Conclusion. a Research Agenda for Political Pragmatism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Conclusion. a Research Agenda for Political Pragmatism Conclusion. A Research Agenda for Political Pragmatism Throughout this book I have contended that, in its broadest terms, a wide view of democracy can help us revive and advance the democratic project, insofar as it reconnects the political phase of democracy to its social roots. Such a theory provides us with precious theoretical resources to tackle some of the most pressing challenges of our time, such as the rise of popu- lism, democratic deficits, the ongoing crisis of formal political institu- tions, and the emergence of new forms of discrimination. By including the whole of social life in the concept of democracy, the wide view is better suited not only to the critical task of identifying the cracks and tensions that threaten the democratic project, but also, and especially, to the recon- structive task of providing concrete guidance for reform projects, whether for democratizing the workplace and other social institutions, for extend- ing the scope of the associational principle to new production practices, for reducing global inequality by politicizing consumerism, or for achiev- ing greater degrees of accountability in global politics. Indeed, it seems to me that it is only by radically broadening our conceptual framework that we can hope to overcome the practical and theoretical deadlocks that democracy faces today, precisely because this enlargement allows us to come closer to the true reasons that render the democratic project so important and so inescapable, even when its political performances appear © The Author(s) 2019 395 R. Frega, Pragmatism and the Wide View of Democracy, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18561-9 396 Conclusion. A Research Agenda for Political Pragmatism so shallow and the legitimacy of its formal institutions so wanting. Those who contend that democracy does not matter to us, that our representa- tive institutions have been emptied of meaning and are therefore worth nothing, or that we have entered a post-democratic­ phase, should look at the immense achievements that the democratic project has brought to our societies in terms of freedom, equality, and social involvement in all spheres of social life. They should also consider that the democratization of our habits, patterns of social interaction, and forms of organization are not only incomplete, but also badly in need of furtherance, and that no jeremiad against neoliberalism or post-­democracy will be of much help in this task. What a wide view of democracy can provide is an all-encompass- ing scheme within which practices of reform and transformation can find their broadest meaning, so that diverse projects and practices such as those discussed in this book will finally appear as coherent instantiations of a single unifying vision of the future we desire and for which we strive. In concluding, I wish merely to recapitulate the three major normative statements that this book has vindicated. The first is that the democratic project advances or retreats according to how patterns of social interaction evolve throughout society. We should, therefore, consistently refer to democracy as the appropriate norm to assess the quality of social life at all its levels, and not only of its political institutions. The second is that experi- mental democratic institutions provide the most adequate strategy to iden- tify, face, and meet social challenges and generate social innovation. This assumption should guide us in inventing new projects of social and institu- tional reform aimed at designing private and public institutions more suited to our times. The third statement is that social involvement matters as much as freedom and equality. We should, therefore, pay more attention to the inclusive nature of social practices, and be less content with merely formal, or legal, patterns of recognition. Democracy is inseparable from an imperative of social involvement, as only active participation in social prac- tices create the concrete belonging which is required by any community to exist. Developing social settings in which not only freedom and equality but also social involvement are effectively achieved, devising new experi- mentalist democratic institutions, and rendering patterns of social interac- tion consistently democratic throughout the social body define the guidelines that committed democrats should prioritize in their agenda. Conclusion. A Research Agenda for Political Pragmatism 397 Arguments supporting these general claims have been developed throughout the book. They vindicate the claim that adopting a wide view of democracy is a necessary step if we are to engage more consciously in the never-ending pursuit of the democratic project, one that is unachiev- able not because of its supposedly elusive or utopian content, but because it requires constant adjustment and transformation of the temporary and fragile solutions with which we meet ever-changing social