<<

Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141 www.elsevier.com/locate/obhdp

The of courage in social predictions: Underestimating the impact of fear of embarrassment on other people ଝ

Leaf Van Boven a,¤, George Loewenstein b, David Dunning c

a Department of Psychology, University of Colorado, 345 UCB, Boulder, CO 80309-0345, USA b Department of Social and Decision Sciences, Carnegie Mellon University, USA c Department of Psychology, Cornell University, USA

Received 7 July 2004

Abstract

The results of two experiments support the thesis that emotional perspective taking entails two judgments: a prediction of one’s own preferences and decisions in a diVerent emotional situation, and an adjustment of this prediction to accommodate perceived diVerences between self and others. Participants overestimated others’ willingness to engage in embarrassing public performances—miming (Experiment 1) and dancing (Experiment 2)—in exchange for money. Consistent with a dual judgment model, this overestimation was greater among participants facing a hypothetical rather than a real decision to perform. Further, participants’ predictions of others’ willingness to perform were more closely correlated with self-predictions than with partici- pants’ estimates of others’ about the costs and beneWts of performing.  2004 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.

Keywords: AVective forecasting; Decision making; Empathy gaps; Emotion; Judgment; Prediction; Perspective taking

Accurately predicting others’ reactions to emotional How do people predict others’ preferences and deci- situations is an important part of everyday social life. sions in emotional situations? That is, how do people Knowing how an employee will deal with criticism is engage in emotional perspective taking? We examine this helpful for deciding how best to provide performance question in the context of people’s predictions of others’ feedback. Knowing how a friend will respond to long- reactions to embarrassing situations. term physical duress is useful in deciding whether to Fear of embarrassment is an important determinant invite him on an extended wilderness adventure. And of social behavior. Social psychologists have cited the knowing how much co-workers will enjoy (or dread) impact of fear of embarrassment in non-intervention in singing in front of friends and colleagues is important emergency situations (Latané & Darley, 1970), failures for deciding whether to schedule a karaoke contest for to oppose unpopular policies or social norms (Miller & the company retreat. McFarland, 1987; Prentice & Miller, 1993; Van Boven, 2000), obedience to authority (Sabini, Seipmann, & Stein, 2001), and lovers’ failure to use contraception ଝ This research was supported by NSF Grant SBR-9521914, by the (Herold, 1981; Leary & Dobbins, 1983). And fear of Center for Integrated Study of the Human Dimensions of Global embarrassment is one reason why regrettable inactions Change at Carnegie Mellon University, by NIMH Grant RO1 56072, are more durable than regrettable actions (Gilovich, and by funds to junior faculty provided by the University of Colorado. ¤ Corresponding author. Fax: +1 303 467 2697. Kerr, & Medvec, 1993; Gilovich & Medvec, 1995). E-mail addresses: [email protected] (L. Van Boven), Because fear of embarrassment is such a potent barrier [email protected] (G. Loewenstein), [email protected] (D. Dunning). to social action (Miller, 1992; Miller & Leary, 1992),

0749-5978/$ - see front matter  2004 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.obhdp.2004.12.001 L. Van Boven et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141 131 making good decisions in social situations and accu- lar the other person is to the self, and, hence, how rately interpreting social behavior often depends on informative the self-prediction is about others’ reactions accurately predicting the impact of fear of embarrass- (the horizontal solid arrow in Fig. 1). Believing that a ment on other people. colleague is more extroverted than oneself suggests Based on our own and others’ research, we hypothe- adjusting one’s own reluctance to sing to accommodate sized that people underestimate the impact of fear of the colleague’s outgoing personality. embarrassment on others’ preferences and decisions. Our dual judgment model of emotional perspective SpeciWcally, we hypothesized that people overestimate taking diVers from other models of perspective taking in others’ willingness to engage in embarrassing public per- two important ways. First, many models of perspective formances. This “illusion of courage” in social predic- taking focus on people’s predictions of others’ reactions tions follows from a model of emotional perspective to situations or decisions that are exactly the same as taking in which predictions of others’ preferences and those faced by the self—for example, others who are decisions in emotional situations depends partly on pre- faced with a similar decision to wear a sandwich board dictions of one’s own reactions to those situations. or not (Ross, Greene, & House, 1977), asked a similar Because people underestimate the impact of fear of question about their preference for 1980s or 1960s music embarrassment on themselves, overestimating their own (Gilovich, 1990), confronted with a similar decision willingness to engage in embarrassing public perfor- about whether to donate to charity (Epley & Dunning, mances (Van Boven, Loewenstein, Dunning, & Welch, 2000; Goethals, Messick, & Allison, 1991), or asked a 2004), we expected them to overestimate others’ willing- similar question about their attitudes toward social ness to engage in public performances. norms (Miller & McFarland, 1987; Prentice & Miller, 1993; Van Boven, 2000). Because this previous research (represented by the horizontal dashed arrow in Fig. 1) A dual judgment model of emotional perspective taking has focused on perspective taking within the same, typi- cally non-emotional, situation, previous theorizing has We propose that emotional perspective taking entails focused primarily on factors that inXuence judgments of two, distinct judgments, represented by the two solid how similar or dissimilar others are to the self (e.g., arrows in Fig. 1 (Van Boven & Loewenstein, 2003, in Krueger & Clement, 1994; Prentice & Miller, 1996). press-a, in press-b). The Wrst is a prediction of what one’s Emotional perspective taking, in contrast, concerns pre- own preferences and decisions would be in a diVerent dictions of how other people would react to being in a emotional situation (the vertical solid arrow in Fig. 1). diVerent emotional situation from the situation the self is For example, one might predict whether a colleague currently in. Accordingly, we suggest that emotional per- would enjoy karaoke by Wrst predicting whether oneself spective taking entails the additional judgment of how would enjoy singing popular tunes in front of an audi- the self would respond to being in a diVerent emotional ence. The second judgment is an estimation of how simi- situation.

