Chapter Summaries Part One: the Basics of Good Reasoning

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Chapter Summaries Part One: the Basics of Good Reasoning Chapter Summaries Part One: The Basics of Good Reasoning Chapter 1: The Basic Tools of Reasoning The most basic concepts in good reasoning are claims and arguments. In this chapter, we define “claim,” explain how claims can be used to support beliefs, and then explain how various types of evidence can be organized into arguments so we can evaluate the strength of this support for the claims that we make. Chapter Sections: 1.1. Claims 1.2. Evidence 1.3. Arguments 1.4. Identifying arguments 1.5. More exercises Real-Life Example: Reasoning through a Crime Scene © Jamie Carlin Watson and Robert Arp (2011) Critical Thinking: An Introduction to Reasoning Well. London: Continuum. Chapter 2: Evaluating Arguments Arguments are usually found embedded in books and articles that are intended to convey information in addition to the argument. In this chapter, we explain how to extract an argument from extraneous material, clarify ambiguous or vague words and phrases, and organize the argument, so that it is clear and pre- cise. In addition, we explain two broad categories of argument (deductive and inductive), identify the distinctive features of these arguments, and then explain what makes a deductive or inductive “good” or “bad.” Chapter Sections: 2.1. Reconstructing arguments 2.1.1. Extraneous material 2.1.2. Implicit claims 2.1.3. Ambiguity and vagueness 2.1.4. Argument form 2.2. Two types of arguments 2.3. Good and bad arguments 2.3.1. Good deductive arguments 2.3.2. Good inductive arguments 2.4. Complex arguments 2.5. More exercises Real-Life Example: A Logic Problem © Jamie Carlin Watson and Robert Arp (2011) Critical Thinking: An Introduction to Reasoning Well. London: Continuum. Part Two: Deductive Reasoning Chapter 3: Categorical Logic An intuitive way of understanding reality is to categorize it (big, red, species, dog, alligator, etc.). We can then use these categories to compare and contrast objects. We can also use them to reason about objects. In this chapter, we explain the basic concepts used in categorical logic, including members, categories, the quantifiers “all,” “some,” and “none,” Venn diagrams, the Venn Diagram Method of testing for validity, and the limitations of categorical logic. Chapter Sections: 3.1. Categories of things 3.2. Relating categories to one another 3.3. Standard-form categorical claims 3.4. Translation tips 3.4.1. Most? 3.4.2. Four parts of categorical claims 3.4.3. Singular expressions and proper nouns 3.4.4. Time and place 3.4.5. Conditional claims 3.5. Syllogisms and testing for validity with Venn Diagrams 3.6. The limitations of categorical logic 3.7. More exercises Real-Life Example: Mexican Holy Week © Jamie Carlin Watson and Robert Arp (2011) Critical Thinking: An Introduction to Reasoning Well. London: Continuum. Chapter 4: Basic Propositional Logic A more powerful logical system than categorical logic is called “propositional logic.” In this chapter, we explain basic logical operators “and,” “or,” “not,” “if . ., then . .,” and “if and only if,” how to translate English claims into the language of propositional logic and vice versa, and explain how propositional logic helps us evaluate arguments. Chapter Sections: 4.1. A new language 4.2. Translating English claims into claims of propositional logic 4.3. Translating claims with operators 4.4. Translation examples 4.5. Basic translation exercises 4.6. Tips for translating 4.7. More difficult translation exercises 4.8. Rules of inference and their value 4.9. More exercises Real-Life Example: Translating a Legal Document © Jamie Carlin Watson and Robert Arp (2011) Critical Thinking: An Introduction to Reasoning Well. London: Continuum. Chapter 5: Truth Tables Logical operators have specific implications for interpreting claims and evaluat- ing arguments. The clearest way to understand these implications is to construct truth tables for them. In this chapter, we explain how to construct a truth table, the truth tables for each logical operator, and how to evaluate the validity of an argument using two different truth table methods. Chapter Sections: 5.1. Constructing truth tables 5.2. Using truth tables to express relationships among claims 5.3. Using truth tables to evaluate short arguments 5.4. Using truth tables to evaluate long arguments 5.5. More exercises Real-Life Example 1: Former Illinois Governor Rob Blagojevich Real-Life Example 2: Political Pundit Rush Limbaugh © Jamie Carlin Watson and Robert Arp (2011) Critical Thinking: An Introduction to Reasoning Well. London: Continuum. Chapter 6: Rules of Inference With a