Cooperation in Conflict Games

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Cooperation in Conflict Games Cooperation in Con‡ict Games Sandeep Baliga and Tomas Sjöström MEDS and Rutgers December 2007 Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 1 / 17 Stag Hunt: aggression feeds on itself and escalates con‡ict (actions are strategic complements). Chicken: toughness deters aggression (actions are strategic substitutes) “World War I was an unwanted spiral of hostility”...“World War II was not an unwanted spiral of hostility-it was a failure to deter Hitler’splanned aggression.”(Joseph Nye (2007)). Stag hunt and chicken have multiple Nash equilibria. Jervis (spiral model), Schelling (reciprocal fear of surprise attack): mutual fear and uncertainty determine the outcome. Introduction In international relations, Stag Hunt, Chicken and Prisoners’Dilemma represent canonical strategic interactions. Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 2 / 17 Chicken: toughness deters aggression (actions are strategic substitutes) “World War I was an unwanted spiral of hostility”...“World War II was not an unwanted spiral of hostility-it was a failure to deter Hitler’splanned aggression.”(Joseph Nye (2007)). Stag hunt and chicken have multiple Nash equilibria. Jervis (spiral model), Schelling (reciprocal fear of surprise attack): mutual fear and uncertainty determine the outcome. Introduction In international relations, Stag Hunt, Chicken and Prisoners’Dilemma represent canonical strategic interactions. Stag Hunt: aggression feeds on itself and escalates con‡ict (actions are strategic complements). Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 2 / 17 “World War I was an unwanted spiral of hostility”...“World War II was not an unwanted spiral of hostility-it was a failure to deter Hitler’splanned aggression.”(Joseph Nye (2007)). Stag hunt and chicken have multiple Nash equilibria. Jervis (spiral model), Schelling (reciprocal fear of surprise attack): mutual fear and uncertainty determine the outcome. Introduction In international relations, Stag Hunt, Chicken and Prisoners’Dilemma represent canonical strategic interactions. Stag Hunt: aggression feeds on itself and escalates con‡ict (actions are strategic complements). Chicken: toughness deters aggression (actions are strategic substitutes) Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 2 / 17 Stag hunt and chicken have multiple Nash equilibria. Jervis (spiral model), Schelling (reciprocal fear of surprise attack): mutual fear and uncertainty determine the outcome. Introduction In international relations, Stag Hunt, Chicken and Prisoners’Dilemma represent canonical strategic interactions. Stag Hunt: aggression feeds on itself and escalates con‡ict (actions are strategic complements). Chicken: toughness deters aggression (actions are strategic substitutes) “World War I was an unwanted spiral of hostility”...“World War II was not an unwanted spiral of hostility-it was a failure to deter Hitler’splanned aggression.”(Joseph Nye (2007)). Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 2 / 17 Introduction In international relations, Stag Hunt, Chicken and Prisoners’Dilemma represent canonical strategic interactions. Stag Hunt: aggression feeds on itself and escalates con‡ict (actions are strategic complements). Chicken: toughness deters aggression (actions are strategic substitutes) “World War I was an unwanted spiral of hostility”...“World War II was not an unwanted spiral of hostility-it was a failure to deter Hitler’splanned aggression.”(Joseph Nye (2007)). Stag hunt and chicken have multiple Nash equilibria. Jervis (spiral model), Schelling (reciprocal fear of surprise attack): mutual fear and uncertainty determine the outcome. Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 2 / 17 Correlation: Con‡ict concerns ownership of some resource and payo¤s are correlated. Enough private information (about preferences or costs) selects a unique equilibrium. (Unlike global games, no need to assume highly correlated private information.) Are long-run relationships more peaceful? Is democracy good for peace? (Other issues: communication? mediation? signalling?) Private Information Independence: Leaders preferences for con‡ict are independent and unrelated. Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 3 / 17 Enough private information (about preferences or costs) selects a unique equilibrium. (Unlike global games, no need to assume highly correlated private information.) Are long-run relationships more peaceful? Is democracy good for peace? (Other issues: communication? mediation? signalling?) Private Information Independence: Leaders preferences for con‡ict are independent and unrelated. Correlation: Con‡ict concerns ownership of some resource and payo¤s are correlated. Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 3 / 17 Are long-run relationships more peaceful? Is democracy good for peace? (Other issues: communication? mediation? signalling?) Private Information Independence: Leaders preferences for con‡ict are independent and unrelated. Correlation: Con‡ict concerns ownership of some resource and payo¤s are correlated. Enough private information (about preferences or costs) selects a unique equilibrium. (Unlike global games, no need to assume highly correlated private information.) Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 3 / 17 Private Information Independence: Leaders preferences for con‡ict are independent and unrelated. Correlation: Con‡ict concerns ownership of some resource and payo¤s are correlated. Enough private information (about preferences or costs) selects a unique equilibrium. (Unlike global games, no need to assume highly correlated private information.) Are long-run relationships more peaceful? Is democracy good for peace? (Other issues: communication? mediation? signalling?) Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 3 / 17 The one-shot game Payo¤s for player i (row-chooser) HD H hi c hi (1) D d 0 Strategic complements (Stag Hunt): (0 <) c < d. Strategic substitutes (Chicken): c > d (> 0). We allow hi to be negative or positive (more soon). Player i’s hostility type hi is made up of a known publicly known component ki and a private idiosyncratic component η [η, η¯ ]. So, i 2 hi = ki + η . Distribution of η conditional on η = y is F ( y). i j i j Assumption 1. (i) F1(x y) > 0 (ii) F2(x y) 0 (a more hostile player i is more pessimistic aboutj j’shostility). j Notice this allows for both independent and positively correlated types. Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 4 / 17 Unique equilibrium (h˜i , h˜j ) is interior: h˜i + (d c) 1 F (h˜j kj h˜i ki ) = 0 j Strategic Complements Strategic complements: H more appealing if the opponent is expected to choose H (c < d) Player i is a dominant strategy hawk if hi 0. Player i is a dominant strategy dove if hi c d or hi c d. In between, we have coordination types. Theorem Suppose both players have dominant strategy hawks and doves. If d > c 1 and F1(s t) + F2(s t) < d c then the game has a unique BNE. This BNE is in cut-o¤j strategies.j Independence: “Large idiosyncratic uncertainty” implies uniqueness. This is our formalization of Schelling’s“reciprocal fear of surprise attack”. Positive correlation helps uniqueness here. Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 4 / 17 Strategic Complements Strategic complements: H more appealing if the opponent is expected to choose H (c < d) Player i is a dominant strategy hawk if hi 0. Player i is a dominant strategy dove if hi c d or hi c d. In between, we have coordination types. Theorem Suppose both players have dominant strategy hawks and doves. If d > c 1 and F1(s t) + F2(s t) < d c then the game has a unique BNE. This BNE is in cut-o¤j strategies.j Independence: “Large idiosyncratic uncertainty” implies uniqueness. This is our formalization of Schelling’s“reciprocal fear of surprise attack”. Positive correlation helps uniqueness here. Unique equilibrium (h˜i , h˜j ) is interior: h˜i + (d c) 1 F (h˜j kj h˜i ki ) = 0 j Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 4 / 17 Player i’snet gain from choosing H instead of D when his type is hi = y is i Ψ (x, y) y + (d c) (1 F (x kj y ki )) . (2) j For a cuto¤ strategy to be a best response, player i should be more inclined to choose H the more hostile he is: i Ψ (x, y) = 1 (d c)F2(x kj y ki ) > 0 (3) 2 j In view of Assumption 1, (3) holds if d > c. (It also holds if d < c and types are not too strongly correlated.) If condition (3) holds then player i’sbest response to player j’scuto¤ x is to use a cuto¤ point denoted βi (x). If player j uses a “cuto¤ strategy” with cuto¤ hostility type hj = x, then for player i with hostility type hi = y, the probability player j plays D is δj (y) = F (x kj y ki ) j Baliga and Sjöström (MEDS and Rutgers) Cooperation in Con‡ict Games 12/07 5 / 17 For a cuto¤ strategy to be a best response, player i should be more inclined to choose H the more hostile he is: i Ψ (x, y) = 1 (d c)F2(x kj y ki ) > 0 (3) 2 j In view of Assumption 1, (3) holds if d > c. (It also holds if d < c and types are not too strongly correlated.) If condition (3) holds then player i’sbest response to player j’scuto¤ x is to use a cuto¤ point denoted βi (x). If player j uses a “cuto¤ strategy” with cuto¤ hostility type hj = x, then for player i with hostility type hi = y, the probability player j plays D is δj (y) = F (x kj y ki ) j Player i’snet gain from choosing H instead of D when his type is hi = y is i Ψ (x, y) y + (d c) (1 F (x kj y ki )) .
