Matherne, Heidegger Lexicon Entries

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Matherne, Heidegger Lexicon Entries Kunst (Art), Riß (Rift, Design), and Anschauung (Intuition) Entries To appear in the Heidegger Lexicon, ed. Mark Wrathall, Cambridge University Press Samantha Matherne (UC Santa Cruz) 1. Kunst, Art According to Heidegger, in order to understand art, we cannot take our cue from the aesthetic tradition; rather, we must analyze art in terms of its relation to truth and ontology. To this end, he defines art as the historical happening of truth in which beings are unconcealed to us by means of a work of art. On his view, it is only within this framework that one can hope to give a proper account of three important aspects of art, viz., its essence, creation, and appreciation. In addition to defending a positive account of art, Heidegger devotes much of his discussion on this topic to a critique of aesthetics. As Heidegger presents it, aesthetics is driven by the idea that subjective experience is the key to understanding what the essence, appreciation, and creation of a work of art involves: The way in which man experiences art is supposed to inform us about its essential nature. Experience is the standard-giving source not only for the appreciation and enjoyment of art but also for its creation. Everything is experience (GA5: 67/50). Teasing this claim out, he suggests that aesthetics takes the essence of a work of art to depend on it being an object of subjective experience: “Aesthetics treated the artwork as an object, as indeed an object of aesthesis, of sensory apprehension… [which] [t]hese days… is called an “experience”” (GA5: 67/50). Meanwhile, he maintains that aesthetics analyzes the appreciation of a work of art in terms of the feelings and experiences the object gives rise to in a subject, e.g., the feeling of pleasure, which defines beautiful art in the classic 18th century aesthetic tradition. Finally, concerning the creation of a work of art, Heidegger claims that aesthetics takes it to involve something akin to handicraft, i.e., the skilled activity through which a craftsperson takes some matter and gives it form in light of an end or purpose. Indeed, he argues that this conception of artistic creativity becomes so influential that “the conceptual pair “matter and form” came to be the really principal schema for all inquiry into art” (GA43: 99/N1 82, see also GA5: 12/9). Heidegger raises several objections to this aesthetic approach to art. To begin, he argues that aesthetics is misguided in applying the form-matter distinction to art because this distinction is not one that “belongs, originally, to the sphere of art and the artwork,” but rather to the sphere of equipment (GA5: 12/9). Unlike equipment, which depends on our ends and purposes, he asserts that there is something about a work of art that is “self-sufficient… which has taken shape by itself and is never forced into being” and in this regard is more like another type of being, viz., a mere thing (GA5: 14/10). Moreover, Heidegger argues that any analysis of a work of art solely in terms of its relation to subjective experience is problematic because it feeds into two worrisome tendencies that dominate the modern era, viz., subjectivism and enframing [Gestell]. Subjectivism, for Heidegger, involves the disposition to carve up the world into subjects and objects and to take the former to be the measure of the latter. Meanwhile, enframing is the more extreme form subjectivism takes in the technological era in which beings come to be defined not just in relation to the subject, but to the subject’s will. Accordingly, in enframing all beings come to be regarded as resources, the value of which we can calculate in relation to our will. According to Heidegger, aesthetics falls under the sway of both of these tendencies. In the first place, its commitment to subjectivism is evident in the fact that it places art within the framework of subjects and objects: [in aesthetics] [t]he artwork is posited as the “object” for a “subject”; definitive for aesthetic consideration is the subject-object relation… The work becomes an object in terms of that surface which is accessible to “lived experience” (GA43: 91/N1 78). Furthermore, he indicates that the influence of technology and enframing is manifest in rise of the “art business” [Kunstbetriebes] and the fact that works of art come to be defined in relation to that business, e.g., as objects to be enjoyed by the connoisseur, preserved by the curator, criticized by the critic, etc. (GA5: 26/19). Heidegger raises a number of objections against aesthetics on the basis of the tendencies towards subjectivism and enframing in