Psychological Review

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Psychological Review Psychological Review The Dual Accumulator Model of Strategic Deliberation and Decision Making Russell Golman, Sudeep Bhatia, and Patrick Bodilly Kane Online First Publication, December 23, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/rev0000176 CITATION Golman, R., Bhatia, S., & Kane, P. B. (2019, December 23). The Dual Accumulator Model of Strategic Deliberation and Decision Making. Psychological Review. Advance online publication. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/rev0000176 Psychological Review © 2019 American Psychological Association 2019, Vol. 1, No. 999, 000 ISSN: 0033-295X http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/rev0000176 The Dual Accumulator Model of Strategic Deliberation and Decision Making Russell Golman Sudeep Bhatia Carnegie Mellon University University of Pennsylvania Patrick Bodilly Kane McGill University What are the mental operations involved in game theoretic decision making? How do players deliberate (intelligently, but perhaps imperfectly) about strategic interdependencies and ultimately decide on a strategy? We address these questions using an evidence accumulation model, with bidirectional connections between preferences for the strategies available to the decision maker and beliefs regarding the opponent’s choices. Our dual accumulator model accounts for a variety of behavioral patterns, including limited iterated reasoning, payoff sensitivity, consideration of risk- reward tradeoffs, and salient label effects, and it provides a good quantitative fit to existing behavioral data. In a comparison with other popular behavioral game theoretic models fit at the individual subject level to choices across a set of games, the dual accumulator model makes the most accurate out-of-sample predictions. Additionally, as a cognitive-process model, it can also be used to make predictions about response time patterns, time pressure effects, and attention during deliberation. Stochastic sampling and dynamic accumulation, cognitive mechanisms foundational to decision making, play a critical role in explaining well-known behavioral patterns as well as in generating novel predictions. Keywords: behavioral game theory, sequential sampling, preference accumulation, bidirectional processing, cognitive modeling Supplemental materials: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/rev0000176.supp Strategic decision making is an important feature of human dependent strategic settings—in which outcomes depend on the behavior. From cooperating on collaborative projects, to nego- choices of two or more decision makers—are ubiquitous in tiating agreements, to competing over limited resources, inter- everyday life. Game theory provides a mathematical framework with which decision making in strategic settings can be for- mally represented and analyzed (Hart, 1992; Luce & Raiffa, 1957; von Neumann & Morgenstern, 1944). It is an important area of research in economics, political science, biology, com- X Russell Golman, Department of Social and Decision Sciences, Car- puter science, philosophy, and psychology, where it is used to negie Mellon University; Sudeep Bhatia, Department of Psychology, Uni- describe the types of coordination, cooperation, and conflict versity of Pennsylvania; Patrick Bodilly Kane, Biomedical Ethics Unit, that can be observed in groups of decision makers. McGill University. Traditional game theory is concerned with studying the be- This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers. Russell Golman and Sudeep Bhatia developed the model, ran the sim- havior of idealized decision makers, who deliberate rationally This article is intended solely for the personal use ofulations the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly. generating predicted behavior across a variety of games, and wrote an initial draft of the article. Patrick Bodilly Kane performed the model and who find themselves in an equilibrium in which they can 1 fitting analysis and helped revise the article along with Russell Golman and form accurate expectations about each other’s choices. Not Sudeep Bhatia. We thank Sally Pan and Andrew Chang for superb research surprisingly, humans display pervasive and systematic depar- assistance. Earlier versions of this article were presented at the Foundations tures from rationality, which cannot be accounted for by the of Utility and Risk Conference, at meetings of the Society for Mathemat- traditional Nash equilibrium prediction or its various refine- ical Psychology and the Cognitive Science Society, and at the Network for Integrated Behavioral Sciences. Some of the results presented in this article have been published in the Proceedings of the 39th Annual Conference of 1 The traditional Nash equilibrium solution concept abstracts away from the Cognitive Science Society (2017). Funding for Sudeep Bhatia was any particular dynamical process that would presumably converge to it. received from the National Science Foundation Grant SES-1626825. The implicit assumption is that any reasonable process would converge to Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Rus- a Nash equilibrium. This is not so (see, e.g., Hofbauer & Sigmund, 2003), sell Golman, Department of Social and Decision Sciences, Carnegie and actually long-run behavior can be quite sensitive to initial conditions as Mellon University, 5000 Forbes Avenue, Pittsburgh, PA 15213. E-mail: well as the specific assumptions about the dynamics describing how [email protected] players adjust their strategies over time (Golman, 2011). 