Tim W. E. Maudlin Curriculum Vitae

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Tim W. E. Maudlin Curriculum Vitae Tim W. E. Maudlin curriculum vitae Dep't of Philosophy 38 Cameron Ct. Davison Hall Princeton, NJ 08540 Douglass College Rutgers University New Brunswick, NJ 08903 (732) 932-9861 (609) 430-9152 Education 1986 Ph.D., University of Pittsburgh, History & Philosophy of Science 1982 M.A., University of Pittsburgh, History & Philosophy of Science 1980 B.A., Yale University, Physics & Philosophy 1976 Diploma, The Sidwell Friends School, Washington DC Employment and Teaching Experience 1996- present Professor, Rutgers University 1996 Visiting Associate Professor, Harvard University 1992- 96 Associate Professor, Rutgers University 1986-92 Assistant Professor, Rutgers University 1985-86 Visiting Lecturer, Carnegie-Mellon University 1984-85 Teaching Fellow, University of Pittsburgh 1982-83 Teaching Fellow, University of Pittsburgh Academic Awards, Honors, and Fellowships 1992 Rutgers University Board of Trustees Research Fellowship for Scholarly Excellence 1992 NEH Summer Stipend to complete book manuscript Quantum Non-Locality and Relativity 1989 Invited participant, Sixty-two Years of Uncertainty: Historical, Philosophical and Physics Inquiries into the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics , International School of History of Science,Ettore Majorana Centre for Scientific Culture, Erice, Italy 1988 Participant in National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Institute on Aristotle's Metaphysics, Biology and Ethics 1986-88 Henry Rutgers Research Fellowship, Rutgers University 1984 Apple for the Teacher Award, College of General Studies, University of Pittsburgh 1980 B.A. awarded Summa Cum Laude and with honors in Physics and Philosophy 1979 Elected to Phi Beta Kappa Areas of Specialization Philosophy of Science, especially Physics; Metaphysics; Ancient Philosophy Areas of Competence 17th & 18th Century Philosophy; Logic; History of Science Publications Books Quantum Non-Locality and Relativity: Metaphysical Intimations of Modern Physics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell (1994); Second Edition, 2002 Truth and Paradox: Solving the Riddles; Oxford University Press, 2004 The Metaphysics Within Physics Under contract to Oxford University Press Articles "Causes, Counterfactuals and the Third Factor", forthcoming in Causes and Counterfactuals edited by N. Hall, L. Paul and J. Collins, MIT Press, June 2004 “Thoroughly Muddled McTaggart or How to Abuse Gauge freedom to Generate Metaphysical Monstrosities” Philosopher’s Imprint, vol. 2, #4 August 2002 <www.philosophersimprint.org/002004> “Distilling Metaphysics from Quantum Physics”, The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, edited by Michael Loux and Dean Zimmerman, Oxford University Press, 2003, pp. 461-487 “The Tale of Quantum Logic”, forthcoming in a book on the philosophy of Hilary Putnam edited by Yemima Ben Menahem, Cambridge University Press “Time Travel and Modern Physics” (With Frank Arntzenius), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://plato.stanford.edu), republished in Time, Reality and Experience edited by C. Callender, Cambridge University Press, 2002 “Remarks on the Passing of Time”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society volume CII (part 3)., pp. 237- 252 "Dickson on Quantum Chance and Non-locality", , British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51, December 2001, pp. 875-882 "Interpreting Probabilities: What's interference got to do with it?", in Chance in Physics, edited by J. Bricmont, D. Dürr, M.C. Galvotti, G. Ghiardi, F. Petruccione, and N. Zanghi, Springer-Verlag Heidleberg 2001 "The Element of Surprise: Novelty and Realism" (critical notice of Jarrett Leplin's A Novel Defense of Scientific Realism) Philosophical Books 1999, pp. 81-86 "Discussion: Healey on the Aharonov-Bohm Effect", Philosophy of Science 65 #2 (June 1998) pp. 361-368 "Part and Whole in Quantum