Back to Parmenides
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Philsci-Archive Back to Parmenides Henrique Gomes1 Perimeter Institute for Theoretical Physics 31 Caroline Street, ON, N2L 2Y5, Canada 1 [email protected] 3 Abstract After a brief introduction to issues that plague the realization of a theory of quantum gravity, I suggest that the main one concerns a quantization of the principle of relative simultaneity. This leads me to a distinction between time and space, to a further degree than that present in the canonical approach to general relativity. With this distinction, superpositions are only meaningful as interference between alternative paths in the relational configuration space of the entire Universe. But the full use of relationalism brings us to a timeless picture of Nature, as it does in the canonical approach (which culminates in the Wheeler-DeWitt equation). After a discussion of Parmenides and the Eleatics' rejection of time, I show that there is middle ground between their view of absolute timelessness and a view of physics taking place in timeless configuration space. In this middle ground, even though change does not fundamentally exist, the illusion of change can be recovered in a way not permitted by Parmenides. It is recovered through a particular density distribution over configuration space which gives rise to `records'. Incidentally, this distribution seems to have the potential to dissolve further aspects of the measurement problem that can still be argued to haunt the application of decoherence to Many- Worlds. I end with a discussion indicating that the conflict between the conclusions of this paper and our view of the continuity of the self may still intuitively bother us. Nonetheless, those conclusions should be no more challenging to our intuition than Derek Parfit’s thought experiments on the same subject. Contents 1 A summary of the construction page 5 2 The problems with quantizing gravity 6 2.1 A tale of two theories6 2.2 The problems of quantum gravity7 2.3 Problems of Time8 2.4 Symmetries, relationalism and `laws of the instant' 12 3 Timelessness, quantum mechanics, and configuration space 15 3.1 The special existence of the present - Parmenides and Zeno 15 3.2 Timeless path integral in quantum mechanics 16 4 Records and timelessness 18 4.1 Born rule and the preferred configuration. 18 4.2 Records 20 5 What are we afraid of? The psychological obstacles. 23 5.1 Zeno's paradox and solipsism of the instant: a matter of topology 23 5.2 The continuity of the self - Locke, Hume and Parfit 24 6 Summary and conclusions 26 6.1 Crippling and rehabilitating Time 26 6.2 Psychological hangups 26 6.3 What gives, Wheeler's quip or superpositions? 26 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS 28 References 29 1 A summary of the construction Quantum mechanics arose in the 1920's. General relativity has been around since the 1910's. But, as of 2018, we still have no quantum theory of the gravitational field. What is taking us so long? I believe the most challenging obstacle in our way is understanding the quantum superposition of general relativistic causal structures. This obstacle is couched on facets of the `problem of time' [Kuchar(2011)] | an inherent difficulty in reconciling a picture of time evolution in quantum mechanics to a `block time' picture of general relativity. I also believe we can overcome this obstacle only if we accept a fundamental distinction between time and space. The distinction is timid in general relativity { even in its ADM form [Arnowitt et al.(1962)] { and here I want to push it further. In this spirit, I will consider space to be fundamental and time to be a derived concept { a concept at which we arrive from change (a loose quote from Ernst Mach). I will here investigate the consequences of this distinction between time and space. The dis- tinction only allows a restricted class of fundamental physical fields | the ones whose content is spatially relational | and it thus also restricts the sort of fundamental theories of reality. It is consequential in that with this view we must reassess our interpretation of quantum me- chanics and its relationship to gravity. The new interpretation is compatible with a version of timelessness that I will explain below. With timelessness, comes the requirement of explaining history without fundamental underlying dynamics. The role of dynamics is fulfilled by what I define as `records'. This paper will consist mainly of two parts: one justifying the timeless approach through problems in quantum gravity, and another describing physics within a general timeless theory proposed here. In the following section, I will introduce more technical reasons for my interest in timeless theories. These have to do with quantum gravity. I thus start with a brief description of what would count as a theory of quantum gravity, before moving on to the sort of problems it has, which I believe timelessness might cure. 2 The problems with quantizing gravity I will start in section 2.1 with what I believe are the main principles of quantum mechanics and gravity. I will then follow in section 2.2 with a brief idiosyncratic exposition of in issues in quantizing gravity in section. Then, in section 2.3 I move on to an illustration of which of these problems signal a fundamental difference between time and space. Finally, in section 2.4, I posit what sort of different fundamental symmetries | i.e. to be imposed also off-shell, or at the quantum mechanical level | would assuage the clash between dynamics and symmetry. These turn out to be the spatial relational symmetries. 