firm grasp of the truth tables of the operators in propositional logic, we can begin to see how to draw inferences from claims of propositional logic. Some of these inferences are so clear and precise that they can be used as rules for all inferences in propositional logic. In this chapter, we explain nine rules of infer- ence, how to use them to derive conclusions from complicated arguments, and three common mistakes associated with these rules. Chapter Sections: 6.1. Deductive inference 6.2. Four basic rules 6.2.1. Simplification 6.2.2. Conjunction 6.2.3. modus ponens 6.2.4. modus tollens 6.3. Basic inference exercises 1 6.4. Three more rules 6.4.1. Disjunctive syllogism 6.4.2. Addition 6.4.3. Hypothetical syllogism 6.5. Basic inference exercises 2 6.6. Two special rules 6.6.1. Conditional proof 6.6.2. reductio ad absurdum / indirect proof 6.7. More complicated inference exercises 6.8. Mistakes to avoid 6.8.1. Affirming the consequent 6.8.2. Denying the antecedent 6.8.3. Affirming the disjunct 6.9. Formal fallacy exercises Real-Life Example: Blagojevich’s Resignation Speech © Jamie Carlin Watson and Robert Arp (2011) Critical Thinking: An Introduction to Reasoning Well. London: Continuum. Part Three: Inductive Reasoning Chapter 7: Probability and Induction In arguments where conclusions do not follow with certainty from premises, we must turn to a different set of rules to evaluate them. In these inductive arguments, the conclusions follow with some degree of probability. In this chapter, we distinguish probability from statistics, explain three common types of probability, explain how statistics and probability are used in inductive reason- ing, and explain the most difficult obstacle to inductive reasoning, “the problem of induction.” Chapter Sections: 7.1. Inductive strength 7.2. Types of probability 7.3. Conditional probabilities 7.4. Using probability in argument: Cost/benefit analysis 7.5. The problem of induction 7.6. Exercises Real-Life Example: The Teleological Argument for God’s Existence © Jamie Carlin Watson and Robert Arp (2011) Critical Thinking: An Introduction to Reasoning Well. London: Continuum. Chapter 8: Inductive Arguments Inductive arguments take a variety of forms and each of these forms must meet a specific set of conditions in order to be considered a “good” argument. In this chapter, we explain four types of inductive argument: inductive enumeration, inductive generalization, argument from analogy, and causal argument, and their strengths and weaknesses. This chapter ends by highlighting some specific wor- ries about evaluating causal arguments. These worries are addressed in the next chapter. Chapter Sections: 8.1. Types of inductive argument 8.2. Enumerative induction 8.3. Exercises with enumerative inductions 8.4. Inductive generalization, or reasoning from a sample 8.5. Statistical errors 8.6. Exercises with inductive generalizations 8.7. Argument from analogy 8.8. Strengths and weaknesses of analogies 8.9. Exercises for arguments from analogy 8.10. Causal arguments 8.11. Exercises with causal arguments Real-Life Example 1: The Ouija Board Real-Life Example 2: Horoscopes © Jamie Carlin Watson and Robert Arp (2011) Critical Thinking: An Introduction to Reasoning Well. London: Continuum. Chapter 9: Experiment and Inference to the Best Explanation Though there are numerous ways that a causal inference can be drawn inappro- priately, philosophers and scientists have devised clever ways of mitigating these worries through various types of experiments. In this chapter, we explain the most common formal and informal experiments, their strengths and limitations, and a method of choosing among theories for which there is conflicting evi- dence, called “inference to the best explanation.” Chapter Sections: 9.1. Testing causal claims 9.2. The structure of an experiment 9.3. Formal experiments 9.4. Exercises with formal experiments 9.5. Informal experiments 9.6. Exercises with informal experiments 9.7. A problem for causal tests: Underdetermination 9.8. A new type of argument: Inference to the best explanation 9.9. Explanatory virtues 9.10. Applying the virtues 9.11. Exercises with inference to the best explanation Real-Life Example: A Murder Mystery © Jamie Carlin Watson and Robert Arp (2011) Critical Thinking: An Introduction to Reasoning Well. London: Continuum. Chapter 10: Informal Fallacies There are probably innumerable ways that inductive inferences can go wrong, but some are so common they have been given names. In this chapter we explain eleven of the most common informal fallacies, including: Argumentum ad Hom- inem, Abusive (appeal to the man/person); Argumentum ad Hominem, Circum- stantial; Tu Quoque (you, too; “hypocrite” fallacy); Argumentum ad