Impartialist Ethics and Psychic Disintegration: a Talking Cure Roman Nakia Briggs University of Arkansas, Fayetteville

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Impartialist Ethics and Psychic Disintegration: a Talking Cure Roman Nakia Briggs University of Arkansas, Fayetteville University of Arkansas, Fayetteville ScholarWorks@UARK Theses and Dissertations 12-2015 Impartialist Ethics and Psychic Disintegration: A Talking Cure Roman Nakia Briggs University of Arkansas, Fayetteville Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.uark.edu/etd Part of the Clinical Psychology Commons, and the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Briggs, Roman Nakia, "Impartialist Ethics and Psychic Disintegration: A Talking Cure" (2015). Theses and Dissertations. 1320. http://scholarworks.uark.edu/etd/1320 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UARK. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UARK. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Impartialist Ethics and Psychic Disintegration: A Talking Cure A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Roman Nakia Briggs Henderson State University Bachelor of Arts in Psychology, 2003 University of Arkansas Master of Arts in Philosophy, 2005 December 2015 University of Arkansas This dissertation is approved for recommendation to the Graduate Council. ____________________________________ Dr. Richard Lee Dissertation Director ____________________________________ ____________________________________ Dr. Eric Funkhouser Dr. Edward Minar Committee Member Committee Member Abstract This dissertation deals with integrity understood as a state of the psyche. Its primary interlocutor is Professor Bernard Williams, and its point of departure is my interpretation of his Objection from Integrity to impartialist moral theories. Against Williams, I hope to show that the active adherent of impartialist ethical systems (e.g., act utilitarianism) may retain both moral integrity and integrity. In demonstrating this, I make use of a variant of Roy Schafer’s action language approach to psychoanalysis, and what I call practical aestheticism . Acknowledgements The plan was to write up a detailed set of acknowledgements, thanking each of you in specifics. However, as I started the first mental draft of this project, it occurred to me that this would involve a dissertation-length manuscript all its own. For the sake of brevity (and expensive paper), please accept by most sincere and perhaps too concise Thanks ! Thanks, first and foremost, to my parents, Ronald and Mona Briggs – words always fail in describing my love for and gratefulness to you both; I couldn’t have done this without you has never been said with more sincerity. I love you and cherish you more than you know. Thanks, too, to Ryder and Wyatt – I love you, boys! And, of course, big thanks to my dissertation committee: the omnibenevolent and über-patient Richard Lee, Eric Funkhouser, and Ed Minar – you guys are the best! And [in alphabetical order] big thank you shout-outs to: Celeste Atkins; Aaron Baker; Oliver Balson; David Barrett; Norm Bates; Tanya and AJ Biami; Chad Bogosian; The Briggs Brothers (and Sister); Bruce and Chico; Jeff Byrnes; Aaron and Kristin Champene; Stefanie Childers-Turner; Paul Cudney; Joshua and Jenna Daniel; Karen Davidson; Wakanda Davidson; Diana Dominguez; Kevin Durand; Adam and Christy Erwin; Alex Felton; Bob and Kara Fink; Reagan Funkhouser; John Gulley; Angela Hackstadt; Karly Hamilton-Scarbrough; Zac Harmon; Dawna and Jake Hendricks; Chuck Hoyack; The Huffman family; Jim Lampinen; Steve Levine; Jack and Raina Lyons; Virginia Pfau- Thompson; Tetima Parnprome; Tatiana Patrone; Cameron Pershall; Jeff Perumal; Matt and Christina Pianalto; James Pierce; Julie Pollock; Ray Porter; Jennifer Rowe; Sharon Seals; Tom and Georgia Senor; Jerry Sillavan; Lynne Spellman; Sherry Sparks; Barry Ward; Denise Wells; Jeremy and PJ Williams; Holly Wimer; Tony Woodside; and, Kathryn Zawisza. And, in memoriam, infinite love and thanks to my sister, Heather Briggs Sillavan – you’re with me every moments of every day, sis. To my grandparents, John Jr. and Jesse Mae Briggs and Ray and Jane Davidson; and, to my dear friends, John Foster, Don Ledford, Cody Moore, and Jack and Kevin Walters – you are missed. Special thanks to Christine Korsgaard for allowing me to view an advanced e-copy of her then-unpublished Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity (2009); and, to Darcia Narvaez for allowing me to view an advanced e-copy of her then-unpublished Character: Essays in Moral Psychology (2009). Special thanks, too, to the attendees of both the International Conference on Persons (BYU, August 2011), and Desire, Drive, Dissent (University of New Mexico, April 2012) for extremely helpful comments on earlier versions of portions of this dissertation. For anyone that I managed to forget in name, please except my apologies. Roman Briggs August 31, 2015 Dedication This dissertation is dedicated to my parents, Ronald and Mona Briggs – persons of integrity. And, it was completed in memory of my sister, Heather Briggs-Sillavan – a beautiful self. Table of Contents Preliminaries Introduction . .1 Notes . 