An Igbo Cultural Defence of Anti-Speciesism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Igbo Cultural Defence of Anti-Speciesism AN IGBO CULTURAL DEFENCE OF ANTI-SPECIESISM By Iheanacho Chukwuemeka METUONU B.A. Philosophy (IMSU), M.A. Philosophy (Ibadan) Matric. No: 119438 A Thesis in the Department of Philosophy, submitted to the Faculty of Arts in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY of University Of Ibadan, Ibadan, Nigeria MARCH 2014 DEDICATION i To I dedicate this thesis to the glory of the Almighty God, the creator and maker of all things; including the human and nonhuman animals: And To all who extend their love and care towards the nonhuman animals. ii CERTIFICATION I certify that this research, titled ―An Igbo Cultural Defence of Anti-speciesism‖ was carried out by Mr. Iheanacho Chukwuemeka Metuonu in the Department of Philosophy, Faculty of Arts, University of Ibadan, Ibadan, Nigeria. ………………………………………………….. SUPERVISOR CHRISTOPHER O. AGULANNA B.A., M.A. (Lagos); MAE (Linkoping University, Sweden); M. A. (Utrecht University, Netherlands); PhD (Ibadan) Professor of Ethics and Social Philosophy iii ABSTRACT Anti-speciesism, as opposed to speciesism, is the view that non-human animals are sentient beings and so should be granted moral status; a position shared by the Igbo culture which accords moral considerability to a good number of non-human animals. Existing studies on animal ethics have addressed these issues mainly from Western socio-cultural perspectives without significant contribution from the African cultural ambient that could provide complementary insights toward the debate. This study, therefore, interrogated the speciesist and the anti-speciesist positions, using cultural elements from the Igbo thought system with a view to evolving a complementary framework that will corroborate the position of anti-speciesism from the African context. The study adopted Peter Singer‘s theory of sentientism and Nwala‘s theory of animism as framework. While sentientism emphasises the ability of a being to experience pleasure or pain, animism grants souls to non-human animals as criteria for moral considerability. Ten core texts on the philosophy of animal ethics which included Singer‘s Animal Liberation and six on Igbo culture such as Nwala‘s Igbo Philosophy, Ilogu‘s Igbo Life and Thought and Onunwa‘s Anthology on Igbo Myths were purposively selected. The critical method was employed to examine the positions of speciesism and anti-speciesism and to analyse cultural concepts such as ube-ariri (animal emotion) and ugwu anu (animal integrity), drawn from the Igbo thought system while the conceptual analysis helped in explaining relevant notions such as sentientism, painism, moral status and equality. Texts on animal ethics revealed two contending traditions in the animal rights debate – speciesism and anti-speciesism. Works by Singer, particularly, Animal Liberation revealed that speciesism assigns moral status to humans on grounds of rationality, self-consciousness and the ability to communicate through verbal language. Anti-speciesism holds that non-human animals are subjects-of-a-life just like humans, and so have inherent worth in themselves. However, these extreme positions have not accommodated other cultural views due to their strong western orientation. Texts on Igbo culture revealed the Igbo belief about non-human animals living in a community of their own; possessing such basic rights as freedom, autonomy and independence – ideas that are expressed in some Igbo proverbials, myths and aphorisms, which, for instance, forbid a hunter from killing or disturbing a pregnant or mating animal. Furthermore, the principle of egbule (do no harm) towards such animals as the duck, sheep or millipede, imply moral considerability. There exist culturally relevant facts from Igbo thought such as ube-ariri (animal emotion) and ugwu anu (animal integrity), captured in the Igbo philosophy of egbe bere, ugo bere (live and let live), which grants mutual tolerance and fair treatment to all beings, justifying the claim of anti-speciesism that non-human animals are worthy of moral consideration. The Igbo culture grants moral privileges to a good number of non-human animals, thereby promoting the mutual flourishing of all beings. Therefore, the Igbo philosophy of egbe bere, ugo bere (live and let live) which accords moral consideration to non-human animals, provides a complementary framework that