Populum (appeal to the people); Appeal to Snobbery/Vanity; Argumentum ad Verecun- diam (appeal to [inappropriate] authority); Argumentum ad Baculum (appeal to force); Argumentum ad Misericordiam (appeal to pity); Argumentum ad Igno- rantiam (appeal to ignorance); Petitio Principii (begging the question); and Straw Man. Chapter Sections: 10.1. Argumentum ad Hominem, Abusive (appeal to the man/person) 10.2. Argumentum ad Hominem, Circumstantial 10.3. Tu Quoque (you, too; “hypocrite” fallacy) 10.4. Argumentum ad Populum (appeal to the people) 10.5. Appeal to snobbery/vanity 10.6. Argumentum ad Verecundiam (appeal to [inappropriate] authority) 10.7. Argumentum ad Baculum (appeal to force) 10.8. Argumentum ad Misericordiam (appeal to pity) 10.9.
Recommended publications
  • Argumentation and Fallacies in Creationist Writings Against Evolutionary Theory Petteri Nieminen1,2* and Anne-Mari Mustonen1
    Nieminen and Mustonen Evolution: Education and Outreach 2014, 7:11 http://www.evolution-outreach.com/content/7/1/11 RESEARCH ARTICLE Open Access Argumentation and fallacies in creationist writings against evolutionary theory Petteri Nieminen1,2* and Anne-Mari Mustonen1 Abstract Background: The creationist–evolutionist conflict is perhaps the most significant example of a debate about a well-supported scientific theory not readily accepted by the public. Methods: We analyzed creationist texts according to type (young earth creationism, old earth creationism or intelligent design) and context (with or without discussion of “scientific” data). Results: The analysis revealed numerous fallacies including the direct ad hominem—portraying evolutionists as racists, unreliable or gullible—and the indirect ad hominem, where evolutionists are accused of breaking the rules of debate that they themselves have dictated. Poisoning the well fallacy stated that evolutionists would not consider supernatural explanations in any situation due to their pre-existing refusal of theism. Appeals to consequences and guilt by association linked evolutionary theory to atrocities, and slippery slopes to abortion, euthanasia and genocide. False dilemmas, hasty generalizations and straw man fallacies were also common. The prevalence of these fallacies was equal in young earth creationism and intelligent design/old earth creationism. The direct and indirect ad hominem were also prevalent in pro-evolutionary texts. Conclusions: While the fallacious arguments are irrelevant when discussing evolutionary theory from the scientific point of view, they can be effective for the reception of creationist claims, especially if the audience has biases. Thus, the recognition of these fallacies and their dismissal as irrelevant should be accompanied by attempts to avoid counter-fallacies and by the recognition of the context, in which the fallacies are presented.
    [Show full text]
  • Argumentum Ad Populum Examples in Media
    Argumentum Ad Populum Examples In Media andClip-on spare. Ashby Metazoic sometimes Brian narcotize filagrees: any he intercommunicatedBalthazar echo improperly. his assonances Spense coylyis all-weather and terminably. and comminating compunctiously while segregated Pen resinify The argument further it did arrive, clearly the fallacy or has it proves false information to increase tuition costs Fallacies of emotion are usually find in grant proposals or need scholarship, income as reports to funders, policy makers, employers, journalists, and raw public. Why do in media rather than his lack of. This fallacy can raise quite dangerous because it entails the reluctance of ceasing an action because of movie the previous investment put option it. See in media should vote republican. This fallacy examples or overlooked, argumentum ad populum examples in media. There was an may select agents and are at your email address any claim that makes a common psychological aspects of. Further Experiments on retail of the end with Displaced Visual Fields. Muslims in media public opinion to force appear. Instead of ad populum. While you are deceptively bad, in media sites, weak or persuade. We often finish one survey of simple core fallacies by considering just contain more. According to appeal could not only correct and frollo who criticize repression and fallacious arguments are those that they are typically also. Why is simply slope bad? 12 Common Logical Fallacies and beige to Debunk Them. Of cancer person commenting on social media rather mention what was alike in concrete post. Therefore, it contain important to analyze logical and emotional fallacies so one hand begin to examine the premises against which these rhetoricians base their assumptions, as as as the logic that brings them deflect certain conclusions.