it. To begin, aesthetics falls prey to Heidegger’s more general objection to these tendencies, viz., that they encourage an overly anthropocentric understanding of beings. Rather than understanding beings on their own terms, according to their own essences, he objects that subjectivism and enframing erroneously lead us to define beings solely in terms of their relation to human beings. For Heidegger, then, aesthetics goes wrong insofar as it overlooks the ways in which works of art manifest something that is not entirely of human making. Furthermore, he objects that by treating a work of art as an object of subjective experience or as a resource, aesthetics overlooks the true value of a work of art. “For us today,” he says, “the beautiful is the relaxing, what is restful, and thus intended for enjoyment. Art then belongs in the domain of the pastry chef” (GA40: 140/IM 146). However, on Heidegger’s view, this misestimates the value of what a work of art as ‘great art’ could be: Great art and its works are great in their historical emergence and Being because in man’s historical existence they accomplish a decisive task: they make manifest, in the way appropriate to works, what beings as a whole are…. Art and its works are necessary only as an itinerary and sojourn for man in which the truth of beings as a whole… opens itself up to him…. [A]rt is great because it is an “absolute need” (GA43: 100/84). As this passage indicates, he thinks great art accomplishes a decisive task in history because it answers an absolute need, viz., to understand the truth of beings as a whole. However, echoing Hegel’s claims about the end of art, Heidegger maintains that although there used to be great art, e.g., in Greece, “when aesthetics achieves its greatest possible height, breadth, and rigor of form, great art comes to an end” (GA43: 100/N1 84, see also GA5: 67-60/50-2). By Heidegger’s lights, by approaching art from within the subjectivist and enframing perspectives, aesthetics mistakenly limits the potential of a work of art to the realm of pastry when it, in fact, once did and perhaps could once again play a decisive historical role in our understanding of the truth of beings. On this point, Heidegger does not appear to share Hegel’s conviction that great art must remain a thing of the past. Rather, he leaves open the possibility that art might one day again be great; indeed, he even indicates that art might be what saves us from the grip of technology: Could it be that [poetic] revealing lays claim to the arts most primally, so that they for their part may expressly foster the growth of the saving power…? Whether art may be granted this highest possibility of its essence in the midst of the extreme danger, no one can tell (GA7:36/QCT 35). At the very least, he acknowledges that art has a possibility higher than that which aesthetics accords it and leaves it open whether it can once again play a decisive role in history, revealing to us the truth of beings as they are in their own essence. Contrary to the aesthetic tradition, Heidegger thus thinks that a proper analysis of the essence, creation, and appreciation of art is one that relies neither on the framework of subjects and objects, nor on the enframing perspective of technology and that, instead, restores the possibility that art can be great insofar as it historically reveals to us the truth of beings. Defending such an account is something that Heidegger undertakes with his first major essay on art, ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’ (1935-6) and that he refines over the years, especially in his lectures and writing on poetry, e.g., his lectures on Hölderlin’s ‘Germania’ and ‘The Rhine’ (GA39, 1934-5), Elucidations of Hölderlin’s Poetry (GA4, 1936-68), ‘Why Poets?’ (1946), and ‘…Poetically Man Dwells…’ (1951).1 In order to develop the details of Heidegger’s account, it makes sense to start, as he does in the ‘Origin’ essay, with a discussion of the essence of art. Heidegger begins this essay by drawing a distinction between a work of art and art. Whereas a work of art is a particular type of being that we can come across in experience, e.g., a painting, he claims that art is what serves as the ‘origin’ of a work of art, i.e., the “source of its nature [Wesen]” (GA5: 1/1). He, in turn, defines art as “a happening of truth,” which involves “the setting-itself-to-work of the truth of beings” [das Sich-ins- Werk-Setzen der Warheit des Seienden] (GA5: 21/16). By ‘truth’ in this context, Heidegger has in mind the Greek conception of truth as aletheia, which involves the “unconcealment of beings”; in which case, when truth happens in art, he thinks the truth of beings is unconcealed (GA5: 21/16).