2.1 A tale of two theories General relativity is one of the pillars of our modern understanding of the Universe, deserving a certain degree of familiarity from all those who purport to study Nature, whether from a philosophical or mathematical point of view. The theory has such pristine logical purity that it can be comprehensively summarized by John A. Wheeler's famous quip [Misner et al.(1973)] \Matter tells spacetime how to curve, and spacetime tells matter how to move." (2.1) We should not forget however, that ensconced within Wheeler's sentence is our conception of spacetime as a dynamical geometrical arena of reality: no longer a fixed stage where physics unfolds, it is part and parcel of the play of existence. In mathematical terms, we have: 1 R − Rg / T (2.2) µν 2 µν µν | {z } | {z } spacetime curving sources for curving Given the sources, one will determine a geometry given by the spacetime metric gµν { the ` matter tells spacetime how to curve' bit. Conversely, it can be shown that very light, very small particles will roughly follow geodesics defined by the geometry of the lhs of the equation { the `spacetime tells matter how to move' part.1 A mere decade after the birth of GR, along came quantum mechanics. It was a framework that provided unprecedented accuracy in experimental confirmation, predictions of new physi- cal effects and a reliable compass for the construction of new theories. And yet, it has resisted the intuitive understanding that was quickly achieved with general relativity. A much less ac- curate characterization than Wheeler's quip for general relativity has been borrowed from the pessimistic adage \everything that can happen, does happen".2 The sentence is meant to raise 1 This distinction is not entirely accurate, as the rhs of equation (2.2) usually also contains the metric, and thus the equation should be seen as a constraint on which kind of space-times with which kind of matter distributions one can obtain, \simultaneously". I.e. it should be seen as a spacetime, block universe, pattern, not as a causal relation (see [Lehmkuhl(2010)]). 2 Recently made the title of a popular book on quantum mechanics [Brian Cox(2011)]. 2.2 The problems of quantum gravity 7 the principle of superposition to the status of core concept of quantum mechanics (whether it expresses this clearly or not is very much debatable). In mathematical terms, the superposition principle can be seen in the Schr¨odingerequation: d H^ = −i (2.3) ~dt whose linearity implies that two solutions 1 and 2 add up to a solution 1 + 2. In the path integral representation, superposition is built-in. The very formulation of the generating function is a sum over all possible field configurations φ, Z Z Z = Dφ exp i L(φ)=~ (2.4) where L(φ) is the Lagrangian density for the field φ and Dφ signifies a summation over all possible values of this field (the second integral is over spacetime). Unfortunately, for the past 90 years, general relativity and quantum mechanics have not really gotten along. Quantum mechanics soon claimed a large chunk of territory in the theoretical physics landscape, leaving a small sliver of no-man's land also outside the domain of general relativity. In most regimes, the theories will stay out of each other's way - domains of physics where both effects need to be taken into account for an accurate phenomenological description of Nature are hard to come by. Nonetheless, such a reconciliation might be necessary even for the self-consistency of general relativity: by predicting the formation of singularities, general relativity \predicts its own demise", to borrow again the words of John Wheeler. Unless, that is, quantum effects can be suitably incorporated to save the day at such high curvature regimes. 2.2 The problems of quantum gravity At an abstract level, the question we need to face when trying to quantize general relativity is: how to write down a theory that includes all possible superpositions and yet yields something like equation (2.2) in appropriate classical regimes? Although the incompatibility between general relativity and quantum mechanics can be of technical character, it is widely accepted that it has more conceptual roots.