Fig. 1. Schematic representation of perspective taking across similar situations and across diVerent emotional situations. The dual judgment model of emotional perspective taking is represented by the two solid arrows. The horizontal dashed arrow represents predictions of others who are in similar situations as the self. The diagonal dashed arrow represents simultaneously accounting for the reactions of diVerent people who are in diVerent situations than the self. 132 L. Van Boven et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141

Second, other examinations of cross-situational per- thirst versus hunger compared with people whose thirst spective-taking posit a single judgment that simulta- is aroused because they just engaged in 20 min of cardio- neously accounts for diVerences between the self and vascular exercise (Van Boven & Loewenstein, 2003). the target and for diVerences between others’ situation Hot/cold empathy gaps arise because people do not and the situation the self is currently in (the diagonal anticipate how much emotional arousal inXuences their dashed arrow in Fig. 2, Epley, Keysar, Van Boven, & construal of the situation. In particular, people underes- Gilovich, 2004; Keysar & Barr, 2002; Nickerson, 1999). timate how much arousal increases their focus on For example, people’s own interpretation of an ambigu- emotional information relative to non-emotional infor- ous communication may serve as a judgmental anchor mation. Emotional arousal, particularly of negative from which they adjust to estimate the interpretation of aVect such as fear and anxiety, narrows (Basso, other people who were provided with diVerent informa- ScheVt, Ris, & Dember, 1996; Derryberry, 1993; Derry- tion about the communication (Epley et al., 2004). berry & Reed, 1998) and inhibits attention to non-emo- Although anchoring and adjustment of this type may tional information (Fox, Russo, & Bowles, 2001; Fox, characterize perspective taking across diVerent non- Russo, & Dutton, 2002). This “emotional focusing” can emotional situations, we contend that perspective increase the judgmental weight of emotional informa- taking across diVerent emotional situations entails two tion relative to non-emotional information, exacerbating separate judgments: a prediction of one’s own reaction the tendency to underweight non-focal information to a diVerent emotional situation, and an adjustment to when making predictions (Chambers, Windschitl, & this prediction to accommodate diVerences between Suls, 2003; Kruger & Burrus, 2003; Moore & Kim, 2003; oneself and others. Savitsky, Epley, & Gilovich, 2001; Schkade & Kahn- A novel implication of our dual-judgment model is eman, 1998; Wilson, Wheatley, Meyers, Gilbert, & that accurate emotional perspective taking depends both Axsom, 2000; Windschitl, Krueger, & Simms, 2003). on the accuracy of self-predictions and on the accuracy In the case of embarrassment, the fear and anxiety of assessments of the similarity between self and others. aroused by facing a real and immediate public perfor- Even if people are perfectly calibrated in their self-pre- mance causes people to focus more on being socially dictions, they may be biased in judging how similar they evaluated relative to the potential beneWts of embarrass- are to others. And even if people are perfectly calibrated ing behavior (Van Boven et al., 2004; Study 5). In one in their judgments of how similar they are to others, study, we found that, compared with those facing a biased self-predictions could produce biased social-pre- purely hypothetical performance, participants facing a dictions. We propose that judgmental bias of both real and immediate decision to dance for money types contribute to the illusion of courage in social- reported thinking more about being evaluated by others predictions. relative to the money they could earn. The diVerence between people’s thoughts about social evaluation and their thoughts about money—an index of emotional The illusion of courage in self-predictions focusing—statistically mediated the impact of facing a hypothetical or real decision on people’s willingness to With respect to self-predictions (the vertical solid dance. arrow in Fig. 1), our own research indicates that people Our other research on the illusion of courage in self- underestimate the impact of fear of embarrassment on predictions led us to predict that people’s overestimation their own preferences and decisions. When an embar- of their own willingness to engage in embarrassing per- rassing public performance is not real and immediate, formances would contribute to the illusion of courage in people overestimate how willing they would be to dance, social-predictions. SpeciWcally, we hypothesized that perform a mime, or tell a joke in exchange for money people who simply imagined facing the choice of engag- (Van Boven et al., 2004). This illusion of courage in self- ing in an embarrassing performance in exchange for predictions is a speciWc case of “hot/cold empathy gaps,” money would predict that others would be more willing which occur when people in an unaroused state underes- to perform compared with people who actually faced the timate the impact of being in an emotional situation on choice of performing for money. their preferences and decisions (Loewenstein, 1999; Loe- wenstein, O’Donoghue, & Rabin, 2003). For instance, people who do not own an object underestimate how DiVerences between self and others in fear of attached they would be to it and how much money they embarrassment would demand to sell the object if they did own it (Loe- wenstein & Adler, 1995; Van Boven, Dunning, & Loe- With respect to assessments of the similarity between wenstein, 2000; Van Boven, Loewenstein, & Dunning, the self and others (the horizontal solid arrow in Fig. 1), 2003). And people who are in a relatively neutral state previous research demonstrates that people have an underestimate how much they would be bothered by enduring intuitive belief that others experience fear of L. Van Boven et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141 133 embarrassment less than the self (McFarland & Miller, people’s predictions of others’ willingness to perform 1990; Miller & McFarland, 1987; Sabini, Cosmas, Siep- were more closely associated with predictions of their mann, & Stein, 1999; Van Boven, 2000). This belief is an own willingness to perform, as implied by our model, or instance of a more general intuitive theory that others with people’s estimates of how much others experience self-conscious emotions less than the self about the costs versus the beneWts of performing. (McFarland & Miller, 1990; Miller & McFarland, 1987; Vorauer & Ratner, 1996). Because people often restrain their display of self-conscious emotions (Kleck et al., Experiment 1: Miming 1976; Kraut, 1982; Lanzetta, Cartwright-Smith, & Kleck, 1976), evidence about the intensity of others’ self- Participants were asked to predict how willing they conscious emotions tends to be less cognitively and other people would be to perform a mime in front of accessible than evidence about one’s own self-conscious a large audience in exchange for money. For some partici- emotions. This diVerential accessibility can lead people pants, the performance was potentially real: they knew to infer that others experience self-conscious emotions that they might actually have to mime if they indicated a less than the self (Schwarz & Vaughn, 2002; Taylor, willingness to do so. For other participants, the perfor- 1982; Tversky & Kahneman, 1973). mance was purely hypothetical: they knew they would not People’s belief that others experience less fear of have to mime no matter how they responded. All partici- embarrassment than the self led us to hypothesize that pants were asked to take the perspective of the other par- people would generally overestimate others’ willingness ticipants facing a real performance, and to predict how to engage in an embarrassing public performance in willing to perform those participants would be, on aver- exchange for money, regardless of whether people them- age. We expected that participants in both groups would selves faced a real or hypothetical performance. More exhibit an illusion of courage, overestimating others’ will- important, our dual judgment model implies that this ingness to perform compared with participants who faced overestimation would be moderated by people’s predic- a potentially real performance. We also expected this tion of their own willingness to perform. overestimation to be pronounced among participants fac- ing a purely hypothetical performance compared with those facing a potentially real performance. Further, we The present research expected this diVerential overestimation of others’ willing- ness to perform to be mediated by participants’ predic- We examined the illusion of courage in social predic- tions of their own willingness to perform. tions in two experiments. We confronted people with either purely hypothetical or potentially real decisions to Method engage in embarrassing public performances in exchange for money. We asked people to predict other people’s willingness to mime (Experiment 1) and dance (Experi- University undergraduates in a large lecture class N D ment 2). Performing in front of an audience is ( 174) participated as part of a class exercise. The embarrassing for many reasons, including simple con- experimenter distributed white and green versions of a spicuousness and the possibility of negative social evalu- questionnaire randomly assigning participants to either D ation (Miller, 1992; Sabini et al., 2001). The decision to the real (n 86) or hypothetical performance condition n D engage in an embarrassing performance is therefore a ( 88). Participants in the real performance condition function of the avoidance motivations associated with read: embarrassing public performances relative to the Students with green sheets of paper—like you—are approach motivation associated with earning money. being given the option of performing one of 20 ran- We expected to diVerentiate the two judgments in our domly selected mimes in front of the class for a payment model by demonstrating two trends. First, we expected of $5. The instructor will randomly select some of the that people’s predictions of others’ willingness to per- students with green sheets who have agreed to perform a form would be strongly correlated with people’s own mime to do so. The instructor will randomly select a willingness to perform. People who faced a hypothetical mime for each student to perform. The instructor will decision to perform for money should therefore predict chose from the following mimes: basketball (the ball that other people would be more willing to perform itself), bicycle, blender, dog, cheetah, computer, elephant, compared with people who faced a real decision to per- Wle cabinet, ocean liner, ocean waves, porcupine, scotch form. Second, we expected that people would generally tape, skeet shooter, snake, stapler, thumb tack, washing overestimate others’ willingness to engage in an embar- machine, waste basket, waterfall, and willow tree. Stu- rassing performance, independent of whether people dents will perform the mime until someone from the themselves faced a real or hypothetical performance. class correctly identiWes it. Mimers may use whatever Furthermore, in Experiment 2 we examined whether body movements they wish, but may not use words or 134 L. Van Boven et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141 props. Notice that because not everyone who indicates a willingness to perform a mime will actually be called upon to do so, no one will notice if you choose not to perform a mime. Participants in the hypothetical performance condi- tion received identical instructions, except they were printed on white paper and speciWed that participants would not actually be asked to mime. As measures of participants’ own willingness to per- form, they stated in dollars the lowest price they would have to be paid to mime in front of the class. They also indicated whether or not they would be willing to per- form a mime in exchange for $5. Participants were also asked to consider the (other) participants in the real per- formance condition and to estimate the average lowest performance price of those participants, as well as the percentage of those participants that would agree to Fig. 2. Experiment 1: Miming. For participants who faced a hypotheti- mime for $5. The order of the two questions pertaining cal and real performance, their own lowest performance price, and to participants themselves and the two questions per- their estimate of the average lowest performance price of other partici- pants who faced a real performance. Reference line indicates the low- taining to the other participants was counterbalanced, est performance price stated by participants who faced a real had no reliable eVect, and is not discussed further. performance. Note. Performance prices are back-transformed averages After the questionnaires were collected, the experi- of natural log transformed individual prices. menter randomly selected Wve willing students from the real performance condition to mime. Participants were thanked, paid, and everyone was debriefed. underestimated their own performance prices (M D $11.24) compared with participants who faced a real Results and discussion performance (d D .43, t [171] D 2.85, p D .005, 95% C.I. D $1.16–$2.22). Furthermore, a mediation analysis Because performance prices were