style. I analyze epis- temic styles as ways of interacting with evidence that express an epistemic character, that is, a distinctive way of being an epistemic agent. Though the notion of epis- temic style has remained under-theorized, the phenomenon is familiar: think here of the charge that American politics has come to be dominated by the “ paranoid style,” which expresses “heated exaggeration, suspiciousness, and conspiratorial fan- tasy” (Hofstadter 2012), of the distinctive ways in which analytic philosophers tend to reason, or of the rigidity of thought of which we accuse bureaucrats (Graeber 2012). I do not take these examples to be curious peculiarities. To the contrary, people take up epistemic styles in stable and predictable ways, tracking facts about social context, their goals, and their affective state, among other factors. This relative stabil- ity enables us to model others’ epistemic styles in a context, and to use such models to select effective strategies for persuasion. Perhaps more importantly, sensitivity to epistemic style furthers our understanding of others. The plan for the paper is as follows. In§2, I articulate difficulties for understand- ing and rational persuasion raised by the multiplicity of ways in which people interact with evidence, and suggest that they constitute a serious social and political problem. In §3, I develop my analysis of epistemic styles. In §4, I argue that people take up epistemic styles with enough stability to enable observers to construct adequate mod- els of others’ epistemic style. In §5, I argue that, equipped with such models, we can come to understand others’ responses to evidence and select more effective strategies of persuasion, addressing the difficulties canvassed in§2. I respond to ethical worries about sensitivity to epistemic styles in §6. 2 The Messy Reality of Interactions with Evidence There is a wide range of different ways in which one may respond to evidence.Dif- ferent people—and even one person when placed in different contexts—can and do respond to evidence different ways. This occurs even when people share the sameset of doxastic attitudes. For one, we find variation in what evidence agents find compelling. For example, some people are unlikely to change their mind based on first-hand testimony, but find statistical surveys highly persuasive, whereas others are resistant to statistical evidence, taking it to occlude crucial fine-grained aspects of human experience.¹ People also vary in what inferences they draw from the evidence. This can be due to finding different hypotheses salient (Nelson 2010). For example, noticing a child’s manual dexterity might lead their art teacher to infer that they could become a painter, while their ambitious parents infer that they would make a highly-paid sur- geon. Similarly, theoretical values—roughly, what features one takes to make for good 1. This variation can also come in degrees: some people might find statistical evidence convincing, butonly to a low extent, while for a different agent this is extremely weighty evidence. Thanks to Caroline Von Klemperer for pointing this out. 2 explanations for observations—affect what one infers from evidence (Kuhn 1977, Dou- ven 2009, Willard-Kyle 2017).² The Quinean with a preference for desert landscapes will opt for a theory with few postulates, whereas the maximalist will prefer a more complex theory that fits more data. As a result, they will come to different beliefs based on the same evidence. Such values and interests affect what one does with the evidence one receives more generally. Sometimes, we make up our minds impulsively, jumping to conclu- sions immediately. Other times, we cautiously consider many alternative hypotheses, and keep them all on the table until decisive evidence comes in. Sometimes we are comfortable with uncertainty, and able to hold in mind considerations pointing in dif- ferent directions; other times, uncertainty feels intolerable. Sometimes we carefully think through the implications of evidence we receive. Other times, we make only the most obvious adjustments in the light of evidence. All of these factors end up affecting what conclusions we draw. Further, people set their evidential thresholds—their thresholds for how much (compelling) evidence it takes to change their mind—in a wide range of different ways. For example, grit in pursuing one’s goals is often aided by resistance to evidence that points to low probability of