Relational Personhood, Extended Diachronic Personal Identity, and Our Moral Obligations Toward Fragile Persons

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Relational Personhood, Extended Diachronic Personal Identity, and Our Moral Obligations Toward Fragile Persons University of Alberta Shadow People: Relational Personhood, Extended Diachronic Personal Identity, and Our Moral Obligations Toward Fragile Persons by Bartlomiej A. Lenart A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfillment of requirements for degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy © Bartlomiej A. Lenart Spring 2014 Edmonton, Alberta Permission is hereby granted to the University of Alberta Libraries to reproduce single copies of this thesis and to lend or sell such copies for private, scholarly or scientific research purposes only. Where the thesis is converted to, or otherwise made available in digital form, the University of Alberta will advise potential users of the thesis of these terms. The author reserves all other publication and other rights in association with the copyright in the thesis and, except as herein before provided, neither the thesis nor any substantial portion thereof may be printed or otherwise reproduced in any material form whatsoever without the author's prior written permission. To Miranda for continuous encouragement and support and for always authentically holding me in my identity and to Urszula, Andrzej, and Kamil for never ceasing to care Abstract This Dissertation argues for a care-centrically grounded account of relational personhood and widely realized diachronic personal identity. The moral distinction between persons and non-persons is arguably one of the most salient ethical lines we can draw since many of our most fundamental rights are delineated via the bounds of personhood. The problem with drawing such morally salient lines is that the orthodox, rationalistic definition of personhood, which is widespread within philosophical, medical, and colloquial spheres, excludes, and thereby de-personifies, a large number and a great variety of human beings such as neonates, young children, the elderly who suffer from dementia, individuals with severe cognitive disabilities, and patients in vegetative states. The reconceptualization of personhood necessary for a more inclusive definition ought to originate with an appropriate moral grounding. To this end, this Dissertation grounds the notion of personhood in the care ethical sphere, thereby emphasizing the role of care relations in the maintenance of the moral consideration of vulnerable individuals. This Dissertation argues that grounding the concept of a person in care relations entails a relational account of personhood, which, along with the insights of the Extended Mind and Social Manifestation Theses, leads to an extended and externalized understanding of diachronic identity, which allows fragile people to be held in their personal identities even if they themselves lack the capacities usually associated with moral personhood. As we trace a person’s identity through time, we track the various relational properties, which constitute personal narratives and thus act as a glue that binds such dynamic and often unique properties into stable, trackable narratives. Since care relations are morally relevant on a care-centric account of personhood, what is lost in cases where such care relating ceases is not merely of sentimental value, but of great moral importance as well. Morally meaningful care relations are not replaceable, and, by extension, neither are the narratives that are constituted by such unique and irreplaceable instances of relating. This Dissertation argues that the constitutive care relational nature of personal narratives makes such narratives irreplaceable and is precisely what makes persons so morally precious. Acknowledgments First and foremost, I owe a great debt of gratitude to my dissertation supervisor, Professor Robert A. Wilson, for his steadfast support, enthusiasm, encouragement, patience, suggestions, and insight throughout the entire process of conceptualizing and writing this dissertation. I would also like to sincerely thank him for his tireless and supererogatory effort to ensure that his graduate students have access to the most recent scholarship and excellent formative academic experiences, many of which, had they not been personally subsidized by him, would not have been accessible to me or his other graduate students (we are all indebted to his farsightedness and generosity). Completing this dissertation would not have been possible without his passion for mentorship, commitment to student growth, and his guidance. I would like to offer a sincere thank you to the members of my thesis committee, Professors Wendy Austin, Wesley Cooper, Eva Feder Kittay, and Howard Nye, for their discerning comments, questions, and suggestions, as well as for their enthusiasm for the project. I would also like to thank Professor Michael Tooley for his helpful comments and suggestions on an earlier draft of this dissertation. I am grateful for the generous funding received throughout the