justifies the position of anti-speciesism. Key words: Speciesism, Anti-speciesism, Sentientism, Moral status, Igbo thought. Word count: 489 iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS My mouth is full of praises to the Almighty God, the King of kings, and the Lord of all lords, for His unfailing love and care towards me. I thank Him for His immense and bountiful blessings as well as unfathomable grace which enabled me to undertake this PhD programme and to pursue it to a logical conclusion. May His name alone be hallowed and praised throughout all eternity. Amen. My profound gratitude goes to my indefatigable supervisor, Prof. Christopher Otito Agulanna for his love, commitment and unalloyed interest in the work and in my academic progression as a whole. I appreciate the depth of his inputs, his constructive criticisms, support and guidance. The zeal, passion and enthusiasm he showed towards the successful completion of the work were matchless and consummate. Sir, I deeply appreciate your efforts and pray that the good Lord will richly bless and remember you for good in all that you do. I thank in an immeasurable manner, my parents, Rev. Canon Jeremiah Omenihi Metuonu and Mrs. Mabel Ogbonie Metuonu who I value so much both as parents and as pro-creators with the great God who made the heaven and the earth. My intellectually perspicacious parents were the ones who first introduced me to this critical genre of reasoning called philosophy. From the very first day of my creative vitality and I became endued as a living being, they have always been there for me; nurturing and guiding me to becoming who I am today. Daddy and Mummy, I am using this medium to tell you and the whole of humanity that I love and appreciate you so dearly. May the Lord continually be with you and bless you, in Jesus‘ name. Amen. I deeply appreciate the invaluable contributions of my teachers and lecturers in the Department of Philosophy, University of Ibadan such as Profs. Oyeshile, Dipo Irele and Ekanola, Drs. Ukpokolo, Offor, Udefi, Lanre-Abass, Afolayan and Adegbindin. These were worthy academic mentors to me. I am also thankful to Dr. C. L. Ochulor of the University of Calabar who introduced me Prof. U. R. Onunwa, who on his part granted me unfettered access to his rich library. The discussions I had with Prof. Onunwa helped to deepen my knowledge about Igbo cosmogony or theory of the universe. I am equally appreciative of the contributions and encouragements of Rev. Fr. I. M. Onyeocha of Imo State University and Dr. Edet Mesembe of the University of Calabar. I thank v my colleague and friend in the United States of America, Mr. Victor Nnadi who assisted me with original texts by Peter Singer, Tom Regan and Richard Ryder, the architects and leading lights of the animal rights movement in the intellectual world of today. Their works have challenged to give more than a passing concern to the interests of the nonhuman animals. I cannot forget the support I received from my colleagues and students in the Department of Philosophy, Joseph Ayo Babalola University. May the good Lord bless them richly as well. My immense gratitude goes to siblings and their families who have remained pillars of support and encouragement to me in all my life‘s pursuits. Their constant intercessions and knockings at the doors of heaven lent a hand in throwing heaven‘s door open and helped in the successful completion of this work. Finally, I cannot but appreciate my loving wife and angel, Vivian; she is my precious jewel of inestimable value and God‘s exceptional gift to me. Through the thick and thin as well as the ups and downs of this academic pursuit, my wife has remained unflinching in her support, patience and endurance. Her prayers and soothing words have been the healing balm for my intellectual soul. To our loving little boys, Marvellous and Manuel who God has used to bless our lives, I extend my gratitude as well. To all others who are too numerous to mention but who have supported me in one way or the other, I am deeply appreciate to you all. And to all lovers of the nonhuman animals, I say, ―keep the fires of love burning.‖ Thank you all and God bless, amen. Iheanacho Chukwuemeka METUONU March 2014 vi TABLE OF CONTENTS TITLE PAGE ………………………………………………………………………………….....i DEDICATION …………………………………………………………………………...........iii CERTIFICATION ………………………………………………………………….…………. iv ABSTRACT ……………………………………………………………………………..