circumstances. These are the normative implications the wide view of democracy bears for political theory. If this picture of democracy is correct, then we have a clear indication for a new research program in democratic theory, as well as some decisive indications for a new political agenda. References Abbott, A. (2016). Processual Sociology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Abensour, M. (2011). Democracy Against the State: Marx and the Machiavellian Movement. Cambridge: Polity. Abraham, J. and Y. Abramson (2015). A Pragmatist Vocation for International Relations: The (Global) Public and Its Problems. European Journal of International Relations 23(1), 26–48. Achen, C. and L. Bartels (2016). Democracy for Realists: Why Elections Do Not Produce Responsive Government. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Addams, J. (1912). Twenty Years at Hull-House. New York: The Macmillan Company. Alexander, J. (2006). The Civil Sphere. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Alexander, M. (2012). The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness. New York: The New Press. Alexander, T. (1990). Pragmatic Imagination. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 325–348. Allen, A. (1998). Rethinking Power. Hypatia 13(1), 21–40. Allen, A. (2016). The End of Progress: De-Colonizing Critical Theory. New York: Columbia University Press. Almond, G. (1993). The Study of Political Culture. In Berg-Schlosser, D. and R. Rytlewski, pp. 13–27. © The Author(s) 2019 399 R. Frega, Pragmatism and the Wide View of Democracy, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18561-9 400 References Almond, G. and S. Verba (1963). The Civic Culture: Political Attitudes and Democracy in Five Nations. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Almond, G. and S. Verba (1980). The Civic Culture Revisited: An Analytic Study. Boston: Little Brown. Anderson, E. (1999). What Is the Point of Equality? Ethics 109(1), 287–337. Anderson, E. (2006). The Epistemology of Democracy. Episteme 1(3), 8–22. Anderson, E. (2009). Democracy: Instrumental vs. Non-instrumental Value. In T. Christiano and J. Christman (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy, pp. 213–27. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. Anderson, E. (2010). The Imperative of Integration. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Anderson, E. (2016). The Social Epistemology of Morality: Learning from the Forgotten History of the Abolition of Slavery. In M. Brady and M. Fricker (Eds.), The Epistemic Life of Groups: Essays in Collective Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Anderson, N. (1923). The Hobo: The Sociology of the Homeless Man. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ansell, C. (2009). Mary Parker Follett and Pragmatist Organization. In The Oxford Handbook of Sociology and Organization Studies: Classical Foundations. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ansell, C. (2011). Pragmatist Democracy: Evolutionary Learning as Public Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ansell, C. and M. Bartenberger (2015). Expanding the Toolkit of Experimen­ tation for Environmental Problem-solving. Ecological Economics. Ansell, C., M. Farjoun, and A. Boin (2015). Pragmatism in Organization Studies: Meeting the Challenges of a Dynamic and Complex World. Organization Science 26(6), 1787–1804. Antic, A. (2016). John Dewey’s Philosophical Legacy for the Global Access to Knowledge Movement in the Digital Age. Kinesis 41(1), 6–16. Arendt, H. (1970). On Violence. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World. Arendt, H. (2006). On Revolution (1st ed. 1963 ed.). London: Penguin. Armstrong, H. D. (2002). Mary P. Follett: Conflict Resolution Through Integration. Peace Research 34(2), 101–116. Arneson, R. (2013). Egalitarianism. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 ed.). Barber, B. (2003). Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age. University of California Press. Bassett, K. (2014). Rancière, Politics, and the Occupy Movement. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 32(5), 886–901. References 401 Bayat, A. (1997). Street Politics: Poor People’s Movements in Iran. Columbia University Press. Bayat, A. (2010). Life as Politics: How Ordinary People Change the Middle East. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Beck, U. (2006). Cosmopolitan Vision. Cambridge: Polity. Beck, U. and E. Grande (2007). Cosmopolitan Europe. Cambridge: Polity Press. Beck, U. and E. Grande (2010). Jenseits des methodologischen nationalismus: Aussereuropäische und europäische variationen der zweiten moderne. Soziale Welt 61(3–4), 187–216. Bell, J. and K. Parker (Eds.) (2014). The Relevance of Royce. New York: Fordham University Press. Benkler, Y. (2003). The Political Economy of
Recommended publications
  • APA Newsletters