    [Show full text]
  • Fallacies of Relevance1
    1 Phil 2302 Logic Dr. Naugle Fallacies of Relevance1 "Good reasons must, of force, give place to better." —Shakespeare "There is a mighty big difference between good, sound reasons, and reasons that sound good." —Burton Hillis "It would be a very good thing if every trick could receive some short and obviously appropriate name, so that when a man used this or that particular trick, he could at once be reproved for it." —Arthur Schopenhauer Introduction: There are many ways to bring irrelevant matters into an argument and the study below will examine many of them. These fallacies (pathological arguments!) demonstrate the lengths to which people will go to win an argument, even if they cannot prove their point! Fallacies of relevance share a common characteristic in that the arguments in which they occur have premises that are logically irrelevant to the conclusion. Yet, the premises seem to be relevant psychologically, so that the conclusion seems to follow from the premises. The actual connection between premises and conclusion is emotional, not logical. To identify a fallacy of relevance, you must be able to distinguish between genuine evidence and various unrelated forms of appeal. FALLACIES THAT ATTACK I. Appeal to Force (Argumentum ad Baculum ="argument toward the club or stick") "Who overcomes by force has overcome but half his foe." Milton. "I can stand brute force, but brute reason is quite unbearable. There is something unfair about its use. It is like hitting below the intellect." Oscar Wilde 1 NB: This material is taken from several logic texts authored by N.
    [Show full text]
  • A Searchable Bibliography of Fallacies – 2016
    A Searchable Bibliography of Fallacies – 2016 HANS V. HANSEN Department of Philosophy University of Windsor Windsor, ON CANADA N9B 3P4 [email protected] CAMERON FIORET Department of Philosophy University of Guelph Guelph, ON CANADA N1G 2W1 [email protected] This bibliography of literature on the fallacies is intended to be a resource for argumentation theorists. It incorporates and sup- plements the material in the bibliography in Hansen and Pinto’s Fallacies: Classical and Contemporary Readings (1995), and now includes over 550 entries. The bibliography is here present- ed in electronic form which gives the researcher the advantage of being able to do a search by any word or phrase of interest. Moreover, all the entries have been classified under at least one of 45 categories indicated below. Using the code, entered as e.g., ‘[AM-E]’, one can select all the entries that have been des- ignated as being about the ambiguity fallacy, equivocation. Literature about fallacies falls into two broad classes. It is either about fallacies in general (fallacy theory, or views about fallacies) or about particular fallacies (e.g., equivocation, appeal to pity, etc.). The former category includes, among others, con- siderations of the importance of fallacies, the basis of fallacies, the teaching of fallacies, etc. These general views about fallacies often come from a particular theoretical orientation about how fallacies are best understood; for example, some view fallacies as epistemological mistakes, some as mistakes in disagreement resolution, others as frustrations of rhetorical practice and com- munication. Accordingly, we have attempted to classify the en- © Hans V. Hansen & Cameron Fioret.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtues and Arguments: a Bibliography†
    VIRTUES AND ARGUMENTS: A BIBLIOGRAPHYy ANDREW ABERDEIN∗ New work on virtue theories of argument: [102, 113, 114, 186, we should expect the wrongness of fallacies to be ex- 229, 311, 352, 369, 425, 485, 499, 500]. Recent (or overlooked) plicable in terms of vices. This approach is defended work relevant to VTA in related topics or fields: arrogance [381]; through case studies of several fallacies, with particu- civility [83, 84, 98, 493]; character [57, 534, 536]; cognitive bias lar emphasis on the ad hominem. [90]; critical thinking [23, 494, 495]; ethos [120, 121, 122, 206, 208]; [4] Andrew Aberdein. In defence of virtue: The legitimacy of agent- based argument appraisal. Informal Logic, 34(1):77–93, 2014. exemplars [46, 325, 503]; intellectual dependability [128]; open- Several authors have recently begun to apply virtue mindedness [367, 432, 472, 537]; moral education [243, 360]; theory to