positively skewed, (Baron & Kenny, 1986) indicated that the impact of the we performed natural log transformations before ana- real or hypothetical nature of the performance on par- lyzing the data. For interpretational ease, we present ticipants’ own performance prices ( D .21) mediated back-transformed averages. We excluded from all analy- the impact of the nature of the performance on partici- ses one participant from the hypothetical performance pants’ predictions of others’ performance prices. The condition who stated an inconsistent performance price correlation between the reality of the performance and and decision to mime (resulting N D 173). predictions of others’ performance prices was reliably As anticipated, participants overestimated others’ reduced (from  D .15 to  D .01, Z D 2.74, p D .006), via willingness to perform a mime, and this overestimation a Sobel (1982) test, when participants’ own perfor- was greater among participants who faced a purely mance prices were included in a multiple regression hypothetical performance compared with those who ( D .64, t [170] D 10.72, p < .001). faced a potentially real performance (see Fig. 2). The A similar pattern emerged for participants’ predicted performance price stated by participants who faced a and actual decisions of whether they would perform for potentially real performance (M D $19.61) was underes- $5. The fraction of participants who faced a real perfor- timated both by participants who faced a hypothetical mance that were willing to mime (15.12%) was overesti- performance (M D $8.57, d D .70, t[171] D 4.58, 95% mated both by participants who faced a hypothetical C.I. D $1.51–$2.79) and those who faced a real perfor- performance (M D 43.33%, d D 2.62, t [86] D 12.05, 95% mance (M D $11.32, d D 1.21, t[85] D 5.57, 95% C.I. D C.I. D 23.56–32.87%) and by those who faced a real per- $1.35–$1.88). Also as anticipated, participants who faced formance themselves (M D 38.74%, d D 2.20, t[85] D a hypothetical performance predicted that participants 10.15, 95% C.I. D 19.00–28.25%). As well, participants facing a real performance would state a lower perfor- who faced a hypothetical performance predicted that a mance price than did participants who faced a poten- greater fraction of other students would agree to mime tially real performance (d D .30, t [171] D 1.94, 95% compared with participants who faced a real perfor- C.I. D–$1.01–$1.67). mance, although the diVerence was not reliable (d D .21, The impact of the reality of the performance on par- t[171] D 1.39, 95% C.I. D –1.93–11.10%). Finally, replicat- ticipants’ social-predictions was mirrored in self-pre- ing our previous research, participants who faced a dictions. Replicating our previous research, hypothetical performance were more likely to predict participants who faced a hypothetical performance that they would mime (M D 31.03%) compared with the L. Van Boven et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141 135 fraction of participants who actually agreed to mime people consider when deciding whether to perform in (M D 15.12%, D .19, 2 [1, N D 173] D 6.17, p D .013). exchange for money. Because being evaluated by others These results demonstrate the illusion of courage in is, intuitively, more closely associated with the emotions social predictions and suggest that it stems from the aroused by facing public performances than the money combination of two judgmental biases. First, partici- one could earn, facing a real and immediate performance pants who faced a purely hypothetical performance pre- causes people to think less about the money relative to dicted that others would be more willing to perform than being socially evaluated (Van Boven et al., 2004). We participants who faced a real performance, implying that therefore expected that people facing a real performance the illusion of courage in self-predictions contributed to would focus more on being evaluated by their peers rela- the illusion of courage in social-predictions. Consistent tive to the money they could earn, and that this emo- with this thesis, the impact of facing a real or hypotheti- tional focusing would mediate the illusion of courage in cal performance on participants’ own willingness to per- self-predictions. form (the vertical solid arrow in Fig. 1) statistically Of greater import for the present investigation, we mediated the impact of the reality of the performance on expected that people’s predictions of others’ willingness their predictions of others’ willingness to perform. Sec- to perform would be more closely associated with their ond, participants generally overestimated how willing own willingness to perform than with people’s estimates other people would be to engage in an embarrassing of others’ thoughts about the relative costs and beneWts public performance, regardless of whether participants of performing. Our dual judgment model of emotional themselves faced a real or hypothetical performance (the perspective taking implies that predictions of others’ horizontal solid arrow in Fig. 1). preferences and decisions are based primarily on predic- tions of one’s own preferences and decisions. Thus, although we expected people to project onto others Experiment 2: Dancing their own thoughts about being evaluated and the money they could earn, we did not expect people’s esti- We designed Experiment 2 with two goals in mind. mates of others’ thoughts to be independently associ- The Wrst was to replicate the primary results of Experi- ated with people’s predictions of others’ willingness to ment 1 in a slightly diVerent setting with somewhat perform. This pattern would provide strong support for diVerent measures. We asked people to indicate how our assertion that predictions of one’s own preferences willing they would be to dance in front of an audience in and decisions form the basis of emotional perspective exchange for money. People were also asked to take the taking. perspective of a speciWc, randomly selected individual, rather than a group of other individuals as in Experi- Method ment 1, and to predict that individual’s willingness to dance for money. The performance was potentially real University undergraduates in a large lecture class for some people and purely hypothetical for others. We (N D 270) participated as part of a class exercise. Upon expected both groups of people to overestimate others’ entering the classroom, a large auditorium with an ele- willingness to dance. We also expected that people facing vated stage in front, students were given an instruction a hypothetical performance would be more likely than packet and questionnaires to read and complete while those facing a real performance to predict that others they listened to Rick James’ 1981 song “Super Freak.” would perform, and that this diVerence in social predic- As in Experiment 1, participants were given green or tions would mirror and be mediated by a corresponding white sheets of paper randomly assigning them to either diVerence in self-predictions. the real (n D 135) or hypothetical (n D 135) performance Our second goal was to examine the extent to which condition. Participants in the real performance condi- predictions of others’ willingness to perform are corre- tion read the following: lated with predictions of one’s own willingness to per- Students with green sheets of paper like you have the form versus estimates of others’ thoughts about the costs option of dancing by themselves in front of the class for and beneWts of performing. Repeating a procedure used a payment of $5. The instructor will randomly select in our other research (Van Boven et al., 2004), people some of the students with green sheets who have agreed were asked to report how much they thought about two to dance to do so. Those students will dance, one at a factors when they decided whether to dance: being eval- time, for one minute, to the song “Super Freak,” by Rick uated by other people, and the money they could earn. James. Notice that because not everyone who indicates People were also asked to estimate how much the other he or she will dance will be called upon to do so, no one person thought about the same two factors when decid- will notice if you choose not to dance. ing whether he or she would dance. These two factors emerged during the debrieWng of our previous studies, The instructions given to participants in the hypothet- including Experiment 1, as the major costs and beneWts ical performance condition were identical, except they 136 L. Van Boven et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141 were printed on white paper, and speciWed that there was no possibility of their dancing. Both groups read that half of the students faced a real performance and half faced a hypothetical performance. Participants were asked to state the smallest amount of money they would have to be paid to dance, and to indicate whether they would dance for $5. Participants were also asked to consider another anonymous, “ran- domly selected” participant in the real performance con- dition, to predict that participant’s lowest performance price, and to predict whether that participant would dance for $5. The order of the two questions pertaining to participants themselves and to the other participant was counterbalanced, had no reliable eVect, and is not discussed further. Fig. 3. Experiment 2: Dancing. For participants who faced a hypothet- Participants were next asked how much they thought ical and real performance, their own lowest performance price, and about two factors when indicating their willingness to their estimate of the lowest performance price of another individual perform: “How much did you think about how you participant who faced a real performance. Reference line indicates lowest performance price stated by participants facing a real perfor- would be evaluated by the other students?” and “How mance. Note. Performance prices are back-transformed averages of much did you think about the $5 you would earn?” They natural log transformed individual prices. answered both questions on scales ranging from 1(not at all) to 9(a great deal). Participants also estimated on hypothetical performance predicted others’ performance identical scales how much the participant whose perfor- prices would be lower than did participants who faced a mance price and choice they predicted had thought real performance (d D .29, t[250] D 2.30, 95% C.I. D about each factor. Participants’ completed question- $1.05–$1.92). Finally, participants who faced a hypothet- naires were collected, the experimenter selected ten will- ical performance underestimated what their own perfor- ing participants from the real performance condition to mance prices would be (M D $21.07) compared with dance, and everyone was debriefed. participants who faced a real performance (d D .42, t[248] D 3.32, 95% C.I. D $1.42–$3.94). Results A similar pattern emerged for participants’ predicted and actual choices. The fraction of students that agreed Because performance prices were positively skewed, to dance when they faced a real performance (8.33%) as in Experiment 1, we performed natural log transfor- was overestimated by participants who faced a hypo- mations before analyzing the data, but present back- thetical performance (M D 35.66%, D .33, 2 [1, N D transformed averages for interpretational ease. We 261] D 28.54, p < .001) and by participants who faced a excluded from all analyses the nine participants (six in real performance themselves (M D 31.01%, McNemar the hypothetical performance condition and three in the N D 132, p D .021). As with performance price predic- real performance condition) who stated inconsistent per- tions, participants who faced a hypothetical perfor- formance prices and decisions, either for themselves or mance were more likely than participants who faced a for the other participant (resulting N D 261). real performance to predict that others would choose to dance ( D .23, 2 [1,N D 261] D 13.34, p < .001). Addi- Willingness to perform. Replicating the illusion of cour- tionally, participants who faced a hypothetical perfor- age in social predictions, participants overestimated oth- mance were more likely to predict that they themselves ers’ willingness to dance; this overestimation was greater would choose to dance (M D 31.01%) compared with the among participants who faced a hypothetical perfor- fraction of participants who actually chose to dance ( mance than among those who faced a real performance D .29, 2 [1, N D 261] D 21.34, p < .001). These results (see Fig. 3). The performance price stated by participants replicate the illusion of courage in social- and self- who faced a real performance (M D $52.88) was underes- predictions. timated both by participants who faced a hypothetical performance (M D $12.71, d D .71, t[250] D 5.63, 95% Emotional focusing. As expected, participants who faced C.I. D $2.39–$6.09) and by those who faced a real perfor- a hypothetical performance reported thinking about the mance themselves (M D $19.22, d D 1.06, t [119] D 5.79, money to be earned versus being evaluated by others 95% C.I. D $1.91–$3.72).1 Also, participants who faced a more than did participants who faced a real perfor- mance (see the left side of Fig. 4). And, as expected, participants projected this shift in focus onto others’ 1 Because of missing data, degrees of freedom vary between tests. thoughts (see the right side of Fig. 4). We submitted L. Van Boven et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141 137