Recommended publications
  • The Determinants of Efficient Behavior in Coordination Games
    The Determinants of Efficient Behavior in Coordination Games Pedro Dal B´o Guillaume R. Fr´echette Jeongbin Kim* Brown University & NBER New York University Caltech May 20, 2020 Abstract We study the determinants of efficient behavior in stag hunt games (2x2 symmetric coordination games with Pareto ranked equilibria) using both data from eight previous experiments on stag hunt games and data from a new experiment which allows for a more systematic variation of parameters. In line with the previous experimental literature, we find that subjects do not necessarily play the efficient action (stag). While the rate of stag is greater when stag is risk dominant, we find that the equilibrium selection criterion of risk dominance is neither a necessary nor sufficient condition for a majority of subjects to choose the efficient action. We do find that an increase in the size of the basin of attraction of stag results in an increase in efficient behavior. We show that the results are robust to controlling for risk preferences. JEL codes: C9, D7. Keywords: Coordination games, strategic uncertainty, equilibrium selection. *We thank all the authors who made available the data that we use from previous articles, Hui Wen Ng for her assistance running experiments and Anna Aizer for useful comments. 1 1 Introduction The study of coordination games has a long history as many situations of interest present a coordination component: for example, the choice of technologies that require a threshold number of users to be sustainable, currency attacks, bank runs, asset price bubbles, cooper- ation in repeated games, etc. In such examples, agents may face strategic uncertainty; that is, they may be uncertain about how the other agents will respond to the multiplicity of equilibria, even when they have complete information about the environment.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 4 Rationalizability & Nash Equilibrium Road
    Lecture 4 Rationalizability & Nash Equilibrium 14.12 Game Theory Muhamet Yildiz Road Map 1. Strategies – completed 2. Quiz 3. Dominance 4. Dominant-strategy equilibrium 5. Rationalizability 6. Nash Equilibrium 1 Strategy A strategy of a player is a complete contingent-plan, determining which action he will take at each information set he is to move (including the information sets that will not be reached according to this strategy). Matching pennies with perfect information 2’s Strategies: HH = Head if 1 plays Head, 1 Head if 1 plays Tail; HT = Head if 1 plays Head, Head Tail Tail if 1 plays Tail; 2 TH = Tail if 1 plays Head, 2 Head if 1 plays Tail; head tail head tail TT = Tail if 1 plays Head, Tail if 1 plays Tail. (-1,1) (1,-1) (1,-1) (-1,1) 2 Matching pennies with perfect information 2 1 HH HT TH TT Head Tail Matching pennies with Imperfect information 1 2 1 Head Tail Head Tail 2 Head (-1,1) (1,-1) head tail head tail Tail (1,-1) (-1,1) (-1,1) (1,-1) (1,-1) (-1,1) 3 A game with nature Left (5, 0) 1 Head 1/2 Right (2, 2) Nature (3, 3) 1/2 Left Tail 2 Right (0, -5) Mixed Strategy Definition: A mixed strategy of a player is a probability distribution over the set of his strategies. Pure strategies: Si = {si1,si2,…,sik} σ → A mixed strategy: i: S [0,1] s.t. σ σ σ i(si1) + i(si2) + … + i(sik) = 1. If the other players play s-i =(s1,…, si-1,si+1,…,sn), then σ the expected utility of playing i is σ σ σ i(si1)ui(si1,s-i) + i(si2)ui(si2,s-i) + … + i(sik)ui(sik,s-i).
