Anaximander. a Re-Assessment Carlo Rovelli
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Load more
Recommended publications
-
St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death
The University of Akron IdeaExchange@UAkron Williams Honors College, Honors Research The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors Projects College Spring 2020 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death Christopher Choma [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects Part of the Christianity Commons, Epistemology Commons, European History Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Metaphysics Commons, Philosophy of Mind Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Please take a moment to share how this work helps you through this survey. Your feedback will be important as we plan further development of our repository. Recommended Citation Choma, Christopher, "St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death" (2020). Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects. 1048. https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects/1048 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors College at IdeaExchange@UAkron, the institutional repository of The University of Akron in Akron, Ohio, USA. It has been accepted for inclusion in Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects by an authorized administrator of IdeaExchange@UAkron. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. 1 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death By: Christopher Choma Sponsored by: Dr. Joseph Li Vecchi Readers: Dr. Howard Ducharme Dr. Nathan Blackerby 2 Table of Contents Introduction p. 4 Section One: Three General Views of Human Nature p. -
The Place of Zeno's Paradox
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 2011, volume 29, pages 924 ^ 937 doi:10.1068/d10010 The place of Zeno's paradox Laurence Paul Hemming Department of Organisation, Work and Technology, Lancaster University Management School, Lancaster LA1 4YX, England; e-mail: [email protected] Received 22 June 2010; in revised form 24 December 2010 Abstract. This paper begins by examining the recent history of interpretations of one of Zeno's paradoxes of motion, the paradox of dichotomy. It then returns to the record of antiquity to ask how Aristotle `solved' the paradox and what decisions about place and motion were assumed in that solution. After appealing to Heidegger's readings of the Aristotelian text, the paper then proceeds to offer an entirely original interpretation of Zeno's paradox of dichotomy, which has important implica- tions for a contemporary understanding of motion and place (rather than space). Instead, the paradox is read as a provocation to `see' something which Zeno, it would appear, believed was `missing', or had been forgotten and had disappeared, and to review all over again what Parmenides might have meant in his claim that being is one, singular, and indivisible. Introduction Zeno, disciple of the Eleatic philosopher Parmenides, leaves to history a series of paradoxes that have either perplexed or excited the disdain of philosophers ever since. No text of Zeno's survives for us to consult: our knowledge of the paradoxes them- selves is drawn almost entirely from Aristotle's Physics and Metaphysics and from the writings of Simplicius. Hermann Diels summarises the fragmentary discussions of Zeno, together with references to lost works and extant citations from Aristotle, Simplicius, Diogenes Laertius, and others in Diels (1922). -
Thales of Miletus Sources and Interpretations Miletli Thales Kaynaklar Ve Yorumlar
Thales of Miletus Sources and Interpretations Miletli Thales Kaynaklar ve Yorumlar David Pierce October , Matematics Department Mimar Sinan Fine Arts University Istanbul http://mat.msgsu.edu.tr/~dpierce/ Preface Here are notes of what I have been able to find or figure out about Thales of Miletus. They may be useful for anybody interested in Thales. They are not an essay, though they may lead to one. I focus mainly on the ancient sources that we have, and on the mathematics of Thales. I began this work in preparation to give one of several - minute talks at the Thales Meeting (Thales Buluşması) at the ruins of Miletus, now Milet, September , . The talks were in Turkish; the audience were from the general popu- lation. I chose for my title “Thales as the originator of the concept of proof” (Kanıt kavramının öncüsü olarak Thales). An English draft is in an appendix. The Thales Meeting was arranged by the Tourism Research Society (Turizm Araştırmaları Derneği, TURAD) and the office of the mayor of Didim. Part of Aydın province, the district of Didim encompasses the ancient cities of Priene and Miletus, along with the temple of Didyma. The temple was linked to Miletus, and Herodotus refers to it under the name of the family of priests, the Branchidae. I first visited Priene, Didyma, and Miletus in , when teaching at the Nesin Mathematics Village in Şirince, Selçuk, İzmir. The district of Selçuk contains also the ruins of Eph- esus, home town of Heraclitus. In , I drafted my Miletus talk in the Math Village. Since then, I have edited and added to these notes. -