Recommended publications
  • Curriculum Vitae Fall 2014
    James C. Olsen ! Georgetown University 43260 Tumbletree Terr Department of Philosophy Broadlands, VA 20148 202.687.7487 [email protected] CURRENT POSITION Researcher, Center for New Designs in Learning and Scholarship, Georgetown University (2013 - present) ! Adjunct Faculty, Georgetown University (2013 - present) EDUCATION !Georgetown University (2006-2013), PhD in Philosophy (September 2013) Dissertation: “Mind, Body, and World: Resolving the Dreyfus-McDowell Debate.” ! Committee: William Blattner (Chair), Mark Lance, and Mark A. Wrathall (UC Riverside) Dissertation Abstract: Hubert Dreyfus has claimed that our situated, skillful and embodied engagement with the world (skillful coping) is an intentional, personal-level phenomena that serves as a ground for conceptual activity. John McDowell has responded by claiming that skillful coping is pervasively conceptual and by dismissing the relevance of the normative phenomena to which Dreyfus calls attention. I argue that a more careful analysis of both reflective and unreflective experience reveals that possessing conceptual capacities—no less than possessing skillful, action-oriented bodies— changes the nature and content of perception. Consequently, while Dreyfus is right to insist on the relevance of our skillful and unreflective bodily practices, he misunderstands the relationship between coping and language specifically, and hence between coping and conceptuality more generally. This leaves him with a problematic dualism in the nature of human experience and understanding. On the
    [Show full text]
  • Ontology and Ethics at the Intersection of Phenomenology and Environmental Philosophy*
    Inquiry, 47, 380–412 Ontology and Ethics at the Intersection of Phenomenology and Environmental Philosophy* Iain Thomson University of New Mexico The idea inspiring the eco-phenomenological movement is that phenomenology can help remedy our environmental crisis by uprooting and replacing environmentally- destructive ethical and metaphysical presuppositions inherited from modern philosophy. Eco-phenomenology’s critiques of subject/object dualism and the fact/value divide are sketched and its positive alternatives examined. Two competing approaches are discerned within the eco-phenomenological movement: Nietzscheans and Husserlians propose a naturalistic ethical realism in which good and bad are ultimately matters of fact, and values should be grounded in these proto- ethical facts; Heideggerians and Levinasians articulate a transcendental ethical realism according to which we discover what really matters when we are appropriately open to the environment, but what we thereby discover is a transcendental source of meaning that cannot be reduced to facts, values, or entities of any kind. These two species of ethical realism generate different kinds of ethical perfectionism: naturalistic ethical realism yields an eco-centric perfectionism which stresses the flourishing of life in general; transcendental ethical realism leads to a more ‘humanistic’ perfectionism which emphasizes the cultivation of distinctive traits of Dasein. Both approaches are examined, and the Heideggerian strand of the humanistic approach defended, since it approaches the best elements of the eco-centric view while avoiding its problematic ontological assumptions and anti-humanistic implications. I. Introduction: Uncovering the Conceptual Roots of Environmental Devastation What happens when you cross phenomenology with environmental philoso- phy? According to the editors of Eco-Phenomenology: Back to the Earth Itself, you get an important interdisciplinary movement.
    [Show full text]
  • Morganna F. Lambeth Department of Philosophy [email protected] Purdue University 773-682-2320 West Lafayette, in 47907-2098
    Morganna F. Lambeth Department of Philosophy [email protected] Purdue University 773-682-2320 West Lafayette, IN 47907-2098 Current Position 2018-2021 Purdue University, Postdoctoral Fellow in Philosophy and Cornerstone Fall 2018 Instruction: PHIL 111: Ethics (2 x 35 students) Spring 2019 Instruction: SCLA 101: Transformative Texts (30 students) PHIL 411: Modern Ethical Theories (35 students) Education 2011-2018 Northwestern University, Doctoral Program in Philosophy Ph.D. in Philosophy Dissertation: Rethinking the Structure of Events: Heidegger on Kant and the Concept of Cause Committee: Cristina Lafont (Chair), Rachel Zuckert, Mark Wrathall ABSTRACT: I draw on Heidegger’s interpretation of Kant to argue that Kant overestimates the role that causality plays in structuring our experience. Heidegger suggests that Kant’s analysis of experience mistakenly universalizes a fraction of our experience: the experience of mechanical objects. I defend the merits of this suggestion by offering a careful reconstruction of Heidegger’s controversial interpretation of the imagination and applying this interpretation in detail to one of the most debated segments of the Critique of Pure Reason: the Second Analogy. In this chapter, Kant suggests that we must employ the concept of cause in order to be aware that an event (i.e. a change in states) has occurred. While Kant’s mechanical account of events captures our experience of mechanical objects, I argue that his analysis does not capture our experience of events initiated by humans. I suggest that we experience human events rather as components of an overarching project oriented toward some goal. 2009-2011 University of California at Riverside, Doctoral Program in Philosophy M.A.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger on Plato, Truth, and Unconcealment: the 1931–32 Lecture on the Essence of Truth
    Inquiry, 47, 443–463 Heidegger on Plato, Truth, and Unconcealment: The 1931–32 Lecture on The Essence of Truth Mark Wrathall Brigham Young University This paper discusses Heidegger’s 1931–32 lecture course on The Essence of Truth.It argues that Heidegger read Platonic ideas, not only as stage-setting for the western philosophical tradition’s privileging of conceptualization over practice, and its correlative treatment of truth as correctness, but also as an early attempt to work through truth as the fundamental experience of unhiddenness. Wrathall shows how several of Heidegger’s more-famous claims about truth, e.g. that propositional truth is grounded in truth as world-disclosure, and including Heidegger’s critique of the self-evidence of truth as correspondence, are first revealed in a powerful (if iconoclastic) reading of Plato. In the 1920s and 1930s, Heidegger repeatedly offered lectures and seminars largely devoted to the topic of truth. His evolving thoughts on the nature and philosophical significance of truth, however, made their way into relatively few publications, and when they were published, they tended to come in an incredibly condensed and enigmatic form. The main published works from this period include }44 of Sein und Zeit (1927), and essays like ‘Vom Wesen des Grundes’ (1929), ‘Vom Wesen des Wahrheit’ (1930), and ‘Platons Lehre von der Wahrheit’ (1942).1 With the publication of Heidegger’s notes from his lecture courses, it is now becoming possible to connect the dots and flesh out Heidegger’s published account of truth.2 These lecture courses are not just of historiographical interest, however.