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture Notes
    GRADUATE GAME THEORY LECTURE NOTES BY OMER TAMUZ California Institute of Technology 2018 Acknowledgments These lecture notes are partially adapted from Osborne and Rubinstein [29], Maschler, Solan and Zamir [23], lecture notes by Federico Echenique, and slides by Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar. I am indebted to Seo Young (Silvia) Kim and Zhuofang Li for their help in finding and correcting many errors. Any comments or suggestions are welcome. 2 Contents 1 Extensive form games with perfect information 7 1.1 Tic-Tac-Toe ........................................ 7 1.2 The Sweet Fifteen Game ................................ 7 1.3 Chess ............................................ 7 1.4 Definition of extensive form games with perfect information ........... 10 1.5 The ultimatum game .................................. 10 1.6 Equilibria ......................................... 11 1.7 The centipede game ................................... 11 1.8 Subgames and subgame perfect equilibria ...................... 13 1.9 The dollar auction .................................... 14 1.10 Backward induction, Kuhn’s Theorem and a proof of Zermelo’s Theorem ... 15 2 Strategic form games 17 2.1 Definition ......................................... 17 2.2 Nash equilibria ...................................... 17 2.3 Classical examples .................................... 17 2.4 Dominated strategies .................................. 22 2.5 Repeated elimination of dominated strategies ................... 22 2.6 Dominant strategies ..................................
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Game Theory Lecture 1: Strategic Game and Nash Equilibrium
    Game Theory and Rational Choice Strategic-form Games Nash Equilibrium Examples (Non-)Strict Nash Equilibrium . Introduction to Game Theory Lecture 1: Strategic Game and Nash Equilibrium . Haifeng Huang University of California, Merced Shanghai, Summer 2011 . • Rational choice: the action chosen by a decision maker is better or at least as good as every other available action, according to her preferences and given her constraints (e.g., resources, information, etc.). • Preferences (偏好) are rational if they satisfy . Completeness (完备性): between any x and y in a set, x ≻ y (x is preferred to y), y ≻ x, or x ∼ y (indifferent) . Transitivity(传递性): x ≽ y and y ≽ z )x ≽ z (≽ means ≻ or ∼) ) Say apple ≻ banana, and banana ≻ orange, then apple ≻ orange Game Theory and Rational Choice Strategic-form Games Nash Equilibrium Examples (Non-)Strict Nash Equilibrium Rational Choice and Preference Relations • Game theory studies rational players’ behavior when they engage in strategic interactions. • Preferences (偏好) are rational if they satisfy . Completeness (完备性): between any x and y in a set, x ≻ y (x is preferred to y), y ≻ x, or x ∼ y (indifferent) . Transitivity(传递性): x ≽ y and y ≽ z )x ≽ z (≽ means ≻ or ∼) ) Say apple ≻ banana, and banana ≻ orange, then apple ≻ orange Game Theory and Rational Choice Strategic-form Games Nash Equilibrium Examples (Non-)Strict Nash Equilibrium Rational Choice and Preference Relations • Game theory studies rational players’ behavior when they engage in strategic interactions. • Rational choice: the action chosen by a decision maker is better or at least as good as every other available action, according to her preferences and given her constraints (e.g., resources, information, etc.).