La Bible: Notes Intégrales – Traduction Œcuménique
Ephemerides Theologicae Lovanienses 88/1 (2012) 179-230. doi: 10.2143/ETL.88.1.2164176 © 2012 by Ephemerides Theologicae Lovanienses. All rights reserved. BOOK REVIEWS La Bible: Notes intégrales – Traduction œcuménique. 11e édition (La Traduc- tion Œcuménique de la Bible). Paris, Cerf; Villiers-le-Bel, Bibli’O – Société biblique française, 2010. (25≈17,5), 2757 p. ISBN 2-204-09382- 8. /65.00. Gérard BILLON – Bernard COYAULT – Sophie SCHLUMBERGER – Andrée THOMAS (eds.). L’aventure de la TOB: Cinquante ans de traduction œcuménique de la Bible (La Traduction Œcuménique de la Bible). Paris, Cerf, 2010. (18≈12), 156 p. ISBN 978-2-204-09267-8. /8.00. La publication de la T.O.B. (en 1972 pour le Nouveau Testament et en 1975 pour l’Ancien) a représenté un véritable événement: c’était la première fois au monde que des Églises de traditions différentes parvenaient à traduire, annoter et éditer une Bible commune. L’idée n’était pas neuve. Au XVIIe siècle déjà l’oratorien Richard Simon avait conçu un tel projet. Mais la révocation de l’Édit de Nantes a mis fin à ce bel espoir. Une nouvelle tentative, à la fin du XIXe siècle, a connu l’échec elle aussi. Ce n’est qu’au début des années 1960 que l’idée a pu reprendre corps et, après quelques tâtonnements, déboucher sur un commencement de réalisation. Les pre- miers travaux ont débuté en 1965, encouragés du côté catholique par la récente promulgation de la Constitution dogmatique Dei Verbum de Vatican II. Il convenait d’effectuer d’abord un galop d’essai. -
Ponos and Aponia
SHAPIRO, H. A., "Ponos" and "Aponia" , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 25:2 (1984) p.107 Ponos and Aponia H. A. Shapiro N GRBS 23 (1982) 147-56, A. L. Boegehold presented an inter I esting argument that, in the years 424-421, a group of dissenters in Athens, led by Nikias, who favored making peace with Sparta, adopted as a slogan 1TOVWV 1TaV(TWI_"dJa. This formulation transformed the connotation of 1TOVO~ from a traditionally patriotic expression of the hard work needed to achieve a noble goal to a more pessimistic term for the hardships and suffering of an unnecessarily protracted war. Boegehold adduced passages in Thucydides, Euripides, and Aris tophanes to illustrate the extraordinary popularity and often highly charged rhetorical uses of 1TOVO~ in this period. It may be relevant to introduce in this context a unique depic tion, on an Athenian vase of the following decade, 420-410, of a woman labelled AIlONIA (PLATE 0.1 There is no literary evidence for Aponia as the name of a divinity, mythological figure, or his torical person, and it is clear from other figures on the same vase, to be discussed infra, that Aponia is meant here as a personified abstraction. The word a1Tovia first occurs in extant Greek literature several de cades after the date of this vase,2 in Xenophon's Cyropaedeia (2.2.25), where its connotation is clearly pejorative ("laziness'), and it is linked with {3AaKEia ('indolence', 'stupidity'). Aristotle once uses the word a1Tovia in this negative sense (Rh. 1370aI4), but once also in a more positive, or at least neutral, sense ('freedom from toil', Gen.An. -
The Fragments of Zeno and Cleanthes, but Having an Important
,1(70 THE FRAGMENTS OF ZENO AND CLEANTHES. ftonton: C. J. CLAY AND SONS, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE, AVE MARIA LANE. ambriDse: DEIGHTON, BELL, AND CO. ltip>ifl: F. A. BROCKHAUS. #tto Hork: MACMILLAX AND CO. THE FRAGMENTS OF ZENO AND CLEANTHES WITH INTRODUCTION AND EXPLANATORY NOTES. AX ESSAY WHICH OBTAINED THE HARE PRIZE IX THE YEAR 1889. BY A. C. PEARSON, M.A. LATE SCHOLAR OF CHRIST S COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE. LONDON: C. J. CLAY AND SONS, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE. 1891 [All Rights reserved.] Cambridge : PBIXTKIi BY C. J. CLAY, M.A. AND SONS, AT THK UNIVERSITY PRKSS. PREFACE. S dissertation is published in accordance with thr conditions attached to the Hare Prize, and appears nearly in its original form. For many reasons, however, I should have desired to subject the work to a more under the searching revision than has been practicable circumstances. Indeed, error is especially difficult t<> avoid in dealing with a large body of scattered authorities, a the majority of which can only be consulted in public- library. to be for The obligations, which require acknowledged of Zeno and the present collection of the fragments former are Cleanthes, are both special and general. The Philo- soon disposed of. In the Neue Jahrbticher fur Wellmann an lofjie for 1878, p. 435 foil., published article on Zeno of Citium, which was the first serious of Zeno from that attempt to discriminate the teaching of Wellmann were of the Stoa in general. The omissions of the supplied and the first complete collection fragments of Cleanthes was made by Wachsmuth in two Gottingen I programs published in 187-i LS75 (Commentationes s et II de Zenone Citiensi et Cleaitt/ie Assio). -
Sextus Empiricus and the Scientific Scepticism