course of my doctorate. I would like to thank the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (SSHRC) for the SSHRC Doctoral Fellowship and the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research (FGSR) for awarding the Queen Elizabeth II Doctoral Graduate Scholarship in 2008 and 2009 as well as the President’s Doctoral Prize of Distinction in 2011. Table of Contents Chapter 1 Shadow People: Exemptions from Personhood 1.1 Persona 1 1.2 Personhood and Exemptions 6 1.3 Faded Personhood: Severe Cognitive Disabilities and Permanent Vegetative States 13 1.4 Shadow People 22 1.5 Sketching the Argument 24 Chapter 2 Moral Motivations 2.1 Asking the Right Questions 31 2.2 Who Am I? 34 2.3 The Moral Fabric of Personal Identity: Picking out the Moral Threads of Personhood 38 Chapter 3 Moral Agents 3.1 Defining Personhood: A Moral Project 52 3.2 Aristotle’s Function Argument 54 3.3 Lockean Persons 61 3.4 Kantian Rationalist Elitism 74 3.5 The Singerian Preference Hierarchy 79 3.6 The Trends Continue 95 3.7 Psychologism and Biologism 100 Chapter 4 Beyond Psychologism and Biologism 4.1 The Biological Account: Olson’s Animalism 102 4.2 Revisiting Animalism: Some Shortcomings of the Biological Account 109 4.3 The Psychological Account and Its Dangers 117 4.4 Noonan’s Neo-Lockeanism 123 4.5 Resetting the Bearings: Where to Go from Here? 127 Chapter 5 Externalizing Personhood: Self-Conception and Externalized Meaning 5.1 The Closest Continuer Theory and the Problem of Excessive Subjectivity 130 5.2 Nozick on Value and the Meaning of Life 142 5.3 The Closest Continuer Theory Extrinsically Bounded and Socially Expanded 145 Chapter 6 Relational Personhood 6.1 Campbell’s Relational Personhood: Ratio-Centrism Veiled in Relations? 151 6.2 Memory: A Brief History 160 6.3 Memory Systems 162 6.4 Episodic Memory and Personhood 165 6.5 Taking Memory Seriously 168 6.6 Relational Personhood 176 6.7 Narratives, Extended Diachronic Personal Identity, and Care Relations 179 Chapter 7 Fragile Personhood: Our Moral Obligations to Care About and Personify Vulnerable Individuals 7.1 Moral Fibres: The Moral Grounding of Personhood 195 7.2 Personalizing People 203 7.3 The Moral Obligations of Carers 224 7.4 Patients in Permanent Vegetative States (PVS) 228 7.5 Summary 236 Chapter 8 Questions, Objections, and Replies 8.1 The Problem of Mistaken Identity 241 8.2 The Great Apes and Feral Children 244 8.3 The Problem of Context Dependence and the Absence of Inclusive Narratives 251 8.4 The Problem of Exclusionary Narratives 255 8.5 The Question of Emotionless Rational Humans 257 8.6 Personhood and Permanent Vegetative States 267 Conclusion 274 Bibliography 278 Appendix 291 Chapter 1 Shadow People: Exemptions from Personhood All the world’s a stage, And all the men and women merely players. They have their exits and their entrances, And one man in his time plays many parts (As You Like It, William Shakespeare, 1623) 1.1 Persona1 In As You Like It, the great English playwright William Shakespeare, likens the human life to a play in seven Acts (Shakespeare 1623, II.vii.138-142), thereby comparing the human person to an actor who assumes several different personas throughout his or her life.2 Being a playwright, Shakespeare may have found it natural to draw analogies between acting on a stage and living life as a person. However, the roots of such analogies are fixed much further in the past. The term person has its origin on the stage, making Shakespeare’s analogy not only fitting, but also instructional. The Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology (1966) traces the word person to persona, and suggests that the word is likely derived from Etruscan (ɸersu), meaning mask 1 The following is not meant to be an argument from etymology since I will offer other, more philosophically acceptable arguments for the properties I assign to personhood, but I think an etymological sketch of the term in question can help point the reader to the kind of understanding of the concept of personhood for which I will be arguing. 2 Each act or age represents a different stage of life: the infantile stage, the whining schoolboy stage, the lover stage, the soldier stage, the wise or just stage, the elder stage, and finally a second childishness. 1 (or masked figure) and was used to render the Greek prósōpon, meaning face, mask, or dramatic part, from the words prós meaning ‘to’ or ‘towards’ and ṓps meaning ‘face.’ Ernest Klein’s A Comprehensive Etymological Dictionary of the English Language states that the Etruscan ɸersu is itself of Greek origin (Πɛpσɛφóvƞ), which is the name of the chief goddess of the underworld, Persephone. According to Ernest Klein (1967), ɸersu refers to “the embodiment of a god of the nether world whose office it was to receive the soul of the dead and to accompany it to Hades” (Klein 1967, 1163-1164). The term person, as The Concise Oxford Dictionary (2001) tells us, was also adopted in Christian Theology to stand for the three modes of being of God (the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit), thereby continuing the tradition of essentially embodying abstract concepts such as divinity.