1 2 GOLMAN, BHATIA, AND KANE ments. This has led to the growth of behavioral game theory, maker’s preferences, and these emerging preferences in turn in- which acknowledges bounded rationality (see Camerer, 2003a, fluence beliefs about the opponent’s choices. Decision makers 2003b; Colman, 2003).2 build up a sense of how much they like their own strategies as well Models of limited iterated reasoning or error-prone reasoning as how much the opponent might like his, but need not form relax the traditional assumptions of perfect rationality and sophis- probabilistic beliefs. They each choose the strategy they like best tication to better predict the behavior of boundedly rational deci- (which is not necessarily a best response to what they believe the sion makers. According to these models, boundedly rational deci- opponent will choose). Still, as decision makers are able to repre- sion makers may have simplistic beliefs about the behavior of their sent an opponent’s actions, they can respond in an intelligent opponents (or partners), but retain the capability to intelligently manner to what they think the opponent might do and also revise choose strategies that maximize their own rewards given these these beliefs as they deliberate (Goodie, Doshi, & Young, 2012; simplistic beliefs, as with Level-k reasoning (Nagel, 1995; Stahl & Hedden & Zhang, 2002). Wilson, 1994, 1995) or cognitive hierarchy theory (Camerer, Ho, We show that our dual accumulator model predicts a variety of & Chong, 2004). Alternatively, they may have sophisticated be- behavioral patterns, including limited iterated reasoning, payoff liefs about their opponents, but occasionally err in their choices of sensitivity, and consideration of risk-reward tradeoffs (Capra, Go- strategies, as with quantal response equilibrium (McKelvey & eree, Gomez, & Holt, 1999; Crawford, Costa-Gomes, & Iriberri, Palfrey, 1995). Bringing both elements together, decision makers 2013; Goeree & Holt, 2001). Additionally, it provides a compel- may hold simplistic beliefs as well as make occasional mistakes, as ling, cognitively grounded account of the effects of strategy sa- with noisy introspection (Goeree & Holt, 1999, 2004). lience on strategic choice (Crawford, Gneezy, & Rottenstreich, Although these behavioral game theoretic models have been 2008; Hargreaves Heap, Rojo Arjona, & Sugden, 2014; Mehta, developed by relaxing one or more of the unrealistically strong Starmer, & Sugden, 1994). Existing behavioral game theory mod- assumptions of Nash equilibrium, they nonetheless require the els cannot account for all of these patterns (with a parsimonious, formation of probabilistic beliefs and the calculation of expected consistent specification across games), and some of these effects values. Decision makers often struggle with these tasks in simple lie entirely outside the scope of many of these models. Finally, we choice settings, suggesting that they may not be employing them in fit our dual accumulator model to individual subject-level data complex strategic settings either (Gigerenzer & Todd, 1999). In- (assuming that each individual has stable parameter values across deed, Agranov, Potamites, Schotter, and Tergiman (2012) find that games) using an existing, publicly available data set (Stahl & approximately half of subjects are unable to best respond to Wilson, 1995) and compare our model’s fit against Level-k rea- computer opponents known to be playing a uniform mixed strategy soning, cognitive hierarchy theory, logit quantal response equilib- in the p-beauty contest game. Our approach is to begin with rium, and (telescoping) noisy introspection. In a hold-one-out plausible cognitive mechanisms—the same cognitive mechanisms analysis, we find that the dual accumulator model makes the most commonly thought to be at play in other domains of preferential accurate out-of-sample predictions. decision making—rather than with the traditional Nash equilib- Our dual accumulator model can be seen as a cognitive imple- rium benchmark. We aim to characterize
Recommended publications
  • The Determinants of Efficient Behavior in Coordination Games
