Eminent Domain and Property Rights in Louisiana Scott .P Ledet

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Eminent Domain and Property Rights in Louisiana Scott .P Ledet Louisiana Law Review Volume 67 | Number 1 Fall 2006 The Kelo Effect: Eminent Domain and Property Rights in Louisiana Scott .P Ledet Repository Citation Scott .P Ledet, The Kelo Effect: Eminent Domain and Property Rights in Louisiana, 67 La. L. Rev. (2006) Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.lsu.edu/lalrev/vol67/iss1/7 This Comment is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews and Journals at LSU Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Louisiana Law Review by an authorized editor of LSU Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Kelo Effect: Eminent Domain and Property Rights in Louisiana* I. INTRODUCTION Most property owners in America have never contemplated the idea that one day the government might force them to leave their home. However, United States law has long recognized the power of a government as sovereign to take private property for what has sometimes been deemed a "public good,"' "public benefit," 2 or "public necessity." 3 The traditional notion of the purposes for which the government was authorized to take private property included building roads,4 railroads,5 and erecting dams.6 Justification for these types of takings rests upon the belief that the individual must forego his right to property for the sake of a 7 common good benefiting society at large. From this country's beginnings, the founders recognized the potential for abuse with respect to the government's eminent domain power. In order to combat potential abuse, they placed a restriction on "takings" in the Fifth Amendment: "nor shall private property be taken for public use, without just compensation." 8 At first glance, this clause plainly seems to contain a restriction, i.e., that the government shall not take property unless it is for public use and just compensation is paid. The evolution of the "public use" limitation evidences an ever- Copyright 2006, by LOUISIANA LAW REvIEw. * At the time of this publication, the Louisiana Legislature has proposed an amendment to the Louisiana Constitution, Article I, Section 4(B). The proposal awaits a vote of the citizens. See S.B. 1, 2006 Leg. Reg. Sess. (La.). 1. See, e.g., In re Forsstrom, 38 P.2d 878 (Ariz. 1934). 2. See, e.g., Filbin Corp. v. United States, 265 F. 354 (E.D.S.C. 1920). 3. See, e.g., Griffith v. S. Ry. Co., 131 S.E. 413 (N.C. 1926). 4. Rindge Co. v. County of Los Angeles, 262 U.S. 700 (1923). 5. Nat'l R.R. Passenger Corp. v. Boston & Maine Corp., 503 U.S. 407 (1992). 6. Boston & Roxbury Mill Corp. v. Newman, 29 Mass. 467 (1832). 7. Compensation for the taking plays a key role and adds to the justification for the government's taking of property, but that is not the focus of this comment. Its sole focus is the public use requirement. 8. U.S. CONST. amend. V. 172 LOUISIANA LA W REVIEW [Vol. 67 broadening interpretation by both legislatures and courts. Thus, a once-meaningful9 restriction is in danger of becoming an empty guarantee. The constitutional line dividing justified and unjustified takings has become a highly debated issue both at the federal and state levels. The United States Supreme Court's latest pronouncement on the issue in Kelo v. City of New London, Connecticut ° has fueled the debate. In Kelo, a five to four decision, the Court explicitly held that "[the] city's decision to take property for the purpose of economic development satisfiesl the 'public use' requirement of the Fifth Amendment."" Louisiana, like many other states, has sprung into action in response to this decision. Specifically, Louisiana legislators are in the process of drafting provisions in an attempt to protect property owners in this state from the sort of taking that occurred in Kelo.12 This comment focuses on Louisiana's law of eminent domain and on Kelo's impact on the interpretation of that law. It also gives suggestions as to the future path of Louisiana law so that this state might protect property rights to a greater extent than required by the United States Constitution as interpreted in Kelo. This landmark case undoubtedly broadened, for better or for worse, the scope of the government's power to use eminent domain. The initial reaction among many is that Kelo was wrongly decided. As Justice John Paul Stevens points out in the majority opinion, however, states are free to enact greater protections of property than those required by the United States Constitution.' 3 This comment is meant to function as a guide for 9. See, e.g., Haw. Hous. Auth. v. Midkiff, 467 U.S. 229 (1984); Berman v. Parker, 348 U.S. 26 (1954). 10. Kelo v. City of New London, Conn., 125 S. Ct. 2655 (2005). 11. Id.at2661. 12. John Kramer, With Governor's Signature Today, Alabama Will Become First State To Curb Eminent Domain Abuse After Kelo, INSTITUTE FOR JUSTICE (2005), http://www.ij.org/private_property/castle/8_3_05pr.html (last visited May 29, 2006) (stating that Louisiana legislators, among others, have announced plans to introduce eminent domain legislation in upcoming sessions). 