Recommended publications
  • 2. Animal Ethics
    2. Animal ethics It was started to provide animal welfare and stop cruel practices on animals, for example factory farming, animal testing, using animals for experimentation or for entertainment. In the most of Western philosophy animals were considered as beings without moral standing, namely those that do not have to be included into our moral choices. The very typical example of this approach is the Cartesian one, according to Rene Descartes (1596-1650), animals are just simple machines that cannot experience pain. The philosopher was known for making vivisections on living animals and claiming that none of the animals could feel the pain during this. In consequence of this approach until modern times there were conducted many unnecessary and cruel experiments with animal usage, also animal’s condition at factory farms or in entrainment were terrible. All these practices caused a huge amount of suffering of animals. The approach to animals was changed with Peter Singer’s influential book on Animal Liberation (1975). Singer raised the issue that animals can suffer and amount of suffering that they experience is not worth what we gain from these cruel practices. His argumentation was utilitarian, which is one of the approaches of normative ethics. Deontological and utilitarian argumentation in animal ethics Normative ethics aims at providing moral standards that regulate right and wrong conduct. This may involve articulating the good habits that we should acquire, the duties that we should follow, or the consequences of our behavior on others. The most popular approaches to normative theory are: deonotology and conseqentialism. The word deontology derives from the Greek words for duty (deon) and science (or study) of (logos).
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Curriculum Vitae Name: Daniel A. Dombrowski Birthdate: August 8, l953 Citizenship: USA Address: Philosophy Department; Seattle University; Seattle, WA 98122 Phone: 206-296-5465 E-mail: <[email protected]> Education: University of Maine, B.A., l974 Saint Louis University, Ph.D., l978 Books: l. Plato's Philosophy of History (Washington, DC: University Press of America, l98l), 217 pp. 2. The Philosophy of Vegetarianism (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, l984), 188 pp. Also Vegetarianism: The Philosophy Behind the Ethical Diet (London: Thorsons, l985), 188 pp. Forward by Peter Singer. 3. Thoreau the Platonist (Frankfurt: Verlag Peter Lang, l986), 219 pp. 4. Hartshorne and the Metaphysics of Animal Rights (Albany: State University of New York Press, l988), 159 pp. 5. Christian Pacifism (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1991), 181 pp. 6. St. John of the Cross: An Appreciation (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992), 219 pp. 7. Analytic Theism, Hartshorne, and the Concept of God (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996), 247 pp. 8. Babies and Beasts: The Argument from Marginal Cases (Champaign: University of Illinois Press, 1997), 221 pp. 9. Kazantzakis and God (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997), 193 pp. 10. A Brief, Liberal, Catholic Defense of Abortion, with Robert Deltete (Champaign: University of Illinois Press, 2000), 158 pp. Also Una Difesa Cattolica Dell’Aborto. Tr. Susi Ferrarello (Rome: Aracne, 2013), 157 pp. 1 11. Not Even a Sparrow Falls: The Philosophy of Stephen R. L. Clark (East Lansing: Michigan State University Press, 2000), 366 pp. 12. Rawls and Religion: The Case for Political Liberalism (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2001), 192 pp.
