This Work Originally Appeared In: Dennett, Daniel C. "Self-Portrait."

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

This Work Originally Appeared In: Dennett, Daniel C. This work originally appeared in: Dennett, Daniel C. "Self-Portrait." A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, edited by S. Guttenplan. 236-244, Oxford: Blackwell Press, 1994. This is Daniel C. Dennett’s final draft before publication. It has been modified to reflect the pagination of the published version of the work. capitulation has just been completed, with a separate volume devoted to each half: The Intentional Stance (1987a) is all and only about content; Consciousness Explained (1991a) presupposes the theory of content in that volume and builds an expanded theory of consciousness. BEGINNINGS AND SOURCES Self Portrait Although quite a few philosophers agree by Daniel C. Dennett that content and consciousness are the two main issues confronting the philosophy of S. Guttenplan, ed., mind, many - perhaps most - follow tradition A Companion to the in favouring the opposite order: consciousness, Philosophy of Mind, they think, is the fundamental Blackwell Press, Oxford, 1994 phenomenon, upon which all intentionality ultimately depends. This difference of perspective is fundamental, infecting the intuitions with which all theorizing must begin, and it is thus the source of some of the deepest and most persistent disagreements in the field. It is clear to me how I came by my renegade vision of the order of dependence: as a graduate student at Oxford, I developed a deep distrust of the methods I saw other philosophers employing, and decided that before I could trust any of my intuitions about the mind, I had to figure Dennett, Daniel C. In my opinion, the two out how the brain could possibly accomplish main topics in the philosophy of mind are the mind's work. I knew next to CONTENT and CONSCIOUSNESS. As the title nothing about the relevant science, but I of my first book. Content and Consciousness had always been fascinated with how (1969) suggested, that is the order in which things worked - clocks, engines, magic they must be addressed: first, a theory of tricks. (In fact, had I not been raised in · content or INTENTIONALITY - a phenomenon a dyed-in-the-wool 'arts and humanities' more fundamental than consciousness academic family, I probably would have - and then, building on that foundation, a become an engineer, but this option would theory of consciousness. Over the years I never have occurred to anyone in our have found myself recapitulating this basic family.) So I began educating myself, always structure twice, partly in order to respond with an eye to the curious question of how to various philosophical objections, but the mechanical responses of 'stupid' more importantly, because my research on neurons could be knit into a fabric of activity foundational issues in cognitive science led that actually discriminated meanings. me into different aspects of the problems. Somehow it had to be possible, I assumed. The articles in the first half of Brainstorms since it was obvious to me that DUALISM (1978a) composed in effect a more detailed was a last resort, to be postponed indefinitely. theory of content, and the articles in the So from the outset I worked from the second half were concerned with specific 'third-person point of view' of science, and problems of consciousness. The second re- took my task to be building - or rather 236 sketching the outlines of - a physical structure foundation of everything I have done since that could be seen to accomplish the then. As I put it in Brainstorms (1978a), puzzling legerdemain of the mind. At the brains are syntactic engines that can mimic time - the mid-60s - no one else in philosophy the competence of semantic engines. (See also was attempting to build that structure, the thought experiment - a forerunner of so it was a rather lonely enterprise, and Searle's Chinese Room - about being locked most of the illumination and encouragement in the control room of a giant robot, in I could find came from the work of a 1978b.) Note how this point forces the few visionaries in science and engineering: order of dependence of consciousness on Warren McCulloch, Donald MacKay, intentionality. The appreciation of meanings Donald Hebb, Ross Ashby, Allen Newell, - their discrimination and delectation - is Herbert Simon, and J. Z. Young come to central to our vision of consciousness, but mind. Miller, Galanter and Pribram's 1960 this conviction that I, on the inside, deal classic, Plans and the Structure of Behaviour, directly with meanings turns out to be was a dimly understood but much appreciated something rather like a benign 'user illusion'. beacon, and Michael Arbib's 1964 What Descartes thought was most primer, Brains, Machines and Mathematics, certain - his immediate introspective grasp was very helpful in clearing away some of of the items of consciousness - turns out to the fog. be not even quite true, but rather a metaphorical Given my lack of formal training in any by-product of the way our brains science, this was a