success, mediated by high evidential thresholds for chang- ing beliefs about one’s chances of succeeding (Paul and Morton 2018). Defeatists do the opposite, taking even the smallest setback to show that they are doomed. Evi- dential thresholds can also vary globally. Some adopt a suspicious, skeptical attitude across the board and require a lot of evidence to update any of their views. At the other extreme, one may adopt a starry-eyed, omnivorous mindset and let one’s mind fluctuate with any evidence that comes one’s way. I do not mean to suggest that all these ways of interacting with evidence are ra- tional, or epistemically permissible. I am merely noting that we do, as a matter of fact, find such variation in how people interact with evidence. Plausibly, not allways of interacting with evidence are rational. It is fairly uncontroversial that some epis- temic thresholds, weightings of theoretical values, and so on result in epistemically impermissible responses to evidence.³ Beyond that, there is substantive disagreement. Proponents of uniqueness hold that, given a body of beliefs and evidence, there is precisely one rationally permissible response (White 2013, Dogramaci and Horowitz 2016, Schultheis 2018). Permissivists think that there is at least sometimes more than one permissible response, and differ as to how varied they take epistemically permissible responses to be (Douven 2009, Kelly 2013, Willard-Kyle 2017, Callahan forthcoming). Again, I am neutral on this debate: my focus here is on the descriptive claim that people respond in different ways, not on the rationality of those responses. The consequences of this diversity are far-reaching. Encountering a person who interacts with evidence in ways that are very different from your own can be a deeply disconcerting experience. Such responses can appear unintelligible. Why would someone respond in a way that is so different from our own? What could they possi- 2. Such theoretical values are not necessarily, or typically, consciously articulated. 3. Though not entirely uncontroversial: James (1979) argues that such settings are part of one’s passional life, and beyond rational assessment. One might then additionally think that the results of any such settings are epistemically permissible. 3 bly be thinking? This generates a sense of distance and alienation, and can easily lead to thinking that it is just not worth engaging with them. More specifically, finding others’ responses to evidence unintelligible easily leads to thinking they are deeply irrational—not merely that they responded to some evi- dence irrationally. Grimm (2019) labels this tendency to infer deep irrationality “judg- mentalism.” On judgmentalist views, others’ responses to evidence, where they differ from our own, are the result of their inability to reason well. From our vantage point, others appear not just to be responding irrationally (which they may or may no be), but to be irredeemably irrational.
Recommended publications
  • Pod of Jake #67 – Julia Galef Ai-Generated Transcript 1
    POD OF JAKE #67 – JULIA GALEF AI-GENERATED TRANSCRIPT Jake 00:59 Thank you so much, Julia, for taking the time and joining me on the show today. I really appreciate it and looking forward to this conversation for some time. And I've actually listened to your podcast a bunch in the past. Most recently. Yeah, your episode with metallic. So funny must be funny to be on the other side of the microphone. Yeah. But thank you for coming on, I think the best place to get started would be for those who don't know you to tell your story a little bit. And then we'll spend a lot of time talking about your book, which recently came out. Julia Galef 01:29 Sounds good. Thanks, Jake. Yes, it's good to be on the show. My story. Basically, for the last 10 years, I've just been devoted to this question of how do we improve human reasoning and decision making? And really interest in this question, both from a theoretical level? Like how do we think about what would ideal reasoning look like? Just almost philosophically, and also, just from a practical level? Like, what are the kinds of mistakes that the human brain tends to make and what kinds of situations and getting really into a lot of the cognitive science literature and kind of experimenting on real people like trying out techniques and seeing how well they work and, you know, talking to people about their experiences, noticing their own biases and things like that.