    The Determinants of Efficient Behavior in Coordination Games Pedro Dal B´o Guillaume R. Fr´echette Jeongbin Kim* Brown University & NBER New York University Caltech May 20, 2020 Abstract We study the determinants of efficient behavior in stag hunt games (2x2 symmetric coordination games with Pareto ranked equilibria) using both data from eight previous experiments on stag hunt games and data from a new experiment which allows for a more systematic variation of parameters. In line with the previous experimental literature, we find that subjects do not necessarily play the efficient action (stag). While the rate of stag is greater when stag is risk dominant, we find that the equilibrium selection criterion of risk dominance is neither a necessary nor sufficient condition for a majority of subjects to choose the efficient action. We do find that an increase in the size of the basin of attraction of stag results in an increase in efficient behavior. We show that the results are robust to controlling for risk preferences. JEL codes: C9, D7. Keywords: Coordination games, strategic uncertainty, equilibrium selection. *We thank all the authors who made available the data that we use from previous articles, Hui Wen Ng for her assistance running experiments and Anna Aizer for useful comments. 1 1 Introduction The study of coordination games has a long history as many situations of interest present a coordination component: for example, the choice of technologies that require a threshold number of users to be sustainable, currency attacks, bank runs, asset price bubbles, cooper- ation in repeated games, etc. In such examples, agents may face strategic uncertainty; that is, they may be uncertain about how the other agents will respond to the multiplicity of equilibria, even when they have complete information about the environment.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 4 Rationalizability & Nash Equilibrium Road
    Lecture 4 Rationalizability & Nash Equilibrium 14.12 Game Theory Muhamet Yildiz Road Map 1. Strategies – completed 2. Quiz 3. Dominance 4. Dominant-strategy equilibrium 5. Rationalizability 6. Nash Equilibrium 1 Strategy A strategy of a player is a complete contingent-plan, determining which action he will take at each information set he is to move (including the information sets that will not be reached according to this strategy). Matching pennies with perfect information 2’s Strategies: HH = Head if 1 plays Head, 1 Head if 1 plays Tail; HT = Head if 1 plays Head, Head Tail Tail if 1 plays Tail; 2 TH = Tail if 1 plays Head, 2 Head if 1 plays Tail; head tail head tail TT = Tail if 1 plays Head, Tail if 1 plays Tail. (-1,1) (1,-1) (1,-1) (-1,1) 2 Matching pennies with perfect information 2 1 HH HT TH TT Head Tail Matching pennies with Imperfect information 1 2 1 Head Tail Head Tail 2 Head (-1,1) (1,-1) head tail head tail Tail (1,-1) (-1,1) (-1,1) (1,-1) (1,-1) (-1,1) 3 A game with nature Left (5, 0) 1 Head 1/2 Right (2, 2) Nature (3, 3) 1/2 Left Tail 2 Right (0, -5) Mixed Strategy Definition: A mixed strategy of a player is a probability distribution over the set of his strategies. Pure strategies: Si = {si1,si2,…,sik} σ → A mixed strategy: i: S [0,1] s.t. σ σ σ i(si1) + i(si2) + … + i(sik) = 1. If the other players play s-i =(s1,…, si-1,si+1,…,sn), then σ the expected utility of playing i is σ σ σ i(si1)ui(si1,s-i) + i(si2)ui(si2,s-i) + … + i(sik)ui(sik,s-i).
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture Notes
    GRADUATE GAME THEORY LECTURE NOTES BY OMER TAMUZ California Institute of Technology 2018 Acknowledgments These lecture notes are partially adapted from Osborne and Rubinstein [29], Maschler, Solan and Zamir [23], lecture notes by Federico Echenique, and slides by Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar. I am indebted to Seo Young (Silvia) Kim and Zhuofang Li for their help in finding and correcting many errors. Any comments or suggestions are welcome. 2 Contents 1 Extensive form games with perfect information 7 1.1 Tic-Tac-Toe ........................................ 7 1.2 The Sweet Fifteen Game ................................ 7 1.3 Chess ............................................ 7 1.4 Definition of extensive form games with perfect information ........... 10 1.5 The ultimatum game .................................. 10 1.6 Equilibria ......................................... 11 1.7 The centipede game ................................... 11 1.8 Subgames and subgame perfect equilibria ...................... 13 1.9 The dollar auction .................................... 14 1.10 Backward induction, Kuhn’s Theorem and a proof of Zermelo’s Theorem ... 15 2 Strategic form games 17 2.1 Definition ......................................... 17 2.2 Nash equilibria ...................................... 17 2.3 Classical examples .................................... 17 2.4 Dominated strategies .................................. 22 2.5 Repeated elimination of dominated strategies ................... 22 2.6 Dominant strategies ..................................