ENCEPHALOS 50, 62-74, 2013 SEXTUS EMPIRICUS AND THE SCIENTIFIC SCEPTI- CISM STAVROS J.BALOYANNIS* Summary philosophical books, which survived, but remained for long in obscurity, been rediscovered in the late Renaissance. Two Sextus Empiricus is the most eminent representative of these works on the title, “Adversus Mathematikus”, include of the ancient sceptisism, which is a Post-Classical, Hellenis- large number of strong arguments against the Logicians, the tic philosophy based on the criterion of life, the experience Physicists and the Ethicists. The third and most important of and the analysis of phenomena, aiming to provide a straight the books on the title “Outlines of Pyrrhonism” provides an out- and practical way of life, leading to interior peace and mental line of Pyrrhonian scepticism, incorporating at the same time tranquility, sharply opposed to a purely theoretical pursuit of his own philosophical doctrines. Sextus offers thoroughly a dogmatic philosophy. The term “sceptic” is a derivative of the general overview of scepticism, describing and explaining the noun, skepsis (σκέψις), which means thought, examination, meaning of the sceptical investigation, the value of suspen- inquiry, consideration, meditation and investigation. The scep- sion of judgment and the importance of the sceptical dialectics. tical school was connected for a long period of time with the Sextus insists that the skepticism does not accept or reject any Empirical school of physicians, who based the good medical impression and substantially does not affirm or deny anything. practice on the clinical experience rather than on the theoret- Sextus claims that appearances (φαινόμενα) are the practical ical erudition, dedicating themselves to observation, memory criteria of approaching to the truth and by the continuous inves- and continuous clinical practice. -
AUGUSTINE of HIPPO and HANNAH ARENDT Antonio Calcagno
PARRHESIA NUMBER 13 • 2011 • 14-27 THE ROLE OF FORGETTING IN OUR EXPERIENCE OF TIME: AUGUSTINE OF HIPPO AND HANNAH ARENDT Antonio Calcagno Hannah Arendt’s work is deeply marked by a rich analysis of temporality. One finds references to it from her earliest works on Augustine of Hippo1 to her last major work, The Life of the Mind. Scholars have rightly explored the significance of temporality and its constitutive centrality for Arendt’s thought.2 Her views of temporality can be divided grosso modo along three axes. First, there is time-lived or the times-experienced, which comprise or touch upon such aspects as history, biography, narrative, and a timely engagement with the issues of the day, which include, for example, various moments in American Cold-War culture and civil-rights movements.3 Second, there is a sense of time understood as spontaneity, as natality, in which a new beginning is made possible today, hodiernus. Arising spontaneously, this time marks a new promise, as in the case of forgiveness.4 Perhaps we can call this the time of the kairos, the opportune time, the now-time that emerges from a set of circumstances but is not merely a result of a series of causal events. Finally, one finds in Arendt’s work a philosophical position on the very nature of time itself, understood as the past and the future that make possible the present, that condition the very existence of the human being. Particularly striking is the account of time that Arendt gives in the concluding parts of her work on “Thinking” in The Life of the Mind. -
Thales of Miletus Sources and Interpretations Miletli Thales Kaynaklar Ve Yorumlar
Thales of Miletus Sources and Interpretations Miletli Thales Kaynaklar ve Yorumlar David Pierce September , Matematics Department Mimar Sinan Fine Arts University Istanbul http://mat.msgsu.edu.tr/~dpierce/ This is a collection of what I have been able to find or figure out about Thales of Miletus. It may be useful for anybody interested in Thales. I focus directly on the ancient sources that we have. ¶ I began collecting these notes in preparation to give one of several -minute talks at the Thales Meeting (Thales Buluşması) at the ruins of Miletus, now Milet, Septem- ber , . Talks at the meeting were in Turkish; the au- dience, members of the general population. I chose for my title “Thales as the originator of the concept of proof” (Kanıt kavramının öncüsü olarak Thales). ¶ The Thales Meeting was arranged by the office of the mayor of Didim. Part of Aydın province, the district of Didim encompasses the ancient cities of Priene and Miletus, along with the temple of Didyma, which was linked to Miletus. Herodotus refers to Didyma under the name of the family of priests there, the Branchidae. ¶ One can visit all three of Priene, Didyma, and Miletus in a day. I did this in , while teaching at the Nesin Mathematics Village in Şirince, in the district of Selçuk, which contains also the ruins of Ephesus, home town of Heraclitus. My excellent guide was George Bean, Aegean Turkey []. Contents . Sources .. AlegendfromDiogenesLaertius . .. Kirk, Raven, and Schofield . .. DielsandKranz. .. Collingwood. .. .. .. Herodotus ..................... ... Solareclipse . ... CrossingoftheHalys . ... BouleuterionatTeos . .. Proclus....................... ... Originofgeometry . ... Bisectionofcircle . ... Isosceles triangles . ... Verticalangles. ... Congruenttriangles. .. Diogenes Laertius: The angle in a semicircle . -
Back to Parmenides
