Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science MINNESOTA STUDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Minnesota Studies in the PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE RONALD N. GIERE, GENERAL EDITOR HERBERT FEIGL, FOUNDING EDITOR VOLUME XIV Scientific Theories EDITED BY C. WADE SAVAGE UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA PRESS, MINNEAPOLIS Copyright © 1990 by the Regents of the University of Minnesota All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photo­ copying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior written permission of the publisher. Published by the University of Minnesota Press 2037 University Avenue Southeast, Minneapolis, MN 55414. Printed in the United States of America. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Scientific theories/edited by C. Wade Savage. p. cm. -(Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science: v. 14) Some of these papers were originally presented at an institute conducted by the Minnesota Center for Philosophy of Science from 1985 to 1987. ISBN 0-8166-1801-1 I. Science-Philosophy. 2. Science-Methodology. 3. Science-Evaluation. I. Savage, C. Wade. II. Minnesota Center for Philosophy of Science. III. Series. Ql75.M64 vol. 14 [Ql75.55] 501-dc20 90-32932 CIP The University of Minnesota is an equal-opportunity educator and employer. Contents Preface vu Introduction 3 Seek and Ye Might Find Arthur L. Caplan 22 The Psychoanalytic Enterprise in Scientific Perspective Adolf Griinbaum 41 On the Nature of Theories: A Neurocomputational Perspective Paul M. Church/and 59 Are Economic Kinds Natural? Alan Nelson 102 Foundational Physics and Empiricist Critique Lawrence Sklar 136 Theories as Mere Conventions Henry E. Kyburg, Jr. 158 Rationality and Objectivity in Science, or Tom Kuhn Meets Tom Bayes Wesley C. Salmon 175 Bayesian Problems of Old Evidence Ellery Eells 205 Fitting Your Theory to the Facts: Probably Not Such a Bad Thing After All Colin Howson 224 The Value of Knowledge Brian Skyrms 245 Demystifying Underdetermination Larry Laudan 267 Dubbing and Redubbing: The Vulnerability of Rigid Designation Thomas S. Kuhn 298 Scientific Revolutions and Scientific Rationality: The Case of the Elderly Holdout John Worrall 319 Realism, Approximate Truth, and Philosophical Method Richard Boyd 355 Contrastive Empiricism Elliott Sober 392 Contributors 413 Consensus Institute Staff 417 Author Index 421 Subject Index 425 Preface From the fall of 1985 through the spring of 1987 the Minnesota Center for Philos­ ophy of Science conducted an institute-an ongoing conference-whose focal question was: Is there a new consensus in the philosophy of science? The old con­ sensus was of course logical empiricism, or positivism, the position forged during the first half of the century by Russell, Schlick, Carnap, Feigl, Reichenbach, Hempel, Nagel, and others, and dissolved during the third quarter by the criti­ cisms of Quine, Hanson, Feyerabend, Kuhn, and others. The explicit purpose of the conference was to ascertain whether, in the wake of this criticism and the resulting loss of focus and direction, some new consensus was emerging that might come to provide the same sort of structure and direction for the field as had the old consensus. For this purpose the field was initially divided into three tradi­ tional areas: scientific explanation, scientific theories, and scientific justification or evaluation. The present volume's predecessor and companion - Scientific Ex­ planation, volume 13, edited by Philip Kitcher and Wesley Salmon-contains papers in the first area. The present volume contains papers in the second and third areas. It is not a conference proceedings in the strict sense, for some par­ ticipants did not write papers and some wrote them afterward, and some papers were additionally solicited. Furthermore, at later stages two other areas were added to the agenda: the relation between history and philosophy of science, and recent developments in the philosophy of cognitive science. With few exceptions, these additional symposia are not represented in the two volumes. What then is our result? Is a new consensus emerging in the philosophy of science, either in general, or in the special areas represented by the two volumes? Comments here will be limited to the nature and acceptance of scientific theories. (Comments on scientific explanation can be found in volume 13.) The answer to the special question would seem to be negative. The syntactic view that a theory is an axiomatized collection of sentences has been challenged by the semantic view that a theory is a collection of nonlinguistic models, and both are challenged by the view that a theory is an amorphous entity consisting perhaps of sentences and models, but just as importantly of exemplars, problems, standards, skills, vii viii Preface practices, and tendencies. Similarly, several views of theory confirmation com­ pete for allegiance. The best confirmed theory is variously held to be the one with the greatest number and variety of observed