    APA Newsletters Volume 06, Number 2 Spring 2007 NEWSLETTER ON PHILOSOPHY AND LAW FROM THE EDITOR, STEVEN SCALET ARTICLES BRIAN H. BIX “Joseph Raz and Conceptual Analysis” JULES L. COLEMAN “Law and Political Morality” TIMOTHY ENDICOTT “Interpretation, Jurisdiction, and the Authority of Law” KENNETH EINAR HIMMA “Revisiting Raz: Inclusive Positivism and the Concept of Authority” LIAM MURPHY “Razian Concepts” STEPHEN PERRY “Two Problems of Political Authority” © 2007 by The American Philosophical Association ISSN: 1067-9464 APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy and Law Steven Scalet, Editor Spring 2007 Volume 06, Number 2 relating to such theories. In particular, I will look at the role of conceptual analysis in legal theory, focusing on some recent FROM THE EDITOR work by Joseph Raz.1 I. Overview Edition in Tribute to Joseph Raz It was a commonplace in the history of jurisprudence to focus on the inquiry, what is law? It is worth taking a few moments Joseph Raz is professor at Columbia University Law School to consider the question more closely. and research faculty at Oxford University. His writings influence generations of scholars and his many students are now among First and foremost, there is a potential confusion (heightened 2 the leading scholars in philosophy of law. in English more than in other major languages ), as “law,” even if focused on matters jurisprudential (and not speaking of physical For this edition of the Newsletter we invited leading political laws, the laws of games, social conventions, etc.), can refer to and legal philosophers to analyze some aspect of Professor a number of different, if related, matters: most prominently, Raz’s ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy (PHIL) 1
    Philosophy (PHIL) 1 PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) PHIL 3000 Plato's Metaphysics (4 Credits) A systematic study of Plato's Middle and Late Period Dialogues that focuses on his arguments for the existence of abstract objects and the development of Plato's theory of Forms. Prerequisite: At least Junior standing or permission of instructor. PHIL 3003 Plato's Theory of Knowledge (4 Credits) A systematic investigation of Plato's treatments of knowledge throughout the dialogues with a focus on the theory of recollection, Forms as objects of knowledge, the relationship between the Forms and perceptual experience, and the challenges posed by notions of true and false belief. Prerequisites: At least Junior standing or permission of instructor. PHIL 3005 Cosmopolitics (4 Credits) This class will be a close reading of Plato's dialogue Timaeus, with a special focus on the cosmological, theological, and political dimensions of the text. PHIL 3010 Great Thinkers: Aristotle (4 Credits) A study of Aristotle's central theories and doctrines. Prerequisite: junior standing or instructor's permission. PHIL 3011 Great Thinkers: Virginia Woolf (4 Credits) In this course we will read Virginia Woolf as a philosopher. We will discuss her philosophy of nature, knowledge, art, politics, science, sensation, gender, and materialism throughout her fiction and non-fiction writings. PHIL 3023 Great Thinkers: Maimonides: Politics, Prophecy and Providence (4 Credits) Using "The Guide for the Perplexed" as our central text, we explore the complex philosophical ideas of Moses Maimonides (1135-1204), one of the central figures in medieval philosophy and Jewish thought. Our study includes analyses of his ideas on principles of faith, human perfection, intellectual vs.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosopher-Prophet in Avicenna's Political Philosophy
    The philosopher-prophet in Avicenna's political philosophy Author: James Winston Morris Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/4029 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Published in Political aspects of Islamic philosophy, pp. 152-198 Use of this resource is governed by the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons "Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 United States" (http:// creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/us/) The P~~losopher-Prophet in. AVic~nna's Political Philosophy. Chapter 4 of The PolItICal Aspects of IslamIc PhIlosophy, ed. C. Butterworth, Cambridge Harvard University Press, 1992, pp. 142-188. ' -FOUR- The Philosopher-Prophet in Avicenna~s Political Philosophy James W. Morris With time, human beings tend to take miracles for granted. Perhaps the most lasting and public of all miracles, those to which Islamic philosophers devoted so much of their reflections, were the political achievements of the prophets: how otherwise obscure figures like Moses, Jesus, and Muhammad came to shape the thoughts and actions of so much of civilized humanity. Within the high culture of Islamic civilization, the thought and writings of an itinerant Persian doctor and court administrator we know as Avicenna (370/980~28/1037) came to play a similarly central role: for almost a millenium, each of the tra­ ditions of Islamic thought claiming a wider, universal human validity has appealed either directly to his works or to logical and metaphysical disciplines whose Islamic forms were directly grounded in them. This study considers some of the central philosophic under­ pinnings of that achievement.