13. Kelo, 125 S.Ct. at 2668. 20061 COMMENTS the State of Louisiana as to measures that might prevent the type of taking that occurred in Kelo.14 The following section, Part II, analyzes the Kelo facts and the reasoning of the majority, concurring, and dissenting opinions of the United States Supreme Court. Part II concludes by outlining the historical basis concerning the law of eminent domain. The current Louisiana constitutional provision on property rights and the ways in which it might be interpreted to prevent a Kelo taking are discussed in Part. III-A. Part III-B analyzes a recent case in which a Louisiana court addressed an issue very similar to the one in Kelo and how that case, or one like it, could be decided if it were to reach the Louisiana Supreme Court. Possible revisions of the constitutional provision on property are assessed in Part IV-A. Part IV-B addresses a Michigan case which might serve as a model for the Louisiana courts when addressing any future Kelo takings. II. BACKGROUND: KELO VS. NEW LONDON AND HISTORICAL ANALYSIS The decision in Kelo stands as a .vitally important development in the law of eminent domain because it has the potential to affect the lives of many in this country. This section discusses the facts from which the case arose, along with the majority, concurring, and dissenting opinions. This case arguably represents the outer limits of the government's power to take property under the Federal Constitution. Understanding this limit helps to guide the development of Louisiana's constitutional law on takings as will be explored later in this comment. At the end of this section, the origin of the power of eminent domain and its development in this country are also discussed. A. Kelo Facts In 2000, on the day before Thanksgiving, Susette Kelo returned to her home in New London, Connecticut, to find a 14. Hereinafter referred to as a "Kelo taking"; that is, one where a private home is taken for the purpose of economic development. LOUISIANA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 67 condemnation notice nailed to her door.15 The reason for her eviction was that the City of New London had approved a redevelopment plan that called for the condemnation of approximately 115 privately-owned properties so that the area could be turned into an industrial park, including office space, hotels, and restaurants. 16 The New London Development Corporation ("NLDC"), a private nonprofit entity which had been created some years earlier to assist the city in economic development, was authorized by the city to condemn the 7 properties in this area.' Moreover, as long as Ms.8 Kelo remained in the house, the city required that she pay rent. ' Most of the owners of these properties in New London acquiesced to the city's demand and voluntarily sold their homes to the NLDC. Susette Kelo and a few of her neighbors, however, refused to leave and subsequently filed suit in the New London Superior Court in December 2000. Petitioners claimed, inter alia, that the taking of their property violated the "public use" restriction in the Fifth Amendment.' 9 After a seven-day bench trial, the court issued a permanent restraining order prohibiting the taking of the part of the condemned property owned by the plaintiffs. On appeal by both sides, the Connecticut Supreme Court reversed the trial court and held that all of the city's takings were constitutional. 21 The Supreme Court of the United States granted Susette Kelo's petition for certiorari. 22 B. Kelo Decision The Supreme Court of the United States presented the issue very succinctly: "We granted certiorari to determine whether a city's decision to take property for the purpose of economic development satisfies the 'public use' requirement of the Fifth 15. Laura Mansnerus, Ties to a NeighborhoodAt Root of Court Fight,N.Y. TIMES, July 24, 2001, at B5. 16. Kelo, 125 S. Ct. at 2659. 17. Id. 18. Id. at 2660. 19. Id. 20. Id. 21. Kelo v. City of New London, 843 A.2d 500 (Conn. 2004). 22. Kelo v. City of New London, Conn., 542 U.S. 965 (2004). 2006] COMMENTS Amendment." 23 At the outset, the Kelo Court recognized two distinctly opposite approaches to the problem.24 The first is the longstanding and widely-accepted principle of Justice Samuel Chase, who proclaimed in Calder v. Bull that the government cannot take property from one citizen and give it to another.25 The competing approach, and the one ultimately adopted by the Court in Kelo, proclaims that "a State may transfer property from one private party to another if future 'use by the public' is the purpose of the taking., 26 The Court recognized that this was a close case; it did not involve a purely private taking, which was condemned in Midk if, nor was this development to be used by the general public in the same way as a road or post office.