    [Show full text]
  • The Bipartite Nature of Attention: Implications for the Phenomenology of Skillful Coping
    Aporia vol. 23 no. 1—2013 The Bipartite Nature of Attention: Implications for the Phenomenology of Skillful Coping KAROLYN CAMPBELL ain McGilchrist’s book The Master and His Emissary has important im- plications for the field of phenomenology and the cognitive sciences. IIn particular, his work on the bipartite nature of attention provides a way by which we can better understand the nature of skillful coping, which paradoxically seems to require careful but relaxed attention. McGilchrist’s book begins with the thesis that the division of the human brain is the result of the need to simultaneously bring two incompatible types of at- tention on the world. In a recent edition of Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, Rupert Read reviews The Master and His Emissary, claiming that, “Besides being a brilliant work, this book is an event” (119), and conclud- ing that “No one who is seriously interested in the focal subject-matter of this journal can afford to ignore his book. At least not, as the saying goes, anyone with half a brain” (124). In this paper, I will discuss the implications of recent research in the cognitive sciences on Hubert Dreyfus’ phenomenology of skillful behav- ior and John Searle’s logical analysis of such behavior. Dreyfus describes the process of engaging in skillful behavior as skillfully coping. ‘Coping’ is a broad word, used in a variety of contexts to imply the ability to deal ef- fectively with something. Skillful coping, within the context of skill acquisi- tion, is a subject that has been examined by philosophers from Aristotle to Heidegger, but most recently and extensively explored by philosophers Karolyn Campbell is a senior majoring in philosophy at Brigham Young University.
    [Show full text]
  • UNIVERSITY of CALIFORNIA RIVERSIDE Agent-Relative
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA RIVERSIDE Agent-Relative Knowledge in Heidegger A Dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Kevin Allen Gin September 2017 Dissertation Committee: Dr. Mark Wrathall, Chairperson Dr. John Perry Dr. Pierre Keller Dr. Michael Nelson Copyright by Kevin Allen Gin 2017 The Dissertation of Kevin Allen Gin is approved: Committee Chairperson University of California, Riverside ACKNOWLEGEMENTS I owe a tremendous amount of gratitude to Mark Wrathall for offering guidance and mentorship over the last seven years. I’ve never had a conversation with Mark that didn’t result in both inspiration and insight. I am also deeply indebted to John Perry, Pierre Keller, and Michael Nelson for both supporting and challenging me while at UCR, and for serving on what I consider to be my “dream” committee. Special thanks are due to John, who spent many selfless hours digging into Heidegger during what eventually turned into the “CSLI / Heidegger” reading group that we sustained for almost two years. It would be difficult to overstate the influence this had on my dissertation. Thanks to Dave Millar, Sam Richards, Josu Acosta, and Dikran Karagueuzian for wrestling through difficult texts during our meetings, and for providing a welcoming place for me to present each chapter of my dissertation. There are countless others from whom I’ve benefited over the years, including Bill Bracken, who allowed me to sit in his Heidegger courses at UCR, and my professors at Messiah College, who first introduced to me the world of philosophy. I’m especially grateful for my wife, Elizabeth, and her immeasurable and unwavering support in all aspects of life.