    [Show full text]
  • Volume 15, Number 2 March-April 2021
    Volume 15, Number 2 March-April 2021 thereasoner.org ISSN 1757-0522 list. (Those were “Decision Theory without Representa- Contents tion Theorems” in 2014, published in Philosophers’ Imprint, and “Dr. Truthlove or: How I Learned to Stop Worry- Guest Editorial 9 ing and Love Bayesian Probabilities” in 2015, published in Noˆus.) Anyone interested in the social epistemology of math Features 9 should know Kenny’s work too: his “Probabilistic Proofs and Transferability” (Philosophia Mathematica, 2009) and News 14 “Rebutting and Undercutting in Mathematics” (Philosophi- cal Perspectives, 2015) are classics and personal favorites. What’s Hot in . 14 Kenny and I first crossed paths Events 15 at a conference in Paris while I Courses and Programmes 15 was a grad student. He joined my dissertation committee a little Jobs and Studentships 16 after that. Fortunately, Kenny is an easy person to keep in touch with: just go to any random phi- losophy conference and there’s a 63% chance he’s there. As you’ll see from our interview, he’s a terri- bly interesting person and a credit Guest Editorial to the profession. I’m happy to of- fer you his opinions on fractal mu- Salutations, reasoners. I’m delighted to be guest editor for this sic, Zoom conferences, being a good referee, teaching in math issue, featuring an interview with the man, the myth, the leg- and philosophy, the rationalist community and its relationship end, Kenny Easwaran. Kenny is a newly-minted Professor of to academia, decision-theoretic pluralism, and the city of Man- Philosophy at Texas A&M University.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Debate on Science Issues Myths of Child Psychology
    Superbug Crisis | Ten Tactics for Skepticism | Claims of Chi | Fake Bomb Detectors the Magazine for Science and Reason Vol. 41 No. 1 | January/February 2017 Public Debate on Project Science Greenglow Issues Creationism Myths of in Europe Child Psychology Doubt and American Fears Uncertainty Survey INTRODUCTORY PRICE U.S. and Canada $5.99 Skepticism Is Nonpartisan Published by the Center for Inquiry in association with the Committee for Skeptical Inquiry Robyn E. Blumner, CEO Massimo Polidoro, Research Fellow Bar ry Karr, Ex ec u tive Di rect or Benjamin Radford, Research Fellow Joe Nickell, Senior Research Fellow Richard Wiseman, Research Fellow www.csicop.org Fellows James E. Al cock*, psy chol o gist, York Univ., Tor on to Mur ray Gell-Mann, pro fes sor of phys ics, San ta Fe In sti tute; Harvard Univ., Cambridge, MA Mar cia An gell, MD, former ed i tor-in-chief, No bel lau re ate Lor en Pan kratz, psy chol o gist, Or e gon Health New Eng land Jour nal of Med i cine Thom as Gi lov ich, psy chol o gist, Cor nell Univ. Sci en ces Univ. Kimball Atwood IV, MD, physician; author; Newton, MA David H. Gorski, cancer surgeon and re searcher at Barbara Robert L. Park, professor of physics, Univ. of Maryland Steph en Bar rett, MD, psy chi a trist; au thor; con sum er ad vo cate, Ann Kar manos Cancer Institute and chief of breast surgery Jay M. Pasachoff, Field Memorial Professor of Al len town, PA section, Wayne State University School of Medicine.
    [Show full text]
  • NYC Skeptics ( Is an All-Volunteer, 501(C)3 Nonprofit That Promotes Critical Thinking, Science Education, and Skeptical Inquiry
    “If you’re thinking of starting a local organization, New York City Skeptics is a fine example of how to do it right.” – James Randi ABOUT NEW YORK CITY SKEPTICS NYC Skeptics (www.nycskeptics.org) is an all-volunteer, 501(c)3 nonprofit that promotes critical thinking, science education, and skeptical inquiry. Our activities and events include the following: • Our Public Lecture Series hosts speakers from the scientific and skeptical worlds including James Randi, John Rennie, Carl Zimmer, Massimo Pigliucci, Michael Shermer, and Richard Wiseman. • We sponsor the annual Northeast Conference on Science and Skepticism (NECSS) (www.necss.org), and NYC Skeptics members receive discount on conference registration. • We sponsor the New York City chapters of Drinking Skeptically, an annual Darwin Day Celebration, and SkeptiCampNYC. • We produce the Rationally Speaking podcast (www.rationallyspeakingpodcast.org) hosted by Massimo Pigliucci and Julia Galef. JOIN NEW YORK CITY SKEPTICS TODAY! Membership is available at the following levels and includes a special thank you gift. Thank you for your support! $35 Student $50 Friend $100 Supporter $250 Associate $500 Gotham Skeptic $1000 Randi Club Other amount _____________________ Payment method: Cash Check Credit card (please circle): Visa MasterCard Discover Amex Credit card # ____________________________________ Exp. date (mm/yy) _______ CSC code_______ Name on card ___________________________________ Signature_______________________________ Billing address_______________________________________________ City_______________________ State __________________ Zip code_______________ E-mail _________________________________ Shipping address (if different) _______________________________________________________________ City ______________________________ State_____________________ Zip code__________________ • Please make checks payable to “New York City Skeptics” and mail to: New York City Skeptics, PO Box 5122 NY, NY 10185. • Please allow 4-6 weeks to process your membership.