Recommended publications
  • CREATING an AMERICAN PROPERTY LAW: ALIENABILITY and ITS LIMITS in AMERICAN HISTORY Claire Priest
    CREATING AN AMERICAN PROPERTY LAW: ALIENABILITY AND ITS LIMITS IN AMERICAN HISTORY Claire Priest Contact Information: Northwestern University School of Law 357 East Chicago Ave. Chicago, IL 60611 Phone: (312) 503-4470 Email: [email protected] Acknowledgements: ∗Associate Professor of Law, Northwestern University School of Law. B.A., J.D., Ph.D. Yale University. I would like to thank James McMasters of Northwestern’s Law Library for his help in finding copies of many of the primary sources used to write this Article. For extremely valuable comments and suggestions, I would like to thank Bernard Bailyn, Stuart Banner, Kenworthey Bilz, Charlotte Crane, David Dana, Michele Landis Dauber, Christine Desan, Tony A. Freyer, Morton J. Horwitz, Daniel Hulsebosch, Stanley N. Katz, Daniel M. Klerman, Naomi Lamoreaux, Charles W. McCurdy, Edmund S. Morgan, Janice Nadler, Sarah Pearsall, Dylan Penningroth, George L. Priest, Richard J. Ross, Emma Rothschild, Dhananjai Shivakumar, Kenneth L. Sokoloff, Vicky Saker Woeste, Gavin Wright and the seminar participants at Northwestern University School of Law’s Faculty Workshop, Stanford Law School’s Faculty Workshop, UCLA’s Legal History Colloquium and Economic History Workshop, NYU’s Legal History Colloquium, the University of Florida Fredric G. Levin College of Law’s Faculty Workshop, the Chicago Legal History Seminar, the American Society for Legal History’s Annual Meeting, the University of Illinois College of Law’s Faculty Workshop, the Omohundro Institute of Early American History’s Annual Conference, and Harvard University’s Conference on Atlantic Legalities. The Julius Rosenthal Fund at Northwestern University School of Law provided generous research support. CREATING AN AMERICAN PROPERTY LAW: ALIENABILITY AND ITS LIMITS IN AMERICAN HISTORY This Article analyzes an issue central to the economic and political development of the early United States: laws protecting real property from the claims of creditors.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Ownership and Property in the Person: Democratization and a Tale of Two Concepts*
    The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 10, Number 1, 2002, pp. 20±53 Self-Ownership and Property in the Person: Democratization and a Tale of Two Concepts* CAROLE PATEMAN Political Science, University of California at Los Angeles Democracy is at war with the renting of human beings, not with private property. David Ellerman URING the 1990s a number of political philosophers turned their attention Dto the concept of self-ownership. Much of the discussion is critical of libertarianism,1 a political theory that goes hand-in-hand with neo-liberal economic doctrines and global policies of structural adjustment and privatization. Attracta Ingram's A Political Theory of Rights and G. A. Cohen's Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality are devoted to such criticism Uand I shall focus much of my argument on their books2). The consensus among most participants in the debate is that self-ownership is merely a way of talking about autonomy, but Ingram and Cohen go against the tide by arguing that the idea is inimical to autonomy and that an alternative is needed. In The Sexual Contract I am also critical of libertarianism, and my conclusion is similar to Ingram's and Cohen's. I argue that the idea of property in the person must be relinquished if a more free and democratic social and political order is to be created. However, despite some common concerns, there are very few points at which my work and that of Cohen and Ingram, or of most contributors to the current debates about self-ownership, come together. In large part this is because property in the person, not self-ownership, is central to my analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Agribusiness and Rural Development