9 Chapter 1 1.0: Introduction . .14 1.1: Selves Disintegrated . 16 1.2: The Objection from Integrity . 26 1.3: Selves Reintegrated . 33 1.4: Selves Perfected . 43 1.5: Selves Abandoned . .57 Notes . 72 Chapter 2 1.0: Introduction . 109 2.1: Persons as Agents . 114 2.2: Agents in Time . .124 2.3: Time and Value . .131 2.4: Evaluators as Selves . .147 2.5: Selves and Moral Selves . .161 Notes . .170 Chapter 3 3.0: Introduction . 196 3.1: Utilitarianism and Disintegration . 198 3.2: Disintegration and Moral Death . .216 3.3: Action and Reintegration . .235 3.4: Reintegration and Aesthetics . .254 3.5: Concluding Thoughts . .280 Notes . 286 Appendices I: The Objection from Integrity . 318 II. Necessary Conditions of Personhood . 319 III. Necessary Conditions of Selfhood . 320 IV. Necessary Conditions of Moral Selfhood . .321 Bibliography . .322 Introduction I’m an avid consumer of hardboiled fiction – the pulpier, the better. As an enthusiast of this genre, I especially enjoy Raymond Chandler’s run of stories featuring the quintessential world-weary gumshoe, Philip Marlowe – The Big Sleep , in particular. The following is an interesting story about that story, which I hope will shed some light on my overall approach to this project, and what I had hoped to accomplish in completing it. When The Big Sleep was being adapted to the silver screen for the first time (the 1946 MGM release, costarring Humphrey Bogart and Lauren Bacall), its trio of screenwriters pored over Chandler’s text in attempt to unravel one uncommonly elusive thread. Namely, they needed to establish who killed General Sternwood’s chauffeur, and what the murderer’s motive was. The novel informs us only that the General’s Buick was fished out of the Pacific, the driver’s body still draped around the steering column; that upon impact he had sustained a broken neck, determined by authorities to be the cause of death; that he had been struck across the temple with a blunt object just prior to this; and, finally, that the car’s throttle had been jammed, causing it to accelerate rapidly off of a wharf, and into the ocean.1 These facts certainly suggest that foul play was involved. But, assuming that this is so, who done it? After unsuccessfully trying to deduce this from more unambiguous plot points, the scriptists eventually relented, and decided to contact the author, himself. When asked who offed the driver and why, Chandler admitted, somewhat embarrassingly I imagine, 1 that he had no idea.2 Forced to take creative license, the screenwriters decided to simply divulge the facetious speculations of Chief Inspector Ohls, and to leave it at that: “Could be a drunk, or a suicide.” Pay no attention to the premortem bump on the head and the obviously tampered-with (in this version) Packard. For whatever reason, Bogie’s Marlowe seems to let this matter go, and the film, like its source material, closes without any resolution. In the 1978 version of the film (distributed by United Artists, and starring Robert Mitchum), the chauffer’s death enjoys its own scene. Here, we see him seem to intentionally speed the General’s Bentley sedan off of a pier, into the choppy waters of the English Channel.3 Rather than providing ultimate explanation, though, this raises another, somewhat more involved question: Why did he do it? Perhaps he had succumbed to the effects of a broken heart. After all, we’re informed, the driver had fallen madly in love with the General’s insatiable daughter, Camilla (in the book and first film, Carmen). And, we all know well and good that that was never going to work out, given the severity of her issues. By the time the Coen Brothers tipped their fedora to Chandler with their deliberately slack homage, The Big Lebowski , the chauffer had disappeared altogether – his few functionary roles being subsumed by other characters less dispensable with respect to pushing forward the narrative. 4 Here we have one sliver of the structural evolution of The Big Sleep . Was Chandler’s story improved by retellings which included such changes? In a strictly 2 formative sense, sure. Otherwise, not so much. The novel, in my mind, bests all film adaptations. The first film adaptation is superior to the second. And, the second, at least insofar as we’re talking about instances of gritty and grisly dime fiction, per se, is preferable to the third. With each successive reworking, however, certain elements of the story – again, the how and why
Recommended publications
  • Plato's Phaedo As a Pedagogical Drama