dubious enterprise, but I do their approximating work. This vision was usually forgiven my naïveté by those tied in beautifully with a doctrine of Quine's who helped me into their disciplines, and that I had actually vehemently resisted as although at the time I considered myself an undergraduate: the indeterminacy of driven by (indeed defined by) my disagreements radical translation. I could now see why, as with my philosophical mentors, Quine famously insisted, indeterminacy was QUINE and RYLE, in retrospect it is clear 'of a piece with' Brentano's thesis of the that my deep agreement with both of them irreducibility of the intentional, and why about the nature of philosophy - so deep as those irreducible intentional contexts were to be utterly unexamined and tacit - was unavoidably a 'dramatic idiom' rather than the primary source of such intellectual an expression of unvarnished truth. I could security as I had. also see how to re-interpret the two philosophical The first stable conclusion I reached, after works on intentionality that had had I discovered that my speculative forays the most influence on me, Anscombe's always wandered to the same place, was Intention (1957) and Taylor's The Explanation that the only thing brains could do was to of Behaviour (1964). approximate the responsivity to meanings If your initial allegiance is to the physical that we presuppose in our everyday mentalistic sciences and the third-person point of view, discourse. When mechanical push this disposition of the issues can seem not came to shove, a brain was always going to just intuitively acceptable, but inevitable, do what it was caused to do by current, satisfying, natural. If on the other hand local, mechanical circumstances, whatever your starting point is the traditional philosophical it ought to do, whatever a God's-eye view allegiance to the mind and the might reveal about the actual meanings of deliverances of introspection, this vision can its current states. But over the long haul, seem outrageous. Perhaps the clearest view brains could be designed - by evolutionary of this watershed of intuitions can be processes - to do the right thing (from the obtained from an evolutionary perspective. point of view of meaning) with high reliability. There was a time, before life on earth, when This found its first published expression there was neither intentionality nor consciousness, in Content and Consciousness (1969, §9, but eventually replication got 'Function and Content') and it remains the under way and simple organisms emerged. 237 Suppose we ask of them: Were they conscious? alike. The tactic did not work for many Did their states exhibit intentionality? thinkers, who continued to harbour the It all depends on what these key terms hunch that I was leaving something out; are taken to mean, of course, but underneath there was, they thought, a special sort of the strategic decisions one might sensitivity - we might call it animal consciousness make about pre-emptive definition of terms - that no thermostat or fancy lies a fundamental difference of outlook. robot could enjoy, but that all mammals One family of intuitions is comfortable and birds (and perhaps all fish, reptiles, declaring that while these earliest ancestors insects, molluscs … ) shared. Since robotic were unconscious automata, not metaphysically devices of considerably greater behavioural different from thermostats or simple and perceptual complexity than the simplest robotic toys, some of their states were of these organisms are deemed unconscious nevertheless semantically evaluable, These by this school of thought, it amounts to organisms were, in my terms, rudimentary some sort of latter-day vitalism. The more intentional systems, and somewhere in the one learns about how simple organisms intervening ascent of complexity, a special actually work, the more dubious this hunch subset of intentional systems has emerged: about a special, organic sort of sensation the subset of conscious beings. According to becomes, but to those who refuse to look at this vision, then, the intentionality of our the science, it is a traditional idea that is unconscious ancestors was as real as intentionality about as comfortable today as it was in the ever gets; it was just rudimentary. seventeenth century, when many were horrified It is on this foundation of unconscious by Descartes's claims about the intentionality that the higher-order complexities mechanicity of (non-human) animals. In developed that have culminated in any event, definitional gambits are ineffective what we call consciousness. The other against it, so in later work I dropped the family of intuitions declares that if these tactic and the nomenclature of 'aware1' and early organisms were mere unconscious 'aware2' - but not the underlying intuitions. automata, then their so-called intentionality My accounts of content and consciousness was not the real thing, Some philosophers have subsequently been revised in of this persuasion are tempted to insist that rather minor ways and elaborated in rather the earliest living organisms were conscious major ways.