………v ACKNOWLEDGMENTS …………………………………………………………...........vi - vii TABLE OF CONTENTS …………………………………………………………….……viii - x INTRODUCTION ……………………………………………………………….............. 1 CHAPTER ONE: THE ANIMAL RIGHTS DEBATE 1.0 Introduction 5 1.1 Animal Rights – A Historical Discourse 5 1.1.1 The Ancient Period 5 1.1.2 The Medieval Period 6 1.1.3 The Renaissance and Modern Eras 8 1.1.4 The Contemporary Period 11 1.2 Conclusion 15 Endnotes 16 CHAPTER TWO: THE QUESTION OF MORAL RIGHTS AND INTRINSIC VALUE 2.0 Introduction 19 2.1 The Concept of Moral Rights 20 2.1.1 Human Rights 25 2.1.2 On the Question of Animal Rights 40 2.2 The Moral Significance of Animals‘ Moral Claims/Rights 60 2.2.1 The Utilitarian Argument (Peter Singer) 61 2.2.2 Alternative Perspectives of Human Relations to Nonhuman Animals 65 2.3 The
Recommended publications
  • The Sexual Politics of Meat by Carol J. Adams
    THE SEXUAL POLITICS OF MEAT A FEMINISTVEGETARIAN CRITICAL THEORY Praise for The Sexual Politics of Meat and Carol J. Adams “A clearheaded scholar joins the ideas of two movements—vegetari- anism and feminism—and turns them into a single coherent and moral theory. Her argument is rational and persuasive. New ground—whole acres of it—is broken by Adams.” —Colman McCarthy, Washington Post Book World “Th e Sexual Politics of Meat examines the historical, gender, race, and class implications of meat culture, and makes the links between the prac tice of butchering/eating animals and the maintenance of male domi nance. Read this powerful new book and you may well become a vegetarian.” —Ms. “Adams’s work will almost surely become a ‘bible’ for feminist and pro gressive animal rights activists. Depiction of animal exploita- tion as one manifestation of a brutal patriarchal culture has been explored in two [of her] books, Th e Sexual Politics of Meat and Neither Man nor Beast: Feminism and the Defense of Animals. Adams argues that factory farming is part of a whole culture of oppression and insti- tutionalized violence. Th e treatment of animals as objects is parallel to and associated with patriarchal society’s objectifi cation of women, blacks, and other minorities in order to routinely exploit them. Adams excels in constructing unexpected juxtapositions by using the language of one kind of relationship to illuminate another. Employing poetic rather than rhetorical techniques, Adams makes powerful connec- tions that encourage readers to draw their own conclusions.” —Choice “A dynamic contribution toward creating a feminist/animal rights theory.” —Animals’ Agenda “A cohesive, passionate case linking meat-eating to the oppression of animals and women .
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Curriculum Vitae Name: Daniel A. Dombrowski Birthdate: August 8, l953 Citizenship: USA Address: Philosophy Department; Seattle University; Seattle, WA 98122 Phone: 206-296-5465 E-mail: <[email protected]> Education: University of Maine, B.A., l974 Saint Louis University, Ph.D., l978 Books: l. Plato's Philosophy of History (Washington, DC: University Press of America, l98l), 217 pp. 2. The Philosophy of Vegetarianism (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, l984), 188 pp. Also Vegetarianism: The Philosophy Behind the Ethical Diet (London: Thorsons, l985), 188 pp. Forward by Peter Singer. 3. Thoreau the Platonist (Frankfurt: Verlag Peter Lang, l986), 219 pp. 4. Hartshorne and the Metaphysics of Animal Rights (Albany: State University of New York Press, l988), 159 pp. 5. Christian Pacifism (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1991), 181 pp. 6. St. John of the Cross: An Appreciation (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992), 219 pp. 7. Analytic Theism, Hartshorne, and the Concept of God (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996), 247 pp. 8. Babies and Beasts: The Argument from Marginal Cases (Champaign: University of Illinois Press, 1997), 221 pp. 9. Kazantzakis and God (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997), 193 pp. 10. A Brief, Liberal, Catholic Defense of Abortion, with Robert Deltete (Champaign: University of Illinois Press, 2000), 158 pp. Also Una Difesa Cattolica Dell’Aborto. Tr. Susi Ferrarello (Rome: Aracne, 2013), 157 pp. 1 11. Not Even a Sparrow Falls: The Philosophy of Stephen R. L. Clark (East Lansing: Michigan State University Press, 2000), 366 pp. 12. Rawls and Religion: The Case for Political Liberalism (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2001), 192 pp.