    Ancient Philosophy 33 (2013) ©Mathesis Publications 333 Plato’s Phaedo as a Pedagogical Drama Sarah Jansen The Phaedo has long been recognized as dramatic in nature (see, e.g., Jowett 1892, 193). Indeed, the dialogue’s dramatic portrayal of a Herculean Socrates attacking the heads of a hydra naturally invites this assessment (89c). At the out- set of the dialogue Socrates and the fourteen named companions are juxtaposed with Theseus and the fourteen Athenian youth, on their way to defeat the Mino- taur (58a-c).1 Also, Socrates’ death scene is particularly dramatic. Fifteen com- panions, the exact number of a tragic chorus, surround the dying Socrates and lament (117c-d).2 Reflection on this scene has prompted scholars to speculate that it is intended to ‘lend moving force’ to the tragic perspective and to ‘rouse’ readers’ emotions (see Halliwell 1984, 57-58 and Crotty 2009, 87, respectively). Despite these scholarly observations and compelling evidence that the dia- logues were treated as dramatic performance literature in antiquity (see Charal- abopoulos 2012), a number of key questions have yet to be satisfactorily and systematically answered: What is drama?; What is the Phaedo a drama about?; What is the function, if any, of the dramatic elements of the Phaedo? I undertake to answer these questions. I conclude with some thoughts about Plato’s purpose in writing dramatic dialogues and Plato’s attitude toward poetry. One of my aims throughout will be to demonstrate how a proper understanding of the literary dimension of the Phaedo sheds light on the philosophical content of the dialogue.
    [Show full text]
  • ON PLATO's CONCEPT of REASON by M. Cole Powers, BA, Philosophy
    ON PLATO’S CONCEPT OF REASON By M. Cole Powers, B.A., Philosophy (McGill 2013) A thesis presented to Ryerson University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of PHILOSOPHY Toronto, Ontario, Canada, 2016 © M. Cole Powers 2016 AUTHOR'S DECLARATION FOR ELECTRONIC SUBMISSION OF A THESIS I, Cole Powers, hereby declare that I am the sole author of this thesis. This is a true copy of the thesis, including any required final revisions, as accepted by my examiners. I authorize Ryerson University to lend this thesis to other institutions or individuals for the purpose of scholarly research. I further authorize Ryerson University to reproduce this thesis by photocopying or by other means, in total or in part, at the request of other institutions or individuals for the purpose of scholarly research. I understand that my thesis may be made electronically available to the public. ii ON PLATO’S CONCEPT OF REASON MATHEW COLE POWERS MASTER OF ARTS ‐ PHILOSOPHY 2016 RYERSON UNIVERSITY ABSTRACT What is reason? A number of contemporary philosophical schools of thought have sought, implicitly or explicitly, to answer the question. That an answer to the question be found is of utmost importance for the practice of philosophy, and yet none seems to be forthcoming. In this thesis, we propose to examine Plato’s concept of reason. Our method in the thesis, however, is to proceed negatively: first, we examine the misology passage from the Phaedo 89d: why is the greatest evil to become a misologue (hater of reason)? What does this say about Plato’s conception of reason? What is the connection between reason, pleasure, and pain? Next, we move to the Phaedrus, where a more constructive account is offered.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato As a Philosophy Salesman in the Phaedo Marlon Jesspher B
    Philosophy for Business – Issue 80 – 11th February 2017 http://www.isfp.co.uk/businesspathways/ Plato as a Philosophy Salesman in the Phaedo Marlon Jesspher B. De Vera Introduction In this paper, I attempt to argue that Plato’s main intent in the Phaedo is not to build and present an argument for the immortality of the soul, but rather to elevate, promote, and in a sense “sell” philosophy as the highest pursuit of humanity. As an initial support for this argument, it is worth emphasizing that the Phaedo presents in a somewhat dramatic manner how Socrates spent the last day of his life philosophizing with his students. Thus, it can be said that the setting of the Phaedo in itself already sets an appropriate backdrop against which philosophy can be promoted as the ultimate human endeavour that is worth undertaking, in the sense that even in the face of death, the true lover of wisdom would still choose to spend his or her remaining time on earth practicing philosophy. However, it would not be sufficient to simply rely on this connection with the dialogue’s dramatic setting to assert that the dialogue’s main purpose is to promote and “sell” philosophy. Thus, I now attempt to strengthen this assertion further by presenting three supporting arguments. 1. Plato’s main intent is to promote philosophy to the Pythagoreans, and not to construct proofs for Pythagorean beliefs It is important to note that Socrates’ main discussants in the dialogue, Simmias and Cebes, are Pythagoreans who had core beliefs on the immortality of the soul, reincarnation, and the notion that the body contaminates the soul.