Recommended publications
  • Non-Duality in Ken Wilber's Integral Philosophy
    NON-DUALITY IN KEN WILBER’S INTEGRAL PHILOSOPHY: A CRITICAL APPRAISAL AND ALTERNATIVE PHYSICALIST PERSPECTIVE OF MYSTICAL CONSCIOUSNESS JEREMY JOHN JACOBS 2009 Ken Wilber Cover Photo: Denver Integral and Ken Wilber Meetup Group (http://www.meetup.com/denver- integral/photos/?photold=716584&photoAlbumld=102985. Accessed 20 February 2009). NON-DUALITY IN KEN WILBER’S INTEGRAL PHILOSOPHY: A CRITICAL APPRAISAL AND ALTERNATIVE PHYSICALIST PERSPECTIVE OF MYSTICAL CONSCIOUSNESS by JEREMY JOHN JACOBS Submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF THEOLOGY in the subject CHRISTIAN SPIRITUALITY at the UNIVERSITY OF SOUTH AFRICA Promoter PROFESSOR C E T KOURIE February 2009 Kenneth Earl Wilber (1949 - ) (theosophist.wordpress.com) Student Number: 3279-583-1 I declare that NON-DUALITY IN KEN WILBER’S INTEGRAL PHILOSOPHY: A CRITICAL APPRAISAL AND ALTERNATIVE PHYSICALIST PERSPECTIVE OF MYSTICAL CONSCIOUSNESS is my own work and that all sources that I have used or quoted have been indicated and acknowledged by means of complete references. _________________________ ______________ Signature Date Jeremy John Jacobs i DEDICATION To Kim and St John ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS My deepest gratitude goes to my wife Kim for her endless patience, encouragement, and support. I gratefully acknowledge Professor Celia Kourie’s professionalism. Her courteous manner of guidance and correction, and also the hospitality she extended to my alternative perspectives are an indication of her academic integrity. Special thanks to my sister Tania Jacobs who typed up reams of notes that I had gathered over the years, and finally my friend Andre Croucamp whose brilliant mind inspired me to think beyond the strictures of my creeds.
    [Show full text]
  • Hell on Earth
    Welcome to Hell on Earth Artificial Intelligence, Babies, Bitcoin, Cartels, China, Democracy, Diversity, Dysgenics, Equality, Hackers, Human Rights, Islam, Liberalism, Prosperity, The Web Michael Starks The saddest day in US history. President Johnson, with two Kennedy’s and ex-President Hoover, gives America to Mexico - Oct 3rd 1965 Reality Press Las Vegas Copyright © 2020 by Michael Starks All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, distributed, or transmitted without the express consent of the author. Printed and bound in the United States of America. ISBN 978-1-951440-81-7 “At what point is the approach of danger to be expected? I answer, if it ever reach us it must spring up amongst us; it cannot come from abroad. If destruction be our lot, we must ourselves be its author and finisher. As a nation of freemen we must live through all time or die by suicide.” Abraham Lincoln Heaven and Earth are inhumane--they view the myriad creatures as straw dogs TaoTe Ching This very body the Buddha, this very earth the lotus paradise Osho I can well imagine a religion in which there are no doctrines, so that nothing is spoken. Clearly, then, the essence of religion can have nothing to do with what is sayable. Wittgenstein What we are supplying are really remarks on the natural history of man, not curiosities; however, but rather observations on facts which no one has doubted and which have only gone unremarked because they are always before our eyes. Wittgenstein RFM I p142 Philosophers constantly see the method of science before their eyes and are irresistibly tempted to ask and answer questions in the way science does.
    [Show full text]
  • The Hard Problem and the Measurement Problem: a No-Go Theorem and Potential Consequences
    The hard problem and the measurement problem: a no-go theorem and potential consequences Igor Salom Institute of Physics, Belgrade University, Pregrevica 118, Zemun, Serbia The \measurement problem" of quantum mechanics, and the \hard problem" of cognitive science are the most profound open problems of the two research fields, and certainly among the deepest of all unsettled conundrums in contemporary science in general. Occasionally, scientists from both fields have suggested some sort of interconnectedness of the two problems. Here we revisit the main motives behind such expectations and try to put them on more formal grounds. We argue not only that such a relation exists, but that it also bears strong implications both for the interpretations of quantum mechanics and for our understanding of consciousness. The paper consists of three parts. In the first part, we formulate a \no-go-theorem" stating that a brain, functioning solely on the principles of classical physics, cannot have any greater ability to induce subjective experience than a process of writing (printing) a certain sequence of digits. The goal is to show, with an attempt to mathematical rigor, why the physicalist standpoint based on classical physics is not likely to ever explain the phenomenon of consciousness { justifying the tendency to look beyond the physics of the 19th century. In the second part, we aim to establish a clear relation, with a sort of correspondence mapping, between attitudes towards the hard problem and interpretations of quantum mechanics. Then we discuss these connections in the light of the no-go theorem, pointing out that the existence of subjective experience might differentiate between otherwise experimentally indistinguishable interpretations.