Mechanics" in Interpreting Bodies: Classical and Quantum Objects in Modern Physics, E. Castellani ed., (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998), pp. 46-60 "Descrying the World in the Wavefunction" The Monist 80, pp. 2-23 (January 1997) "On the Impossibility of Lewis's Modal Realism" Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74, pp. 669-682 (December 1996) "On the Unification of Physics" Journal of Philosophy 93, pp. 129-144 (March 1996) "Kuhn édenté: incommensurabilité et choix entre théories" (Kuhn Defanged: Incommensuarability and Theory Choice) Revue Philosophique de Louvain 94, pp. 428-446 (August, 1996) "Space-Time in the Quantum World", in Bohmian Mechanics and Quantum Theory: An Appraisal, J. Cushing, A. Fine and S. Goldstein eds. (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1996) pp. 285-307 "Between the Motion and the Act….” Psyche 2:40-51 "Why Bohm's Theory Solves the Measurement Problem" Philosophy of Science 62, pp. 479-483 (September, 1995) "Three Measurement Problems" Topoi 14 , pp. 7-15 (March 1995) "The Irrelevance of Incommensurability", Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 26, pp. 113-120 (February, 1995) "The Unbuttoned Empiricist: van Fraassen Speculates on the Quantum World" (critical notice of Quantum Mechanics: An Empiricist View), Philosophical Books 35, pp. 94-101 (April 1994) "Buckets of Water and Waves of Space: Why Space-Time is Probably a Substance", Philosophy of Science 60, pp. 183-203 (June 1993) "Bell's Inequality, Information Transmission and Prism Models", In D. Hull, M. Forbes, and K. Okruhlik (eds) PSA 1992, vol. 1, East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 404-17 "Time Travel and Topology", Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association Meeting, 1990, vol. 1, pp. 304-15 "Substances and Space-Time: What Aristotle Would Have Said to Einstein", Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science Vol. 21, No. 4, pp. 531-561 (also published in Biologie, Logique et Metaphysique chez Aristote, (ed. D. Devereux and P. Pellgrin) Paris: editions du CNRS, 1990) "Computation and Consciousness", Journal of Philosophy 86, pp. 407-432 "A Model of Classical Space-Times", The Physics Teacher 27, no. 7, pp. 540-544 "The Essence of Space-Time", Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association Meetings, 1988, vol. 2, pp. 82-91 "Keeping Body and Soul Together: the Z.3 Puzzle and the Unity of Substances", The Dayton Review 19, no. 3, Winter 1988-89, pp. 121-133 (This is the first section of "Substances and Space-Time", listed above. "The Structure of Skepticism", Ancient Philosophy VI, pp. 177-193 "De Anima 3.1: Is Any Sense Missing?", Phronesis XXXI.1, pp. 51-67 Reviews Review of David Bohm and Basil Hiley's The Undivided Universe, Philosophical Books 36, pp. 281-83 (October 1995) Review of James Cushing's Quantum Mechanics: Historical Contingency and the Copenhagen Interpretation, American Journal of Physics 63, pp. 1155-56 (December 1995) Review of Lawrence Sklar's Physics and Chance and Philosophy of Physics, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46, pp. 145-49 (March 1995) Review of Nancy Cartwright's Nature's Capacities and their Measurement, Journal of Philosophy XC, pp. 599-603 (November 1993) Review of David Armstrong's A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility , Philosophy of Science 59, pp. 716- 718 (December 1992) Review of Deborah Modrak's Aristotle: The Power of Perception , The Philosophical Review , XCIX, no. 2, pp. 305-309 Works in Progress “Two Problems About Evaporating Black Holes” “Grading, Sorting, and the Sorites” Articles on Relativity, Quantum Theory, Gauge Theory, Non-Locality, and Bell’s Theorem for The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Presentations and Papers Read “On the Passing of Time” , Sydney, Australia, July 2004 Workshop presentations on the interpretation of quantum theory and non-loacality, Urbino Italy, July 2004 “Suggestions from Physics for Deep