Fig. 4. Experiment 2: Dancing. For participants who faced a hypothet- ical and real performance, their own thoughts about being evaluated and the money they could earn, as well as their estimate of how much another participant thought about the same two factors. participants’ thought ratings to a 2(thought: evaluation vs. money) £ 2(target: self vs. others) £ 2(performance: hypothetical vs. real) mixed model Analysis of Variance (ANOVA), with repeated measures on the Wrst two fac- tors. This analysis yielded the expected interaction Fig. 5. Experiment 2: Dancing. Structural equation model of partici- 2 between thoughts and performance ( D .023, F [1,258] D pants’ own lowest performance price and their estimate of another 6.09, 95% C.I. D .16–1.47). None of the other interactions participant’s lowest performance price. Solid lines represent statisti- were reliable (all F’s < 2.29). We next analyzed separately cally reliable associations (ps < .05); dashed lines represent non-reli- participants’ reports of their own thoughts and their pre- able associations. Numbers are standardized regression weights. dictions of others’ thoughts with two 2(thought: social evaluation vs. money) £ 2(performance: hypothetical vs. mance increases thoughts about evaluation relative to real) mixed-model ANOVAs. The expected interaction thoughts about money, we Wrst created two indices of was reliable both for participants’ own thoughts emotional focusing, one for participants’ own thoughts (2 D .017, F [1,258] D 4.53, 95% C.I. D .07–1.84), and their and one for their predictions of others’ thoughts. We predictions of others’ thoughts (2 D .017, F [1,258] D subtracted participants’ ratings of thoughts about the 4.39, 95% C.I. D .04–1.32). money from their ratings of thoughts about being eval- uated by other people. Higher numbers on each index Paths of courage. Our analysis of the illusion of cour- indicate a greater focus on being evaluated by others age in social predictions implies two paths of media- relative to the money. We then included Wve measures tion. First, as in our other research (Van Boven et al., in the SEM analysis: (a) a binary variable indicating 2004), the impact of facing a real or hypothetical per- whether participants were in the hypothetical or real formance on participants’ willingness to engage in performance condition (coded 0 or 1, respectively), (b) embarrassing performances should be at least partially the diVerence score indexing participants’ focus on mediated by their increased focus on being socially being evaluated by their peers, (c) the diVerence score evaluated relative to the money. Second, the impact of indexing participants’ belief about others’ focus on facing a real or hypothetical performance on predic- being evaluated by their peers, (d) participants’ own tions of others’ willingness to perform should be medi- performance price (natural log transformed), and (e) ated by participants’ own willingness to perform—and their estimate of the other participants’ performance not by participants’ estimates of others’ focus on social price (natural log transformed).3 evaluation. The fully saturated model is displayed in Fig. 5. Sta- We examined these predictions simultaneously with tistically reliable and non-reliable correlations in the the structural equation modeling (SEM) program model, each controlling for all other correlations, are within the AMOS procedure.2 Because our analysis of represented by solid and dashed arrows, respectively. emotional focusing implies that facing a real perfor-