consequences, the one with the highest degree of confirmation (probability) on the observed evidence, or the one that best explains the observed evidence. Some theorists regard a decision­ theoretic approach as superior to those above. Still others hold that theories of confirmation beg the question of whether theories are, can be, or should be "confirmed" and recommend replacing them by accounts of how theories are dis­ covered, accepted, and developed. The answer to the general question is more complex, partly because it applies to more areas than the traditional three above, and partly because it includes second-order questions about the nature and scope of philosophy of science (which naturally complicate the first-order questions). Nonetheless, the answer here also seems to be negative. The once dominant conception of philosophy of science as the logical analysis and reconstruction of science is generally regarded to be moribund, and no comparably general conception has replaced it. Philoso­ phy of science has become exceedingly broad and diverse. It now attends to prac­ tical and experimental science in addition to theoretical science, and it examines a virtually unrestricted range of sciences and scientific practices. It is no longer simply the logic and methodology of science, but involves in addition the history, sociology, and psychology of science. These developments have been accompa­ nied by the growing view that philosophy of science should be scientific, naturalistic. This view regards previous theories of the structure and acceptance of scientific theories as idealizations, and recommends replacing them by ac­ counts of what science is actually, in its natural psychosocial setting. Such studies have led some to conclude that science is not an objective, rule-governed, rational activity, and that its development is not a rational process. On one suggestion, the development of science is a process comparable to Darwinian natural selec­ tion. Another view is that, although scientific rationality cannot be equated with logicality, science is rational in a sense philosophers are currently attempting to explicate. The welter of conflicting views has suggested to many that the only consensus in philosophy of science is that there is no consensus. Indeed, the pluralistic ideol­ ogy currently in favor is unsympathetic to attempts to achieve or even locate con­ sensus, for fear that some new and equally stifling dogma will replace the old. It seems that to seek now for anything so definite as consensus in philosophy of science-some set of doctrines to rival the positivist consensus of earlier years - is premature at best. The field seems to contain too much diversity and too much ferment to permit it. Most of the essays presented here reflect the concerns and themes of current philosophy of science, either by pursuing them, or by criticizing them, or by at­ tempting to harmonize them with others, occasionally with some of the old con- PREFACE ix sensus. Although they do not constitute a new consensus, and perhaps do not even point toward one, they do provide a bridge between the old and the new. One goal of our institute was to survey current philosophy in a manner that would be useful to a general academic audience as well as to specialists in the field. As a consequence, most of the essays are relatively accessible, and the in­ troduction has been designed to increase their accessibility and usefulness to those who wish to sample the field. The volume should therefore be suitable for begin­ ning graduate and advanced undergraduate courses, as well as the more advanced contexts. We wish to acknowledge the support of institutions and individuals who made our institute on consensus possible. A major grant from the National Endowment of the Humanities provided most of the funds for the conference. (Philip Kitcher and Wade Savage were the principal investigators.) The College of Liberal Arts and the Office of the President of the University of Minnesota provided a substan­ tial supplementary grant. We thank them all. We also thank the faculty who staffed the institute; their names appear at the end of the volume. Finally, we thank the students and faculty who attended the lectures and contributed to the discussions. It was a stimulating experience for everyone involved. CONTRIBUTORS Contributors Richard Boyd is a professor of philosophy in the Sage School of Philosophy at Cornell University. He is the author of a long series of papers defending scientific realism, one of which appears in this volume. His other published works have been in the philosophy of mind, the philosophy of psychology, semantic theory, the theory of natural kinds, and metaethics. Arthur Caplan is a professor of philosophy and member of the Center for Philoso­ phy of Science at the University of Minnesota. He is also director of the Center for Biomedical Ethics and a professor of surgery at the University of Minnesota. Caplan received his Ph.D. in philosophy from Columbia University and has taught there and at the University of Pittsburgh.