argumentation. Critics of this programme phronesis [216, 228]; practical reasoning [347, 516, 518, 519]; have suggested that no such theory can avoid commit- rhetorical vice [224]; rhetorical virtue [450, 458]; theoretical rea- ting an ad hominem fallacy. This criticism is shown to soning [316, 338]; virtuous speech acts [391]. trade unsuccessfully on an ambiguity in the definition Please send suggestions and corrections to aberdein@fit.edu. of ad hominem. The ambiguity is resolved and a virtue- theoretic account of ad hominem reasoning is defended. [5] Andrew Aberdein. Interview with Daniel Cohen. The Reasoner, 9(11):90–93, 2015. References [6] Andrew Aberdein. Arguments with losers. Florida Philosophical Review, 16(1):1–11, 2016. Presidential Address of the 61st Annual [1] .
    [Show full text]
  • Unveiling the Link Between Logical Fallacies and Web Persuasion
    Unveiling the link between logical fallacies and web persuasion Abstract Antonio Lieto Fabiana Vernero In the last decade Human-Computer Interaction (HCI) University of Turin, Dept. of University of Turin, Dept. of has started to focus attention on persuasive Computer Science Computer Science technologies having the goal of changing users’ Corso Svizzera 185 Corso Svizzera 185 behavior and attitudes according to a predefined 10149, Torino, Italy 10149, Torino, Italy direction. In this work, we hypothesize a strong [email protected] [email protected] connection between logical fallacies (forms of reasoning which are logically invalid but cognitively effective) and some common persuasion strategies adopted within web technologies. With the aim of empirically evaluating our hypothesis, we carried out a pilot study on a sample of 150 e-commerce websites. Author Keywords Web persuasion; logical fallacies; captology; human computer interaction ACM Classification Keywords H.5.m. Information interfaces and presentation (e.g., HCI): Miscellaneous. Introduction In the last decade several studies in the field of Copyright is held by the author/owner(s). Human-Computer Interaction (HCI) have started to focus attention on forms of persuasive interaction WebSci’13, May 2 – May 4, 2013, Paris, France. where the goal of one of the two agents involved in the ACM 978-1-4503-1889-1 process, namely, the artifact, is that one of “orienting” the attitudes and/or behaviors of the other agent (the user) according to a predefined direction. In this work, we hypothesize that there is a strong connection However, not all the inferences are deductive and, between logical fallacies (forms of reasoning which are therefore, logically valid [4].
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography
    BIBLIOGRAPHY [Adams, 1954] E. M. Adams. The Fundamentals ofGeneral Logic. Longmans , Green & Co., New York, 1954. [Allport, 1958] Gordon W. Allport. The Nature ofPrejudice. Doubleday An­ chor Books, Garden City, New York" 1958. [Atherton, 1993] Catherine Atherton. The Stoics on Ambiguity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1993. [Atlas, 1989] Jay David Atlas. Philosophy Without Ambiguity: A Logico­ Linguistic Essay. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1989. [Barth and Krabbe, 1982] E. M. Barth and E. C. W. Krabbe. From Axiom to Dialogue. De Gruyter, New York, 1982. [Barth and Martens, 1977] E. M. Barth and J. L. Martens. Argumentum Ad Hominem : From chaos to formal dialectic. Logique et Analyse, 77-78:76­ 96, 1977. [Beardsley, 1950] Monroe C. Beardsley. Practical Logic. Prentice-Hall, New York,1950. [Beardsley, 1956] Monroe C. Beardsley. Thinking Straight. Prentice-Hall, En­ glewood Cliffs, 1956. [Bentham, 1969] Jeremy Bentham. The book of fallacies (1824) . In Mary P. Mack, editor, A Bentham Reader, pages 331-358. Pegasus, New York, 1969. [Bertin, 1995] Oliver Bertin . Poor communication cited in ship mishaps . The Globe and Mail, B2, 18 October 1995. [Black, 1946] Max Black. Critical Thinking . Prentice-Hall, New York, 1946. [Blair, 1988] J. Anthony Blair. What is bias? In Trudy Govier, editor, Selected Issues in Logic and Communication, pages 93-103. Wadsworth , Belmont, 1988. [Brinton, 1986] Alan Brinton. Ethotic argument. History ofPhilosophy Quar­ terly, 3:245-257, 1986. [Broad and Wade, 1982] William Broad and Nicholas Wade. Betrayers ofthe Truth: Fraud and Deceit in the Halls ofScience. Simon & Schuster, New York,1982. 281 282 FALLACIES ARISING FROM AMBIGUITY [Burtt, 1931] Edwin Arthur Burtt.