    [Show full text]
  • Artificial Intelligence Beyond the Philosophy of Mind
    RETHINKING MACHINES: ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE BEYOND THE PHILOSOPHY OF MIND BY DANIEL JOSE ESTRADA DISSERTATION Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate College of the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, 2014 Urbana, Illinois Doctoral Committee: Associate Professor Jonathan Waskan, Chair Associate Professor Daniel Korman Emeritus Professor Steven Wagner Associate Professor Andrew Arana Abstract Recent philosophy of mind has increasingly focused on the role of technology in shaping, influencing, and extending our mental faculties. Technology extends the mind in two basic ways: through the creative design of artifacts and the purposive use of instruments. If the meaningful activity of technological artifacts were exhaustively described in these mind-dependent terms, then a philosophy of technology would depend entirely on our theory of mind. In this dissertation, I argue that a mind-dependent approach to technology is mistaken. Instead, some machines are best understood as independent participants in their own right, contributing to and augmenting a variety of social practices as active, though often unrecognized, community members. Beginning with Turing’s call for “fair play for machines”, I trace an argument concerning the social autonomy of nonhuman agents through the artificial intelligence debates of the 20th century. I’ll argue that undue focus on the mind has obscured the force of Turing’s proposal, leaving the debates in an unfortunate stalemate. I will then examine a network theoretic alternative to the study of multi- agent complex systems that can avoid anthropocentric, mind-dependent ways of framing human- machine interactions. I argue that this approach allows for both scientific and philosophical treatment of large and complicated sociotechnical systems, and suggests novel methods for designing, managing, and maintaining such systems.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Toolkit Is How to Think About Things in the World Over a Wide Range of Magnitudes and Time Scales
    226 WHAT SCIENTIFIC CONCEPT WOULD IMPROVE EVERYBODY'S COGNITIVE TOOLKIT? The term 'scientific"is to be understood in a broad sense as the most reliable way of gaining knowledge about anything, whether it be the human spirit, the role of great people in history, or the structure of DNA. A "scientific concept" may come from philosophy, logic, economics, jurisprudence, or other analytic enterprises, as long as it is a rigorous conceptual tool that may be summed up succinctly (or "in a phrase") but has broad application to understanding the world. [Thanks to Steven Pinker for suggesting this year's Edge Question and to Daniel Kahneman for advice on its presentation.] 158 CONTRIBUTORS (109,600 words): Richard Thaler, Brian Eno, J. Craig Venter, Martin Rees, Mahzarin Banaji, V.S. Ramachandran, Stefano Boeri, Nigel Goldenfeld, Gary Marcus, Andrew Revkin, Stuart Firestein, Beatrice Golomb, Diane Halpern, Kevin Hand, Barry Smith, Kevin Hand, Garrett Lisi, David Dalrymple, Xeni Jardin, Seth Lloyd, Brian Knutson, Carl Page, Victoria Stodden, David Rowan, Hazel Rose Markus & Alana Conner, Fiery Cushman, David Eagleman, Joan Chiao, Max Tegmark, Tecumseh Fitch, Joshua Greene, Stephon Alexander, Gregory Cochran, Tor Norretranders , Laurence Smith, Carl Zimmer, Roger Highfield, Marcelo Gleiser, Richard Saul Wurman, Anthony Aguirre, Sam Harris, P.Z. Myers, Sue Blackmore, Bart Kosko, David Buss, John Tooby, Eduardo Salcedo-Albaran, Paul Bloom, Evgeny Morozov, Mark Pagel, Kathryn Schulz, Ernst Pöppel, Tania Lombrozo, Paul Saffo, Jay Rosen, Timothy Taylor, Jonah Lehrer, Marco Iacoboni, Dave Winer, George Church, Kai Krause, Gloria Origgi, Tom Standage, Vinod Khosla, Dan Sperber, Geoffrey Miller, Satyajit Das, Alun Anderson, Eric Topol, Amanda Gefter, Scott D.
    [Show full text]
  • The World Without Knowledge: the Theory of Brain-Sign
    Durham E-Theses The world without knowledge: The Theory of Brain-Sign CLAPSON, PHILIP,JOHN How to cite: CLAPSON, PHILIP,JOHN (2012) The world without knowledge: The Theory of Brain-Sign, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/3560/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk The world without knowledge: The Theory of Brain-Sign Philip Clapson Abstract This thesis proposes the theory of brain-sign should replace the theory of consciousness, and mind generally. Consciousness is first described, and it is evident there is neither a consistent account of it, nor an adequate rationale for its existence beyond its (tautological) self- endorsing characterisation as knowledge. This is the target of the critique. Human history and human self-appraisal have assumed knowledge as an (ontologically) intrinsic facet of human make-up, and human disciplines (of ‘thought’) have relied upon it.