Metaphysics”, invited lecture, Society for Exact Philosophy, College Park Maryland, May 2004 “On the Passing of Time” University of Maryland, May 2004 “Two Problems About Evaporating Black Holes”, University of California, San Diego, June 2003 “On the Passing of Time”, The Einstein Forum, Potsdam, Germany, May 2003 “Logic and the Liar Paradox”, NYU, April 2003 “On the Albertian Demon” March 2003, Columbia University Participant in episode of No Dogs and Philosophers Allowed on the interpretation of quantum mechanics, recorded February 2003, aired beginning in September 2003 “On the Passing of Time”, Philosophy of Time Society, APA, Philadelphia, December 2002 “Logic and Liar Paradox”, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, September 2002 “Remarks on the Passing of Time”, The Aristotelian Society, London, June, 2002 "Suggestions from Physics for Deep Metaphysics", MIT, April 2001 "Suggestions from Physics for Deep Metaphysics", CUNY, March 2001 "The Character of Chaos", invited presentation, APA Eastern Division Meetings, New York, December 2000 "Suggestions from Physics for Deep Metaphysics", University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, October 2000 Organizer and participant in roundtable discussion on Philosophy of Probability, Chance in Physics: Foundations and Perspectives, Nov.-Dec. 1999, Naples, Italy "What Physics Can Teach Metaphysics", William Patterson University, October 1999 "Science, Pseudoscience, and Religion", Bergen County Community College, October 1999 Descrying the World in the Wave-Function", Columbia University, November 1998 "From Physics to Metaphysics", Johns Hopkins, October 1998 "Descrying the World in the Wave-Function", Conference on the Metaphysics of Quantum Theory, Rutgers, April 1998 "The Problem of Quantum Gravity", Dep't of Mathematics, Rutgers, February 1998 "Why Be Humean?", University of Minnesota, January 1998 "The Real Problems of Quantum Mechanics", Emory University, October 1997 "Solving the
Recommended publications
  • Here’S No Speed of Light, So What the Heck Did Michelson Measure?” “What the Humean Should Say About Quantities: a Reply to Bricker”
    Hellems Building, Office 282 [email protected] CU Boulder, Dept of Philosophy (215)-262-3126 Boulder, CO 80309 www.zrperry.com Zee R. Perry curriculum vitae Employment 2018–present Center Visiting Scholar Center for the Study of Origins, University of Colorado, Boulder 2018–present Visiting Instructor Department of Philosophy, University of Colorado, Boulder 2016–2018 Andrew W. Mellon Foundation Postdoctoral Associate Department of Philosophy, Rutgers University, New Brunswick Education 2009–2016 Ph.D. in Philosophy, New York University. Dissertation: Physical Quantities: Mereology and Dynamics Committee: Tim Maudlin (chair), Cian Dorr, Hartry Field, Shamik Dasgupta (ex- ternal, Princeton) 2007–2009 B.A. in Philosophy, Rutgers University Summa Cum Laude. 2005–2007 Moravian College Areas of Specialization Metaphysics, Philosophy of Physics Areas of Competence Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Art, Logic Fellowships and Awards Summer Early Career Researcher Visiting Fellowship, ANU School of Philosophy and Centre 2019 for the Philosophy of the Sciences 2018–present Visiting Scholarship Award (Project: Origins of Measurement), Center for the Study of Origins, CU Boulder 2015–2016 Mellon Dissertation Fellowship, NYU 2015 Student Senator’s Council Conference Funding Travel Award, NYU 2015 Outstanding Teaching Award, NYU 2014 Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Dean’s Student Travel Grant, NYU 2009–2014 MacCracken Fellowship, NYU 1 Publications 2017 “How to be a Substantivalist Without Getting Shifty About It”. Philosophical Issues: Metaphysics. 27, (1). (2017). http://philpapers.org/rec/PERHTB 2017 “What the Humean Should Say about Entanglement” (with Harjit Bhogal). Noûs. 51, (1). (2017). http://philpapers.org/rec/BHOWTH 2015 “Properly Extensive Quantities”. Philosophy of Science. University of Chicago Press.