    [Show full text]
  • After the Death of God: from Political Nihilism to Post-Foundational Democracy
    After The Death Of God: From Political Nihilism To Post-Foundational Democracy Clayton Lewis A Dissertation Submitted To The Faculty Of Graduate Studies In Partial Fulfillment Of The Requirements For The Degree Of Doctor Of Philosophy Graduate Program In Social And Political Thought York University Toronto Ontario April 2017 © Clayton Lewis ii Abstract The topic of this dissertation is Heidegger’s deconstruction of metaphysics viewed through the prism of Nietzsche’s declaration that ‘God is dead’. I argue that Nietzsche’s transvaluation of value remains ensnared by the ‘will to power’ and the nihilistic destiny of the ‘eternal return’. I look at Heidegger’s late thought as a response to the disenchantment of nature and the technological ‘framing’ of Earth. I argue that the delineation of a non-instrumental way life requires a political turn that is quite different from Heidegger’s own conservative nationalism. While the post-structuralist appropriation of Heidegger’s late thought makes some tentative moves towards a post- foundational democracy, I argue that the deconstruction of political community stemming from Derrida, Levinas, and Nancy fails to adequately deal with the question of democratic sovereignty. In light of this inadequacy, I take up the political theory of Benjamin, Schmitt, and Agamben in order to further delineate a ‘negative political theology’ without reference to any metaphysical grounding of sovereign power. Essential to such a politics is the non-linear experience of time as ‘event’. I contrast Benjamin’s notion of empty ‘homogenous time’ with Agamben’s analysis of non-linear ‘revolutionary time’. I suggest that the eschatological remembrance of democracy requires an interruption of history as a linear sequence of time.
    [Show full text]
  • Mark Wrathall: a Philosophical Pluralist
    DOI: http://doi.org/10.12795/HASER/2013.i4.07 MARK WRATHALL: A PHILOSOPHICAL PLURALIST MARK WRATHALL: UN FILÓSOFO PLURALISTA MARK WRATHALL University of California MARTA FIGUERAS [email protected] Universidad Autónoma de Barcelona JOAN MÉNDEZ [email protected] Presidente de la Asociación de Filosofía Práctica de Cataluña RECIBIDO: 14/06/2012 ACEPTADO: 31/07/2012 Marta Figueras – Joan Méndez Mark Wrathall is professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. His work focuses on phenomenology, existentialism, the philosophy of popular culture, and the philosophy of art. He is considered a leading interpreter of the philosophy of Martin Heidegger. And he is author of books like How to Read Heidegger (2005) and Heidegger and Unconcealment: Truth, Language, History (2010). Professor Wrathall is currently editing The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger’s Being and Time (forthcoming 2012), and finishing up a book manuscript on Heidegger’s later work. Philosophy is often criticized, at least in Europe, for being too theoretical. And over the last century, it seems to have been confined to university classrooms. Now, at a time when the fragmentation of society and its values lead back to a reflection on the meaning of existence, the practical aspect of philosophy recovers the importance it had at its origins. In this context, what use is philosophy? HASER. Revista Internacional de Filosofía Aplicada, nº 4, 2013, pp. 171-179 172 MARK WRATHALL – MARTA FIGUERAS – JOAN MÉNDEZ Mark Wrathall Part of the problem with our world is that we are so instrumentally minded. We value things to the extent that we can put them to use, exploit them, commodify them, and make them readily available for use and consumption.
    [Show full text]
  • Nihilism and Metaphysics in Martin Heidegger's Thought
    THE GROWING DESERT: NIHILISM AND METAPHYSICS IN MARTIN HEIDEGGER’S THOUGHT A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY MUSA DUMAN IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY MARCH 2009 Approval of the Graduate School of Social Sciences Prof.Dr. Sencer Ayata Director I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Prof.Dr. Ahmet İnam Head of Philosophy Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Prof.Dr. Ahmet İnam Supervisor Examining Committee Members Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam (METU, Philosophy) Prof. Dr. Kayhan Mutlu (METU, Sociology) Assist. Prof. Dr. Elif Çırakman (METU, Philosophy) Assist. Prof. Dr. Ertuğrul R. Turan (AÜ, Philosophy) Assist. Prof. Dr. Barış Parkan (METU, Philosophy) I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last name : Musa Duman Signature : iii ABSTRACT THE GROWING DESERT: NIHILISM AND METAPHYSICS IN HEIDEGGER’S THOUGHT Duman, Musa Ph. D., Department of Philosophy Supervisor : Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam March 2009, 209 pages In this study, we explore Heidegger’s understanding of nihilism as the essential dimension of metaphysics, of metaphysical experience of Being, and in the following, we address his responses to it.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth As Unconcealment in Heidegger's Being And
    ISSN 1393-614X Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy 16 (2012): 116-128 ____________________________________________________ Truth as Unconcealment in Heidegger’s Being and Time Jani Koskela Abstract In his early masterpiece Being and Time (Sein und Zeit), Heidegger articulates a specific understanding of truth as unconcealment (German: Unverborgenheit). This notion differs greatly from the modern view of truth, based on the classical notion of logos apophanticos. Heidegger’s understanding of truth as disclosure or unconcealment, or alêtheia, has been written about largely in terms of the complete range of Heidegger’s work (Carman 2003; Cowell 2007; Dahlström 2007; Mulhall 1996; Wrathall 2011). However, I will specifically focus on the view Heidegger establishes in Being and Time. In my interpretation, Heidegger claims that truth is not separable from the entities in the world, including the one who uncovers the entities and also itself, Dasein. I also contend that attempts to incorporate traditional propositional truth and Heidegger’s alêtheia, such as Wrathall (2011), will fail, especially in terms of the theoretical extraction of Being and Time’s pre-propositional theory of truth. 1. Introduction In this article I will articulate the early notion of unconcealment (in German: Unverborgenheit) in Martin Heidegger’s (1889-1976) Being and Time. In his early masterpiece of philosophical literature, Heidegger points out two important results of the analysis of the phenomenon of truth: 1) that truth belongs primordially to Dasein1 and 2) that Dasein is both in truth and untruth. He also shows in greater detail that the modern understanding of propositional truth is derivative from truth as uncovering.