    [Show full text]
  • “Follow the Argument” and Two Other Socratic Principles for the Christian
    DRAFT VERSION ©2004 David H. Calhoun All rights reserved. “Follow the Argument” and Two Other Socratic Principles for the Christian Academic David Calhoun, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, September 10, 2004 “What indeed has Athens to do with Jerusalem?” So asked the early church father Tertullian, who notoriously answered, Nothing good.1 What has philosophical reason to do with Christian faith? What has Socrates to do with Christ? Tertullian’s answer to the question has not been the majority position throughout Christian history, but it has a particular resonance for many people today. Thanks in large part to the perception of conflicts between science—especially evolutionary biology—and religion, many critics of Christianity,2 and indeed many Christians, have posited a radical distinction between reason, argument, and evidence on the one hand and Christian faith and practice on the other. Few Christians today are willing to embrace the austere anti-logic of Tertullian’s “I believe because it is absurd,”3 preferring instead to think of faith in existential-fideistic terms. I mean by “existential-fideistic” something like the standard contemporary account that faith is a matter of “just believing,” of passionately giving assent to beliefs that in principle cannot be justified rationally. Christian beliefs might not be absurd or crazy—after all, the story goes, each person is entitled to believe whatever he or she wants—but it would be mistaken to look for reasons to ground these beliefs. For anyone holding this view, Socrates makes a rather odd patron saint. Still worse, critics in the spirit of Tertullian might argue that Socrates’ philosophical mission was essentially anti-religious, insofar as he attacked the traditional religious mythology of his time and set up human rationality as a competing source of truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Misology and the Natural Dialectic
    volume 19, no. 47 1. Philosophy and Common Moral Cognition october 2019 Towards the conclusion of the First Section of the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant describes a process whereby a subject can undergo a certain kind of moral corruption. This process, which he calls a “natural dialectic”, can cause one to undermine one’s own or- dinary grasp of the demands of morality (4: 405).1 The threat of the natural dialectic is of particular interest since it not only gives a precise Kant on Misology and causal account of the phenomenon of moral corruption but also con- stitutes Kant’s case for the relevance of philosophy to everyday practi- cal life. The question as to whether and how philosophy can have any practical significance within our ordinary moral lives is one that Kant the Natural Dialectic himself had just raised at the conclusion of the section. According to his own account of “common moral cognition”, the cognitive capacity of ordinary human beings “is very well informed in all cases that occur, to distinguish what is good, what is evil, what conforms with duty or is contrary to it” (4: 404). This commitment stemmed from Kant’s reading of Rousseau in the 1760s.2 Rousseau had convinced him that the unreflective responses of ordinary uneducated human subjects are more reliable than those of philosophical experts. Kant’s previous prioritization of the improve- ment of the intellect and the thought that “this alone could constitute the honor of mankind” later struck him as constituting both a philo- John J.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Plato's Phaedo
    Sean Hannan The Examined Life Autumn 2015 Notes on Plato’s Phaedo 1. Background a. The Phaedo tells the story of Socrates’ final days. Taking place after the events depicted in the Euthyphro, Apology, and Crito, this dialogue serves as his swansong. b. Whereas the Apology had a fairly straightforward structure, consisting mainly of Socrates’ monologues to the citizens of Athens (with a bit of back-and-forth with Meletus thrown in), the Phaedo is a full-blown dialogue. In fact, it operates as a dialogue on multiple levels. First we have the framing dialogue, which consists of the eponymous main character Phaedo’s account of Socrates’ final words, which he gives to Echecrates and others on his way home from Athens. Then