    [Show full text]
  • Julia Galef: Welcome to Rationally Speaking, the Podcast Where We Explore the Borderlands Between Reason and Nonsense
    Rationally Speaking #181: Will MacAskill on “Moral Uncertainty” Julia Galef: Welcome to Rationally Speaking, the podcast where we explore the borderlands between reason and nonsense. I'm your host, Julia Galef, and with me today is my good friend and today's guest, Will MacAskill. Will is probably most famous worldwide for helping create and popularize the effective altruism movement, which I've talked about in several past episodes of the podcast. He co-founded and is the CEO of the Center for Effective Altruism, and is the author of the book Doing Good Better. But today we're not going to be talking about effective altruism, at least not primarily. We're going to be talking about Will's work in philosophy. Oh, I didn't mention in my list of Will's achievements that he's also ... When he became a tenured professor of philosophy at Oxford, he was the youngest person in the world to be a tenured professor of philosophy. We're going to be talking about Will's main research focus in philosophy, which is moral uncertainty. This is a topic that's on my list, at least, of philosophical questions that I think are meaningful, and real, and important to actual real-life decision-making -- and that are unresolved, but that I feel like we might potentially be able to make progress on. This is not a long list of topics, but moral uncertainty is on it. Will, welcome to the show. Will MacAskill: Thanks so much for having me on. Julia Galef: I can't believe I haven't had you on sooner.
    [Show full text]
  • CFI Calls on FDA to Label Homeopathic Drugs As Untested and Unproven
    [ NEWS AND COMMENT CFI Calls on FDA to Label Homeopathic Drugs as Untested and Unproven Consumers spend $3 billion a year on homeopathic drugs, yet most remain unaware that the Food and Drug Administration (FDA) has not evalu- ated them for safety and effectiveness. In comments filed with the FDA the week of August 17, the Center for Inquiry (CFI) urged the FDA to sub- ject homeopathic drugs to the same testing requirements as conventional drugs. Failing that, CFI urged the FDA to at least require homeopathic prod- ucts to be clearly labeled as untested and unproven. Homeopathy is a centuries-old pseudoscience, developed before the discovery of disease-causing pathogens, based on the false beliefs that “like cures like” and that the more an ingredient is diluted the more potent it is, due to water’s “memory” of the diluted ingre- for not distinguishing between effec- tive remedies and pseudoscience Homeopathy is a centuries-old dient. As CFI stated in its comments, from the 1700s if both products “By its own definition, homeopathy share the same store shelves, and pseudoscience, developed cannot work.” Yet for historical reasons there is no labeling on homeopathic relating to the passage of the original drugs to indicate they are given a before the discovery of Food, Drug, and Cosmetic Act in 1938 pass by the FDA. Clear labeling on disease-causing pathogens. (which had a homeopathic practitioner homeopathic products, that catches consumers’ attention and informs as a key sponsor), homeopathic prod- them that the FDA does not evalu- can result in people becoming sicker or ucts can be marketed even though they ate these products for safety or effec- even dying for lack of real, scientifically are not subject to the rigorous testing tiveness, is an easy way to ensure that for safety and effectiveness that conven- people looking to treat their illnesses proven treatments.