    [Show full text]
  • “Good Death” in Small Animals and Consequences for Euthanasia in Animal Law and Veterinary Practice
    animals Article Philosophy of a “Good Death” in Small Animals and Consequences for Euthanasia in Animal Law and Veterinary Practice Kirsten Persson 1,*, Felicitas Selter 2, Gerald Neitzke 2 and Peter Kunzmann 1 1 Stiftung Tierärztliche Hochschule Hannover, Bünteweg 9, 30559 Hannover, Germany; [email protected] 2 Medizinische Hochschule Hannover, Carl-Neuberg-Straße 1, 30625 Hannover, Germany; [email protected] (F.S.); [email protected] (G.N.) * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 30 November 2019; Accepted: 7 January 2020; Published: 13 January 2020 Simple Summary: Euthanasia in veterinary practice is often discussed as one of the profession’s major burdens. At the same time, it is meant to bring relief to terminally ill and/or severely suffering animal patients. This article examines “euthanasia” from a philosophical perspective regarding different definitions and underlying basic assumptions concerning the meaning of death and welfare for nonhuman animals. These theoretical issues will then be discussed in relation to laws and guidelines on euthanasia and practical challenges with end-of-life decisions in small animal practice. Factors which are identified as potential causes of the complex problems regarding euthanasia are as follows: the confusing framework for euthanasia in law and soft regulations; the inclusion of many stakeholders’ perspectives in end-of-life decision-making; potential conflicts between the veterinarians’ personal morality and legal requirements and professional expectations; and, most of all, the veterinarians’ lack of awareness for underlying philosophical assumptions regarding possible understandings of euthanasia. Different practical suggestions are made to clarify and facilitate euthanasia in small animal practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Book Reviews
    Book Reviews Robin ATTFIELD. Environmental Ethics. Cambridge: Polity, 2014. 278 pp. The counterculture of the 1960s gave rise to the plea for new moral values: a new environmental ethic. While some works in this discipline still give the impression that ‘environmental ethics’ is a label for a particular set of norms, Robin Attfield correctly points out that it is just another field of application of normative enquiry, which encom- passes very diverse substantial views. As such, environmental ethics has made its way into university and college courses, where it is accompanied by partly overlapping fields of applied ethics, such as climate ethics, population ethics and animal ethics. The first edition of Attfield’s Environmental Ethics appeared around the turn of the new millennium and was meant to assist students, researchers and scholars in this discipline. It intro- duced relevant concepts and issues and it discussed a wide range of relevant schools of thought. Attfield also defended his own normative theory, which is called ‘biocentric consequentialism’. Throughout the book, Attfield provided opportunities to pause and review the issues raised in proceeding sections. Furthermore, he offered chapter summaries, a glossary of key terms, and suggestions for further reading as well as useful websites. The second edition retains these features, but is fully revised and expanded, most notably with a chapter on climate ethics. This makes for the following outline: Chapter 1 provides a categorization of environmental problems and introduces theories about the genesis of these problems. Chapter 2 introduces the major contending views concerning which entities ought to be given direct moral consideration: only humans or all sentient beings, or even plants or collectives, such as species or ecosystems? Chapter 3 explores in more detail whether a concern for human good covers all that matters morally and inquires to what extent going beyond it is useful and even possible.