    Journal of Agribusiness pISSN 1899-5241 eISSN 1899-5772 and Rural Development www.jard.edu.pl 4(34) 2014, 159-171 PERPETUAL USUFRUCT OF AGRICULTURAL LANDS – SELECTED LEGAL AND FINANCIAL ISSUES Aneta Suchoń Adam Mickiewicz University in Poznań Abstract. The article makes an attempt to determine whether the legal regulations provide a perpetual lessee with, first of all, stable conditions to hold agricultural lands and to run a business activity on these lands and, second of all, whether the regulations make it easi- er for perpetual lessees to acquire the right to own the lands they possess. The first part of the article concentrates on the legal nature of perpetual usufruct as well as the rights and financial obligations of a perpetual lessee. Then, the paper focuses on the transformation of perpetual usufruct into the right of ownership and the expiry of perpetual usufruct. Next, the article analyses the issue of a perpetual lessee as an agricultural producer. At the end, the Author states that perpetual lessee possesses a wide range of rights and can freely run an agricultural activity on agricultural lands. The legislator has acknowledged perpet- ual usufruct, along with the most popular forms of holding lands such as ownership and lease, to be a stable element of rural relations. Thus, a perpetual lessee can be granted the European funds, agricultural tax reliefs and insurance in KRUS. Key words: perpetual usufruct, agricultural lands, agricultural activity, EU funds INTRODUCTION For each agricultural producer it is essential to possess lands in an autonomous and stable way in order to ensure uninterrupted course of an agricultural activity.
    [Show full text]
  • American Law Institute Cle Eminent Domain and Land Valuation Litigation Keynote Address: “Property Rights: Foundation for a Free Society”
    AMERICAN LAW INSTITUTE CLE EMINENT DOMAIN AND LAND VALUATION LITIGATION KEYNOTE ADDRESS: “PROPERTY RIGHTS: FOUNDATION FOR A FREE SOCIETY” PALM SPRINGS, CALIFORNIA JANUARY 24, 2019 KEYNOTE ADDRESS SPEAKER W. Taylor Reveley, III, President Emeritus of William & Mary, and John Stewart Bryan Professor of Jurisprudence Emeritus at William & Mary Law School* Friends, let’s think back to September 1787. Our country’s Consti- tutional Convention was nearing its end in Philadelphia when a formidable woman encountered Benjamin Franklin, a delegate to the Convention.1 She braced him with this question: “Well[,] Doctor[,] what have we got[,] a republic or a monarchy[?]”2 The wise, old, battle- tested Franklin replied simply: “A republic . if you can keep it.”3 So, friends, we have a republic if we can keep it. We have a free so- ciety if we can keep it. Just what role do property rights—the freedom to acquire and govern our assets—play in nurturing our republic and our society? It is the rare American these days who doesn’t feel that our coun- try’s civic life and democratic institutions have gotten pretty ragged, and our political and social fabric dangerously frayed. This feeling runs across the political and cultural spectrum from citizens who find Donald Trump and Fox News the “be all and end all” to those who sit at the feet of Nancy Pelosi or Bernie Sanders, aided and abetted by CNN and MSNBC. Perhaps the citizens most concerned about the sad state of our political and social fabric are those who fall be- tween these two poles, hoping everyone will take a deep breath, cool the invective, and get on with the work at hand.