    [Show full text]
  • The Conservation Game ⇑ Mark Colyvan A, , James Justus A,B, Helen M
    Biological Conservation 144 (2011) 1246–1253 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Biological Conservation journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/biocon Special Issue Article: Adaptive management for biodiversity conservation in an uncertain world The conservation game ⇑ Mark Colyvan a, , James Justus a,b, Helen M. Regan c a Sydney Centre for the Foundations of Science, University of Sydney, Sydney, NSW 2006, Australia b Department of Philosophy, Florida State University, Tallahassee, FL 32306, USA c Department of Biology, University of California Riverside, Riverside, CA 92521, USA article info abstract Article history: Conservation problems typically involve groups with competing objectives and strategies. Taking effec- Received 16 December 2009 tive conservation action requires identifying dependencies between competing strategies and determin- Received in revised form 20 September 2010 ing which action optimally achieves the appropriate conservation goals given those dependencies. We Accepted 7 October 2010 show how several real-world conservation problems can be modeled game-theoretically. Three types Available online 26 February 2011 of problems drive our analysis: multi-national conservation cooperation, management of common-pool resources, and games against nature. By revealing the underlying structure of these and other problems, Keywords: game-theoretic models suggest potential solutions that are often invisible to the usual management pro- Game theory tocol: decision followed by monitoring, feedback and revised decisions. The kind of adaptive manage- Adaptive management Stag hunt ment provided by the game-theoretic approach therefore complements existing adaptive management Tragedy of the commons methodologies. Games against nature Ó 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Common-pool resource management Multi-national cooperation Conservation management Resource management Prisoners’ dilemma 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Game Theory Model and Empirical Evidence
    UC Irvine UC Irvine Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Cheap Talk, Trust, and Cooperation in Networked Global Software Engineering: Game Theory Model and Empirical Evidence Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/99z4314v Author Wang, Yi Publication Date 2015 License https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ 4.0 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, IRVINE Cheap Talk, Trust, and Cooperation in Networked Global Software Engineering: Game Theory Model and Empirical Evidence DISSERTATION submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in Information and Computer Science by Yi Wang Dissertation Committee: Professor David F. Redmiles, Chair Professor Debra J. Richardson Professor Brian Skyrms 2015 Portion of Chapter 4 c 2013 IEEE. All other materials c 2015 Yi Wang DEDICATION To Natural & Intellectual Beauty ii TABLE OF CONTENTS Page LIST OF FIGURES vii LIST OF TABLES ix LIST OF ALGORITHMS x ACKNOWLEDGMENTS xi CURRICULUM VITAE xiii ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION xvi 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Motivating Observations . 3 1.1.1 Empirical Observations . 3 1.1.2 Summary . 6 1.2 Dissertation Outline . 7 1.2.1 Overview of Each Chapter . 7 1.2.2 How to Read This Dissertation . 9 2 Research Overview and Approach 10 2.1 Overall Research Questions . 10 2.2 Research Approach . 11 2.3 Overview of Potential Contributions . 12 3 Backgrounds 14 3.1 Related Work . 14 3.1.1 Trust in Globally Distributed Collaboration . 14 3.1.2 Informal, Non-work-related Communication in SE and CSCW .
    [Show full text]
  • Zbwleibniz-Informationszentrum
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Chierchia, Gabriele; Tufano, Fabio; Coricelli, Giorgio Working Paper The differential impact of friendship on cooperative and competitive coordination CeDEx Discussion Paper Series, No. 2020-07 Provided in Cooperation with: The University of Nottingham, Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics (CeDEx) Suggested Citation: Chierchia, Gabriele; Tufano, Fabio; Coricelli, Giorgio (2020) : The differential impact of friendship on cooperative and competitive coordination, CeDEx Discussion Paper Series, No. 2020-07, The University of Nottingham, Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics (CeDEx), Nottingham This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/228371 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu Discussion Paper No.