    [Show full text]
  • “Good Death” in Small Animals and Consequences for Euthanasia in Animal Law and Veterinary Practice
    animals Article Philosophy of a “Good Death” in Small Animals and Consequences for Euthanasia in Animal Law and Veterinary Practice Kirsten Persson 1,*, Felicitas Selter 2, Gerald Neitzke 2 and Peter Kunzmann 1 1 Stiftung Tierärztliche Hochschule Hannover, Bünteweg 9, 30559 Hannover, Germany; [email protected] 2 Medizinische Hochschule Hannover, Carl-Neuberg-Straße 1, 30625 Hannover, Germany; [email protected] (F.S.); [email protected] (G.N.) * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 30 November 2019; Accepted: 7 January 2020; Published: 13 January 2020 Simple Summary: Euthanasia in veterinary practice is often discussed as one of the profession’s major burdens. At the same time, it is meant to bring relief to terminally ill and/or severely suffering animal patients. This article examines “euthanasia” from a philosophical perspective regarding different definitions and underlying basic assumptions concerning the meaning of death and welfare for nonhuman animals. These theoretical issues will then be discussed in relation to laws and guidelines on euthanasia and practical challenges with end-of-life decisions in small animal practice. Factors which are identified as potential causes of the complex problems regarding euthanasia are as follows: the confusing framework for euthanasia in law and soft regulations; the inclusion of many stakeholders’ perspectives in end-of-life decision-making; potential conflicts between the veterinarians’ personal morality and legal requirements and professional expectations; and, most of all, the veterinarians’ lack of awareness for underlying philosophical assumptions regarding possible understandings of euthanasia. Different practical suggestions are made to clarify and facilitate euthanasia in small animal practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Book Reviews
    Book Reviews Robin ATTFIELD. Environmental Ethics. Cambridge: Polity, 2014. 278 pp. The counterculture of the 1960s gave rise to the plea for new moral values: a new environmental ethic. While some works in this discipline still give the impression that ‘environmental ethics’ is a label for a particular set of norms, Robin Attfield correctly points out that it is just another field of application of normative enquiry, which encom- passes very diverse substantial views. As such, environmental ethics has made its way into university and college courses, where it is accompanied by partly overlapping fields of applied ethics, such as climate ethics, population ethics and animal ethics. The first edition of Attfield’s Environmental Ethics appeared around the turn of the new millennium and was meant to assist students, researchers and scholars in this discipline. It intro- duced relevant concepts and issues and it discussed a wide range of relevant schools of thought. Attfield also defended his own normative theory, which is called ‘biocentric consequentialism’. Throughout the book, Attfield provided opportunities to pause and review the issues raised in proceeding sections. Furthermore, he offered chapter summaries, a glossary of key terms, and suggestions for further reading as well as useful websites. The second edition retains these features, but is fully revised and expanded, most notably with a chapter on climate ethics. This makes for the following outline: Chapter 1 provides a categorization of environmental problems and introduces theories about the genesis of these problems. Chapter 2 introduces the major contending views concerning which entities ought to be given direct moral consideration: only humans or all sentient beings, or even plants or collectives, such as species or ecosystems? Chapter 3 explores in more detail whether a concern for human good covers all that matters morally and inquires to what extent going beyond it is useful and even possible.
    [Show full text]
  • The Inconsistencies of the Replaceability Argument A
    THE INCONSISTENCIES OF THE REPLACEABILITY ARGUMENT A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Humanities By CAITLIN MARIE BAUER B.A., Wright State University, 2011 2015 Wright State University WRIGHT STATE UNIVERSITY GRADUATE SCHOOL April 27 2015 I HEREBY RECOMMEND THAT THE THESIS PREPARED UNDER MY SUPERVISION BY Caitlin Marie Bauer ENTITLED The Inconsistencies of the Replaceability Argument BE ACCEPTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF Master of Humanities. _______________________________ Scott Wilson, Ph.D. Thesis Director _______________________________ Valerie Stoker, Ph.D. Director, Master of Humanities Program Committee on Final Examination _______________________________ Scott Wilson, Ph.D. _______________________________ Erik Banks, Ph.D. _______________________________ Julienne Weinzimmer, Ph.D. _______________________________ Robert E.W. Fyffe, Ph.D. Vice President for Research and Dean of the Graduate School ABSTRACT Bauer, Caitlin Marie. M.Hum. Master of Humanities Program, Wright State University, 2015. The Inconsistencies of the Replaceability Argument. In this paper, I will argue against Peter Singer's replaceability argument. I start by showing how Singer's ethical theory of preference-utilitarianism leads to his assertion that everyone should be vegetarian, and later his conclusion that some animals are replaceable. To refute Singer, I argue that death deprives sentient beings of pleasure, and any other good they are capable of experiencing, so death is harmful to animals. Next, I discuss one last claim central to Singer's replaceability argument, that merely sentient animals are not the same individual between periods of consciousness because they have no memory or psychological connections. I refute the claim that they don't retain their individuality by arguing that their individuality is biological, rather than psychology.