    [Show full text]
  • The Essential JOHN STUART MILL the Essential DAVID HUME
    The Essential JOHN STUART MILL The Essential DAVID HUME DAVID The Essential by Sandra J. Peart Copyright © 2021 by the Fraser Institute. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission except in the case of brief quotations embodied in critical articles and reviews. The author of this publication has worked independently and opinions expressed by him are, therefore, his own, and do not necessarily reflect the opinions of the Fraser Institute or its supporters, directors, or staff. This publication in no way implies that the Fraser Institute, its directors, or staff are in favour of, or oppose the passage of, any bill; or that they support or oppose any particular political party or candidate. Printed and bound in Canada Cover design and artwork Bill C. Ray ISBN 978-0-88975-616-8 Contents Introduction: Who Was John Stuart Mill? / 1 1. Liberty: Why, for Whom, and How Much? / 9 2. Freedom of Expression: Learning, Bias, and Tolerance / 21 3. Utilitarianism: Happiness, Pleasure, and Public Policy / 31 4. Mill’s Feminism: Marriage, Property, and the Labour Market / 41 5. Production and Distribution / 49 6. Mill on Property / 59 7. Mill on Socialism, Capitalism, and Competition / 71 8. Mill’s Considerations on Representative Government / 81 Concluding Thoughts: Lessons from Mill’s Radical Reformism / 91 Suggestions for Further Reading / 93 Publishing information / 99 About the author / 100 Publisher’s acknowledgments / 100 Supporting the Fraser Institute / 101 Purpose, funding, and independence / 101 About the Fraser Institute / 102 Editorial Advisory Board / 103 Fraser Institute d www.fraserinstitute.org Introduction: Who Was John Stuart Mill? I have thought that in an age in which education, and its improvement, are the subject of more, if not of profounder study than at any former period of English history, it may be useful that there should be some record of an education which was unusual and remarkable.
    [Show full text]
  • Handbook for New Jersey Assessors
    Handbook For New Jersey Assessors PHIL MURPHY, Governor ELIZABETH MAHER MUOIO, State Treasurer Issued by Property Administration – Local Property Division of Taxation – Department of the Treasury State of New Jersey Trenton, New Jersey Revised April 2021 April 2021 April 2021 April 2021 April 2021 New Jersey Property Taxpayers’ Bill of Rights P.L. 2017, c.128 N.J.S.A. 54:1-2.1 Overview The Property Taxpayers’ Bill of Rights ensures that: 1. All property taxpayers are accorded the basic rights of fair and equitable treatment under the State Constitution and laws of New Jersey; 2. All property taxpayers receive the information and assistance they need to understand and meet their property tax responsibilities. Services to Property Taxpayers As a property taxpayer, you have the right to obtain information explained in simple, nontechnical terms about: Your responsibilities and rights as a property owner and property taxpayer; Your real property assessment and how it is determined and calculated; Your right to appeal and how to appeal an assessment you believe is incorrect as to your property or as to another property in the same county and the time limits involved; Your right, in the context of a property tax appeal, to view the property record card of other real property in the municipality. Responsiveness You have the right to expect questions will be responded to within a reasonable amount of time. Statements and Notices You have the right to expect all notices you receive will clearly identify the purpose of the communication and the proper procedure when responding. For More Information Many Local Property Tax forms and publications are available on the Division of Taxation’s website at: www.state.nj.us/treasury/taxation/.