3 We used performance prices rather than decisions as the key depen- 2 This analysis includes the 240 participants who provided all rele- dent measures in this model because prices are a more sensitive index vant data. of participants’ willingness to perform. 138 L. Van Boven et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141

The pattern of correlations is consistent with both medi- performance compared with those who faced a poten- ational hypotheses.4 tially real performance, a pattern that mirrored people’s Consider Wrst participants’ own performance price. overestimation of their own willingness to perform. Whether participants faced a hypothetical or real perfor- Compared with those who faced a hypothetical perfor- mance (Hypothetical or Real Performance) is reliably mance, people who faced a real performance reported correlated with their own focus on being evaluated (Self thinking about, and predicted others would think about, Focus on Evaluation, Z D 2.10, p D .036) and with their being evaluated by their peers more than the money to lowest performance price (Self Performance Price, be earned. Z D 2.86, p D .004). Participants’ own focus on evaluation Inspection of Fig. 4 reveals that this shift in focus is strongly correlated with their own performance price occurred mainly because of changes in thoughts about (Z D 7.18, p < .001). (Participants’ performance price is money. Regressions estimating the thoughts about also unexpectedly correlated with their prediction of money revealed reliable eVects of the type of perfor- other participants’ focus on evaluation, Z D 1.98, mance, both for participants’ own thoughts ( D¡.13, p D .046.) Furthermore, there is a reliable indirect path t[258] D 2.03, p D .044), and for their estimates of others’ from the hypothetical or real performance to partici- thoughts. ( D¡.14, t[258] D 2.23, p D .026). Regressions pants’ focus on evaluation to their own predicted perfor- estimating the thoughts about evaluation failed to reveal mance price (Z D 2.02, p D .044, Sobel, 1982). This reliable eVects of the type of performance for partici- pattern replicates our previous Wnding that participants’ pants’ own thoughts ( D .08, t[258] D 1.28, p D .203) and focus on evaluation partially mediated the illusion of for their estimates of others’ thoughts ( D .04, t < 1). courage in self-predictions. This pattern of results is consistent with our other Wnd- Next, consider participants’ predictions of other par- ings (Van Boven et al., 2004), and suggests that emo- ticipants’ performance price (Others’ Performance tional focusing is primarily caused by decreased Price). This prediction is reliably correlated only with attention to non-emotional information, rather than by participants’ own performance price (Z D 11.94, increased attention to emotional information. p < .001). None of the other variables in the model is reli- In any event, the key point of Experiment 2 is that the ably correlated with participants’ predictions of others’ predictions of others’ willingness to engage in an embar- performance prices (all Zs < 1), not even participants’ rassing public performance is reliably correlated only estimates of the other participant’s focus on evaluation with predictions of one’s own willingness to perform. (Others’ Focus on Evaluation). This is rather striking According to our model, people’s predictions of others’ given that participants’ own focus on evaluation was preferences and decisions in emotional situations—in this closely correlated with their own performance price. case, facing an embarrassing public performance—are Thus, participants’ own performance price—but not based on their predictions of what their own preferences their estimates of others’ thoughts—statistically medi- and decisions would be in those situations. Consistent ated the impact of the real versus hypothetical nature of with this thesis, a structural equation model indicated the performance on participants’ predictions of others’ that predictions of others’ willingness to engage in an performance prices.5 Participants’ predictions of others’ embarrassing performance were correlated only with par- willingness to engage in an embarrassing performance, ticipants’ predictions of their own willingness to engage this analysis suggests, were based primarily on their own in an embarrassing performance. Participants’ predic- willingness to perform, not on any judgment about tions of what other people thought about were not inde- others’ thoughts. pendently correlated with their predictions of others’ preferences. Discussion