    [Show full text]
  • Pressure and Argumentation in Public Controversies: a Dialogical Perspective
    Pressure and Argumentation in Public Controversies: A Dialogical Perspective JAN ALBERT VAN LAAR ERIK C. W. KRABBE Faculty of Philosophy University of Groningen Oude Boteringestraat 52 9712 GL Groningen The Netherlands [email protected] [email protected] Abstract: When can exerting pressure Résumé: Quand le fait de faire pres- in a public controversy promote rea- sion dans une controverse publique sonable outcomes, and when is it peut-il promouvoir des résultats rai- rather a hindrance? We show how sonnables, et quand est-ce plutôt un negotiation and persuasion dialogue obstacle? Nous montrons comment la can be intertwined. Then, we examine négociation et le dialogue de persua- in what ways one can in a public con- sion peuvent être entrelacés. Ensuite, troversy exert pressure on others nous examinons de quelle manière on through sanctions or rewards. Finally, peut, dans une controverse publique, we discuss from the viewpoints of faire pression sur les autres par le biais persuasion and negotiation whether de sanctions ou de récompenses. En- and, if so, how pressure hinders the fin, du point de vue de la persuasion et achievement of a reasonable outcome. de la négociation, nous discutons de la question de savoir si, et si oui, com- ment la pression empêche la réalisa- tion d’un résultat raisonnable. Keywords: argumentation, fallacies, negotiation dialogue, persuasion dialogue, pressure, public controversy 1. Introduction In public controversies, such as those about the energy transition, discussants—whether they represent authorities, interest groups, companies, or other stakeholders—are not only arguing for their © J. A. van Laar, E.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 4 – Identifying Fallacies 4.1 Introduction Ludwig Wittgenstein Once Said That His Aim in Philosophy Was to Turn Disguised Nonsense Into Patent Nonsense
    Logic: A Brief Introduction Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University Chapter 4 – Identifying Fallacies 4.1 Introduction Ludwig Wittgenstein once said that his aim in philosophy was to turn disguised nonsense into patent nonsense. What he was implying in this cryptic remark is that patent (obvious) nonsense, being easy to spot, is not as dangerously misleading as nonsense that is disguised as sense. Our task in this chapter is to unmask some common cases of disguised nonsense. When we do, we will be less prone to fall for their illusion of sense. At one time or another, we have all had the illusion that some conclusion followed from a given set of premises when in fact it did not. We might have even acted on such an illusion. Logicians call such deceptive arguments, however psychologically convincing they may be, logical fallacies. Some of these fallacies occur so often and are so psychologically convincing that we need to be on special alert to avoid them. The best way to do this is to identify (by name) examples of them, and to see exactly why the conclusions of such fallacious arguments do not follow from their premises. (There are a couple of exceptions to this rule. As we will discuss presently, the fallacy of complex question may not be formally invalid, but it is always invites bad reasoning. The other exception is the fallacy of begging the question, which is technically both valid and sound, but nevertheless a case of bad reasoning. I will say more about these exceptions in due course.) The list of fallacies varies with different authors.