    [Show full text]
  • Ui(Α) = −(Ni (Α) + Ni (Α) + Ni (Α)), R C B Where Ni (Α), Ni (Α), Ni (Α) Is the Number of Repetitions of Numbers in I’S Row, Column and Block Respec- Tively
    6.207/14.15: Networks Problem Set 4 Due: Friday, November 6, 2009 Problem 1. [Sudoku as a game of cooperation] In the popular game of Sudoku, the number placement puzzle, the objective is to fill a 9 × 9 grid so that each column, each row, and each of the nine 3 × 3 boxes (also called blocks or regions) contains the digits from 1 to 9 only one time each (see figure). The puzzle setter provides a partially completed grid and the puzzle solver is asked to fill in the missing numbers. Consider now a multi-agent extension of the Sudoku game, in which each of the 81 boxes is controlled by one agent. The agent’s action space is choosing a number from 1 to 9 to put in her box, i.e., Ai = f1, ··· , 9g, where Ai denotes the action space of agent i. Let a denote the vector of choices of the agents. Then, agent i’s utility is given by: R C B ui(a) = −(ni (a) + ni (a) + ni (a)), R C B where ni (a), ni (a), ni (a) is the number of repetitions of numbers in i’s row, column and block respec- tively. Show that the multi agent Sudoku game is a potential game and write down explicitly the associated potential function. Figure 1: Sudoku Problem 2. Consider the network formation game discussed in Lecture 12. (i) Find conditions for which the ring network, in which the agents form a circle (each one has two neighbors), is a pairwise stable equilibrium of the game.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Game Theory
    Publicly•available solutions for AN INTRODUCTION TO GAME THEORY Publicly•available solutions for AN INTRODUCTION TO GAME THEORY MARTIN J. OSBORNE University of Toronto Copyright © 2012 by Martin J. Osborne All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Martin J. Osborne. This manual was typeset by the author, who is greatly indebted to Donald Knuth (TEX), Leslie Lamport (LATEX), Diego Puga (mathpazo), Christian Schenk (MiKTEX), Ed Sznyter (ppctr), Timothy van Zandt (PSTricks), and others, for generously making superlative software freely available. The main font is 10pt Palatino. Version 6: 2012-4-7 Contents Preface xi 1 Introduction 1 Exercise 5.3 (Altruistic preferences) 1 Exercise 6.1 (Alternative representations of preferences) 1 2 Nash Equilibrium 3 Exercise 16.1 (Working on a joint project) 3 Exercise 17.1 (Games equivalent to the Prisoner’s Dilemma) 3 Exercise 20.1 (Games without conflict) 3 Exercise 31.1 (Extension of the Stag Hunt) 4 Exercise 34.1 (Guessing two-thirds of the average) 4 Exercise 34.3 (Choosing a route) 5 Exercise 37.1 (Finding Nash equilibria using best response functions) 6 Exercise 38.1 (Constructing best response functions) 6 Exercise 38.2 (Dividing money) 7 Exercise 41.1 (Strict and nonstrict Nash equilibria) 7 Exercise 47.1 (Strict equilibria and dominated actions) 8 Exercise 47.2 (Nash equilibrium and weakly dominated
    [Show full text]
  • The Evolution of Inefficiency in a Simulated Stag Hunt
    Behavior Research Methods, Instruments, & Computers 2001, 33 (2), 124-129 The evolution of inefficiency in a simulated stag hunt J. NEIL BEARDEN University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill, North Carolina We used genetic algorithms to evolve populations of reinforcement learning (Q-learning) agents to play a repeated two-player symmetric coordination game under different risk conditions and found that evolution steered our simulated populations to the Pareto inefficient equilibrium under high-risk conditions and to the Pareto efficient equilibrium under low-risk conditions. Greater degrees of for- giveness and temporal discounting of future returns emerged in populations playing the low-risk game. Results demonstrate the utility of simulation to evolutionary psychology. Traditional game theory assumes that players have have enough food for one day and the other will go hun- perfect rationality, which implicitly assumes that they gry. If both follow the rabbit, each will get only a small have infinite cognitivecapacity and, as a result, will play amount of food. Nash equilibria.Evolutionarygame theory (Smith, 1982) Clearly, it is in the players’ best interests to coordinate does not necessarily endow its players with these same their actions and wait for the deer; however, a player is capabilities; rather it uses various selection processes to guaranteed food by following the rabbit. Thus, the play- take populations of players to an equilibrium point over ers have a dilemma: Each must choose between potential the course of generations. Other