The results of Experiment 2 replicated the illusion of General discussion courage in social predictions. People generally overesti- mated how willing other people would be to dance in Predicting how emotions impact others’ preferences front of an audience. This overestimation was pro- and decisions is a particularly important but also partic- nounced among people who faced a purely hypothetical ularly diYcult task of everyday social life. The two experiments presented here demonstrate that such emo- 4 We also conducted a SEM including only the associations implied tional perspective taking falls short when it comes to by our hypotheses, all of which remained reliable (all Zs > 2.4, all embarrassing situations. People systematically underes- ps < .01). The restricted model Wt the data well (comparative Wt timate the impact on others’ preferences and decisions of W index D .99), and the fully saturated model does not t the data reliably fear of embarrassment. People underestimated how better than the restricted model (2 [5, N D 240] D 6.07, p D .299). 5 According to Cohen and Cohen (1983) for analyses of two or more willing other people would be to mime (Experiment 1) mediating variables, a reasonable substitute for an exact signiWcance and dance (Experiment 2) in front of an audience. This test is whether all of the component path coeYcients are signiWcant. illusion of courage emerged both when people made L. Van Boven et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141 139 predictions about groups of people (Experiment 1) and The results of our experiments echo a central theme in about speciWc others (Experiment 2). social judgment: People’s judgments are egocentric and Two judgmental biases produce the illusion of cour- the self is the gravitational center of social age in social-predictions. First, and most important, peo- (Dunning & Cohen, 1992; Dunning & Hayes, 1996; ple base their social predictions on predictions of what Heider, 1958; Ichheiser, 1946; Krueger, 1998; Sherif & their own preferences and decisions would be in emo- Hovland, 1961). In both experiments, people’s predic- tionally arousing situations. Because people underesti- tions of others’ willingness to engage in an embarrassing mate the impact of being in an embarrassing situation performance were based largely on their own willingness on their own preferences and decisions (Van Boven et al., to perform. The egocentric nature of social judgment fol- 2004), they also underestimate the impact of being in an lows largely from people’s assumption that, because their embarrassing situation on others’ preferences and deci- perceptual and emotional apparatus is for the most part sions. Consistent with this thesis, the impact of facing a similar to others’ perceptual and emotional apparatus, real or hypothetical performance on participants’ pre- other people will experience similar reactions as the self dictions of others’ willingness to perform was statisti- (GriYn & Ross, 1991; Ross & Ward, 1995). Because of cally mediated in both experiments by the impact of such “naive realism,” people attribute their reluctance to facing a real versus hypothetical performance on partici- perform partly to the inherent properties of the choice, pants’ predictions of their own willingness to perform. implying that others will exhibit a similar reluctance. And in Experiment 2, a SEM indicated that predictions Our results also echo another theme in social judg- of others’ willingness to perform was independently cor- ment, seemingly inconsistent with egocentrism, that, related only with self-predictions, and not with estimates compared with others’ experience, one’s own experience of others’ focus on being evaluated by their peers. These is unique (Campbell, 1986; Katz & Allport, 1938; Pren- results suggest that predictions of others’ preferences in tice & Miller, 1996; Snyder & Fromkin, 1977; Suls & embarrassing situations are not based on coherent men- Wan, 1987). In both of our experiments, people generally tal representations of others’ thoughts and preferences, expected others to be more willing to perform than but at least partly on a (biased) representation of one’s themselves. That people simultaneously judge others to own preferences. be both similar and dissimilar to the self reXects the The second judgmental bias responsible for the illu- simultaneous operation of conXicted psychological pro- sion of courage in social predictions is an enduring intui- cesses (cf., Monin & Norton, 2003; Sabini et al., 1999). tive belief that others are less inXuenced by fear of On the one hand, people experience public performances embarrassment than themselves (Miller & McFarland, as inherently embarrassing and undesirable, both to the 1987; Sabini et al., 1999). As a result, people generally self and to others. One the other hand, people believe expect others to be more willing than themselves to that others react to embarrassing situations somewhat engage in embarrassing performances. Indeed, partici- diVerently than the self. pants in both experiments overestimated how willing An important question for future research is whether other people would be to engage in an embarrassing per- these two processes—egocentrism and perceived unique- formance, whether or not participants themselves faced ness—diVer in priority or eVort. Do people initially a real or hypothetical performance. assume that others’ reactions are similar to their own The results of these experiments were anticipated by before eVortfully accounting for potential diVerences and provide support for a dual judgment model of emo- between oneself and others? Or do people initially assume tional perspective taking (Van Boven & Loewenstein, that their reactions are unique before accounting for the 2003, in press-a, in press-b). According to this model, commonality of their own and others’ emotionality? represented by the solid arrows in Fig. 1, people’s predic- The results of our experiments, and of our model more tion of others’ preferences and decisions in emotional generally, also raise the question of whether and in what situations is the result of two distinct judgments: (a) peo- way perspective taking across diVerent emotional situa- ple’s prediction of what their own preferences and deci- tions diVers from perspective taking across diVerent non- sions would be in an emotional situation, and (b) emotional situations. To be sure, similar egocentric biases adjustments to this prediction to accommodate per- in perspective taking across both emotional and non- ceived diVerences between self and others. The results of emotional situations imply overlap in the processes our experiments provide a more precise test of this underlying emotional and non-emotional perspective model by simultaneously showing that people use them- taking (Van Boven & Loewenstein, in press-a, in press-b). selves as basis for predicting others’ willingness to As mentioned earlier, recent research indicates that per- engage in an embarrassing performance (the vertical spective taking across diVerent non-emotional situations solid arrow in Fig. 1), and that people generally believe entails using the current self as an anchor from which one that others’ are more willing than themselves to engage adjusts to accommodate simultaneously diVerences in an embarrassing performance (the horizontal solid between situations and between the self and others (Epley arrow in Fig. 1). et al., 2004; Nickerson, 1999, 2001). 140 L. Van Boven et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141