Recommended publications
  • Curriculum Vitae
    BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN Curriculum Vitae Last updated 3/6/2019 I. Personal and Academic History .................................................................................................................... 1 List of Degrees Earned ........................................................................................................................................................ 1 Title of Ph.D. Thesis ........................................................................................................................................................... 1 Positions held ..................................................................................................................................................................... 1 Invited lectures and lecture series ........................................................................................................................................ 1 List of Honors, Prizes ......................................................................................................................................................... 4 Research Grants .................................................................................................................................................................. 4 Non-Academic Publications ................................................................................................................................................ 5 II. Professional Activities .................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Issues Concerning Scientific Realism
    The Future of the Scientific Realism Debate: Contemporary Issues Concerning Scientific Realism Author(s): Curtis Forbes Source: Spontaneous Generations: A Journal for the History and Philosophy of Science, Vol. 9, No. 1 (2018) 1-11. Published by: The University of Toronto DOI: 10.4245/sponge.v9i1. EDITORIALOFFICES Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology Room 316 Victoria College, 91 Charles Street West Toronto, Ontario, Canada M5S 1K7 [email protected] Published online at jps.library.utoronto.ca/index.php/SpontaneousGenerations ISSN 1913 0465 Founded in 2006, Spontaneous Generations is an online academic journal published by graduate students at the Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology, University of Toronto. There is no subscription or membership fee. Spontaneous Generations provides immediate open access to its content on the principle that making research freely available to the public supports a greater global exchange of knowledge. The Future of the Scientific Realism Debate: Contemporary Issues Concerning Scientific Realism Curtis Forbes* I. Introduction “Philosophy,” Plato’s Socrates said, “begins in wonder” (Theaetetus, 155d). Two and a half millennia later, Alfred North Whitehead saw fit to add: “And, at the end, when philosophical thought has done its best, the wonder remains” (1938, 168). Nevertheless, we tend to no longer wonder about many questions that would have stumped (if not vexed) the ancients: “Why does water expand when it freezes?” “How can one substance change into another?” “What allows the sun to continue to shine so brightly, day after day, while all other sources of light and warmth exhaust their fuel sources at a rate in proportion to their brilliance?” Whitehead’s addendum to Plato was not wrong, however, in the sense that we derive our answers to such questions from the theories, models, and methods of modern science, not the systems, speculations, and arguments of modern philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Dissertation Abstract
    SCIENTIFIC ANOMALY AND BIOLOGICAL EFFECTS OF LOW-DOSE CHEMICALS: ELUCIDATING NORMATIVE ETHICS AND SCIENTIFIC DISCOVERY A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Notre Dame in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Kevin Christopher Elliott, B.S., M.A. _________________________________ Kristin S. Shrader-Frechette, Director Graduate Program in History and Philosophy of Science Notre Dame, Indiana April 2004 © Copyright by Kevin C. Elliott 2004 All rights reserved SCIENTIFIC ANOMALY AND BIOLOGICAL EFFECTS OF LOW-DOSE CHEMICALS: ELUCIDATING NORMATIVE ETHICS AND SCIENTIFIC DISCOVERY Abstract by Kevin Christopher Elliott The notion of “anomaly” has persisted for over 2,000 years, but its precise meaning and significance remains unclear. This dissertation analyzes the importance of scientific anomaly both for the philosophy of science and for ethical decision-making that draws on scientific information. In the philosophy of science, it develops a novel account of anomaly. It first provides a conceptual framework for describing anomalies and critically evaluates previous descriptions by Karl Popper, Thomas Kuhn, Imre Lakatos, Larry Laudan, and Lindley Darden. Using the anomalous contemporary biological phenomenon known as “chemical hormesis” (i.e., beneficial effects from low doses of toxins) as a case study, the dissertation argues for a novel account that emphasizes three features of anomaly. Namely, researchers “characterize” anomalies in multiple ways, scientists use multiple strategies to “confirm” them, and anomalies interact with novel hypotheses in an ongoing, dialectical fashion. The dissertation argues that this account is significant because it facilitates increased understanding of scientific discovery and of the role that value judgments play in science.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory Choice, Theory Change, and Inductive Truth-Conduciveness