    [Show full text]
  • Admit No Force but Argument
    Informal Logic X.2, Spring 1988 Admit No Force But Argument MICHAEL J. WREEN Marquette University Much has been written in recent years I about informal fallacies, and many people, this author included, have wanted to get The article I have in mind appeared in beyond what has been rightly, even if these pages in 1980, and is by Charles somewhat pejoratively, called the standard Kielkopf. Kielkopf thinks, as do I and a treatment of them. Even so, detailed discus­ number of others, that textbook treatments sions of the individual fallacies (or better, of ad baculum are superficial; but, unlike putative fallacies) found in contemporary most of us who share the view, he's gone logic texts are, with the exception of petitio on to offer a diagnosis: the superficiality is principii and argumentum ad hominem, due to "a failure to distinguish between relatively few in number. reading a conclusion primarily as a descrip­ Consider, for example, argumentum tion as opposed to reading it primarily as ad baculum, or appeal to force. Argumen­ a prescription."3 Consider, he says, the tum ad baculum is a fallacy, logic texts following reconstructed argument: often claim, and consists in appealing to Lifting the sanctions [against Zimbabwe­ force in order to prove a point. Somewhat Rhodesia] would be regarded as a more rigorously, the fallacy is said to be hostile act towards Afro-Arab nations. committed if, and only if, "an arguer Afro-Arab nations can produce serious poses a conclusion to another person and economic and political problems for tells that person either implicitly or ex­ the U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rhetoric of Law and Economics
    Michigan Law Review Volume 86 Issue 4 1988 The Rhetoric of Law and Economics Donald N. McCloskey University of Iowa Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Law and Economics Commons Recommended Citation Donald N. McCloskey, The Rhetoric of Law and Economics, 86 MICH. L. REV. 752 (1988). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol86/iss4/4 This Essay is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. .ESSAYS THE RHETORIC OF LAW AND ECONOMICS Donald N. McCloskey* Economics and law have contrasting rhetorics, which is one reason perhaps why economics has become influential in law. It is a new way of arguing, and lawyers are on the watch for new ways of arguing. These "rhetorics" are not always bad. "Rhetoric" here is not merely ornament and trickery, but all persuasion, from arithmetic to moral character. We humans must decide what arguments we find persuasive. The lawyer's appeal to stare decisis or the economist's claim to scientific status are rhetorical acts, good or bad. I want to argue that economics is a sweet science, but the rhetoric of science in economics is mainly bad, not least because it makes lawyers feel like unscientific imbeciles. Economics, like mathematics, thinks it uses no rhetoric but logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Poe's Law (Nathan Poe 2005)
    (Most quotes and definitions from Wikipedia) Poe's Law (Nathan Poe 2005) "Without a winking smiley or other blatant display of humour, it is impossible to create a parody of fundamentalism that someone won't mistake for the real thing." Relates to the impossibility of parodying extremism. In particular, it addresses the difficulty of an independent observer being able to distinguish fundamentalism from parodies of fundamentalism. Godwin’s Law (Mike Godwin 1990) "As an online discussion grows longer, the probability of a comparison involving Nazis or Hitler approaches 1." Hanlon's razor (Robert Hanlon 1980) "Never attribute to malice that which can be adequately explained by stupidity." or "Never assume malice when stupidity will suffice." No True Scotsman (Antony Flew): Or, the self-sealing fallacy, is a fallacy of equivocation and question begging. An ad hoc shift in argument, also known as "moving the goalposts". Argument: "No Scotsman puts sugar on his porridge." Reply: "But my uncle Angus, who is a Scotsman, likes sugar with his porridge." Rebuttal: "Aye, but no true Scotsman puts sugar on his porridge." Argumentum ad Ignorantiam, Argument from Ignorance: A logical fallacy in which it is claimed that a premise is true only because it has not been proven false. * Something is currently unexplained or insufficiently understood or explained, so it is not (or must not be) true. * Because there appears to be a lack of evidence for one hypothesis, another chosen hypothesis is therefore considered proven. Argument from Personal Incredulity, Argument from Personal Belief, Argument from Personal Conviction: An assertion that, because one personally finds a premise to be unlikely or unbelievable, the premise can be assumed to not be true.
    [Show full text]