    [Show full text]
  • 3669 MYTHS PT/Bp
    1111 2 3 4 5 THE MYTHS WE LIVE BY 6 7 8 9 1011 1 2 3 4 5111 In The Myths We Live By, Mary Midgley argues in her customary brilliant 6 prose that myths are neither lies nor mere stories but a network of powerful 7 symbols that suggest particular ways of interpreting the world. She spells 8 out how we go wrong about several of the most powerful, such as the 9 myth of the Social Contract, and points out how profoundly some of our 20111 strongest myths today are shaped by our favourite technologies, notably 1 the microscope and the computer. There is also the myth of progress – 2 now disguised as evolution – the myth of a body quite separate from the 3 mind, and the myth of omnicompetent science. 4 Drawing shrewdly on a wealth of examples such as the unhelpfulness of 5 memes – the alleged genes of culture – as explanations of social change 6 and the way in which current hopes for biotechnology are repeating the 7 errors of the alchemists, she spells out what goes wrong when we try to 8 apply the atomistic metaphors of science to the large-scale problems of our 9 lives. She does not, however, blame science itself for this. Instead, she deftly 30111 shows how its name is unfairly blackened when we pressgang it into the 1 wrong places. 2 A tour de force of clear thinking on why we are more than the sum of 3 our molecules, The Myths We Live By is essential reading for anyone 4 concerned about how we should understand the world today.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 5. Planet of the Apes
    Troubles in Paradise-Downard 465 Chapter 5. Planet of the Apes Antievolutionists and Human Origins: Not connecting the fossil dots – p. 482 Making Up Our Minds: Home erectus, Neanderthal and the roots of us – p. 503 Dr. Doolittle in the Cartesian Theater: Human consciousness and language – p. 519 Mystery Creation Scientist Theater 1996: The Mysterious Origins of Man – p. 536 Few of those who have seen the 1968 film Planet of the Apes can easily forget its surprise ending. Stranded on what he believes to be an alien planet populated by intelligent apes, astronaut George Taylor (played by Charlton Heston) sets off to explore, accompanied by the mute human female Nova he had rescued from the apes’ zoo. They ride along the desolate beach until they encounter the rusting remains of a metallic structure (revealed to the audience only in carefully framed shots to obscure its identity) which turns out to be the Statue of Liberty, buried askew hip- deep in the sand. Taylor now realizes that he had made it home after all. And while a puzzled Nova looked on in complete non-comprehension at what was upsetting him, Taylor collapsed on the beach to declaim: “We finally, really did it. You maniacs! You blew it up! God damn you—god damn you all to hell.”1 If all you went by was this final scene, Planet of the Apes was a dandy statement against the futility of nuclear war. The symbolism of the Statue of Liberty was intensely visceral—an icon of what had been lost in a brief lapse of mankind’s MAD strategic folly.
    [Show full text]
  • Communication Without Consciousness: the Theory of Brain-Sign
    Activitas Nervosa Superior 2016, 58, No. 3-4 ………………………... Journal ANS: Journal for Neurocognitive Research Homepage: www.activitas.org IDEAS & OPINION ………………………... COMMUNICATION WITHOUT CONSCIOUSNESS: THE THEORY OF BRAIN-SIGN Philip Clapson Department of Psychological Sciences, Birkbeck, University of London, UK Abstract Despite developments in neuroscience, consciousness is unidentified in the brain. Moreover there is no scientific definition of what it is or does. This paper proposes that consciousness is not a scientific category. However, by ‘postulating’ consciousness as self-explanation, the brain can communicate with other brains in collective action. But the brain can generate a more plausible self-description as brain- sign. There are two foundational tenets. (1) Brain-sign arises from the brain’s interpretation of its causal orientation towards the world at each moment, and is ‘apparent’ as the world; and (2) It facilitates communication between brains about the world in collective action which is uncertain or imprecise. It is therefore grounded in the brain’s bio-physical operation. Signs are ubiquitous bio-physical states, but they are not causal for the hosting organism. The paper contrasts brain-sign with consciousness both as theory, and in empirical findings. Brain-sign is the source of all theories, including itself. Key words: Brain science; Brain-sign; Brain-to-brain communication; Collective action; Consciousness 1. INTRODUCTION The many theories developed through the years which propose to explain the brain phenomenon called consciousness are founded on a misconception of its fundamental nature. Science does not have to “creep up on consciousness”, in Andy Clark’s words (2016). The supposed ability of consciousness to transcend the organism’s bio-physical operation in the world is a prescientific myth.