    Theory Choice, Theory Change, and Inductive Truth-Conduciveness Konstantin Genin Kevin T. Kelly Carnegie Mellon University [email protected] [email protected] Konstantin Genin (CMU) May 21, 2015 1 This talk is about ... (1) the synchronic norms of theory choice, (2) the diachronic norms of theory change, and the justification of (1-2) by reliability, or truth-conduciveness. Konstantin Genin (CMU) May 21, 2015 2 This talk is about ... (1) the synchronic norms of theory choice, (2) the diachronic norms of theory change, and (3) the justification of (1-2) by reliability, or truth-conduciveness. Konstantin Genin (CMU) May 21, 2015 3 This talk is about ... (1) the synchronic norms of theory choice, (2) the diachronic norms of theory change, and (3) the justification of (1-2) by reliability, or truth-conduciveness. Konstantin Genin (CMU) May 21, 2015 4 The Norms of Theory Choice Synchronic norms of theory choice restrict the theories one can choose in light of given, empirical information. Konstantin Genin (CMU) May 21, 2015 5 The Norms of Theory Choice: Simplicity Figure: William of Ockham, 1287-1347 All things being equal, prefer simpler theories. Konstantin Genin (CMU) May 21, 2015 6 The Norms of Theory Choice: Falsifiability Figure: Sir Karl Popper, 1902-1994 All things being equal, prefer more falsifiable theories. Konstantin Genin (CMU) May 21, 2015 7 The Norms of Theory Choice: Reliable? Is the simpler / more falsifiable theory more plausible? Yes! Can prior probabilities encode that preference? Yes! Konstantin Genin (CMU) May 21, 2015
    [Show full text]
  • PHYSICS, PHILOSOPHY and PSYCHOANALYSIS Essays in Honor of Adolf Grilnbaum
    PHYSICS, PHILOSOPHY AND PSYCHOANALYSIS Essays in Honor of Adolf Grilnbaum Edited by R. s. COHEN Boston University and L. LAUDAN Virginia Polytechnic Institute D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY A MEMBER OF THE KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS GROUP DORDRECHT I BOSTON I LANCASTER Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Main entry under title: Physics, philosophy, and psychoanalysis. (Boston studies in the philosophy of science; v. 76) Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Physics-Philo sophy-Addresses, essays, lectures. 2. Philos- ophy-Addresses, essays, lectures. 3. Psychoanalysis-Addresses, essays;lectures. 4. Griinbaum, Adolf. I. Griinbaum, Adolf. II. Cohen, Robert Sonne. III. Series. Q174.B67 vol. 76 [QC6.21 501s 1530'.011 83-4576 ISBN-I3: 978-94-009-7057-1 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-7055-7 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-009-7055-7 Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17,3300 AA Dordrecht, Holland. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Boston Inc., 190 Old Derby Street, Hingham, MA 02043, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, Holland. All Rights Reserved. Copyright © 1983 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland and copyright holders as specified on appropriate pages within. Softcover reprint of the hardcover 15t edition 1983 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any informational storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner.
    [Show full text]
  • Private Vices, Scientific Virtues: Using Economics to Think About Science
    Private Vices, Scientific Virtues: Using Economics to Think about Science THOMAS C. LEONARD Department of Economics Fisher Hall Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544 United States [email protected] phone: (609) 258-4036 fax: (609) 258-5561 1999 Private Vices, Scientific Virtues: Using Economics to Think about Science Abstract This paper makes a case for using economics to study science and its product, scientific knowledge. Traditional theories of science – due mainly to epistemology – imply that science is successful because scientists are selfless truth seekers, and because they rigidly adhere to a method. Post-modern theories of science – due mainly to sociology and literary theory – argue that science cannot be successful, because scientists are neither disinterested nor selfless, and because methodological rules derive from a faulty epistemology. An economic theory of science argues that, contra the traditional view, successful science doesn’t require the restrictive premises of Traditional theory of science, and that, as a result, contra the Post-modern view, successful science is not ruled out when those premises are. An economic theory of science accommodates both a realistic conception of scientific motivation and procedure, and the possibility of genuine scientific success. In so doing, it offers an intellectual means to address a central question in the theory of science: how do self-interested scientists, who have wordly goals, come to produce the collectively beneficial outcome of reliable scientific knowledge. Keywords Economics of science, philosophy of science, bounded rationality, institutions, scientific knowledge, economic methodology 2 1. Introduction This paper takes up a conundrum that immediately presents itself to the economist considering science.