    [Show full text]
  • Vegetarian Ecofeminism: a Review Essay
    Vegetarian Ecofeminism: A Review Essay Gaard, Greta Claire. Frontiers: A Journal of Women Studies, Volume 23, Number 3, 2002, pp. 117-146 (Article) Published by University of Nebraska Press DOI: 10.1353/fro.2003.0006 For additional information about this article http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/fro/summary/v023/23.3gaard.html Access provided by Tsinghua University Library (23 Apr 2013 06:09 GMT) 08-N2534 1/17/03 8:47 AM Page 117 Vegetarian Ecofeminism A Review Essay greta gaard Although the roots of ecofeminism can be located in the work of women gar- deners, outdoor enthusiasts, environmental writers, botanists, scientists, ani- mal welfare activists, and abolitionists over the past two centuries, ecofemi- nism’sfirst articulation in the 1980s was shaped by the convergence of the peace, antinuclear, and feminist movements. In the past two decades ecofeminism has developed so rapidly that the time for a broad review of it has already passed; even recent taxonomies do not adequately describe its internal variations. For these reasons, I have chosen to trace the branch of ecofeminism that has been the subject of most disagreement by feminists, ecofeminists, and environmen- talists and is the least understood. This misunderstanding (and the subsequent misrepresentation) of vegetarian ecofeminism must be addressed, I will argue, because this branch of ecofeminism is the logical outgrowth of both feminism and ecofeminism. For if ecofeminism can be seen as the offspring of feminism, then vegetarian ecofeminism is surely feminism’s third generation. Since its inception ecofeminism has had a contentious relationship with the idea of animal liberation. While some ecofeminists have remained silent on the topic of animals, others have emphasized the oppression of nonhuman ani- mals (speciesism) as implicit within an ecofeminist analysis, arguing that speciesism functions like and is inherently linked to racism, sexism, classism, heterosexism, and naturism.
    [Show full text]
  • Speciesism: a Form of Bigotry Or a Justified View? Evelyn Pluhar
    -------~------------ - SPECIESISM: A FORM OF BIGOTRY OR A JUSTIFIED VIEW? EVELYN PLUHAR Pennsylvania State UniversityUniversity Fayette Campuscampus Editor's Note: An abridgedabridged version of this paper and thethe commentary on it by Prof.Prof. Sapontzis were delivered atat the December, 1987, meetingmeeting of the Society for the StudyStudy of Ethics and Animals held inin New York City.City. g~;~~~:Fr:iiil~~JmoDs. He ..... York: Dover, 1979 We humans tend to view ourselves as the paradigms of morally considerable beings. Humans, it is often claimed, are the most morally valuable (perhaps the ~ morally PHILOSOPHY valuable) beings on this planet. It is commonly assumed that "lesser" beings 83 BRIWEENBEIWEEN THE SPECIES should be sacrificed for our benefit. When For those who continue to think that it is not pressed to provide a rational defense for the wrong to eat and vivisect non humans, but belief in human pre-eminence, philosophers indefensible to do so to even less well have argued that our autonomous, richly mentally endowed humans, the issue should complex lives warrant our special status. be very pressing indeed. They stand accused Few, however, have argued that humans who of moral inconsistency by two very are incapable of autonomy may properly be different groups. Those who have become sacrificed to further the interests of normal convinced that moral considerability is not humans. restricted to humanity are urging that we cease even the painless exploitation of It was inevitable that this prima facie non humans. According to quite another, inconsistency would be challenged. Writers very disturbing view, we should consider like Peter Singer and Tom Regan advanced exploiting mentally defective humans in the argument from marginal cases to show addition to nonhumans.
