Recovering Nature Essays in Natural Philosophy, Ethics, and Metaphysics in Honor of Ralph Mcinerny

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Recovering Nature Essays in Natural Philosophy, Ethics, and Metaphysics in Honor of Ralph Mcinerny Page iii Recovering Nature Essays in Natural Philosophy, Ethics, and Metaphysics in Honor of Ralph McInerny Edited by Thomas Hibbs and John O'Callaghan Page iv Disclaimer: Some images in the original version of the book are not available for inclusion in the netLibrary eBook. Copyright 1999 by University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, IN 46556 All Rights Reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging­in­Publication Data Recovering nature : essays in natural philosophy, ethics, and metaphysics in honor of Ralph McInerny / edited by Thomas Hibbs and John O'Callaghan. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 0­268­01666­6 (alk. paper) 1. —Philosophy of nature. 2. Thomists. I. McInerny, Ralph M. II. Hibbs, Thomas S. III. O'Callaghan, John. BD581.R39 1999 149'.91—dc21 99­38120 The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the American National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39.48­1984. Page v CONTENTS Acknowledgments vii Introduction 1 Thomas Hibbs and John O'Callaghan I. Natural Philosophy Quantification in Sixteenth­Century Natural Philosophy 11 William Wallace, O.P. The Failure of Positivism and the Enduring Legacy of Comte 25 Jude P. Dougherty The Philosophies of Mind and Nature 37 John Haldane Persons and Things 53 Thomas De Koninck II. Ethics John Case: An Example of Aristotelianism's Self­Subversion? 71 Alasdair MacIntyre Keeping Virtue in Its Place: A Critique of Subordinating Strategies 83 David Solomon Deliberation about Final Ends: Thomistic Considerations 105 Daniel McInerny Moral Terminology and Proportionalism 127 Janet E. Smith The Gospels, Natural Law, and the American Founding 147 Michael Novak Page vi McInerny Did It, or Should a Pacifist Read Murder Mysteries? 163 Stanley Hauerwas III. Metaphysics Religious Pluralism and Natural Theology 179 Laura Garcia Reid, Hume, and God 201 Alvin Plantinga Two Roles for Catholic Philosophers 229 Alfred J. Freddoso From Analogy of "Being" to the Analogy of Being 253 David B. Burrell, C.S.C. Index 267 Page vii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS We have incurred a number of debts in the process of editing this volume. First, we would like to thank Mrs. Alice Osberger, longtime administrative assistant to Ralph McInerny, for her assistance and advice on numerous matters. Second, we wish to express our gratitude to the contributors, who have graciously and promptly responded to all of our requests. We especially wish to acknowledge one of the contributors, David Solomon. The idea for this volume was born in a conversation we had with David a few summers ago. Along the way, he has provided encouragement, wit, and prudential judgment. Third, we would like to thank Mr. Michael Joyce and Ms. Dianne Sehler of the Lynde and Harry Bradley Foundation. The Foundation generously provided a grant to defray the costs of the publication of this volume and to support a celebration in honor of the achievements of Ralph McInerny. Finally, we gratefully acknowledge the assistance of John McCudden, Ann Rice, and Jeffrey Gainey of the University of Notre Dame Press, who have made many helpful editorial corrections and suggestions and who have expressed enthusiasm about the project from the very beginning. Page 1 INTRODUCTION Thomas Hibbs and John O'Callaghan The recovery of nature has been a unifying and enduring aim of the writings of the man to whom this book is dedicated, Ralph McInerny, Michael P. Grace Professor of Medieval Studies at the University of Notre Dame, director of the Jacques Maritain Center, former director of the Medieval Institute, and author of numerous works in philosophy, literature, and journalism. The list of achievements and accolades could go on and on. But, although we have come to praise not bury McInerny, we want to do so by showing what we have learned from his teaching and writing. Clearly, one of the central preoccupations of his brand of Thomism, as an Aristotelian­Thomist, has been attention to nature. In his persistent, clear, and creative defenses of natural theology and natural law, Ralph has appealed to nature in order to establish a dialogue between theists and nontheists, to contribute to the moral and political renewal of American culture, and particularly to provide philosophical foundations for Catholic theology. While many of the fads that have plagued philosophy and theology during the last half­century have come and gone, recent developments suggest that Ralphs commitment to Aristotelian­Thomism has been boldly, if quietly, prophetic. Philosophers of religion and proponents of the ethics of virtue draw with increasing confidence upon premodern insights, arguments, and modes of inquiry. The rejuvenation of variants on Aristotle's conception of nature is now a pervasive feature of the philosophical landscape. Consider, for example, (a) the exploration of an anthropology