    [Show full text]
  • Lawrence Sklar
    LAWRENCE SKLAR Born: June 25, 1938 in Baltimore, MD Married to: Elizabeth S. Sklar; one child Education Oberlin College, B.A., 1958 Princeton University, M.A., 1960; Ph.D., 1964 Fellowships, Awards and National Offices Held Undergraduate Ford Foundation Early Admission Scholarship Honors List (all years) Phi Beta Kappa (elected in junior year) Sigma Xi (associate member) Graduate Woodrow Wilson Fellowship, 1959-60 Chancellor Green Fellowship, 1960-61 Charlotte Elizabeth Proctor Advanced Fellowship (awarded to top ten students in third year graduate class), 1961-62 National Science Foundation Cooperative Fellowship, 1962-63 Post-Graduate American Council of Learned Societies Study Fellowship (held at Oxford University), 1965-66 John Simon Guggenheim Memorial Foundation Fellowship, 1974-75 Franklin J. Matchette Prize. Awarded by the American Philosophical Association to Space, Time, and Spacetime as outstanding philosophical book of 1973 and 1974 National Science Foundation Research Grants, 1977-78, 1979-80, 1982, 1984-85, 1986-87, 1988-89, 1998-2001, 2002-03 Rackham Foundation Summer Research Fellowship, 1983, 1994 2 Nelson Fellow, Philosophy Department, University of Michigan, l991-l994, 1995- James B. and Grace J. Nelson Professorship, Philosophy Department, University of Michigan, 1994-95 National Endowment for the Humanities Fellowship, 1995-96 Faculty Recognition Award, University of Michigan, 1995-98 William K. Frankena Collegiate Professorship, University of Michigan, 1995-2002 Lakatos Award. Awarded to Physics and Chance as outstanding book in the philosophy of science for 1995. Physics and Chance selected by Choice Magazine as Outstanding Academic Book in philosophy of science for 1995 Fellow, American Academy of Arts and Sciences John Locke Lectureship in Philosophy, 1998, Oxford University Visiting Fellowship, All Souls College, Oxford University, 1998 Michigan Humanities Award, 1998-99.
    [Show full text]
  • The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
    The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T.
    [Show full text]
  • Ernan Mcmullin's Thought on Science and Theology: an Appreciation
    Open Theology 2015; 1: 512–523 Science and/or Religion: a 21st Century Debate Open Access Research Article Amerigo Barzaghi*, Josep Corcó Ernan McMullin’s Thought on Science and Theology: An Appreciation DOI 10.1515/opth-2015-0032 Received July 30, 2015; accepted September 24, 2015 Abstract: The thought of Ernan McMullin on the relationship between science and theology can be summarized with a word that he himself used: consonance. We briefly describe this epistemological proposal, and we show a concrete instance of its application by way of a short analysis of one of McMullin’s interdisciplinary works, “Cosmic Purpose and the Contingency of Human Evolution.” With the help of the authoritative comment that William Stoeger has made on this paper, we sketch McMullin’s effort to find a consonance between two different claims: the theological one – humans expected – and the evolutionary one – humans unexpected. In this case, consonance is reached by recurring to the classic Augustinian notion of the atemporality of God. We then show how McMullin’s way of interpreting consonance affects the question of the viability of a natural theology in a scientifically informed era. In fact, his distrust of various kinds of natural theology is another crucial aspect of his epistemological framework for interdisciplinary dialogue. Keywords: consonance, Ernan McMullin, evolutionary contingency, natural theology Introduction Ernan McMullin (1924-2011) was an Irish thinker very well-known for being a learned scholar in different disciplines. During his long career, he provided important contributions in distinct areas of knowledge, such as the philosophy of science, the history of science, and the science-theology relationship.1 In this paper, we will focus on some of McMullin’s reflections in the third of these fields of inquiry.