    [Show full text]
  • A Diet for a Sensitive Soul: Vegetarianism in Eighteenth-Century Britain
    A Diet for a Sensitive Soul: Vegetarianism in Eighteenth-Century Britain Anita Guerrini While vegetarianism has a long history in Western culture, it reemerged forcefully in late seventeenth- and eighteenth-century Britain. Three main motivations for vegetarianism converged in this period: religious, medical, and moral. In addition, a vegetarian diet entered mainstream medical and popular thought in the works of the physician George Cheyne. By the time of Joseph Ritson's Essay on Abstinence from Animal Food in 1802, however, vegetarianism was about to rejoin the irrational fringe, exemplified in the nineteenth century by Sylvester Graham and his followers. 1 In this essay, I shall focus on three vegetarians of the period: the radical hatter Thomas Tryon (1634-1703), George Cheyne (1671-1743), and the man of letters Joseph Ritson (1752-1803). Cheyne's work, especially his Essay of Health and Long Life (1724) and The English Malady (1733), defined the nascent concept of the sensitive character and explicitly connected it to diet and lifestyle. To Cheyne, a vegetarian diet was preeminently a diet for the sensitive soul. Over the century, the sensitive soul negotiated a path from the overtly religious Tryon to the covertly religious Cheyne to the professedly antireligious Ritson. To each, in addition, vegetarianism was part of a wider critique of contemporary society. Tryon was one of a number of religiously motivated vegetarians in the period following the English Civil War. 2 The context of his ideas can be delineated by examining an earlier
    [Show full text]
  • The Inconsistencies of the Replaceability Argument A
    THE INCONSISTENCIES OF THE REPLACEABILITY ARGUMENT A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Humanities By CAITLIN MARIE BAUER B.A., Wright State University, 2011 2015 Wright State University WRIGHT STATE UNIVERSITY GRADUATE SCHOOL April 27 2015 I HEREBY RECOMMEND THAT THE THESIS PREPARED UNDER MY SUPERVISION BY Caitlin Marie Bauer ENTITLED The Inconsistencies of the Replaceability Argument BE ACCEPTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF Master of Humanities. _______________________________ Scott Wilson, Ph.D. Thesis Director _______________________________ Valerie Stoker, Ph.D. Director, Master of Humanities Program Committee on Final Examination _______________________________ Scott Wilson, Ph.D. _______________________________ Erik Banks, Ph.D. _______________________________ Julienne Weinzimmer, Ph.D. _______________________________ Robert E.W. Fyffe, Ph.D. Vice President for Research and Dean of the Graduate School ABSTRACT Bauer, Caitlin Marie. M.Hum. Master of Humanities Program, Wright State University, 2015. The Inconsistencies of the Replaceability Argument. In this paper, I will argue against Peter Singer's replaceability argument. I start by showing how Singer's ethical theory of preference-utilitarianism leads to his assertion that everyone should be vegetarian, and later his conclusion that some animals are replaceable. To refute Singer, I argue that death deprives sentient beings of pleasure, and any other good they are capable of experiencing, so death is harmful to animals. Next, I discuss one last claim central to Singer's replaceability argument, that merely sentient animals are not the same individual between periods of consciousness because they have no memory or psychological connections. I refute the claim that they don't retain their individuality by arguing that their individuality is biological, rather than psychology.
    [Show full text]
  • Benjamin Franklin's Autobiography As an Eighteenth-Century Omnivore's
    Benjamin Franklin’s Autobiography as an Eighteenth-Century Omnivore’s Dilemma Dana Medoro University of Manitoba Custom makes killing, handling, and feeding upon flesh and blood, without distinction, so easy and familiar unto mankind. And the same is to be under- stood of men killing and oppressing those of their own kind. […] If men have but Power and Custom on their side, they think all is well. Thomas Tryon (1634–1703) My refusing to eat Flesh occasioned an Inconveniency, and I was frequently chid for my Singularity. Benjamin Franklin (1706–1790) lthough Benjamin Franklin tried his hand at virtually every intel- Alectual pursuit the eighteenth century had to offer—from scientific inven- tion and music to politics and philosophy—he always referred to himself as the “printer of Philadelphia.” And although he died a rich and internation- ally renowned man, he paints a vivid picture of himself in the early pages of The Autobiography as a half-starved runaway stuffing bread into his mouth as he wanders through Philadelphia looking for somewhere to sleep. Having just escaped his violent brother, to whom he had been indentured as a printer’s apprentice, Franklin sets into motion what he came to stand for in and beyond the revolutionary era: the promise of a self-made man, free from tyranny and caste. Keeping a sense of this promise or potential ESC 36.4 (December 2010): 91–107 at the surface of his recollections, he skilfully crafts his autobiography according to a philosophy of character as something made, broken down, and reassembled, like a composed form of moveable type in a printing Dana Medoro is press.