    [Show full text]
  • A Glossary of Terms and Concepts in Peace and Conflict Studies
    A GLOSSARY OF TERMS AND CONCEPTS IN PEACE AND CONFLICT STUDIES AUTHOR: CHRISTOPHER E. MILLER EDITOR: MARY E. KING A GLOSSARY OF TERMS AND CONCEPTS IN PEACE AND CONFLICT STUDIES SECOND EDITION A GLOSSARY OF TERMS AND CONCEPTS IN PEACE AND CONFLICT STUDIES AFRICA PROGRAMME © 2005 University for Peace Portions of this publication may be reproduced free of charge provided that the source is acknowledged. Views expressed in this publication are those of the author(s). They do not necessarily reflect the views of the University for Peace. ISBN 9977-925-36-4 A GLOSSARY OF TERMS AND CONCEPTS IN PEACE AND CONFLICT STUDIES The mission of the University for Peace is to provide humanity with an international institution of higher education for peace with the aim of promoting among all human beings a spirit of understanding, tolerance, and peaceful coexistence, to stimulate cooperation among peoples, and to help lessen obstacles and threats to world peace and progress in keeping with the noble aspirations proclaimed in the Charter of the United Nations. A GLOSSARY OF TERMS AND CONCEPTS IN PEACE AND CONFLICT STUDIES UNIVERSITY FOR PEACE AFRICA PROGRAMME Addis Ababa Office UPEACE Africa Programme Post Office Box 1176 Addis Ababa, Ethiopia Telephone: + 251 1 234 026 Email: [email protected] Web: www.africa.upeace.org Geneva Office 5 chemin du Rivage 1292 Chambésy / Geneva, Switzerland Telephone: +41 22 737 30 80 Fax: +41 22 737 30 90 Email: [email protected] Main Campus & Headquarters Post Office Box 138-6100 San José, Costa Rica Telephone: +506 205-9000
    [Show full text]
  • Islamic Philosophy and Politics (The Experience of Interpretation)
    ISSN 2039-2117 (online) Mediterranean Journal of Social Sciences Vol 6 No 6 S1 ISSN 2039-9340 (print) MCSER Publishing, Rome-Italy November 2015 Islamic Philosophy and Politics (The Experience of Interpretation) Viktor Vasilievich Zheltov Maxim Viktorovich Zheltov Sergey Vladimirovich Birukov Kemerovo State University, Russian Federation, 650043, Kemerovo, Krasnaya Street,6 Doi:10.5901/mjss.2015.v6n6s1p537 Abstract The article highlights the historical background of the diversity of Islam related to the influence of pre-Islamic culture in different countries, as well as the impact of socio-economic cooperation of Islamic countries with the West. It analytically reveals the phenomenon of Islamization of ancient Greek philosophy as a phenomenon of its adaptation to the realities of the Islamic world showing opportunities of philosophy as a science in the Islamic world, and the role of the Qur'an in the development of philosophy and politics in the Muslim countries. The article touches upon the questions of the role of Islam in the Muslim countries` politics, trans-prospects and building democracy in the Arab world analyzing “The Arab Spring” political legacy and future perspectives of its influence. Keywords: ancient Greek philosophy, Islamic philosophy, Islam, Moslem world, the Koran, Revelation, politics, democracy, pluralism 1. Introduction As a rule, the philosophical and political literature says about Islam, as they say in general terms, i.e. as a single doctrine. Meanwhile, there is no single Islam. Political scientists and religious-WIDE Islamic thinkers rightly speak of the existence of: Sunni-ray and Shia Islam; Islam, which are practiced in Riyadh (Saudi Arabia) and Bamako (Mali); version of Islam in Morocco and Indonesia.
    [Show full text]
  • The Analytical-Continental Divide: Styles of Dealing with Problems
    Haverford College Haverford Scholarship Faculty Publications Political Science 2016 The analytical-Continental divide: Styles of dealing with problems Thomas J. Donahue Haverford College, [email protected] Paulina Ochoa Espejo Haverford College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.haverford.edu/polisci_facpubs Repository Citation Donahue J. Thomas, Espejo Ochoa Paulina, (2016). "The analytical-Continental divide: Styles of dealing with problems." European Journal of Political Theory, 15(2):138-154 This Journal Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Political Science at Haverford Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Haverford Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. XML Template (2015) [12.5.2015–3:37pm] [1–17] //blrnas3.glyph.com/cenpro/ApplicationFiles/Journals/SAGE/3B2/EPTJ/Vol00000/150024/APPFile/SG- EPTJ150024.3d (EPT) [PREPRINTER stage] Article EJPT European Journal of Political Theory 0(0) 1–17 ! The Author(s) 2015 The analytical–Continental Reprints and permissions: divide: Styles of dealing sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/1474885115585324 with problems ept.sagepub.com Thomas J. Donahue and Paulina Ochoa Espejo Haverford College, USA Abstract What today divides analytical from Continental philosophy? This paper argues that the present divide is not what it once was. Today, the divide concerns the styles in which philosophers deal with intellectual problems: solving them, pressing them, resolving them, or dissolving them. Using ‘the boundary problem’, or ‘the democratic paradox’, as an example, we argue for two theses. First, the difference between most analytical and most Continental philosophers today is that Continental philosophers find intelligible two styles of dealing with problems that most analytical philosophers find unintelligible: pressing them and resolving them.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Politics 9503A/Philosophy 9119A: Central Problems in Political Theory