    [Show full text]
  • Paradox Regained? a Brief Comment on Maudlin on Black Hole Information Loss
    (Information) Paradox Regained? A Brief Comment on Maudlin on Black Hole Information Loss JB Manchak, James Owen Weatherall Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science University of California, Irvine Abstract We discuss some recent work by Tim Maudlin concerning Black Hole Information Loss. We argue, contra Maudlin, that there is a paradox, in the straightforward sense that there are propositions that appear true, but which are incompatible with one another. We discuss the significance of the paradox and Maudlin's response to it. Keywords: Black holes; Information loss paradox; Kodama-Wald theorem; evaporation event; Global hyperbolicity The black hole information loss paradox (Hawking, 1976) is a widely discussed (putative) puzzle that arises when one attempts to make sense of physicists' expectation that global quantum dynamics will be unitary in light of the postulated phenomenon of black hole evaporation (Hawking, 1974, 1975; Unruh, 1976), which is apparently a consequence of Hawking radiation.1 In a provocative recent manuscript, Tim Maudlin (2017) forcefully argues that \There is no `information loss' paradox." The \solution" to the \paradox", he claims, requires no new physics and indeed, was already available, though not appreciated, in 1975. The appearance of paradox arises only because of persistent errors, both mathematical and conceptual in character, by prominent members of the physics community. There is much to admire in Maudlin's treatment of the subject. We agree, for instance, with his discussion of the (non-)role of \information" in the putative paradox. What is really at issue is predictability, or even better, retrodictability, and not information (at least in the sense of information theory): as we will describe in more detail below, the puzzle concerns whether any specification of data on a particular surface is sufficient to retrodict the physical process by which that data came about.
    [Show full text]
  • II Physical Geometry and Fundamental Metaphysics
    ! 1 II Physical Geometry and Fundamental Metaphysics CIAN DORR Final version: Thursday, 16 September 2010 I. Tim Maudlin’s project sets a new standard for fruitful engagement between philosophy, mathematics and physics. I am glad to have a chance to be part of the conversation. I think we can usefully distinguish two different strands within the project: one more conceptual, the other more straightforwardly metaphysical. The conceptual strand is an attempt to clarify certain concepts, such as continuity, connectedness, and boundary, which are standardly analysed in terms of the topological concept of an open set. The metaphysical strand is a defence of a hypothesis about the geometric aspects of the fun- damental structure of reality—the facts in virtue of which the facts of physical geometry are what they are. What I have to say mostly concerns the metaphysical side of things. But I will begin by saying just a little bit about the conceptual strand. II. In topology textbooks, expressions like ‘continuous function’, ‘connected set of points’, and ‘boundary of a set of points’ are generally given stipulative definitions, on a par with the definitions of made-up words like ‘Hausdorff’ (the adjective) and ‘paracompact’. But as Maudlin emphasises, the former expressions can be used to express concepts of which we have enough of an independent grip to make it reasonable to wonder whether the topological definitions are even extensionally adequate. And he argues quite persuasively that we have no reason to believe that they are. The most important and general argu- ment concerns the live epistemic possibility that physical space is discrete, for example by ! 2 containing only finitely many points.
    [Show full text]
  • Credence—And Chance—Without Numbers (And with the Euclidean Property)
    Credence—and Chance—Without Numbers (and with the Euclidean Property) Tim Maudlin NYU and John Bell Institute Abstract Accounts of both rational credence and of objective chance have always confronted difficulties associated with events that are assigned “probability zero” by the usual Kolmogorov probability function used to model the situation. One sort of solution recommends extending the number field used to represent credences and chance to the surreals or hyperreals. But the correct solution—the solution that always respects the Euclidean property—is to eliminate numbers from the fundamental representation of credence and chance altogether in favor of a system of relations. This solution also sheds light on other paradoxes, such as the Banach-Tarski paradox and the St. Petersburg paradox. The Problem (?) Suppose that an infinitely sharp dart is thrown at a circular dartboard in such a way that each individual point might be hit: nothing would prevent the dart from landing there. In other words, suppose that a point is randomly chosen from a disk in such a way that every point might be chosen. Let two of these points be labeled p and q. Here are some propositions about credence and chance that every rational person should accept. First, the proposition that either p or q will be chosen is strictly more credible—more rationally believable—than the proposition that p will be hit. If someone did not believe the former more firmly or to a higher degree than the latter then we would have no idea how to make sense of their state of belief. We can illustrate our bewilderment by appeal to practical rationality.