    [Show full text]
  • Vegetarianismamong
    The Society ofofEnglish English Studies l45 Vegetarianism among Quakers through History Tomoko YAMAGUCHI I) Introduction Thesc days many people are becoming concerned their health, and are getting interested in playing sports or reyiewing their life style, especially their way of eating. Because it involves one of our most basic bodily needs, eating could be said to be one of the most important and fundamentai matters in our daily life. One of the ways achieving a health life style, living only on vegetables, Vegetarianism, has been practiced for many years and continues today. Of course this practice contains several concerns such as health, peace, preservation of animals, religious matters, and so forth. Vegetarianism was also practiced by some Quakers in earlier days. Now they have a special pamphlet, the Friendly Vegetarian. It seems that interest in Vegetarianisrn has come to be more popular than bcfore among Quakers, I am interested in what QuakeTs think about their dieting life style, as a whole, religiously as well as spiritually. Their ways of thinking on their dieting life style is related to the idea of an ecological environment. In this I am to discusshow paper, going Quakers have advocated the natural way ef eating, and its connection with the histerical movement of vegetarianism. In addition, I invcstigated how Quakers, considering their health, have tried to continue eating well. II) The Historical Background of Quakers The rnovement of started Quakerism in 1652, yet the ideas were first preached by George Fox in 1647. His main philosophical ideas are described in one of the Quakers' "His cookbooks, Quaker Ftavors, A Cookbooh published by Williston Friends Meeting: `that `Light' `Christ centrar thought was of God', a oT within' every man; that the Divine Being epcrates directly upon the human life and the spiritual life begins when the individual becomes aware and sets himself to obey Him." In Quakerism, this concept is oftefi NII-Electronic Library Service The Society ofofEnglish English Studies t46 Tomoko YAMAGUCHI "faith" "truth".
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Tryon, 1634 .. 1703
    Thomas Tryon, 1634.. 1703. s Baptists we are sometimes charged with claiming, on the slightest pretext, any considerable person as an adherent. A Claims need to be distinguished by our critics and our­ selves. For instanoe, the broad assertion that John Milton was a Baptist, 'apart from some qualifying epithet, may be too inclusive; for the full oonfessions of faith, the genius and temper of the Anabaptists of the seventeenth century, in England, least no spell upon him. It was our practice with regard to baptism by immersion he approv·ed; the integrity of our mode, when traced to primitive precedents, he endorsed. It may be in one point of oontact only, that men may be in harmony with us; this should be scrupulously indicated. Candour and precision should characterize our statements; we must not be more courteous in our inclusions, than jealous in our disclaimers. Thomas Tryon, the subject of this brief sketch, held no ambiguous relation to our body at one period of his life. This he makes abundantly clear in his .. Memoirs." He was in full fellowship with a church of .. Anabaptists" in London for a period; was the genuine contemporary of John Bunyan-being bom six years later-and must have read some of the stirring pamphlets of John M:ilton still wet from the press. He is here introduced simply as an illustration of the influence of Baptists in London during the seventeenth century upon the young lif.e of the country, that then, as now, poured into the Metropolis. Though he did not r·emain in fellowship with our people, his first inspirations to a singularly noble life were re­ ceived from them.