to complement virtue ethics, (b) the reformulation of a variety of traditional arguments from nature for the existence of God, (c) the rehabilitation, even in discussions of evolutionary theory, of teleology, (d) the search for conceptions of the human person that avoid the reductionist alternatives of dualism and materialism, and (e) the renewed interest in the viability of natural law as a basis for political and legal reasoning. This volume brings together essays by an impressive group of scholars. The contributors certainly do not all agree with one another nor on every Page 2 point with the man whom their essays honor; nor, finally, do all the essays focus equally on the Aristotelian­Thomist conception of nature. Yet the topics and modes of inquiry in the essays complement one another nicely and all have been written with Ralph in mind. Indeed, it is a sign of the admiration that Ralph elicits in colleagues and friends that, when asked, a group of very busy scholars eagerly agreed to submit an essay and that they finished their pieces, if not in every case at the deadline, well in advance of what academic custom now considers punctual. Had we but world enough and time, we are convinced we could produce a number of lively and interesting volumes dedicated to the work and life of Ralph McInerny. As some small token of our gratitude, this one will have to suffice. We have divided the essays into three categories, following the order of learning recommended by Aristotle: natural philosophy, ethics, and metaphysics. Natural Philosophy The chief impediment to the recovery of the classical, Aristotelian conception of nature is undoubtedly the assumption that the modern sciences have decisively refuted the central tenets of Aristotle's natural philosophy, or at least that their rejection was a necessary prelude to the impressive and irreversible advances of the sciences. The essays by William Wallace ("Quantification in Sixteenth­Century Natural Philosophy') and Jude Dougherty ("The Failure of Positivism") treat, respectively, the sixteenth­century origins of modern science and nineteenth­century positivism. Wallace shows how the birth of the modern sciences did not occur ex nihilo in the seventeenth century, but rather grew out of the sixteenth­century development of "new techniques of quantification . of space, motion, and force." By demonstrating the medieval sources of these sixteenth­century developments, Wallace underscores the continuity between medieval and early modern science and suggests possibilities for integrating the new mathematical approach to nature with the older Aristotelian approach. If Wallace shows how attention to the history of science undermines naive assumptions about the incompatibility of ancient and modern views of nature, Dougherty suggests that the actual practice of nineteenth­ and twentieth­century science is incompatible with the interpretation of science most antithetical to Aristotle's natural philosophy: Comte's positivism. Positivism "not only ruled out metaphysics but ruled out theoretical physics as well." At the root of its failure is its denial of the efficacy of causal reasoning. Like Wallace, Dougherty thinks the time is ripe for seeing modern science in Page 3 a more Aristotelian light: "Volumes of contemporary work in the philosophy of science . have taken a realist turn as many philosophers have recovered a realist perspective often directly inspired by Aristotle in their attempt to remain true to actual practice in the natural sciences." As Dougherty observes, the lingering effects of positivism can still be seen in the human sciences. Perhaps the most striking way in which the Aristotelian order of this volume displays itself is in the inclusion of the papers by John Haldane and Thomas De Koninck under the heading of philosophy of nature. One lasting inheritance of positivism is the sense that philosophy and in particular metaphysics deal with all the problems left over after natural science has had its way. According to positivism, metaphysics will have a role to play only so long as conceptual difficulties about the mind and personal identity remain. Nothing could be further from the Aristotelian study of being­qua­being or the study of human nature as an area within the philosophy of nature. And yet, as John Haldane urges in "Mind and Nature," recent developments in philosophy of mind provide starting points for a fruitful dialogue between the Aristotelian­Thomistic philosophy of nature and analytic philosophical writing on thought and agency. With attention to the recent work of Davidson and Putnam, Haldane argues that physicalist reductionism is a lingering but now outdated prejudice. The key to his argument is the revival of formal causality as distinct from efficient causality. Form, which is evident in structures and patterns of behavior, "brings order, but not by pushing things this way or that." In philosophy of mind, we are at a "significant juncture"; we can move toward physicalism and reduction or away from it and toward hylomorphic personalism. Another vexed question in contemporary philosophy concerns the nature of personhood.