    [Show full text]
  • Download (2MB)
    This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights and duplication or sale of all or part is not permitted, except that material may be duplicated by you for research, private study, criticism/review or educational purposes. Electronic or print copies are for your own personal, non- commercial use and shall not be passed to any other individual. No quotation may be published without proper acknowledgement. For any other use, or to quote extensively from the work, permission must be obtained from the copyright holder/s. Neutral Monism Against the Qualiophiles George Peter Carpenter Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy October 2018 Keele University ii Abstract This thesis argues for an austere form of monism that incorporates aspects of panpsychism and physicalism, with the aim of putting naturalist epistemology on a secure footing. I criticise panpsychism for failing to live up to its promises of defending what we ordinarily think of as consciousness against physicalism, and criticise the metaphysical presuppositions of its current high‐ profile proponents. These presuppositions are contrasted with more recent approaches in philosophy of science. The mind‐body problem itself endures these assaults, however, and I criticise physicalists who claim their position is the more common‐sensical, along with naturalists who think they can avoid metaphysics. Both tendencies are represented by phenomenal concept strategists, whose position comes to seem extreme over the course of two chapters. I then offer my own solution to the mind‐body problem. My position seeks a dialectical reconciliation between the possibility of directly experiencing reality, associated with anti‐physicalist mysticism, and physical reductionism.
    [Show full text]
  • Experience, Reality and Representation
    Experience, Reality and Representation On the Implications of a Maximally Non-Deflationary Phenomenal Realism Jason Peter Whatley B.A. (Hons) Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Tasmania April 2015 ! Authority of Access This thesis may be made available for loan and limited copying and communication in accordance with the Copyright Act 1968. ""! Declaration This thesis contains no material which has been accepted for a degree or diploma by the University or any other institution, except by way of background information and duly acknowledged in the thesis, and to the best of my knowledge and belief no material previously published or written by another person except where due acknowledgement is made in the text of the thesis, nor does the thesis contain any material that infringes copyright. iii Acknowledgements Firstly, I’d like to thank those whose help manifests in some way in the content of this thesis. Most importantly, I’d like to thank my primary supervisor James Chase. It has been a joy and a privilege to discuss my ideas, and philosophy in general, with somebody possessed of so much knowledge and insight. This thesis has benefited immensely from his input. I’d also like to thank my secondary supervisor Graham Wood for several enjoyable conversations and for his comments on various draft chapters. It was also helpful to be able to discuss my ideas with fellow Launceston campus postgraduates Bonnie Britton, Nicholas Clements, Tony Kerr, Michael Kidd and Miriam Roser. I am also grateful to my friend Richard Barker, who provided some much needed technical assistance and support.
    [Show full text]
  • Artificial Intelligence Beyond the Philosophy of Mind
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Illinois Digital Environment for Access to Learning and Scholarship Repository RETHINKING MACHINES: ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE BEYOND THE PHILOSOPHY OF MIND BY DANIEL JOSE ESTRADA DISSERTATION Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate College of the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, 2014 Urbana, Illinois Doctoral Committee: Associate Professor Jonathan Waskan, Chair Associate Professor Daniel Korman Emeritus Professor Steven Wagner Associate Professor Andrew Arana Abstract Recent philosophy of mind has increasingly focused on the role of technology in shaping, influencing, and extending our mental faculties. Technology extends the mind in two basic ways: through the creative design of artifacts and the purposive use of instruments. If the meaningful activity of technological artifacts were exhaustively described in these mind-dependent terms, then a philosophy of technology would depend entirely on our theory of mind. In this dissertation, I argue that a mind-dependent approach to technology is mistaken. Instead, some machines are best understood as independent participants in their own right, contributing to and augmenting a variety of social practices as active, though often unrecognized, community members. Beginning with Turing’s call for “fair play for machines”, I trace an argument concerning the social autonomy of nonhuman agents through the artificial intelligence debates of the 20th century. I’ll argue that undue focus on the mind has obscured the force of Turing’s proposal, leaving the debates in an unfortunate stalemate. I will then examine a network theoretic alternative to the study of multi- agent complex systems that can avoid anthropocentric, mind-dependent ways of framing human- machine interactions.
    [Show full text]