    [Show full text]
  • The Right to Privacy? Andrew Koppelman
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Chicago Law School: Chicago Unbound University of Chicago Legal Forum Volume 2002 Article 6 2002 The Right to Privacy? Andrew Koppelman Follow this and additional works at: http://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/uclf Recommended Citation Koppelman, Andrew (2002) "The Right to Privacy?," University of Chicago Legal Forum: Vol. 2002, Article 6. Available at: http://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/uclf/vol2002/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Chicago Legal Forum by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Right to Privacy? Andrew Koppelman Laws that discriminate against gay people discriminate on the basis of sex. If Lucy may marry Fred, but Ricky may not marry Fred, then (assuming that Fred would be a desirable spouse for either) Ricky is suffering legal disadvantage because of his sex. Moreover, such laws depend on and reinforce the subor- dination of women. I have argued for years that this is the princi- pal constitutional defect with such laws.1 I have not, however, said very much about the comparative part of this claim, and in- stead have emphasized the strengths of the sex discrimination argument. The conventional wisdom, on the other hand, is that the appropriate starting point for any discussion of the legal rights of gay people is the idea that certain private matters are none of the law's business.! Certainly this has been, for a long time, the most commonly made argument for the legal equality of gay people.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Ownership, Property, and Moral Desert
    Adrian Bardon FROM NOZICK TO WELFARE RIGHTS: SELF-OWNERSHIP, PROPERTY,AND MORAL DESERT ABSTRACT: The Kantian moral foundations of Nozickian libertarianism sug- gest that the claim that self-ownership grounds only negative rights to property should be rejected. The moral foundations of Nozick’s libertarianism better support basing property rights on moral desert. It is neither incoherent nor im- plausible to say that need can be a basis for desert. By implication, the liber- tarian contention that persons ought to be respected as persons living self-shap- ing lives is inconsistent with the libertarian refusal to accept that claims of need can sometimes outweigh claims to property. Nozickian libertarians maintain the view that persons can hold absolute rights to property, even though the assertion of such rights may place others in a position such that their basic subsistence needs are not met. In this paper I examine the moral foundations of Nozickian libertarian- ism. I argue that the libertarian claim that persons ought to be re- spected as persons living self-shaping lives entails that claims of need can sometimes outweigh claims to property. In the first part of the paper, I outline some arguments that under- mine the standard libertarian claim that self-ownership is the moral ground for absolute negative rights to property. I also examine argu- ments showing that moral desert based on labor is a more secure foun- Critical Review (), no. ISSN ‒.© Critical Review Foundation. Adrian Bardon, Department of Philosophy, Wake Forest University, Winston-Salem, NC , thanks Bruce Aune, Fred Feldman, Jack Hanson, Clay Splawn, Jean-Paul Vessel, and two anonymous reviewers for their extensive and invaluable comments on an earlier draft.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Ownership, Freedom and Eudaimonia
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy Spring 5-13-2011 Self-Ownership, Freedom and Eudaimonia Keith D. Fox Georgia State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Fox, Keith D., "Self-Ownership, Freedom and Eudaimonia." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2011. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/78 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. “SELF-OWNERSHIP, FREEDOM AND EUDAIMONIA” by KEITH D. FOX Under the direction of Andrew Jason Cohen ABSTRACT In this thesis I will explore the relationship between Nozick’s self-ownership principle and freedom. I will defend G.A. Cohen’s critique of self-ownership and try to show how his argument that self-ownership is hostile to genuine freedom presents a problem for Nozick. I think it is clear that Nozick’s self-ownership does little to protect a meaningful sort of freedom; and a meaningful sort of freedom is exactly what Nozick aims to protect. This is true because eudaimonistic moral beliefs ought to undergird Nozick’s self-ownership thesis, and self-ownership can therefore be assessed in light of whether it actually promotes human flourishing in the relevant ways. This undergirding eudaimonism becomes clear when we see that self-ownership is intended to protect the ability of each individual to pursue and act upon her own conception of the good.