Recommended publications
  • Hunting the White Elephant. When and How Did Galileo
    MAX-PLANCK-INSTITUT FÜR WISSENSCHAFTSGESCHICHTE Max Planck Institute for the History of Science PREPRINT 97 (1998) Jürgen Renn, Peter Damerow, Simone Rieger, and Michele Camerota Hunting the White Elephant When and how did Galileo discover the law of fall? ISSN 0948-9444 1 HUNTING THE WHITE ELEPHANT WHEN AND HOW DID GALILEO DISCOVER THE LAW OF FALL? Jürgen Renn, Peter Damerow, Simone Rieger, and Michele Camerota Mark Twain tells the story of a white elephant, a present of the king of Siam to Queen Victoria of England, who got somehow lost in New York on its way to England. An impressive army of highly qualified detectives swarmed out over the whole country to search for the lost treasure. And after short time an abundance of optimistic reports with precise observations were returned from the detectives giving evidence that the elephant must have been shortly before at that very place each detective had chosen for his investigations. Although no elephant could ever have been strolling around at the same time at such different places of a vast area and in spite of the fact that the elephant, wounded by a bullet, was lying dead the whole time in the cellar of the police headquarters, the detectives were highly praised by the public for their professional and effective execution of the task. (The Stolen White Elephant, Boston 1882) THE ARGUMENT In spite of having been the subject of more than a century of historical research, the question of when and how Galileo made his major discoveries is still answered insufficiently only. It is mostly assumed that he must have found the law of fall around the year 1604 and that only sev- 1 This paper makes use of the work of research projects of the Max Planck Institute for the History of Science in Berlin, some pursued jointly with the Biblioteca Nazionale Centrale in Florence, the Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza, and the Istituto Nazionale die Fisica Nucleare in Florence.
    [Show full text]
  • Sources: Galileo's Correspondence
    Sources: Galileo’s Correspondence Notes on the Translations The following collection of letters is the result of a selection made by the author from the correspondence of Galileo published by Antonio Favaro in his Le opere di Galileo Galilei,theEdizione Nazionale (EN), the second edition of which was published in 1968. These letters have been selected for their relevance to the inves- tigation of Galileo’s practical activities.1 The information they contain, moreover, often refers to subjects that are completely absent in Galileo’s publications. All of the letters selected are quoted in the work. The passages of the letters, which are quoted in the work, are set in italics here. Given the particular relevance of these letters, they have been translated into English for the first time by the author. This will provide the international reader with the opportunity to achieve a deeper comprehension of the work on the basis of the sources. The translation in itself, however, does not aim to produce a text that is easily read by a modern reader. The aim is to present an understandable English text that remains as close as possible to the original. The hope is that the evident disadvantage of having, for example, long and involute sentences using obsolete words is compensated by the fact that this sort of translation reduces to a minimum the integration of the interpretation of the translator into the English text. 1Another series of letters selected from Galileo’s correspondence and relevant to Galileo’s practical activities and, in particular, as a bell caster is published appended to Valleriani (2008).