    [Show full text]
  • The Replaceability Argument
    Uppsala universitet Filosofiska institutionen The Replaceability Argument - An evaluation of a utilitarian argument for the permissibility of purchasing meat Hampus Gunnarsson C-uppsats VT-18 Handledare: Simon Rosenqvist Contents 1. Introduction 2 2. The Replaceability Argument 2 3. Premise One: The Causal Impotence Problem 4 3.1 Causal Impotence 5 3.2 Counterarguments 6 3.3 Responses to the Counterarguments 7 3.4 Discussion 9 3.5 Conclusions 10 4. Premise Two: Living a Valuable Life 11 4.1 Two Theories of Welfare 12 4.2 The Lives of Animals in the Meat Industry 14 4.3 Conclusions 17 5. Premise Three: Alternative Acts 17 5.1 Environmental Effects 18 5.2 Human Health Effects 20 5.3 Conclusions 21 6. Conclusion 22 1 1. Introduction Utilitarian arguments for the permissibility of purchasing meat have a long history. In 1914, the British writer and animal rights campaigner Henry Salt lamented what he called the “logic of the larder” – the way meat purchases are justified by the alleged fact that they allow the slaughtered animals to live in the first place.1 Recent proponents of this view include Torbjörn Tännsjö who thinks that as long as animals reared for slaughter live valuable lives, the practice of eating meat isn’t problematic. 2 This type of argument is also described as one of the possible utilitarian arguments for meat consumption by Bob Fisher in his contribution to The Oxford Handbook of ​ Food Ethics.3 The thinkers who argue for versions of the logic of the larder model ​ stand in sharp contrast to the large number of contemporary utilitarian philosophers who claim that the impermissibility of buying meat follows from the utilitarian theory.4 The aim of this thesis is to examine and evaluate the utilitarian argument for the permissibility of buying meat that I call “the replaceability argument”.
    [Show full text]
  • Vulnerability, Care, Power, and Virtue: Thinking Other Animals Anew
    Vulnerability, Care, Power, and Virtue: Thinking Other Animals Anew by Stephen Thierman A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Copyright by Stephen Thierman 2012 Vulnerability, Care, Power, and Virtue: Thinking Other Animals Anew Stephen Thierman Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2012 Abstract This thesis is a work of practical philosophy situated at the intersection of bioethics, environmental ethics, and social and political thought. Broadly, its topic is the moral status of nonhuman animals. One of its pivotal aims is to encourage and foster the “sympathetic imaginative construction of another’s reality”1 and to determine how that construction might feed back on to understandings of ourselves and of our place in this world that we share with so many other creatures. In the three chapters that follow the introduction, I explore a concept (vulnerability), a tradition in moral philosophy (the ethic of care), and a philosopher (Wittgenstein) that are not often foregrounded in discussions of animal ethics. Taken together, these sections establish a picture of other animals (and of the kinship that humans share with them) that can stand as an alternative to the utilitarian and rights theories that have been dominant in this domain of philosophical inquiry. 1 Josephine Donovan, “Attention to Suffering: Sympathy as a Basis for the Ethical Treatment of Animals,” in The Feminist Care Tradition in Animal Ethics, ed. Josephine Donovan and Carol Adams (New York: Columbia University Press, 2007), 179. ii In my fifth and sixth chapters, I extend this conceptual framework by turning to the work of Michel Foucault.