    [Show full text]
  • Questioning the Universal
    DE TOLEDO Marie Université Paris 3 – Sorbonne Nouvelle QUESTIONING THE UNIVERSAL with Nietzsche, Heidegger, Dada and surrealism Northwestern University – Université de Paris Sorbonne Nouvelle Program in Art, Literature, and Contemporary European Thought Prof. Mickael LORIAUX Prof. Marc CRÉPON Prof. Isabelle ALFANDARY December 2017 INTRODUCTION: FROM THE CRITIQUE OF UNIVERSALISM TO THE CRITIQUE OF THE UNIVERSAL Since 1948, the world or, at least, a very large part of its inhabitants is supposed to live according to the principles established in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights [UDHR]. This text can be considered as the pure expression of political universalism, based on the idea that all human beings, no matter where or when they live, have to be treated equally: as explained by the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights, these "are not country-specific, or particular to a certain era or social group. They are the inalienable entitlements of all people, at all times, and in all places – people of every colour, from every race and ethnic group; whether or not they are disabled; citizens or migrants; no matter their sex, their class, their caste, their creed, their age or sexual orientation"1. This long enumeration shows explicitly a will to include absolutely all humanity, without any exception, under this universal legislation. It is not an easy task to find the origin of such an idea – if, of course, we consider universalism as the result of a historical development. It is sometimes presented as a Christian invention2– etymologically, the word "Catholic" actually comes from the Greek expression καθόλου, translated as "universally"3 – or, more generally, as a principle on which are based most monotheistic religions; but from a political point of view, we usually believe that universalism such as we still know it today is a creation of Western modernity and was born in Europe during the XVIIIth century, as a consequence of the Enlightment.
    [Show full text]
  • Fighting Nihilism: the Parts of Our Experiences That Are Constitutive of the Ping” Is Another Technical Term for Dreyfus, and It Desig- Experiences Themselves
    ARTIKKEL SAMTALE & KRITIKK SPALTER BREV making us aware of the aspects of our experiences of is exactly our nature as skilful copers is something that is the world without us being aware of them as such, i.e. always in the background of his discussions. “Skilful co- FIGHTING NIHILISM: the parts of our experiences that are constitutive of the ping” is another technical term for Dreyfus, and it desig- experiences themselves. For instance, when asked how nates the way in which we humans are absorbed in and A REVIEW OF we see the table in front of us, most of us will pause by our activities in virtue of our skilful, engaged rapport for a moment before we begin to describe its colour, with artefacts and other humans in our surroundings. In BACKGROUND PRACTICES shape, etc. This is what Bertrand Russell famously the mode of skilful coping, the distinction between subject does when discussing epistemological concerns in his and object disappears, and all that is left is the ongoing Problems of Philosophy (1912). Describing the table in flow of the activity. The idea is that when the flow is dis- Review of this way is all well and good for some purposes, but to rupted, we enter the contemplative mode, and then the Background Practices: Essays on the Understanding of Being the phenomenologist, this is not how the table is first condition of the possibility of viewing ourselves as subjects Hubert Dreyfus (Mark Wrathall, ed.) encountered. The table is not first perceived as a set that stand against unfamiliar objects, is established.
    [Show full text]