By contrast, our model and the results of our experi- Epley, N., Keysar, B., Van Boven, L., & Gilovich, T. (2004). Perspective ments suggest that emotional perspective taking entails taking as egocentric anchoring and adjustment. Journal of Person- two distinct judgments, one of which is a prediction of ality and , 87, 312–326. V Fox, E., Russo, R., & Bowles, R. (2001). Do threatening stimuli draw or how the self would react to being in a di erent emo- hold visual attention in subclinical anxiety?. Journal of Experimen- tional situation. These two processes do not exhaust tal Psychology: General, 130, 681–700. the possible perspective taking processes, are not inher- Fox, E., Russo, R., & Dutton, K. (2002). Attentional bias for threat: ently inconsistent, and may vary in their relative inXu- Evidence for delayed disengagement from emotional faces. Cogni- ence across perspective taking contexts. It may be, for tion and Emotion, 16, 355–379. Gilbert, D. T., & Mallone, P. S. (1995). The correspondence bias. Psy- example, that when perspective taking across emo- chological Bulletin, 117, 21–38. tional situations, using self-predictions as a basis for Gilovich, T. (1990). DiVerential construal and the false consensus predicting others is intuitively more appealing—and eVect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 59, 623–634. may even be automatic (Hodges & Wegner, 1997)— Gilovich, T., Kerr, M., & Medvec, V. H. (1993). EVect of temporal per- W than when perspective taking across non-emotional spective on subjective con dence. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64, 552–560. situations. Gilovich, T., & Medvec, V. H. (1995). The experience of regret: What, In conclusion, our Wndings provide support for a recent when, and why. Psychological Review, 102, 379–395. assertion that underestimating fear of embarrassment is a Goethals, G. R., Messick, D. M., & Allison, S. T. (1991). The unique- major cause of biased and erroneous social judgment ness bias: Studies of constructive social comparison. In J. Suls & T. (Sabini et al., 2001). More generally, to the extent that peo- A. Will (Eds.), Social comparison: Contemporary theory and research (pp. 149–176). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. ple underestimate the impact of transient emotions on the GriYn, D. W., & Ross, L. (1991). Subjective construal, social inference, self, others’ emotionally induced behaviors may be misin- and human misunderstanding. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in terpreted as stemming from enduring dispositions (Gilbert experimental social psychology (Vol. 24, pp. 319–359). San Diego: & Mallone, 1995; Jones, 1990; Ross, 1977). We believe Academic Press. that people’s underestimation of the power of emotion is a Heider, F. (1958). The psychology of interpersonal relations. New York: Wiley. fundamental error in social judgment. Herold, E. S. (1981). Contraceptive embarrassment and contraceptive behavior among young single women. Journal of Youth and Adoles- cence, 10, 233–242. Hodges, S., & Wegner, D. (1997). Automatic and controlled empathy. References In W. J. Ickes (Ed.), Empathic accuracy (pp. 311–339). New York, NY: The Guilford Press. Baron, R. M., & Kenny, D. A. (1986). The moderator-mediator vari- Ichheiser, D. (1946). Projection and another form of false social per- able distinction in social psychological research: Conceptual, stra- ception. American Psychologist, 1, 258. tegic, and statistical considerations. Journal of Personality and Jones, E. E. (1990). Interpersonal . New York: W.H. Freeman. Social Psychology, 51, 1173–1182. Katz, C., & Allport, F. (1938). Students’ attitudes. Syracuse, NY: Basso, M. R., ScheVt, B. K., Ris, M. D., & Dember, W. N. (1996). Mood Craftsman Press. and global-local visual processing. Journal of the International Neu- Keysar, B., & Barr, D. J. (2002). Self-anchoring in conversation: Why ropsychological Society, 2, 249–255. language users don’t do what they should. In T. Gilovich, D. Campbell, J. D. (1986). Similarity and uniqueness: The eVects of attri- GriYn, & D. Kahneman (Eds.), Heuristics and biases: The psychol- bute type, relevance, and individual diVerences in self-esteem and ogy of intuitive judgment (pp. 150–166). Cambridge: Cambridge depression. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 50, 281– University Press. 294. Kleck, R. E., Vaughan, R. C., Cartwright-Smith, J., Vaughan, K. B., Chambers, J. R., Windschitl, P. D., & Suls, J. (2003). Egocentrism, event Colby, C. Z., & Lanzetta, J. T. (1976). EVects of being observed on frequency, and comparative optimism: When what happens fre- expressive, subjective, and physiological response to painful stimuli. quently is more likely to happen to me. Personality and Social Psy- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 34, 1211–1218. chology Bulletin, 29, 1343–1356. Kraut, R. E. (1982). Social presence, facial feedback, and emotion. Cohen, J., & Cohen, P. (1983). Applied multiple regression/correlation Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 42, 853–863. analysis for the behavioral sciences (2nd ed.). Hillsdale, NJ: Law- Krueger, J. (1998). On the perception of social consensus. In M. Zanna rence Erlbaum. (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 30, pp. 163– Derryberry, D. (1993). Attentional consequences of outcome-related 240). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. motivational states: Congruent, incongruent, and focusing eVects. Krueger, J., & Clement, R. W. (1994). The truly false consensus eVect: Motivation and Emotion, 17, 65–89. An ineradicable and in social perception. Journal of Derryberry, D., & Reed, M. A. (1998). Anxiety and attentional focus- Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 596–610. ing: Trait, state, and hemispheric inXuences. Personality and Indi- Kruger, J., & Burrus, J. (2003). Egocentrism and focalism in unrealistic vidual DiVerences, 25, 745–761. optimism (and pessimism). Journal of Experimental Social Psychol- Dunning, D., & Cohen, G. L. (1992). Egocentric deWnitions of traits ogy, 40, 332–340. and abilities in social judgment. Journal of Personality Social Psy- Lanzetta, J. T., Cartwright-Smith, J., & Kleck, R. E. (1976). EVects of chology, 63, 341–355. nonverbal dissimulation on emotional experience and autonomic Dunning, D., & Hayes, A. F. (1996). Evidence for egocentric compari- arousal. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 33, 354–370. son in social judgment. Journal of Personality Social Psychology, Latané, B., & Darley, J. M. (1970). The unresponsive bystander: Why 71, 213–229. doesn’t he help? Englewood CliVs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Epley, N., & Dunning, D. (2000). Feeling holier than thou: Are self- Leary, M. R., & Dobbins, S. E. (1983). Social anxiety, sexual behavior, serving assessments produced by errors in self- or social prediction? and contraceptive use. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol- Journal of Personality Social Psychology, 79, 861–875. ogy, 45, 1347–1354. L. Van Boven et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 96 (2005) 130–141 141