    [Show full text]
  • Lawrence Sklar
    LAWRENCE SKLAR Born: June 25, 1938 in Baltimore, MD Married to: Elizabeth S. Sklar; one child Education Oberlin College, B.A., 1958 Princeton University, M.A., 1960; Ph.D., 1964 Fellowships, Awards and National Offices Held Undergraduate Ford Foundation Early Admission Scholarship Honors List (all years) Phi Beta Kappa (elected in junior year) Sigma Xi (associate member) Graduate Woodrow Wilson Fellowship, 1959-60 Chancellor Green Fellowship, 1960-61 Charlotte Elizabeth Proctor Advanced Fellowship (awarded to top ten students in third year graduate class), 1961-62 National Science Foundation Cooperative Fellowship, 1962-63 Post-Graduate American Council of Learned Societies Study Fellowship (held at Oxford University), 1965-66 John Simon Guggenheim Memorial Foundation Fellowship, 1974-75 Franklin J. Matchette Prize. Awarded by the American Philosophical Association to Space, Time, and Spacetime as outstanding philosophical book of 1973 and 1974 National Science Foundation Research Grants, 1977-78, 1979-80, 1982, 1984-85, 1986-87, 1988-89, 1998-2001, 2002-03 Rackham Foundation Summer Research Fellowship, 1983, 1994 2 Nelson Fellow, Philosophy Department, University of Michigan, l991-l994, 1995- James B. and Grace J. Nelson Professorship, Philosophy Department, University of Michigan, 1994-95 National Endowment for the Humanities Fellowship, 1995-96 Faculty Recognition Award, University of Michigan, 1995-98 William K. Frankena Collegiate Professorship, University of Michigan, 1995-2002 Lakatos Award. Awarded to Physics and Chance as outstanding book in the philosophy of science for 1995. Physics and Chance selected by Choice Magazine as Outstanding Academic Book in philosophy of science for 1995 Fellow, American Academy of Arts and Sciences John Locke Lectureship in Philosophy, 1998, Oxford University Visiting Fellowship, All Souls College, Oxford University, 1998 Michigan Humanities Award, 1998-99.
    [Show full text]
  • The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
    The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Fundamentality and Time's Arrow Christian Loew (University
    Fundamentality and Time’s Arrow Christian Loew (University of Luxembourg, University of Cologne) ABSTRACT. The distribution of matter in our universe is strikingly time asymmetric. Most famously, the Second Law of Thermodynamics says that entropy tends to increase toward the future but not toward the past. But what explains this time-asymmetric distribution of matter? In this paper, I explore the idea that time itself has a direction by drawing from recent work on grounding and metaphysical fundamentality. I will argue that positing such a direction of time, in addition to time-asymmetric boundary conditions (such as the so-called “past hypothesis”), enables a better explanation of the thermodynamic asymmetry than is available otherwise. Contact Information. Université du Luxembourg, Maison des Sciences Humaines; 11, Porte des Sciences; L-4366 Esch-sur-Alzette. Email: [email protected] Acknowledgments. I am grateful to Eddy Keming Chen, Florian Fischer, Roman Frigg, Richard Healey, Andreas Hüttemann, David Glick, Marc Lange, Tim Maudlin, Carlo Rovelli, and two anonymous referees for this journal for their helpful comments and suggestions. Special thanks to Siegfried Jaag for helpful discussion and for comments on earlier drafts of this paper. 1 §1 Introduction The distribution of matter in our universe is strikingly time asymmetric. Most famously, the Second Law of Thermodynamic says that entropy tends to increase toward the future but not toward the past. But what explains this time-asymmetric distribution of matter? The received understanding in the philosophy of physics is that the thermodynamic asymmetry is fully explicable from time-asymmetric boundary conditions, including the low entropy of the early universe (see, e.g., Albert 2015 and Loewer 2012).