    [Show full text]
  • Construction of Subgame-Perfect Mixed-Strategy Equilibria in Repeated Games
    games Article Construction of Subgame-Perfect Mixed-Strategy Equilibria in Repeated Games Kimmo Berg 1,* ID and Gijs Schoenmakers 2 1 Department of Mathematics and Systems Analysis, Aalto University School of Science, P.O. Box 11100, FI-00076 Aalto, Finland 2 Department of Data Science and Knowledge Engineering, Maastricht University, P.O. Box 616, 6200MD Maastricht, The Netherlands; [email protected] * Correspondence: kimmo.berg@aalto.fi; Tel.: +358-40-7170-025 Received: 26 July 2017 ; Accepted: 18 October 2017 ; Published: 1 November 2017 Abstract: This paper examines how to construct subgame-perfect mixed-strategy equilibria in discounted repeated games with perfect monitoring. We introduce a relatively simple class of strategy profiles that are easy to compute and may give rise to a large set of equilibrium payoffs. These sets are called self-supporting sets, since the set itself provides the continuation payoffs that are required to support the equilibrium strategies. Moreover, the corresponding strategies are simple as the players face the same augmented game on each round but they play different mixed actions after each realized pure-action profile. We find that certain payoffs can be obtained in equilibrium with much lower discount factor values compared to pure strategies. The theory and the concepts are illustrated in 2 × 2 games. Keywords: repeated game; mixed strategy; subgame perfection; payoff set MSC: 91A20 JEL Classification: C73 1. Introduction This paper examines how mixed actions can be used in obtaining subgame-perfect equilibria in discounted repeated games. In repeated games, the set of subgame-perfect equilibria can be defined recursively: a strategy profile is an equilibrium if certain equilibrium payoffs are available as continuation payoffs, and these continuation payoffs may be generated by means of other equilibrium strategy profiles.
    [Show full text]
  • Game-Theoretic Learning
    Game-Theoretic Learning Amy Greenwald with David Gondek, Amir Jafari, and Casey Marks Brown University ICML Tutorial I July 4, 2004 Overview 1. Introduction to Game Theory 2. Regret Matching Learning Algorithms ◦ Regret Matching Learns Equilibria 3. Machine Learning Applications Introduction to Game Theory 1. General-Sum Games ◦ Nash Equilibrium ◦ Correlated Equilibrium 2. Zero-Sum Games ◦ Minimax Equilibrium Regret Matching Learning Algorithms 1. Regret Variations ◦ No Φ-Regret Learning ◦ External, Internal, and Swap Regret 2. Sufficient Conditions for No Φ-Regret Learning ◦ Blackwell’s Approachability Theorem ◦ Gordon’s Gradient Descent Theorem – Potential Function Argument 3. Expected and Observed Regret Matching Algorithms ◦ Polynomial and Exponential Potential Functions ◦ External, Internal, and Swap Regret 4. No Φ-Regret Learning Converges to Φ-Equilibria So Φ-Regret Matching Learns Φ-Equilibria Machine Learning Applications 1. Online Classification 2. Offline Boosting Game Theory and Economics ◦ Perfect Competition agents are price-takers ◦ Monopoly single entity commands all market power ◦ Game Theory payoffs in a game are jointly determined by the strategies of all players Knowledge, Rationality, and Equilibrium Assumption Players are rational: i.e., optimizing wrt their beliefs. Theorem Mutual knowledge of rationality and common knowledge of beliefs is sufficient for the deductive justification of Nash equilibrium. (Aumann and Brandenburger 95) Question Can learning provide an inductive justification for equilibrium? Dimensions of Game
    [Show full text]