    [Show full text]
  • GALILEO CREATION and COSMOGONY a Study on the Interplay Between Galileo’S Science of Motion and the Creation Theme [M-STO/05, M-FIL/06]
    DOCTORAL DISSERTATION GALILEO CREATION AND COSMOGONY A Study on the Interplay between Galileo’s Science of Motion and the Creation Theme [M-STO/05, M-FIL/06] Ph.D. Candidate Ph.D. Coordinator IVAN MALARA Prof. ANDREA PINOTTI Registration number: R11933 JOINT PH.D. SUPERVISORS Università degli Studi di Milano Prof. LUCA BIANCHI Doctoral course in Philosophy and Human Sciences – XXXIII Cycle Prof. ELIO NENCI (Dipartimento di Filosofia “Piero Martinetti”) Gent Universiteit Prof. MAARTEN VAN DYCK Academic Year 2019/2020 È chiaro che il pensiero dà fastidio anche se chi pensa è muto come un pesce anzi è un pesce e come pesce è difficile da bloccare perché lo protegge il mare Com’è profondo il mare LUCIO DALLA, Com’è profondo il mare (1977) Non ’mbrischiare a calia ca ’nzudda (Calabrian saying) Table of contents Abstract English .........................................................................................................VII Italian ..........................................................................................................VIII Dutch.............................................................................................................IX Introduction .............................................................................................................XI PART ONE: CREATION I. Anno 1607: Galileo and Castelli 1. Galileo in 1607..............................................................................................3 2. Castelli in 1607. The epistulae Cavenses.......................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Galileo's De Motu Antiquiora Notes for a Reappraisal
    GALILEO’S DE MOTU ANTIQUIORA NOTES FOR A REAPPRAISAL Raymond Fredette This lecture is dedicated to my venerable master Raymond Klibansky (1905- ) Abstract In this lecture, I will briefly furnish first some relevant personal life events of my intellectual involvment with the De motu antiquiora (DMA) to satisfy a legitimate curiosity about this obscure scholar who for all pratical purposes published only one article in Physis back in 1972, disappeared for more than twenty years, and sud- denly comes back. The main intent is to reappraise the conflicting diversity of how scholars from Viviani (1674) down to Giusti (1998) reacted to this Pisan autograph on local motion which Galileo did not publish but never discarded, but also to emphasize the need in our community for less “psittacism”, that is, more rereading of the original textual sources instead of “parroting” secondary ones however authoritative, and more replicating of the experimentations these texts contain. During my teens, I developed a strong taste both for science and for phi- losophy, so much so that after majoring in 1959 with a B.A. in chemistry and a minor in biology, instead of entering medical school as expected, I decided to register at the Institut d’Études Médiévales of the Université de Montréal. There, for five years, I had the immense privilege of having fallen in the hands of the best teachers, amongst them Benoît Lacroix, Mathieu de Durand, Henri-Iréné Marrou, Etienne Gilson, Paul Vignaux and Raymond Klibansky. If I am here today, it is thanks to them and to the tools they handed down to me for the pursuit of a passion.
    [Show full text]
  • Homage to Galileo Galilei 1564-2014 Reading Iuvenilia Galilean Works Within History and Historical Epistemology of Science
    Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences 21-1 | 2017 Homage to Galileo Galilei 1564-2014 Reading Iuvenilia Galilean Works within History and Historical Epistemology of Science Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/1229 DOI: 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.1229 ISSN: 1775-4283 Publisher Éditions Kimé Printed version Date of publication: 15 February 2017 ISBN: 978-2-84174-801-3 ISSN: 1281-2463 Electronic reference Philosophia Scientiæ, 21-1 | 2017, “Homage to Galileo Galilei 1564-2014” [Online], Online since 15 February 2019, connection on 30 March 2021. URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ philosophiascientiae/1229; DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/philosophiascientiae.1229 Tous droits réservés Editorial Gerhard Heinzmann Laboratoire d’Histoire des Sciences et de Philosophie, Archives H.-Poincaré, Université de Lorraine, CNRS, Nancy (France) Le premier cahier de Philosophia Scientiæ est paru il y a plus de vingt ans, en juin 1996. Il a été édité par une jeune équipe des Archives Henri-Poincaré à Nancy et dirigé par le même rédacteur en chef dans un souci constant : promouvoir la recherche en philosophie des sciences, tout particulièrement en ce qui concerne la logique, l’informatique, les mathématiques et la physique, en s’inscrivant dans la tradition analytique, en prenant en compte l’histoire et la pratique des sciences, en préservant le français, l’anglais et l’allemand comme langues « scientifiques » à titre égal. En passant la main à la nouvelle équipe, Manuel Rebuschi comme rédacteur en chef et Baptiste Mélès comme rédacteur en chef adjoint, j’exprime ma gratitude à Manuel, rédacteur en chef adjoint depuis 2008, et à Sandrine Avril, secrétaire de rédaction, pour leur travail efficace et leur dévouement.