View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Philsci-Archive Back to Parmenides Henrique Gomes1 Perimeter Institute for Theoretical Physics 31 Caroline Street, ON, N2L 2Y5, Canada 1 [email protected] 3 Abstract After a brief introduction to issues that plague the realization of a theory of quantum gravity, I suggest that the main one concerns a quantization of the principle of relative simultaneity. This leads me to a distinction between time and space, to a further degree than that present in the canonical approach to general relativity. With this distinction, superpositions are only meaningful as interference between alternative paths in the relational configuration space of the entire Universe. But the full use of relationalism brings us to a timeless picture of Nature, as it does in the canonical approach (which culminates in the Wheeler-DeWitt equation). After a discussion of Parmenides and the Eleatics' rejection of time, I show that there is middle ground between their view of absolute timelessness and a view of physics taking place in timeless configuration space. In this middle ground, even though change does not fundamentally exist, the illusion of change can be recovered in a way not permitted by Parmenides. It is recovered through a particular density distribution over configuration space which gives rise to `records'. Incidentally, this distribution seems to have the potential to dissolve further aspects of the measurement problem that can still be argued to haunt the application of decoherence to Many- Worlds. I end with a discussion indicating that the conflict between the conclusions of this paper and our view of the continuity of the self may still intuitively bother us. -
Augustine, Wannabe Philosopher: the Search for Otium Honestum
University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Supervised Undergraduate Student Research Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects and Creative Work 5-2014 Augustine, Wannabe Philosopher: The Search for Otium Honestum Allen G. Wilson University of Tennessee Knoxville, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, Christianity Commons, Classical Literature and Philology Commons, History of Christianity Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Intellectual History Commons, and the Other Classics Commons Recommended Citation Wilson, Allen G., "Augustine, Wannabe Philosopher: The Search for Otium Honestum" (2014). Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj/1722 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Supervised Undergraduate Student Research and Creative Work at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Augustine, Wannabe Philosopher: The Search for Otium Honestum Honors Thesis By: Allen Wilson Faculty Advisor: Dr. Maura Lafferty University of Tennessee Knoxville 1 Abstract On the path from teacher of rhetoric to bishop of Hippo three important milestones present themselves: Cassiacum, Thagaste, and Hippo. At each of these places Augustine led his own Christian community. Cassiacum marks the beginning of a momentous journey where Augustine, having quit his rhetorical position in Milan, retires with some friends and students (along with his mother Monica) to discourse on philosophy and Christianity before he and his friend Alypius are to be baptized. -
The Scultori and Ghisi Engraving Enterprise in Sixteenth-Century Mantua and Beyond
“OLD IN SUBSTANCE AND NEW IN MANNER”: THE SCULTORI AND GHISI ENGRAVING ENTERPRISE IN SIXTEENTH-CENTURY MANTUA AND BEYOND by Hilary Letwin A dissertation submitted to Johns Hopkins University in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Baltimore, Maryland December, 2013 Part 1 Abstract: This dissertation seeks to reframe the way in which the prints of the incisori Mantovani, Giovanni Battista (1503-1575), Adamo (1530?-1587) and Diana Scultori (1547-1612), and Giorgio Ghisi (1520-1582), are examined. Previously, their contributions in the printmaking process, largely engraving prints that are after the designs of other artists, have been dismissed as reproductive. This dissertation examines the ways in which these printmakers worked to elevate their engravings from simply reproductive to creative works of art in their own right. Their engravings, which certainly took inspiration from the designs of Giulio Romano, among others, were not the product of a close collaboration between a master and the engravers. Instead, the engravers appear to have worked fairly autonomously, in Mantua and elsewhere, engaging with and manipulating their source material, experimenting technically and in the design of their prints, and finally questioning the role of engraving within the greater framework of artistic practice in the sixteenth century. Chapter one examines the work of Giovanni Battista, who used printmaking as a creative outlet, seeking a freedom not possible in his other sculptural projects that were carried out according to the specifications of patrons and artistic masters. His engravings can be seen as an attempt to “conquer” these outside influences. Chapter two considers the prints and career of Adamo Scultori, who used his prints to comment on the “enslavement” of reproductive printmakers to their sources.