    [Show full text]
  • Singularity Summit 2011 Workshop Report
    MIRI MACHINE INTELLIGENCE RESEARCH INSTITUTE Singularity Summit 2011 Workshop Report Anna Salamon, Luke Muehlhauser Machine Intelligence Research Institute Salamon, Anna, and Luke Muehlhauser. 2012. Singularity Summit 2011 Workshop Report. Technical Report, 2012-1. The Singularity Institute, San Francisco, CA. The Machine Intelligence Research Institute was previously known as the Singularity Institute. Anna Salamon, Luke Muehlhauser Workshop Participants Anna Salamon (organizer) Researcher, Singularity Institute Luke Muehlhauser (organizer) Researcher, Singularity Institute Seth Baum Graduate student, Pennsylvania State University Nick Beckstead Graduate student, Rutgers University David Brin Author and futurist David Chalmers Philosopher, Australian National University Paul Christiano Graduate student, MIT Kevin Fischer Entrepreneur Alexander Funcke Owner, Zelta Deta Julia Galef Science writer Phil Goetz Researcher, J. Craig Venter Institute Katja Grace Graduate student, Carnegie Mellon University Robin Hanson Economist, George Mason University Louie Helm Director of Development, Singularity Institute Jey Kottalam Entrepreneur Nathan Labenz Co-founder, Stik.com Zvi Mowshowitz Co-founder, Variance Luke Nosek Co-founder, Paypal Carl Shulman Researcher, Singularity Institute Tim Sullivan Co-founder, CO2Stats Jaan Tallinn Co-founder, Skype Michael Vassar President, Singularity Institute Alexander Wissner-Gross Research Affiliate, MIT Media Lab Eliezer Yudkowsky Researcher, Singularity Institute Executive Summary The Singularity Summit 2011
    [Show full text]
  • How to Run a Successful Less Wrong Meetup Group
    How to Run a Successful Less Wrong Meetup Group Tips and tricks for starting, running, and growing a successful Less Wrong meetup group by Kaj Sotala and Luke Muehlhauser Acknowledgements Our thanks to Alex Demarsh, Alexey Morgunov, Axel Glibert, Benjamin Noble, Bill McGrath, Danny Hintze, David Perry, Hermione Davies, Erica Edelman, Julia Galef, Julian Pulgarin, Nisan Stiennon, Sam Bhagwat, William Ryan and Zvi Mowshowitz, as well as everyone else who is quoted in this document or who has commented in the feedback threads on Less Wrong. Special thanks to Stanislaw Boboryk, who created the design for this document. How to Use This Document This document is written for anyone who wants to organize a Less Wrong meetup. We have written most sections so that they can help you whether you want to start a new group or improve an existing group. Do you have additional suggestions? Are you encountering problems not solved by the advice in this document? Please contact [email protected] — we will incorporate your feedback and try to solve your problems with the next version of this document. II Contents: Why Organize a Meetup? 1 Getting help 1 Announcing and Organize Your Meetups 1 Choosing avenue 1 Making the announcement 2 The first meetup 3 Beyond the first meetup 3 Pioneering new meetups 4 Restarting dead or inactive groups 5 How to build your team of heroes 6 The organizer 7 The welcomer 7 The learning coach 7 Content providers 7 The visionary 7 The networker 8 Retain members by being a social group 8 Long-term Meetup Group Maintenance
    [Show full text]
  • In Silicon Valley by Sam Frank
    Cockburn and Gray: u Exhuming u Daniel Mendelsohn: A New Cold War? Pablo Neruda Down on Downton HARPER’S MAGAZINE/JANUARY 2015 $6.99 POWER AND PARANOIA IN SILICON VALLEY BY SAM FRANK u LOVE CRIMES What Liberation Looks Like for Afghan Women BY JEN PERCY THE PROBLEM OF PAIN MANAGEMENT The Makers of OxyContin Play Dirty BY JOnaH CamPBELL anD SIMON LIEM REPORT COME WITH US IF YOU WANT TO LIVE Among the apocalyptic libertarians of Silicon Valley By Sam Frank ust by a quick show user input; in Neal Ste- “ofJ hands, has anyone phenson’s science-fiction heard of a D.A.O. or an novel Snow Crash, hu- agent before?” asked mans interact with one Jonathan Mohan. He another and with intel- was in his mid-twenties ligent agents within and wore a beige the more-than-virtual- Bitcoin T-shirt. As if to reality Metaverse. scratch my head, I half- “Imagine if you wrote way raised my right some program that arm. A dozen others could render a service, raced up past mine. and it generated enough Forty or fifty of us of a profit that it could were in a glass-walled cover its own costs. It coworking space at could perpetuate indefi- 23rd Street and Park nitely . because it’s just Avenue in Manhattan, the code running itself.” at a Meetup for a tech- “How much Skynet nology called Ethere- risk is there?” a young um. Invented by a man asked Mohan, us- nineteen-year-old Rus- ing sci-fi shorthand: sian Canadian named Could a few lines of Vitalik Buterin, and open-source code, still unreleased and un- meant to augment hu- der development on the man autonomy by obvi- day of the Meetup, in ating opaque institu- February 2014, Ethere- tions like Goldman um is intended to decentralize control “Effectively, what a D.A.O.