    [Show full text]
  • Galileo's Construction of Idealized Fall in the Void
    Hist. Sci., xliii (2005) GALILEO’S CONSTRUCTION OF IDEALIZED FALL IN THE VOID Paolo Palmieri University of Pittsburgh 1. INTRODUCTION How did Galileo achieve his mathematical natural philosophy? How did he discover the times-squared law, the pendulum isochronism, the parabolic trajectory of projec- tiles — by experiment or by mathematical reasoning? Questions like these have long divided scholars into two camps: the advocates of experiment and the advocates of geometry. Is there an alternative to the two horns of this dilemma? I am convinced that there is indeed a viable alternative. Before substantiating my claim, however, I need to sketch the essential elements characterizing the division. I will do so through the exemplar case which is central to my study here. In 1604 Galileo wrote a letter to Paolo Sarpi, in which he put forward an “errone- ous” principle from which he claimed that he could derive the times-squared law of fall. The principle is as follows: the ratio of the speeds of fall is the same as the ratio of the spaces fallen through. In referring to that “erroneous” principle, Alexandre Koyré argues that Galileo already knew all the details concerning the phenomenon of fall, such as the sameness of ratios between the spaces traversed and the squares of the elapsed times (on sameness of ratios more below, in Section 3).1 What Galileo had long wanted to discover, in Koyré’s view, was a general principle from which he could deduce the law of fall geometrically. In other words, Koyré continues, Galileo sought to fi nd the essence, i.e., the defi nition, or law, of the phenomenon “fall of bodies”.
    [Show full text]
  • Reaching Beyond the Discipline Melinda Gormley3, Reilly Center for Science, Technology, and Values, University of Notre Dame
    Vol. 42, No. 1 EWS January 2013 N of the Historyletter of Science Society TABLE OF CONTENTS MAKING A DIFFERENCE (ALMOST) TEN WAYS HISTORY OF SCIENCE Notes from the Inside 4 MAKES A DIFFERENCE Article: The “Dinosaurs” Guide From the President, Lynn K. Nyhart 1. It puts a human face on science, reminding us that to Technology in the History Classroom 5 At the beginning of a new year, many of us resolve scientists are people like the rest of us. (In fact, it puts to make a difference in the world. We may seek to be many different human faces on science, which is a Article: That Was Then. This Is Now 8 kinder to others; to give more of ourselves; to work for good idea.) justice, democracy, health, and peace; to increase beauty. Article: Reaching Beyond the 2. It provides a long-term perspective on science-related Discipline 11 But how can we work as historians of science to make ideas and trends of which scientists themselves are Article: A Conversation with the a difference? Late December, as I write this, is a list- often unaware. It thus can reveal hidden connections making time of year. I have made two. American Historical Association’s to the past, and show how the past continues to bear Jim Grossman, 4 October 2012 13 The first aims at pithiness: a “top ten” list that we can on the present. Member News 15 post on our websites, blogs, and office doors. Something 3. It counters the naive view that “science = truth” by we can fall back on for friends, relatives, students treating science as part of particular cultures.