    [Show full text]
  • The Logic of Consistent Histories: a Reply to Maudlin
    The Logic of Consistent Histories: A Reply to Maudlin Robert B. Griffiths∗ Department of Physics, Carnegie-Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA 15213, USA Version of 26 September 2011 Abstract The relationship between quantum logic, standard propositional logic, and the (consistent) histories rules for quantum reasoning is discussed. It is shown that Maudlin’s claim [1], that the histories ap- proach is inconsistent, is incorrect. The histories approach is both internally consistent and adequate for discussing the physical situations considered by Maudlin. Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Logic and Quantum Mechanics 2 2.1 Propositional logic . ....... 2 2.2 QuantumLogic...................................... ...... 2 2.3 Histories Logic and Its Consistency . ........... 2 2.4 RoleofLogicinQuantumTheory . .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. ....... 3 3 Spins Prepared in Boxes 3 4 GHZ Paradox 4 5 Conclusion 5 1 Introduction The argument for the locality of quantum mechanics in [2] based on the (“consistent” or “decoherent”) histories interpretation has been criticized by Maudlin [1] who claims that the histories approach is inconsis- arXiv:1110.0974v1 [quant-ph] 5 Oct 2011 tent. It will be shown here that Maudlin’s arguments are incorrect: the histories approach is both internally consistent as a form of quantum logic, and also an appropriate tool for consistently analyzing the two specific physical situations mentioned in [1]. Naturally, a system of reasoning that is internally consistent may not be appropriate or adequate when applied to a particular problem, and it could be that Maudlin’s complaint about inconsistency is really about, or perhaps includes, something which might better be called inadequacy. In what follows some attempt will be made to address adequacy along with consistency in the narrower sense, though the emphasis will be on the latter.
    [Show full text]
  • Tim W. E. Maudlin Curriculum Vitae
    Tim W. E. Maudlin curriculum vitae Dep't of Philosophy Davison Hall Douglass College Rutgers University New Brunswick, NJ 08903 (732) 932-9861 Education 1986 Ph.D., University of Pittsburgh, History & Philosophy of Science 1982 M.A., University of Pittsburgh, History & Philosophy of Science 1980 B.A., Yale University, Physics & Philosophy 1976 Diploma, The Sidwell Friends School, Washington DC Employment and Teaching Experience 2005- present Professor II, Rutgers University 1996-2005 Professor, Rutgers University 1996 Visiting Associate Professor, Harvard University 1992- 96 Associate Professor, Rutgers University 1986-92 Assistant Professor, Rutgers University 1985-86 Visiting Lecturer, Carnegie-Mellon University 1984-85 Teaching Fellow, University of Pittsburgh 1982-83 Teaching Fellow, University of Pittsburgh Academic Awards, Honors, and Fellowships 2008 Guggenheim Fellowship 2007 Elected to Academie Internationale de Philosophie des Sciences 1992 Rutgers University Board of Trustees Research Fellowship for Scholarly Excellence 1992 NEH Summer Stipend to complete book manuscript Quantum Non-Locality and Relativity 1989 Invited participant, Sixty-two Years of Uncertainty: Historical, Philosophical and Physics Inquiries into the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics , International School of History of Science,Ettore Majorana Centre for Scientific Culture, Erice, Italy 1988 Participant in National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Institute on Aristotle's Metaphysics, Biology and Ethics 1986-88 Henry Rutgers Research Fellowship, Rutgers
    [Show full text]
  • 208 Tim Maudlin. Philosophy of Physics: Space and Time. Princeton
    Philosophy in Review XXXV (August 2015), no. 4 Tim Maudlin. Philosophy of Physics: Space and Time. Princeton University Press 2012. 200 pp. $45.00 USD (Hardcover ISBN 9780691143095); $19.95 USD (Paperback ISBN 9780691165714). Tim Maudlin’s Philosophy of Physics: Space and Time is the first of a two-volume survey of key foundational issues in the philosophy of physics. The two volumes concern the two historically dis- tinct subject matters of physics: space and time; and their material contents. The present volume is an accessible and highly engaging introduction to the major issues in the physics of space and time that guides the reader through the philosophical foundations of physical geometry, the special and general theories of relativity, and the topology of time, and is suitable both for the philosopher with minimal physics background and for the physicist interested in the main historical philosophical issues concerning spacetime theories. The central theme of Maudlin’s presentation of the history of spacetime is a focus on geometrical rather than arithmetical methods. The absence of equations from the presentation of the Newtonian laws of motion is due not to a fear of putting off the lay reader, but rather to the conviction that the arithmetization of physics is unnecessary and misleading. Aside from the fact that Newton himself used geometry rather than arithmetic to present his theory, Maudlin emphasizes that ‘[t]o put it bluntly, the physical world is not composed of numbers or of entities for which the standard arith- metic operations are defined’. Rather, ‘[t]he physical world contains physical magnitudes that have a geometrical structure’ and hence ‘[g]eometry is more directly connected to the physical world than is arithmetic’ (25, emphases in original).
