<<

i praksis The objectivity of subjectivity A note on Kant and modern

By Bente Larsen

n Aesthetic Theory, TheodorW . Adorno writes: lows for the thing-in-itself to rest, opening not only for I the importance of the object of the art object, but Kant was the first to achieve the insight, never since also for the importance and relevance of autonomy in re- forgotten, that aesthetic comportment is free from lation to in particular. An expression of this is immediate desire; he snatched art away from that the Kantian emphasis on the aesthetic as not avaricious philistinism that always wants to touch being dependent on a beautiful object: “Only one kind it and it. (Adorno 1997, 10) of ugliness cannot be represented in a way adequate to nature without destroying all aesthetic satisfaction, hence in art, namely, that which arouses loathing” (de What the citation reflects is how Adorno share with Kant Duve 2010, 263). According to de Duve, this opens for a rejection of art as ‘agreeable’, that is, objects designed a discussion of Kant’s aesthetic judgement as including a with a view to producing the sensation of pleasure in the relation between pleasure and displeasure, or a relation spectator. Unlike the ‘agreeable art’ a work of fine art, ac- between beauty and ugliness. An important claim made cording to Kant, is produced to form not only pleasure by de Duve is that, psychologically speaking, pleasure is but also reflection, or modes of cognition, a free play of definitely a positive feeling to Kant, at the same time as he the cognitive faculties of imagination and understanding emphasizes that displeasure or negative pleasure also that is determined by an object with no external end or means. In relation to this, Adorno (1997, 510) emphasizes that Kant’s third Critique – the Critique of the Power of ... is a positive sensation, in the sense that it is po- Judgment (1790) – most compellingly expresses the dilem- sitively a sensation rather than the cancellation of ma of , which “appears immanently in the fact sensation it would be if negative pleasure had been that it can be constituted neither from above nor from a mere contradiction in terms … If the positiveness below, neither from concepts nor from aconceptual ex- of negative pleasure is read into the Analytic, as I perience.” These aporetic aspects of the thirdCritique are am convinced, then to say that ugliness negates the singled out for praise in Aesthetic Theory, where Adorno of the faculties is not enough; ugliness (1997, 163) states that “Kant envisioned a subjectively positively generates the conflict of the faculties. (de

mediated but objective aesthetics.” Duve 2010, 266) It is in line with this, that Ross Wilson (2008, 66) in an article on Adorno’s Kantian Rettung argues, that instead Seeing in Kant’s text a negativity or a pain, and empha- of defining Kant’s philosophy as subjectivist, “Kant’s in- sizing the need to have it brought to the surface de Duve tention is better characterized by its attempt to rescue or introduces the word ‘empathy’ as the gesture of willingness salvage objectivity by way of the subject.” to share someone else’s pain: “Pain, not pleasure, is the This is convincingly argued for in Thierry de Duve’s only sure sign indicating that all human beings must be essay on Kant and modern art “Resisting Adorno, endowed with sensus communis” (de Duve 2010, 271). Revamping Kant” (2010). In this essay, de Duve claims In opening up empathy as sensus communis de Duve that in contradistinction to Hegel, Kant’s aesthetics al- also opens up the relevance of Kant’s Critique in relation 68 Artikkel samtale & kritikk spalter brev

Illustrasjon av Åshild Aurlien

to what Adorno would call authentic modern art in which nature is beautiful”. And in Kant after Duchamp de Duve the beauty and harmony of classical art is emphatically ab- (1999) observes Duchamp to be a modernist artist making sent. In his emphasis on the Kantian critique not being de- the logic of modernist art practice into the subject matter pended on a beautiful object, de Duve introduces pathos of his work, formulating a replacement of a shift in aes- as the aesthetic bond that unites the human species and to thetic judgment from the classical “this is beautiful” with which modern art, in its rejection of beauty and harmony, “this is art” replacing the word “beauty” by the word “art”. opens. Essential here is also Adorno’s claim that expression in modernity is scarcely to be conceived except as the ex- LITERATURE Adorno, TheodorW . 1997. Aesthetic Theory. Translated by Robert pression of suffering.I t is thus in accordance with Adorno Hullot-Kentor. London: Althlone. that de Duve (2010, 271) claims pain to be central as an de Duve, Thierry. 1999. Kant after Duchamp. Massachusetts: MIT active and positive force of negation making pleasure diffi- Press. de Duve, Thierry. 2010. “Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant”. In Art cult or impossible.This forms the background to deD uve’s and Aesthetics After Adorno, edited by J.M. Bernstein (et al.). claim (2010, 290) that Kant transferred the beautiful in berkeley: University of California Press. nature to the domain of art, replacing the pure aesthetic Wilson, Ross. 2008. “Dialectical Aesthetics and the Kantian Rettung: judgement being “This artifact is art” with “This fruit of on Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory”, New German Critique, No. 104, Adornos Aesthetics: 55-69.

69