    [Show full text]
  • Deep Vegetarianism
    CHAPTER A Historical-Ph ilosophical Overview 1. Learning from the History of Vegetarianism Two approaches to the history of ideas have relevance to the topic of vegetarianism. One of these is the view, suggested by William James (1842-1910), that theories pass through three “classic” stages: “First, you know, a new theory is attacked as absurd; then it is admitted to be true, but obvious and in- significant; finally it is seen to be so important that its adver- saries claim that they themselves discovered it.”’ James’s metatheory about theories may be applied to ideas equally well. A catchy but oversimplified formula, it derives its force from the notions that the truth will triumph, and that a baptism by fire must first be endured by positions that initially defy con- ventional wisdom, human prejudices, or vested interests. Usual examples include such theories as the fundamental equality of all human beings, the heliocentric solar system, the evolution of species, and the nonexistence of absolute truth. While some 1 2 Chapter 1 might contend that vegetarianism is an idea whose time has ar- rived, it seems unlikely that, even if this were so, such a claim could be construed as implying that vegetarianism has passed through all of these stages, let alone the first. Vegetarianism-long well-established in the East-is no longer being ignored in the West by such prominent portions of society as opinion-makers, publishers, and the service sector, but it is still frequently subject to ridicule and hostile/aggres- sive or suspicious/skeptical interrogation. It is somewhat easier to place attitudes toward vegetarianism on a scale of develop- ment or evolution if we acknowledge that the broader concept of animals as beings having or deserving moral status-an ini- portant ground for vegetarianism-is itself in its infancy in terms of social acceptance, normative affirmation, and public advocacy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Replaceability Argument
    Uppsala universitet Filosofiska institutionen The Replaceability Argument - An evaluation of a utilitarian argument for the permissibility of purchasing meat Hampus Gunnarsson C-uppsats VT-18 Handledare: Simon Rosenqvist Contents 1. Introduction 2 2. The Replaceability Argument 2 3. Premise One: The Causal Impotence Problem 4 3.1 Causal Impotence 5 3.2 Counterarguments 6 3.3 Responses to the Counterarguments 7 3.4 Discussion 9 3.5 Conclusions 10 4. Premise Two: Living a Valuable Life 11 4.1 Two Theories of Welfare 12 4.2 The Lives of Animals in the Meat Industry 14 4.3 Conclusions 17 5. Premise Three: Alternative Acts 17 5.1 Environmental Effects 18 5.2 Human Health Effects 20 5.3 Conclusions 21 6. Conclusion 22 1 1. Introduction Utilitarian arguments for the permissibility of purchasing meat have a long history. In 1914, the British writer and animal rights campaigner Henry Salt lamented what he called the “logic of the larder” – the way meat purchases are justified by the alleged fact that they allow the slaughtered animals to live in the first place.1 Recent proponents of this view include Torbjörn Tännsjö who thinks that as long as animals reared for slaughter live valuable lives, the practice of eating meat isn’t problematic. 2 This type of argument is also described as one of the possible utilitarian arguments for meat consumption by Bob Fisher in his contribution to The Oxford Handbook of ​ Food Ethics.3 The thinkers who argue for versions of the logic of the larder model ​ stand in sharp contrast to the large number of contemporary utilitarian philosophers who claim that the impermissibility of buying meat follows from the utilitarian theory.4 The aim of this thesis is to examine and evaluate the utilitarian argument for the permissibility of buying meat that I call “the replaceability argument”.
    [Show full text]
  • Animals, Moral Risk and Moral Considerability
    Durham E-Theses Animals, moral risk and moral considerability Tanner, Julia K. H. How to cite: Tanner, Julia K. H. (2007) Animals, moral risk and moral considerability, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/2477/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk Animals, Moral Risk and Moral Considerability The copyright of this thesis rests with the author or the university to which it was submitted. No quotation from it, or information derived from it may be published without the prior written consent of the author or university, and any information derived from it should be acknowledged. Name: Julia K. H. Tanner Degree for which thesis is being submitted: Ph.D University: University of Durham Department: Philosophy Department Year of submission: 2007 The copyright of this thesis rests with the author.
    [Show full text]