we have the dialogue recounted by Phaedo, which takes place between Socrates and those who were with him in his final hours. c. First, let’s take a closer look at the framing dialogue. Phaedo (the character) is on his way back from Athens after attending the trial and execution of Socrates. As he approaches his hometown of Elis in the Peloponnese, he runs into a group of Pythagoreans, the most vocal of which is Echecrates. These men are dubbed ‘Pythagoreans’ because they follow the teachings of Pythagoras. While most of us are familiar with his theorem, Pythagoras had much more to say on the topics of philosophy and mathematics. For our purposes here, we should only note these Pythagoreans would’ve been especially open to the mathematical examples Phaedo tells them Socrates made use of in his final conversation—e.g., the difference between odd and even numbers, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • I Am Your Brother Joseph: Ratzinger and the Rehabilitation of Reason
    Digital Commons @ Assumption University Philosophy Department Faculty Works Philosophy Department 2011 I Am Your Brother Joseph: Ratzinger and the Rehabilitation of Reason Nalin Ranasinghe Assumption College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.assumption.edu/philosophy-faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Ranasinghe, Nalin. "I Am Your Brother Joseph: Ratzinger and the Rehabilitation of Reason." Gained Horizons: Regensburg and the Enlargement of Reason, edited by Bainard Cowan, St. Augustine's Press, 2011, pp. 49-60. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at Digital Commons @ Assumption University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Department Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Assumption University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. I Am Your Brother Joseph: Ratzinger and the Rehabilitation ofReason Na/in Ranasinghe The full significance of Pope Benedict XVI's controversial address at Regensburg in September 2006 has yet to be properly appreciated. The pontiff's main theme, a stirring call for the re-Hellenization of the West, was drowned out by a nearly unanimous chorus of criticism. Ironically, Western academics were so carried away by shallow outrage on behalf of the 'Other' that they inadvertently illustrated the pope's point regarding the breakdown of speech and rationality. Their unwillingness to appreciate the deep connection between Greek Reason and Hebrew Revelation that constitutes the very basis of our intellectual tradition strongly suggests that many academics are at least dangerously unaware of, and perhaps even consciously hostile to, their own origins.
    [Show full text]
  • Phaedo Plato
    Phaedo Plato TRANSLATED BY BENJAMIN JOWETT ROMAN ROADS MEDIA Classical education, from a Christian perspective, created for the homeschool. Roman Roads combines its technical expertise with the experience of established authorities in the field of classical education to create quality video courses and resources tailored to the homeschooler. Just as the first century roads of the Roman Empire were the physical means by which the early church spread the gospel far and wide, so Roman Roads Media uses today’s technology to bring timeless truth, goodness, and beauty into your home. By combining excellent instruction augmented with visual aids and examples, we help inspire in your children a lifelong love of learning. Phaedo by Plato translated by Benjamin Jowett This text was designed to accompany Roman Roads Media's 4-year video course Old Western Culture: A Christian Approach to the Great Books. For more information visit: www.romanroadsmedia.com. Other video courses by Roman Roads Media include: Grammar of Poetry featuring Matt Whitling Introductory Logic taught by Jim Nance Intermediate Logic taught by Jim Nance French Cuisine taught by Francis Foucachon Copyright © 2013 by Roman Roads Media, LLC Roman Roads Media 739 S Hayes St, Moscow, Idaho 83843 A ROMAN ROADS ETEXT Phaedo Plato TRANSLATED BY BENJAMIN JOWETT INTRODUCTION After an interval of some months or years, and at Phlius, a town of Peloponnesus, the tale of the last hours of Socrates is narrated to Echecrates and other Phliasians by Phaedo the 'beloved disciple.' The Dialogue necessarily takes the form of a narrative, because Socrates has to be described acting as well as speaking.