    [Show full text]
  • Galileo's Mathematization of Nature at the Crossroad Between the Empiricist and the Kantian Tradition
    Edinburgh Research Explorer Galileo's Mathematization of Nature at the Crossroad between the Empiricist and the Kantian Tradition Citation for published version: Massimi, M 2010, 'Galileo's Mathematization of Nature at the Crossroad between the Empiricist and the Kantian Tradition', Perspectives on Science, vol. 18, no. 2, pp. 152-188. https://doi.org/10.1162/posc.2010.18.2.152 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1162/posc.2010.18.2.152 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: Perspectives on Science Publisher Rights Statement: © MIT. Massimi, M. (2010). Galileo's Mathematization of Nature at the Crossroad between the Empiricist and the Kantian Tradition. Perspectives on Science, 18(2), 152-188doi: 10.1162/posc.2010.18.2.152 General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 26. Sep. 2021 Galileo’s Mathematization of Nature at the Crossroad between the Empiricist and the Kantian Tradition Michela Massimi University College London The aim of this paper is to take Galileo’s mathematization of nature as a springboard for contrasting the time-honoured empiricist conception of phe- nomena, exempliªed by Pierre Duhem’s analysis in To Save the Phenomena (1908), with Immanuel Kant’s.
    [Show full text]
  • Galileo's Free Fall Into History of Physics & Nature of Science Teaching
    Galileo’s Free Fall into History of Physics & Nature of Science Teaching Raffaele Pisano - IEMN, Lille University, France; Associate to CPNSS, LSE, United Kingdom - [email protected] Vincenzo Cioci - PhD Student, Lille University, France - [email protected] Abstract: In Discorsi e Dimostrazioni Matematiche su Due Nuove Scienze, Galileo Galilei (1564-1642) described in detail his experiments about free fall motion, the motion along an inclined plane and the parabolic motion. By notes on the subject Stillman Drake (1910-1993) suggested its historical account. Recent works proposed that the notion of time received a mathe- matical treatment and a physical measurement entering into the equations of the fall of the bodies. Our paper aims to describe an historical and Nature of Science/experimental path on Galilean physics and mathematics. One of us (VC) is currently working at a high school in Naples (Italy) with the follow- ing educational aspects of the present research: analysing Galilean sources (about free fall) and secondary literature on the subject. The main idea is starting from the analysis of the pendulum motion and of the water clock essential to perform the measurement of time – right in the historical context. Keywords: Galileo, Free fall, Nature of Science Teaching, History of Phys- ics. 1. Introduction The overall aim of this work is to address the Nature of Science (NoS)-teaching of sci- ence (physics, physics-mathematics) and educational aspects of the teaching-learning of physics in high school and University,
    [Show full text]
  • Galileo Galilei 1 Galileo Galilei
    Galileo Galilei 1 Galileo Galilei « La filosofia è scritta in questo grandissimo libro che continuamente ci sta aperto innanzi a gli occhi (io dico l'universo), ma non si può intendere se prima non s'impara a intender la lingua, e conoscer i caratteri, ne' quali è scritto. Egli è scritto in lingua matematica, e i caratteri son triangoli, cerchi, ed altre figure geometriche, senza i quali mezzi è impossibile a intenderne umanamente parola; senza questi è un aggirarsi vanamente per un oscuro laberinto. » (Galileo Galilei, Il Saggiatore, Cap. VI) Galileo Galilei Galileo Galilei (Pisa, 15 febbraio 1564 – Arcetri, 8 gennaio 1642) è stato un fisico, filosofo, astronomo e matematico italiano, padre della scienza moderna. Il suo nome è associato ad importanti contributi in dinamica[1] e in astronomia - fra cui il perfezionamento del telescopio, che gli permise importanti osservazioni astronomiche[2] - e all'introduzione del metodo scientifico (detto spesso metodo galileiano o metodo scientifico sperimentale). Di primaria importanza furono il suo ruolo nella rivoluzione astronomica e il suo sostegno al sistema eliocentrico e alle teorie copernicane. Accusato di voler sovvertire la filosofia naturale aristotelica e le Sacre Scritture, Galileo fu per questo condannato come eretico dalla chiesa cattolica e costretto, il 22 giugno 1633, all'abiura delle sue concezioni astronomiche, nonché a trascorrere il resto della sua vita in isolamento. Biografia La giovinezza (1564-1588) Galileo Galilei nacque il 15 febbraio 1564 a Pisa, [3] primogenito dei sette