Loewenstein, G. (1999). A visceral account of addiction. In J. Elster & Schkade, D. A., & Kahneman, D. (1998). Does living in california make O. J. Skog (Eds.), Getting hooked: Rationality and addiction. Cam- people happy? A focusing illusion in judgments of life satisfaction. bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Psychological Science, 9, 340–346. Loewenstein, G., & Adler, D. (1995). A bias in the prediction of tastes. Schwarz, N., & Vaughn, L. A. (2002). The revis- The Economic Journal, 105, 929–937. ited: Ease of and content of recall as distinct sources of infor- Loewenstein, G., O’Donoghue, T., & Rabin, M. (2003). Projection bias mation. In T. Gilovich, D. GriYn, & D. Kahneman (Eds.), in predicting future utility. Quarterly Journal of Economics(118), Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment (pp. 103– 1209–1248. 119). New York: Cambridge University Press. McFarland, C., & Miller, D. T. (1990). Judgments of self-other similar- Sherif, M., & Hovland, D. (1961). Social judgment: Assimilation and ity: Just like other people, only more so. Personality and Social Psy- contrast eVects in communication and attitude change. New Haven, chology Bulletin, 16, 475–484. CT: Yale University Press. Miller, D. T., & McFarland, C. (1987). Pluralistic ignorance: When Snyder, C. R., & Fromkin, H. L. (1977). Abnormality as a positive char- similarity is interpreted as dissimilarity. Journal of Personality and acteristic: The development and validation of a scale measuring Social Psychology, 53, 298–305. need for uniqueness. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 86, 518–527. Miller, R. S. (1992). The nature and severity of self-reported embarrass- Sobel, M. E. (1982). Asymptotic conWdence intervals for indirect eVects ing circumstances. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 18, of structural models. In S. Leinhardt (Ed.), Sociological methodol- 190–198. ogy (pp. 290–312). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Miller, R. S., & Leary, M. R. (1992). Social sources and interactive Suls, J., & Wan, C. K. (1987). In search of the false consensus phenom- functions of emotion: The case of embarrassment. In M. S. Clark enon: Fear and estimates of social consensus. Journal of Personality (Ed.), Review of personality and social psychology (Vol. 14, pp. 202– and Social Psychology, 52, 211–217. 221). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Taylor, S. E. (1982). The availability bias in social perception and inter- Monin, B., & Norton, M. I. (2003). of Xuid consensus: action. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgment Uniqueness bias, false consensus, false polarization, and pluralistic and uncertainty: Heuristics and biases (pp. 190–200). Cambridge, ignorance in a water conservation crisis. Personality and Social Psy- UK: Cambridge University Press. chology Bulletin, 29, 559–567. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judg- Moore, D. A., & Kim, T. G. (2003). Myopic social prediction and the ing frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5, 207–232. solo comparison eVect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol- Van Boven, L. (2000). Pluralistic ignorance and political correctness: ogy, 85, 1121–1135. The case of aYrmative action. Political Psychology, 21, 267–276. Nickerson, R. S. (1999). How we know—and sometimes misjudge— Van Boven, L., Dunning, D., & Loewenstein, G. (2000). Egocentric what others know: Imputing one’s own knowledge to others. Psy- empathy gaps between owners and buyers: Misperceptions of the chological Bulletin, 125, 737–759. endowment eVect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, Nickerson, R. S. (2001). The projective way of knowing: A useful heu- 66–76. ristic that sometimes misleads. Current Directions in Psychological Van Boven, L., & Loewenstein, G. (2003). of transient Science, 10, 168–172. drive states. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 29, 1159– Prentice, D. A., & Miller, D. T. (1993). Pluralistic ignorance and alco- 1168. hol use on campus: Some consequences of misperceiving the social Van Boven, L., & Loewenstein, G. (in press-a). Cross-situational pro- norm. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64, 243–256. jection. In M. D. Alicke, D. Dunning, & J. Krueger (Eds.), The self Prentice, D. A., & Miller, D. T. (1996). Pluralistic ignorance and the in social perception. Psychology Press. perpetuation of social norms by unwitting actors. In M. Zanna Van Boven, L., & Loewenstein, G. (in press-b). Empathy gaps in aVec- (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 28, pp. 161– tive perspective taking. In B. Malle & S. Hodges (Eds.), Other minds. 209). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Guilford Press. Ross, L. (1977). The intuitive psychologist and his shortcomings: Dis- Van Boven, L., Loewenstein, G., & Dunning, D. (2003). Mispredicting tortions in the process. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances the endowment eVect: Underestimation of owners’ selling prices in experimental social psychology (Vol. 10, pp. 174–221). New York: buy buyer’s agents. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, Academic Press. 51, 351–365. Ross, L., Greene, D., & House, P. (1977). The false-consensus eVect: An Van Boven, L., Loewenstein, G., Dunning, D., & Welch, N. (2004). The egocentric bias in social perception and attribution processes. Jour- illusion of courage: Underestimating the impact of fear of embar- nal of Experimental Social Psychology, 13, 279–301. rassment on the self. Unpublished manuscript, University of Colo- Ross, L., & Ward, A. (1995). Psychological barriers to dispute resolu- rado, Boulder. tion. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychol- Vorauer, J. D., & Ratner, R. K. (1996). Who’s going to make the Wrst ogy (Vol. 27, pp. 255–304). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. move. Pluralistic ignorance as an impediment to relationship for- Sabini, J., Cosmas, K., Siepmann, M., & Stein, J. (1999). Underesti- mation. Journal of Social and Personal Relationships, 13, 483– mates and truly false consensus eVects in estimates of embarrass- 506. ment and other emotions. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 21, Wilson, T. D., Wheatley, T., Meyers, J. M., Gilbert, D. T., & Axsom, 233–241. D. (2000). Focalism: A source of the durabiltiy bias in aVective Sabini, J., Seipmann, M., & Stein, J. (2001). The really fundamental forecasting. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, attribution error in social psychological research. Psychological 821–836. Inquiry, 12, 1–15. Windschitl, P. D., Krueger, J., & Simms, E. N. (2003). The inXuence of Savitsky, K., Epley, N., & Gilovich, T. (2001). Is it as bad as we think? egocentrism and focalism on people’s optimism in competitions: Overestimating the impact of our failures, shortcomings, and mis- When what aVects us equally aVects me more. Journal of Personal- haps. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 44–56. ity and Social Psychology, 85, 389–408.