    [Show full text]
  • Logos and Psyche in Plato's Phaedo Jesse I
    Sacred Heart University DigitalCommons@SHU Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies Faculty Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies Publications 12-2011 Logos and Psyche in Plato's Phaedo Jesse I. Bailey Sacred Heart University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.sacredheart.edu/rel_fac Part of the Ancient Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Bailey, Jesse I. "Logos and Psyche in Plato's Phaedo." Dissertation. Pennsylvania State University, 2011. Web. https://etda.libraries.psu.edu/paper/12631/ This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies at DigitalCommons@SHU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@SHU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Pennsylvania State University The Graduate School College of the Liberal Arts Logos and Psyche in Plato’s Phaedo A Dissertation in Philosophy by Jesse I. Bailey © 2011 Jesse I. Bailey Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2011 The dissertation of Jesse I. Bailey was reviewed and approved* by the following: Dennis Schmidt Liberal Arts Research Professor of Philosophy, Comparative Literature, and German Dissertation Adviser Chair of Committee Chris Long Associate Professor of Philosophy and Classics Shannon Sullivan Professor of Philosophy, Women's Studies, and African and African
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Phaedo
    Platoʼs Phaedo - Classics - Oxford Bibliographies 10/9/17, 320 PM Plato’s Phaedo David Ebrey LAST MODIFIED: 23 AUGUST 2017 DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195389661-0272 Introduction Plato’s Phaedo is set on the last day of Socrates’ life, ending with his moving death scene. The dialogue is one of Plato’s literary masterpieces, with classic discussions of forms, the immortality of the soul, and the value of the philosophical life. It is typically considered one of Plato’s middle-period dialogues due to its contrast between forms and sensible things, defense of the immortality of the soul, interest in natural science, and engagement with Pythagorean ideas. The primary interlocutors are Socrates, Simmias, and Cebes. Early in the dialogue, Socrates suggests that the poet Evenus should follow him in death. This shocks Simmias, leading Socrates first to defend the claim that a philosopher’s soul would be better separated from its body, and then the claim that the soul is immortal. Socrates’ four arguments for the immortality of the soul rely on considerations about the nature of change, causation, and the contrast between forms and sensible things. The two parts of the Phaedo that have received the most scholarship since the 1950s—among the most scholarship on any topic in ancient philosophy—are Socrates’ second argument for immortality, the Recollection Argument, which discusses central issues in Plato’s metaphysics and epistemology, and the so-called Autobiographical Section, which discusses Socrates’ earlier interest in natural science, the method of hypothesis, and his approach to providing causes. The dialogue ends with a long myth followed by Socrates’ death scene.
    [Show full text]
  • Misology: the Hatred of Argument and the Life of the Intellect
    MISOLOGY: THE HATRED OF ARGUMENT AND THE LIFE OF THE INTELLECT John Francis Nieto In the few hours before the city of Athens executed the philosopher Socrates, his conversation dwelt upon his hope to spend the rest of time with the gods. In Plato's dialogue Phaedo, a young man by the name ofEchecrates asks the title character to report this last conversation. Socrates assured his friends of this expectation of a better life and explained that his life as a philosopher, a life cultivating his intellect, was nothing more than a preparation for death. But his friends fear that with death Socrates' existence may altogether end. He encourages them with several arguments concluding to the soul's immortality. Although the arguments at first con­ vince them, they raise objections that appear to undo these arguments. 1 Before he answers the objections, Socrates warns his friends of the danger ofbecoming "misologists," "as there is," he says, "no greater evil someone could suffer than hating arguments." He discusses this "malady" and then insists, We shall not admit into our souls that there may be no health in arguments, but rather that we are not yet healthy John.Francis Nieto has been a tutor for ten years at Thomas Aquinas College, where he did his undergraduate work, after studying political science and music at various California colleges and universities. At the University ofNotre Dame he wrote his dissertation on "Continuity and the Reality of Movement" and received a doctorate in philosophy. His first collection of poems, The Gloss, will soon be published by Mellon Poetry Press.
    [Show full text]
  • Extemporalia: Music, Philology, and Nietzsche's Misology
    Extemporalia: music, philology, and Nietzsche's misology The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Hamilton, John T. 2012. Extemporalia: music, philology, and Nietzsche's misology. Philia & Filia 3 (2): 7-27. Published Version http://seer.ufrgs.br/index.php/Philiaefilia/article/view/37247/24087 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:14065829 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA ISSN 2178-1737 Extemporalia Music, Philology, and Nietzsche’s Misology John T. Hamilton Harvard University Estados Unidos Resumo: Os biógrafos de Nietzsche geralmente basearam sua mudança para a filosofia no abandono da filologia acadêmica. As frequentes declarações dos filósofos de suspeita em relação à linguagem verbal – a misologia de Nietzsche – parece confirmar então essa mudança decisiva. No entanto, se alguém considerar, ao invés disso, a obra filosófica como mais contínua aos 7 estudos filológicos prévios, pode-se considerar a preocupação incansável de Nietzsche com a ______ escrita, tanto filológica como filosófica, primeiro como renúncia e depois como redescoberta de Extemporalia suas aspirações musicais. Depois de explorar o envolvimento inicial de Nietzsche com a música, Music, Philology, o seguinte artigo centra-se nas reflexões sobre ritmo e música do jovem professor, as quais and Nietzsche’s Misology parecem referir-se ao seu desejo de uma filologia mais musical e subsequentemente uma John T.
    [Show full text]