    Politics 9503A/Philosophy 9119A: Central Problems in Political Theory September-December 2020 Tuesday Zoom meetings 3:30-5:20 Charles Jones, 661-2111 x85060, [email protected], SSC 4129 Zoom Office Hours: Wednesdays 1:30-3:00 & by appointment This course examines some central problems in political theory: political authority, property and the market, distributive justice and equality, liberty, and democracy. We will study both classic works and recent scholarship on these issues. By the end of the course, students will be able to: (1) Describe the problem of political authority and explain (and evaluate) the main arguments in its favour, (2) Assess the case for and against private property rights, (3) Explain the pros and cons of markets in goods and services as a means of organizing an economy, (4) Describe the problem of distributive justice (‘who should get what?’) and explain the relative merits of competing approaches to this problem, (5) Evaluate the value of equality and sufficiency as competing goals of just distribution, (6) Explain the arguments on both sides of the debate between distributive egalitarians and relational egalitarians in their answers to the question, ‘What is the point of equality?’, (7) Identify the competing conceptions of liberty in the history of political theory and adjudicate between them, (8) Evaluate the case for and against ‘libertarian paternalism’ as an approach to public policy, and (9) Outline the most important arguments against and for democracy as a form of public and private decision-making. Texts Course readings will be posted on the OWL site. There is one book to purchase: Elizabeth Anderson, Private Government: How Employers Rule Our Lives (and Why We Don’t Talk about it), Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2017.
    [Show full text]
  • SCIENTIFIC AUTHORITY: an Epistemic Proceduralist Framework for the Legitimate Authority of Science in Environmental Policy
    SCIENTIFIC AUTHORITY: An Epistemic Proceduralist Framework For The Legitimate Authority Of Science In Environmental Policy by MATTHEW EVAN HELLER B.S., Warren Wilson College 2004 M.A., Lehigh University 2007 M.A., University of Colorado 2010 A thesis submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Colorado in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science 2015 This thesis entitled: Scientific Authority: An epistemic proceduralist framework for the legitimate authority of science in environmental policy written by Matthew Evan Heller has been approved for the Department of Political Science Steve Vanderheiden Michaele Ferguson Horst Mewes Roger Pielke, Jr. David Mapel Date The final copy of this thesis has been examined by the signatories, and we Find that both the content and the form meet acceptable presentation standards Of scholarly work in the above mentioned discipline. iii Heller, Matthew Evan (Ph.D., Political Science) SCIENTIFIC AUTHORITY: An Epistemic Proceduralist Framework For The Legitimate Authority Of Science In Environmental Policy Dissertation directed by Associate Professor Steve Vanderheiden The formation and implementation of effective environmental policies by Western liberal democracies are frequently hindered by disagreement over the appropriate role of scientific knowledge. In my dissertation, I argue this obstruction is resolved by recognizing the legitimate authority of science in environmental policy-making. Drawing on David Estlund’s epistemic proceduralist theory of democracy, I demonstrate the compatibility of the authority of scientific knowledge claims about the cause and effect relationships of the biophysical world in environmental policy-making with our normative expectations for the justifications of democratic governance.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Authority and Its Critics
    EPISTEMIC AUTHORITY AND ITS CRITICS LINDA ZAGZEBSKI University of Oklahoma The purpose of Epistemic Authority1 is to defend the rationality of belief on authority from the modern assumption that the ultimate authority over the self is the self. More specifically, the strategy is to show that traditional epistemic authority, including the teaching authority of institutions such as the Catholic Church, can be justified even if we accept the modern value of autonomy. The book begins with a brief historical and philosophical investigation of the rejection of epistemic authority, particularly as it is arises from the ideal of epistemic self-reliance. I argue that although that ideal dominates much of contemporary discourse, it cannot be defended from the work of Plato, Descartes, Locke, or Kant, and that the epistemological and moral arguments for self-reliance are weak. I then turn to an extended argument that the conscientiously self-reflective person is committed to authority in the realm of belief. I argue that epistemic (and emotional) self-trust is both rational and inescapable, that consistent epistemic self- trust commits us to trust in others, and that some of those others satisfy conditions for epistemic authority modelled on Joseph Raz’s well-known theses of political authority. I apply epistemic authority to authority in communities, defend epistemic authority in the domains of morality and religion, and argue that the account of epistemic authority I give shows that epistemic authority is compatible with intellectual autonomy. Believing on authority is a demand of conscientious self-governance. It is not only compatible with autonomy, but follows from it.