    [Show full text]
  • La Argumentación De Singer En Liberación Animal: Concepciones Normativas, Interés En Vivir Y Agregacionismo Diánoia, Vol
    Diánoia ISSN: 0185-2450 [email protected] Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México México HORTA, OSCAR La argumentación de Singer en Liberación animal: concepciones normativas, interés en vivir y agregacionismo Diánoia, vol. LVI, núm. 67, noviembre, 2011, pp. 65-85 Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México Distrito Federal, México Disponible en: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=58433540004 Cómo citar el artículo Número completo Sistema de Información Científica Más información del artículo Red de Revistas Científicas de América Latina, el Caribe, España y Portugal Página de la revista en redalyc.org Proyecto académico sin fines de lucro, desarrollado bajo la iniciativa de acceso abierto La argumentación de Singer en Liberación animal: concepciones normativas, interés en vivir y agregacionismo OSCAR HORTA Fundación Española para la Ciencia y la Tecnología/ Rutgers University [email protected] Resumen: Este artículo examina los presupuestos metodológicos, axiológicos y normativos en los que descansa la que posiblemente sea la obra más co- nocida de Peter Singer, Liberación animal. Se exploran las tensiones entre la posición normativa, de compromisos mínimos, que se intenta adoptar en esa obra, y las posiciones de Singer acerca del utilitarismo de las preferencias y el argumento de la reemplazabilidad. Se buscará elucidar en particular el modo en el que surgen tales tensiones al abordarse la consideración del agregacio- nismo y el interés en vivir en relación con el uso de animales no humanos. Palabras clave: especismo, principio de no maleficencia, utilitarismo, valor de la vida Abstract: This paper examines the methodological, axiological and normative assumptions on which Animal Liberation —arguably the most poular work by Peter Singer— rests.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Ethics Around the Turn of the Twenty-First Century ?
    D. DEGRAZIA ANIMAL ETHICS AROUND THE TURN OF THE TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY ? A couple of decades after becoming a major area of both public and philosophical concern, animal ethics continues its inroads into main- stream consciousness. Increasingly, philosophers, ethicists, professionals who use animals, and the broader public confront specific ethical issues regarding human use of animals as well as more fundamental questions about animals’ moral status. A parallel, related development is the explo- sion of interest in animals’ mental lives, as seen in exciting new work in cognitive ethology1 and in the plethora of movies, television commercials, and popular books featuring apparently intelligent animals. As we approach the turn of the twenty-first century, philosophical animal ethics is an area of both increasing diversity and unrealized poten- tial – a thesis supported by this essay as a whole. Following up on an earlier philosophical review of animal ethics (but without that review’s focus on animal research),2 the present article provides an updated narrative – one that offers some perspective on where we have been, a more detailed account of where we are, and a projection of where we might go. Each of the three major sections offers material that one is unlikely to find in other reviews of animal ethics: the first by viewing familiar territory in a different light (advancing the thesis that the utility-versus-rights debate in animal ethics is much less important than is generally thought); the second by reviewing major recent works that are not very well-known (at least ? My thanks to Tom Beauchamp, Maggie Little, and Barbara Orlans for their comments on a draft of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Volume 3, Number 2 June 2014 Edited by John Berkman, Charles C
    Volume 3, Number 2 June 2014 NON-HUMAN ANIMALS Edited by John Berkman, Charles C. Camosy, and Celia Deane-Drummond Introduction: Catholic Moral Theology and the Moral Status of Non-Human Animals .......................................1 John Berkman and Celia Deane-Drummond From Theological Speciesism to a Theological Ethology: Where Catholic Moral Theology Needs to Go ......................................... 11 John Berkman Animals, Evil, and Family Meals ................................................................ 35 Julie Rubio The Use of Non-Human Animals in Biomedical Research: Can Moral Theology Fill the Gap? .......................................................... 54 Charles C. Camosy and Susan Kopp Evolutionary Perspectives on Inter-Morality and Inter-Species Relationships Interrogated in the Light of the Rise and Fall of Homo sapiens sapiens .................. 72 Celia Deane–Drummond Moral Passions: A Thomistic Interpretation of Moral Emotions in Nonhuman and Human Animals ....................... 93 Jean Porter Speaking Theologically of Animal Rights ................................................. 109 James E. Helmer Contributors .............................................................................................. 130 EDITOR David M. McCarthy, Mount St. Mary’s University EDITORIAL BOARD Melanie Barrett, University of St. Mary of the Lake/Mundelein Seminary Jana M. Bennett, University of Dayton Mara Brecht, St. Norbert College Joseph Capizzi, The Catholic University of America David Cloutier, Mount St. Mary's
    [Show full text]