    [Show full text]
  • Locke and the Right to (Acquire) Property: a Lockean Argument for the Rawlsian Difference Principle
    1 Locke and the Right to (Acquire) Property: A Lockean Argument for the Rawlsian Difference Principle Richard Oxenberg I. Introduction The purpose of my paper is to show the derivation of what has sometimes been called the ‘new liberalism’ (or, as we might now call it, ‘progressive liberalism’) from the basic principles of classical liberalism. In particular, I wish to argue that a careful analysis of the right to property as developed by John Locke shows that this right is neither absolute nor unlimited. Indeed, analysis shows that, considered in the light of modern capitalist society, to honor this right will demand a fairly robust and ongoing program of progressive taxation, aid to the poor, and social programs sufficient to bring the distribution of property into accord with John Rawls’ difference principle. To properly grasp Locke’s theory of property rights it is first of all necessary to make a distinction between the natural right to property as it exists in the Lockean ‘state of nature’ and the societal right to property as it may be established by consent in a socio-economic political system. I begin, then, with an examination of the natural right to property and then proceed to consideration of the societal right to property. II. The Natural Right to Property Of classical liberalism’s celebrated triad of natural rights – life, liberty, and property – the right to property is distinctive. Unlike the others, it is a right to something not inherent to our individual natures. Whereas life belongs to us as biological entities and liberty, arguably, as 2 rational agents, material property does not naturally inhere in us at all.
    [Show full text]
  • Transformative Environmental Constitutionalism's Response to The
    humanities Article Transformative Environmental Constitutionalism’s Response to the Setting Aside of South Africa’s Moratorium on Rhino Horn Trade Melanie Murcott Department of Public Law, University of Pretoria, Lynnwood Road, Hatfield 0002, South Africa; [email protected] Received: 7 September 2017; Accepted: 5 November 2017; Published: 7 November 2017 Abstract: South Africa’s rhino population is under threat of extinction due to poaching for purposes of illegal international trade of rhino horn. The South African government has thus far been unable to regulate rhino poaching effectively. One of the legal responses was to introduce a moratorium on local trade of rhino horn. However, in 2015 the High Court set aside the moratorium. Subsequent appeals against the High Court’s decision to the Supreme Court of Appeal and the Constitutional Court were dismissed without a hearing. The anthropocentric approach to the protection of biodiversity under South African environmental law is reflected upon in this article. It is argued that the High Court adopted an unapologetic and uncritical anthropocentric approach to the issues before it. A legal theory of transformative environmental constitutionalism is proposed as a means to infuse litigation about global environmental problems with substantive environmental considerations, such as precaution, prevention and equity. These principles could facilitate a more ecocentric orientation towards the application of environmental laws. Keywords: rhino; environmental law; transformative environmental constitutionalism 1. Introduction Species extinction and biodiversity loss are two of the many disturbing impacts of the Anthropocene, a time that acknowledges ‘the devastating and overwhelming impact of people on Earth and its systems’, as ‘the consequences of human actions have become the major factor in influencing ecological outcomes’1.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 7 the CONCEPT of PROPERTY
    Chapter 7 THE CONCEPT OF PROPERTY Section 1. THE UTILITARIAN THEORY Justifications of property on utilitarian grounds are at least as old as David Hume, the eighteenth-century Scottish empirical philosopher. In Hume’s treatment, the utilitarian argument is at once an answer to Locke—property is not a natural right but a product of civil society—and a justification of property—civil society needs a concept of property in order to operate. See L. BECKER, PROPERTY RIGHTS: PHILOSOPHIC FOUNDATIONS 57–64 (1970); Berry, Property and Possession: Two Replies to Locke-Hume and Hegel, in PROPERTY 89–95 (J. Pennock & J. Chapman eds., Nomos No. 22, 1980). The following extracts expand on Hume’s ideas in two different directions: the first from the great utilitarian philosopher Jeremy Bentham, emphasizes how dependent property is on society; the second, by a modern economist, emphasizes how important property is for maximizing the wealth of society: [p*133] J. BENTHAM, THEORY OF LEGISLATION 111–13 (R. Hildreth ed. 1864)1 The better to understand the advantages of law let us endeavor to form a clear idea of property. We shall see that there is no such thing as natural property, and that it is entirely the work of law. Property is nothing but a basis of expectation; the expectation of deriving certain advantages from a thing which we are said to possess, in consequence of the relation in which we stand towards it. There is no image, no painting, no visible trait, which can express the relation that constitutes property. It is not material, it is metaphysical; it is a mere conception of the mind.
    [Show full text]