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Game Theory Lecture 1: Strategic Game and Nash Equilibrium
    Game Theory and Rational Choice Strategic-form Games Nash Equilibrium Examples (Non-)Strict Nash Equilibrium . Introduction to Game Theory Lecture 1: Strategic Game and Nash Equilibrium . Haifeng Huang University of California, Merced Shanghai, Summer 2011 . • Rational choice: the action chosen by a decision maker is better or at least as good as every other available action, according to her preferences and given her constraints (e.g., resources, information, etc.). • Preferences (偏好) are rational if they satisfy . Completeness (完备性): between any x and y in a set, x ≻ y (x is preferred to y), y ≻ x, or x ∼ y (indifferent) . Transitivity(传递性): x ≽ y and y ≽ z )x ≽ z (≽ means ≻ or ∼) ) Say apple ≻ banana, and banana ≻ orange, then apple ≻ orange Game Theory and Rational Choice Strategic-form Games Nash Equilibrium Examples (Non-)Strict Nash Equilibrium Rational Choice and Preference Relations • Game theory studies rational players’ behavior when they engage in strategic interactions. • Preferences (偏好) are rational if they satisfy . Completeness (完备性): between any x and y in a set, x ≻ y (x is preferred to y), y ≻ x, or x ∼ y (indifferent) . Transitivity(传递性): x ≽ y and y ≽ z )x ≽ z (≽ means ≻ or ∼) ) Say apple ≻ banana, and banana ≻ orange, then apple ≻ orange Game Theory and Rational Choice Strategic-form Games Nash Equilibrium Examples (Non-)Strict Nash Equilibrium Rational Choice and Preference Relations • Game theory studies rational players’ behavior when they engage in strategic interactions. • Rational choice: the action chosen by a decision maker is better or at least as good as every other available action, according to her preferences and given her constraints (e.g., resources, information, etc.).
    [Show full text]
  • The Conservation Game ⇑ Mark Colyvan A, , James Justus A,B, Helen M
    Biological Conservation 144 (2011) 1246–1253 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Biological Conservation journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/biocon Special Issue Article: Adaptive management for biodiversity conservation in an uncertain world The conservation game ⇑ Mark Colyvan a, , James Justus a,b, Helen M. Regan c a Sydney Centre for the Foundations of Science, University of Sydney, Sydney, NSW 2006, Australia b Department of Philosophy, Florida State University, Tallahassee, FL 32306, USA c Department of Biology, University of California Riverside, Riverside, CA 92521, USA article info abstract Article history: Conservation problems typically involve groups with competing objectives and strategies. Taking effec- Received 16 December 2009 tive conservation action requires identifying dependencies between competing strategies and determin- Received in revised form 20 September 2010 ing which action optimally achieves the appropriate conservation goals given those dependencies. We Accepted 7 October 2010 show how several real-world conservation problems can be modeled game-theoretically. Three types Available online 26 February 2011 of problems drive our analysis: multi-national conservation cooperation, management of common-pool resources, and games against nature. By revealing the underlying structure of these and other problems, Keywords: game-theoretic models suggest potential solutions that are often invisible to the usual management pro- Game theory tocol: decision followed by monitoring, feedback and revised decisions. The kind of adaptive manage- Adaptive management Stag hunt ment provided by the game-theoretic approach therefore complements existing adaptive management Tragedy of the commons methodologies. Games against nature Ó 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Common-pool resource management Multi-national cooperation Conservation management Resource management Prisoners’ dilemma 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Game Theory Model and Empirical Evidence
    UC Irvine UC Irvine Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Cheap Talk, Trust, and Cooperation in Networked Global Software Engineering: Game Theory Model and Empirical Evidence Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/99z4314v Author Wang, Yi Publication Date 2015 License https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ 4.0 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, IRVINE Cheap Talk, Trust, and Cooperation in Networked Global Software Engineering: Game Theory Model and Empirical Evidence DISSERTATION submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in Information and Computer Science by Yi Wang Dissertation Committee: Professor David F. Redmiles, Chair Professor Debra J. Richardson Professor Brian Skyrms 2015 Portion of Chapter 4 c 2013 IEEE. All other materials c 2015 Yi Wang DEDICATION To Natural & Intellectual Beauty ii TABLE OF CONTENTS Page LIST OF FIGURES vii LIST OF TABLES ix LIST OF ALGORITHMS x ACKNOWLEDGMENTS xi CURRICULUM VITAE xiii ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION xvi 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Motivating Observations . 3 1.1.1 Empirical Observations . 3 1.1.2 Summary . 6 1.2 Dissertation Outline . 7 1.2.1 Overview of Each Chapter . 7 1.2.2 How to Read This Dissertation . 9 2 Research Overview and Approach 10 2.1 Overall Research Questions . 10 2.2 Research Approach . 11 2.3 Overview of Potential Contributions . 12 3 Backgrounds 14 3.1 Related Work . 14 3.1.1 Trust in Globally Distributed Collaboration . 14 3.1.2 Informal, Non-work-related Communication in SE and CSCW .