    [Show full text]
  • Julia Galef: Welcome to Rationally Speaking, the Podcast Where We Explore the Borderlands Between Reason and Nonsense
    Rationally Speaking #240: David Manheim on “Goodhart’s Law and how metrics fail” Julia Galef: Welcome to Rationally Speaking, the podcast where we explore the borderlands between reason and nonsense. I'm your host, Julia Galef, and my guest today is David Manheim. David is a decision theorist with a PhD in public policy from Pardee Rand Graduate School. And one of the topics that David has studied and written a lot about over the years, in blog posts and academic articles alike, is a principle called Goodhart's law. It's in that small set of deceptively simple principles that once you understand it, kind of explains so much of what's wrong with the world. So Goodhart's law, you might have heard it stated as “When a measure becomes a target, it ceases to be a good measure.” We're going to talk today about what that means, how Goodhart's law shows up and and kind of the dynamics of how it works. So David, welcome to Rationally Speaking. David Manheim: Thanks. I'm excited to be here. Julia Galef: I'm curious how you got interested in Goodhart's law in the first place, and specifically whether it was more like, seeing how consequential this law is to education and healthcare and policy and business and things like that, in the real world? Versus the kind of mathematician’s, “Wow, what an intellectually interesting set of dynamics for me to puzzle over”? David Manheim: So it's interesting. It was kind of a weird path.
    [Show full text]
  • Progress Report
    PROGRESS 2016 REPORT Message from the President and CEO This aptly named Progress Report gives you a sense of the Cen- CFI’s efforts to stand up for secular people here and abroad were ter for Inquiry’s incredible ambition and range of endeavors to particularly active in 2016. As a multi-year project, we have been promote reason and science. From our two flagship magazines, Free challenging the exclusion of secular celebrants from those who Inquiry and Skeptical Inquirer, to our work defending secular activists may solemnize marriages. In too many states, religious leaders are around the world at the United Nations Human Rights Council, automatically given the right to solemnize marriages alongside cer- CFI is working to bring the values of the Enlightenment—critical tain public officials, while secular celebrants are excluded. In 2014 thinking, scientific literacy, humanism, and individual freedom—to we won a lawsuit against Indiana’s exclusion, and just at the start the 21st century. of 2017, we heard the good news that an Illinois judge opened the way for secular celebrants there as well. The big news for CFI is that we have formally merged with the Richard Dawkins Foundation for Reason & Science (RDFRS). Another notable CFI victory was the crackdown by the Federal Throughout 2016, the two organizations worked hand-in-glove. Trade Commission on the marketing of homeopathy, something Now, we are one, with RDFRS becoming a division of CFI, CFI had urged in formal testimony. Hopefully this will put a dent and the RDFRS board, including Richard Dawkins, joining the in the $3 billion a year that Americans spend on this consumer CFI board.
    [Show full text]
  • Intellectual Honesty, Cryptocurrency, & More (Vitalik Buterin) Julia Galef
    #253: Intellectual honesty, cryptocurrency, & more (Vitalik Buterin) Julia Galef: Welcome to Rationally Speaking, the podcast where we explore the borderlands between reason and nonsense. I’m your host, Julia Galef, and today’s guest is Vitalik Buterin, the creator of Ethereum, an open source blockchain platform, and its corresponding currency Ether, which is the second biggest cryptocurrency in the world after Bitcoin. Vitalik came up with Ethereum eight years ago, when he was 19, and the year before that he co-founded Bitcoin Magazine, the oldest publication devoted to cryptocurrencies. But the reason I started following Vitalik a few years ago, and reading his blog is because he’s also a really sharp and insightful thinker about politics, economics, rationality, how to improve the world. And even though I’m not that into crypto myself, I came to really enjoy reading Vitalik’s public communications as a leader of Ethereum because – as we talk about in our conversation – I find his leadership style refreshingly nuanced and intellectually honest. So that is one of a wide range of things we talk about in this episode and I hope you enjoy it! Here is my conversation with Vitalik Buterin. [musical interlude] Julia Galef: Well, Vitalik, let's start by talking about your most recent blog post, which is about something I've been personally very interested in recently. That is: Why prediction markets seemed kind of disappointingly irrational in predicting the results of the last election. Could you just summarize what the irrational behavior was? What is the mystery in need of an explanation here? Vitalik Buterin: Sure.
    [Show full text]