    [Show full text]
  • Intermediate Philosophy of Physics Reading List
    Intermediate Philosophy of Physics Reading List James Read [email protected] This is James Read’s reading list for the Finals paper, Intermediate Philosophy of Physics. If you have any questions, comments, or suggestions, please email me at the above address. 1 1 Special Relativity As preparation for the special relativity section of the paper, you might consider reading: (Warning: All of these books are stellar, but some of the later entries are very technical!) 1. N. David Mermin, It’s About Time: Understanding Einstein’s Relativity, Princeton: Prince- ton University Press, 2009. 2. Tim Maudlin, Philosophy of Physics Volume I: Space and Time, Princeton: Princeton Uni- versity Press, 2012. 3. Hans Reichenbach, The Philosophy of Space and Time, New York: Dover, 1957. 4. Harvey R. Brown, Physical Relativity: Spacetime Structure from a Dynamical Perspective, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. 5. Roberto Torretti, Relativity and Geometry, New York: Dover, 1996. 6. Michael Friedman, Foundations of Space-Time Theories, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983. 2 1.1 Newton’s laws State Newton’s laws of motion and define all terms therein. How (if at all) do the laws depend upon one another? Do the laws together imply that Newtonian mechanics is Galilean invariant? Core reading 1. Herbert Pfister and Markus King, Inertia and Gravitation, Heidelberg: Springer, 2015. xx1.1-1.3. 2. Roberto Torretti, Relativity and Geometry, New York: Dover, 1996. Ch. 1. 3. Harvey R. Brown, Physical Relativity: Spacetime Structure from a Dynamical Perspective, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. xx2.2, 3.1, 3.2. 4. Michael Friedman, Foundations of Space-Time Theories, Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univer- sity Press, 1983.
    [Show full text]
  • Rovelli's World
    Rovelli’s World* Bas C. van Fraassen forthcoming in Foundations of Physics 2009 ABSTRACT Carlo Rovelli’s inspiring “Relational Quantum Mechanics” serves several aims at once: it provides a new vision of what the world of quantum mechanics is like, and it offers a program to derive the theory’s formalism from a set of simple postulates pertaining to information processing. I propose here to concentrate entirely on the former, to explore the world of quantum mechanics as Rovelli depicts it. It is a fascinating world in part because of Rovelli’s reliance on the information-theory approach to the foundations of quantum mechanics, and in part because its presentation involves taking sides on a fundamental divide within philosophy itself. KEY WORDS: Carlo Rovelli, Einstein-Podolski-Rosen, quantum information, Relational Quantum Mechanics * I happily dedicate this paper to Jeffrey Bub, whose work has inspired me for a good quarter of a century. Rovelli’s World 1 Rovelli’s World* Bas C. van Fraassen Rovelli’s inspiring “Relational Quantum Mechanics” provides an original vision of what the world of quantum mechanics is like.1 It is fascinating in part because its presentation involves taking sides on a fundamental divide within philosophy itself. 1. Placing Rovelli 1.1. Rovelli’s description of Rovelli’s world In Rovelli’s world there are no observer-independent states, nor observer- independent values of physical quantities. A system has one state relative to a given observer, and a different state relative to another observer. An observable has one value relative to one observer, and a different value relative to another observer.
    [Show full text]