    [Show full text]
  • Zbwleibniz-Informationszentrum
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Chierchia, Gabriele; Tufano, Fabio; Coricelli, Giorgio Working Paper The differential impact of friendship on cooperative and competitive coordination CeDEx Discussion Paper Series, No. 2020-07 Provided in Cooperation with: The University of Nottingham, Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics (CeDEx) Suggested Citation: Chierchia, Gabriele; Tufano, Fabio; Coricelli, Giorgio (2020) : The differential impact of friendship on cooperative and competitive coordination, CeDEx Discussion Paper Series, No. 2020-07, The University of Nottingham, Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics (CeDEx), Nottingham This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/228371 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu Discussion Paper No.
    [Show full text]
  • Ui(Α) = −(Ni (Α) + Ni (Α) + Ni (Α)), R C B Where Ni (Α), Ni (Α), Ni (Α) Is the Number of Repetitions of Numbers in I’S Row, Column and Block Respec- Tively
    6.207/14.15: Networks Problem Set 4 Due: Friday, November 6, 2009 Problem 1. [Sudoku as a game of cooperation] In the popular game of Sudoku, the number placement puzzle, the objective is to fill a 9 × 9 grid so that each column, each row, and each of the nine 3 × 3 boxes (also called blocks or regions) contains the digits from 1 to 9 only one time each (see figure). The puzzle setter provides a partially completed grid and the puzzle solver is asked to fill in the missing numbers. Consider now a multi-agent extension of the Sudoku game, in which each of the 81 boxes is controlled by one agent. The agent’s action space is choosing a number from 1 to 9 to put in her box, i.e., Ai = f1, ··· , 9g, where Ai denotes the action space of agent i. Let a denote the vector of choices of the agents. Then, agent i’s utility is given by: R C B ui(a) = −(ni (a) + ni (a) + ni (a)), R C B where ni (a), ni (a), ni (a) is the number of repetitions of numbers in i’s row, column and block respec- tively. Show that the multi agent Sudoku game is a potential game and write down explicitly the associated potential function. Figure 1: Sudoku Problem 2. Consider the network formation game discussed in Lecture 12. (i) Find conditions for which the ring network, in which the agents form a circle (each one has two neighbors), is a pairwise stable equilibrium of the game.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Game Theory
    Publicly•available solutions for AN INTRODUCTION TO GAME THEORY Publicly•available solutions for AN INTRODUCTION TO GAME THEORY MARTIN J. OSBORNE University of Toronto Copyright © 2012 by Martin J. Osborne All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Martin J. Osborne. This manual was typeset by the author, who is greatly indebted to Donald Knuth (TEX), Leslie Lamport (LATEX), Diego Puga (mathpazo), Christian Schenk (MiKTEX), Ed Sznyter (ppctr), Timothy van Zandt (PSTricks), and others, for generously making superlative software freely available. The main font is 10pt Palatino. Version 6: 2012-4-7 Contents Preface xi 1 Introduction 1 Exercise 5.3 (Altruistic preferences) 1 Exercise 6.1 (Alternative representations of preferences) 1 2 Nash Equilibrium 3 Exercise 16.1 (Working on a joint project) 3 Exercise 17.1 (Games equivalent to the Prisoner’s Dilemma) 3 Exercise 20.1 (Games without conflict) 3 Exercise 31.1 (Extension of the Stag Hunt) 4 Exercise 34.1 (Guessing two-thirds of the average) 4 Exercise 34.3 (Choosing a route) 5 Exercise 37.1 (Finding Nash equilibria using best response functions) 6 Exercise 38.1 (Constructing best response functions) 6 Exercise 38.2 (Dividing money) 7 Exercise 41.1 (Strict and nonstrict Nash equilibria) 7 Exercise 47.1 (Strict equilibria and dominated actions) 8 Exercise 47.2 (Nash equilibrium and weakly dominated
    [Show full text]
  • The Evolution of Inefficiency in a Simulated Stag Hunt