    [Show full text]
  • Authority, Legitimacy and Epistemic Accounts of Democratic Law
    Authority, Legitimacy and Epistemic Accounts of Democratic Law: Estlund vs. Habermas Jonathan Trejo-Mathys ABSTRACT: David Estlund has recently articulated the most sophisticated form of epistemic proceduralism available in Anglophone legal and political philosophy, one that grants that there are normative political truths and that some possess superior knowledge of them but defeats the claim that superior knowledge can successfully confer legislative authority. In the course of his argument, he charges Habermas’ rival version of proceduralism with ‘political nihilism’. The first two sections of this paper show that this charge is false and based upon a misunderstanding of Habermas and that it obscures the fact that Habermas provides a potentially stronger form of epistemic proceduralism that defeats the claim that those who know should rule by undermining the very idea that there could be some who possess superior normative political knowledge. The third section discusses a weak point in Habermas’ justification of coercive democratic law that is revealed in the course of the defense and suggests a Kantian way of remedying it. Trejo-Mathys 1 Epistemic Accounts of Democratic Authority and Legitimacy: Estlund vs. Habermas1 Epistemic views of democracy defend its legitimacy, or stronger, its authority in light of the epistemic virtues that the democratic process displays with respect to tracking some normative standard such as justice or the common good, however those are understood. They involve the belief that the truth about such matters, and in particular a sufficiently strong and effective tendency to pursue and discover it, is a necessary part of the justification of political authority and the legitimacy of the norms issued by such authority.
    [Show full text]
  • Justification of Political Authority in Theological(Islamic) Epistemology
    JISMOR 5 JISMOR 5 Justification of Political Authority in Theological(Islamic) Epistemology Mojtaba Zarvani Abstract The political views of the speculative theologians have been more abstraction and justification of the events of the age rather than an issue resulting from their scholastic theological geometry. “In other words, in the field of politics, the speculative theology [not only today, but also always] has been a sort of filling the gap and resurfacing the work”. In order to prove this argument, we will show a process during which from the early days of Islam up to Ghazzali, gradually the monitoring elements which challenge the authority of the Islamic ruler became fade. Moreover, the speculative theologians in their political views gradually reach to a point in which they consider a ruler with no specific features qualified to serve as a judge. That is to say, the authoritative nature of the Abbasid government, which according to many thinkers is the heritage of imitation from the Iranian and Sāsānid traditions made a situation that even the Ash’arits thinker who used to consider the return to the age of The rightly Guided Caliphs as a Utopia, mutilated and made a selection out of the traditions of the holy prophet and the caliphs. Keywords: political authority, kalām, epistemology Foreword This research has taken form round a problem rather than a subject. Therefore, the appropriate statement of the issue and faithfulness to it has been emphasized. The difficulty of conducting research by a researcher who is so naive in such kind of experiences is clear to everybody.
    [Show full text]
  • Utilitarianism and Beyond: Contemporary Analytical Political Theory David Miller
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Political Science Faculty Publications Political Science 2006 Utilitarianism and Beyond: Contemporary Analytical Political Theory David Miller Richard Dagger University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/polisci-faculty-publications Part of the Political Theory Commons Recommended Citation Miller, David, and Richard Dagger. "Utilitarianism and Beyond: Contemporary Analytical Political Theory." In The Cambridge History of Twentieth-Century Political Thought, edited by Terence Ball and Richard Bellamy, 446-70. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Political Science at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Political Science Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 21 Utilitarianism and beyond: contemporary analytical political theory david miller and richard dagger General features In this chapter we sketch a body of political thought that became predom- inant in the second half of the twentieth century among academic politi- cal philosophers, primarily in the English-speaking world, but increasingly elsewhere, too. To call this type of political thought ‘analytical’ may not be particularly revealing, but no other term better describes the movement in question. Sometimes ‘liberal political theory’ is used, and there is in- deed a close connection between analytical theory and liberalism. But that label is in one way too broad and in another too narrow for this kind of political thinking: too broad because liberalism has assumed many different philosophical guises in the course of a history much longer than that of our subject; and too narrow because those who engage in this kind of political theory use methods of analysis and techniques of argument that are not confined to liberals.
    [Show full text]