    [Show full text]
  • 2014 Hss/Psa Meeting - Chicago, Illinois
    THANK YOU TO OUR SUPPORTERS! National Science Foundation Morris Fishbein Center for the History of Science and Medicine at the University of Chicago The Weinberg College of Arts and Sciences, Northwestern University The Graduate School, Northwestern University The Department of History, Northwestern University 2014 hss/psa Meeting - Chicago, illinois 2014 hss/psa Meeting - Chicago, Science in Human Culture Program, Northwestern University University of Chicago Press University of Chicago Press, Journals Division University of Maryland, Baltimore County The Chemical Heritage Foundation Brent Dibner, Dibner Institute Miles Davis Pfize Educational Advancement Foundation Albert C. Lewis David Kaiser, Germeshausen Chair funds National Science Foundation Science, Technology and Society Program at the University of Michigan Program in Science, Technology and Society at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology Center for Philosophy of Science at the University of Pittsburgh Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science at the University of California, Irvine Program for History and Philosophy of Science at the University of Notre Dame Minnesota Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Minnesota Program Cover.indd 1 10/21/2014 5:03:31 PM Cover Design done using www.tagxedo.com. The titles of the papers on the HSS and PSA program were used to create the word cloud. The words ‘science,’ ‘scientific,’ ‘history,’ and ‘philosophy’ were removed from the word list. The design was inspired by a word cloud of the HSS session titles created by Henry Cowles (Yale University). HISTORY OF SCIENCE SOCIETY PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE ASSOCIATION 6-9 November 2014 Chicago, Illinois TABLE OF CONTENTS HSS Acknowledgements ............................................................ 2 HSS Officers and Program Chairs .............................................
    [Show full text]
  • Galileo Galilei - Wikipedia
    12/2/2018 Galileo Galilei - Wikipedia Galileo Galilei Galileo Galilei (Italian: [ɡaliˈlɛːo ɡaliˈlɛi]; 15 February 1564[3] – 8 January 1642) was an Italian polymath. Galileo is a central Galileo Galilei figure in the transition from natural philosophy to modern science and in the transformation of the scientific Renaissance into a scientific revolution. Galileo's championing of heliocentrism and Copernicanism was controversial during his lifetime, when most subscribed to either geocentrism or the Tychonic system.[4] He met with opposition from astronomers, who doubted heliocentrism because of the absence of an observed stellar parallax.[4] The matter was investigated by the Roman Inquisition in 1615, which concluded that heliocentrism was "foolish and absurd in philosophy, and formally heretical since it explicitly contradicts in many places the sense of Holy Scripture."[4][5][6] Galileo later defended his views in Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems, which appeared to attack Pope Urban VIII and thus alienated him and the Jesuits, who had both supported Galileo up until this point.[4] He was tried by the Inquisition, found "vehemently suspect of heresy", and forced to recant. He spent the rest of his life under house arrest.[7][8] While under house arrest, he wrote one of his best-known works, Two New Sciences, in which he summarized work he had done some forty years earlier on the two sciences now called kinematics and strength of materials.[9][10] Galileo studied speed and velocity, gravity and free fall, the principle of relativity, inertia, projectile motion and also worked Portrait by Giusto Sustermans in applied science and technology, describing the properties of pendulums and "hydrostatic balances", inventing the thermoscope and various military compasses, and using the telescope for scientific observations of celestial objects.
    [Show full text]