    [Show full text]
  • Roberto Festa – Curriculum E Pubblicazioni
    ROBERTO FESTA – CURRICULUM E PUBBLICAZIONI CURRICULUM Attività scientifica Nel 1979 mi sono laureato in Filosofia presso l =Università di Bologna, discutendo una tesi su ALa valutazione delle ipotesi scientifiche: dalla teoria della conferma alla teoria delle decisioni cognitive @. Nel 1982 ho conseguito il diploma di perfezionamento in Metodologia della Ricerca Filosofica e Filosofia delle Scienze, presso l =Università di Padova, con una tesi su AL'approssimazione alla verità come obiettivo teorico della scienza @. Grazie a borse di studio del Ministero degli Esteri, ho trascorso un periodo di studio all'Università di Helsinki e due all'Università di Groningen. A Helsinki (a.a. 1981-1982) ho condotto una ricerca sulla verosimilitudine delle teorie scientifiche con la supervisione di Ilkka Niiniluoto; a Groningen (a.a. 1983-84 e 1986-87) mi sono occupato di verosimilitudine e probabilità induttive, in collaborazione con Theo Kuipers. A partire dal 1986 ho lavorato ! con la supervisione di T. Kuipers (Facoltà di Filosofia di Groningen) e W. Molenaar (Dipartimento di Statistica di Groningen) ! a una dissertazione dal titolo AOptimum Inductive Methods @, che ho discusso il 12 novembre 1992, ottenendo così il titolo di Philosophiae Doctor (Ph. D.) in Filosofia della scienza. Il volume Optimum Inductive Methods , uscito nel 1993 per i tipi della Kluwer Academic Publishers, è una versione modificata della dissertazione dottorale. L'argomento principale del volume è il problema della scelta delle probabilità iniziali nelle inferenze bayesiane. Esso include diversi risultati originali, tra i quali una nuova soluzione del problema della scelta del metodo induttivo >ottimale = per le inferenze multinomiali. Tale soluzione viene ottenuta usando strumenti concettuali provenienti da tre diverse aree di indagine: la teoria delle probabilità induttive, la statistica bayesiana, e le ricerche sulla verosimilitudine.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Pessimistic Induction & Two Fallacies
    On The Pessimistic Induction & Two Fallacies Juha Saatsi University of Leeds Abstract. The Pessimistic Induction from falsity of past theories forms a perennial argument against scientific realism. This paper considers and rebuts two recent arguments due to Lewis (2001) and Lange (2002) to the conclusion that the argument from Pessimistic Induction (in its best known form) is actually fallacious. With this I want to re-establish the dignity of the Pessimistic Induction by calling to mind the basic objective of the argument, and hence restore the propriety of the realist program of responding to PMI by undermining one or another of its premises. 1. Introduction Probably the best known and the most central single argument against scientific realism is the argument from Pessimistic Induction (Poincaré 1952; Putnam 1978; Laudan 1981). This argument in some form or another has been part and parcel of the quintessential realism debate for quite some time now; it is therefore very interesting to come across two recent papers which both claim that the argument in its best-known form is actually fallacious (Lange 2002; Lewis 2001). Here I want to re-establish the dignity of the Pessimistic Induction by calling to mind the basic objective of the argument, and hence restore the propriety of the realist program of responding to PMI by undermining one or another of the premises of this otherwise valid argument. I take the Pessimistic (Meta-)Induction (PMI) against scientific realism to be in essence the argument employed by Larry Laudan in his highly influential anti-realist manifesto A confutation of convergent realism (1981).
    [Show full text]
  • Tim W. E. Maudlin Curriculum Vitae
    Tim W. E. Maudlin curriculum vitae Dep't of Philosophy Davison Hall Douglass College Rutgers University New Brunswick, NJ 08903 (732) 932-9861 Education 1986 Ph.D., University of Pittsburgh, History & Philosophy of Science 1982 M.A., University of Pittsburgh, History & Philosophy of Science 1980 B.A., Yale University, Physics & Philosophy 1976 Diploma, The Sidwell Friends School, Washington DC Employment and Teaching Experience 2005- present Professor II, Rutgers University 1996-2005 Professor, Rutgers University 1996 Visiting Associate Professor, Harvard University 1992- 96 Associate Professor, Rutgers University 1986-92 Assistant Professor, Rutgers University 1985-86 Visiting Lecturer, Carnegie-Mellon University 1984-85 Teaching Fellow, University of Pittsburgh 1982-83 Teaching Fellow, University of Pittsburgh Academic Awards, Honors, and Fellowships 2008 Guggenheim Fellowship 2007 Elected to Academie Internationale de Philosophie des Sciences 1992 Rutgers University Board of Trustees Research Fellowship for Scholarly Excellence 1992 NEH Summer Stipend to complete book manuscript Quantum Non-Locality and Relativity 1989 Invited participant, Sixty-two Years of Uncertainty: Historical, Philosophical and Physics Inquiries into the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics , International School of History of Science,Ettore Majorana Centre for Scientific Culture, Erice, Italy 1988 Participant in National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Institute on Aristotle's Metaphysics, Biology and Ethics 1986-88 Henry Rutgers Research Fellowship, Rutgers
    [Show full text]