    Behavior Research Methods, Instruments, & Computers 2001, 33 (2), 124-129 The evolution of inefficiency in a simulated stag hunt J. NEIL BEARDEN University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill, North Carolina We used genetic algorithms to evolve populations of reinforcement learning (Q-learning) agents to play a repeated two-player symmetric coordination game under different risk conditions and found that evolution steered our simulated populations to the Pareto inefficient equilibrium under high-risk conditions and to the Pareto efficient equilibrium under low-risk conditions. Greater degrees of for- giveness and temporal discounting of future returns emerged in populations playing the low-risk game. Results demonstrate the utility of simulation to evolutionary psychology. Traditional game theory assumes that players have have enough food for one day and the other will go hun- perfect rationality, which implicitly assumes that they gry. If both follow the rabbit, each will get only a small have infinite cognitivecapacity and, as a result, will play amount of food. Nash equilibria.Evolutionarygame theory (Smith, 1982) Clearly, it is in the players’ best interests to coordinate does not necessarily endow its players with these same their actions and wait for the deer; however, a player is capabilities; rather it uses various selection processes to guaranteed food by following the rabbit. Thus, the play- take populations of players to an equilibrium point over ers have a dilemma: Each must choose between potential the course of generations. Other
    [Show full text]
  • Construction of Subgame-Perfect Mixed-Strategy Equilibria in Repeated Games
    games Article Construction of Subgame-Perfect Mixed-Strategy Equilibria in Repeated Games Kimmo Berg 1,* ID and Gijs Schoenmakers 2 1 Department of Mathematics and Systems Analysis, Aalto University School of Science, P.O. Box 11100, FI-00076 Aalto, Finland 2 Department of Data Science and Knowledge Engineering, Maastricht University, P.O. Box 616, 6200MD Maastricht, The Netherlands; [email protected] * Correspondence: kimmo.berg@aalto.fi; Tel.: +358-40-7170-025 Received: 26 July 2017 ; Accepted: 18 October 2017 ; Published: 1 November 2017 Abstract: This paper examines how to construct subgame-perfect mixed-strategy equilibria in discounted repeated games with perfect monitoring. We introduce a relatively simple class of strategy profiles that are easy to compute and may give rise to a large set of equilibrium payoffs. These sets are called self-supporting sets, since the set itself provides the continuation payoffs that are required to support the equilibrium strategies. Moreover, the corresponding strategies are simple as the players face the same augmented game on each round but they play different mixed actions after each realized pure-action profile. We find that certain payoffs can be obtained in equilibrium with much lower discount factor values compared to pure strategies. The theory and the concepts are illustrated in 2 × 2 games. Keywords: repeated game; mixed strategy; subgame perfection; payoff set MSC: 91A20 JEL Classification: C73 1. Introduction This paper examines how mixed actions can be used in obtaining subgame-perfect equilibria in discounted repeated games. In repeated games, the set of subgame-perfect equilibria can be defined recursively: a strategy profile is an equilibrium if certain equilibrium payoffs are available as continuation payoffs, and these continuation payoffs may be generated by means of other equilibrium strategy profiles.
    [Show full text]
  • Game-Theoretic Learning
    Game-Theoretic Learning Amy Greenwald with David Gondek, Amir Jafari, and Casey Marks Brown University ICML Tutorial I July 4, 2004 Overview 1. Introduction to Game Theory 2. Regret Matching Learning Algorithms ◦ Regret Matching Learns Equilibria 3. Machine Learning Applications Introduction to Game Theory 1. General-Sum Games ◦ Nash Equilibrium ◦ Correlated Equilibrium 2. Zero-Sum Games ◦ Minimax Equilibrium Regret Matching Learning Algorithms 1. Regret Variations ◦ No Φ-Regret Learning ◦ External, Internal, and Swap Regret 2. Sufficient Conditions for No Φ-Regret Learning ◦ Blackwell’s Approachability Theorem ◦ Gordon’s Gradient Descent Theorem – Potential Function Argument 3. Expected and Observed Regret Matching Algorithms ◦ Polynomial and Exponential Potential Functions ◦ External, Internal, and Swap Regret 4. No Φ-Regret Learning Converges to Φ-Equilibria So Φ-Regret Matching Learns Φ-Equilibria Machine Learning Applications 1. Online Classification 2. Offline Boosting Game Theory and Economics ◦ Perfect Competition agents are price-takers ◦ Monopoly single entity commands all market power ◦ Game Theory payoffs in a game are jointly determined by the strategies of all players Knowledge, Rationality, and Equilibrium Assumption Players are rational: i.e., optimizing wrt their beliefs. Theorem Mutual knowledge of rationality and common knowledge of beliefs is sufficient for the deductive justification of Nash equilibrium. (Aumann and Brandenburger 95) Question Can learning provide an inductive justification for equilibrium? Dimensions of Game
    [Show full text]