SCIENTIFIC AUTHORITY: an Epistemic Proceduralist Framework for the Legitimate Authority of Science in Environmental Policy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

SCIENTIFIC AUTHORITY: an Epistemic Proceduralist Framework for the Legitimate Authority of Science in Environmental Policy SCIENTIFIC AUTHORITY: An Epistemic Proceduralist Framework For The Legitimate Authority Of Science In Environmental Policy by MATTHEW EVAN HELLER B.S., Warren Wilson College 2004 M.A., Lehigh University 2007 M.A., University of Colorado 2010 A thesis submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Colorado in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science 2015 This thesis entitled: Scientific Authority: An epistemic proceduralist framework for the legitimate authority of science in environmental policy written by Matthew Evan Heller has been approved for the Department of Political Science Steve Vanderheiden Michaele Ferguson Horst Mewes Roger Pielke, Jr. David Mapel Date The final copy of this thesis has been examined by the signatories, and we Find that both the content and the form meet acceptable presentation standards Of scholarly work in the above mentioned discipline. iii Heller, Matthew Evan (Ph.D., Political Science) SCIENTIFIC AUTHORITY: An Epistemic Proceduralist Framework For The Legitimate Authority Of Science In Environmental Policy Dissertation directed by Associate Professor Steve Vanderheiden The formation and implementation of effective environmental policies by Western liberal democracies are frequently hindered by disagreement over the appropriate role of scientific knowledge. In my dissertation, I argue this obstruction is resolved by recognizing the legitimate authority of science in environmental policy-making. Drawing on David Estlund’s epistemic proceduralist theory of democracy, I demonstrate the compatibility of the authority of scientific knowledge claims about the cause and effect relationships of the biophysical world in environmental policy-making with our normative expectations for the justifications of democratic governance. After defending this approach to understanding the science-policy interface, I demonstrate the feasibility of my theory and its expected impacts through detailed application to the case of climate policy. Specifically, I argue that the authority of science that I defend will increase the effectiveness of policies at achieving desired ends, while avoiding the difficulties presented by the politicization of scientific explanations. iv CONTENTS CHAPTER INTRODUCTION 1 Why Scientific Authority Matters for Achieving Sustainability 4 An Outline of My Argument 10 I. THE DISCURSIVE POWER OF SCIENCE AS A SOURCE OF BIOPHYSICAL EXPLANATION 15 Why Co-Production Confuses the Problem and Fails to Offer a Solution 17 A Clearer Understanding of the Influence of Scientific Knowledge on Individuals 25 Science’s Discursive Role in Democratic Policy-making 31 Conclusion 36 II. NORMATIVE CONSENT AND SCIENTIFIC AUTHORITY 38 Why Deference to Scientific Expertise Will Not Prevent the Politicization of Science 43 Normative Consent and a Duty to Contribute to Sustainability 56 Grounds for Scientific Authority: Normative Consent and Pragmatic Liberalism 69 Scientific Authority within Environmental Policy-making 82 Conclusion 91 III. THE LEGITMACY OF SCIENTIFIC CONSTRAINT ON ENVIRONMENTAL POLICIES 94 Science, Environmental Policy, and the Avoidance of Ecological Collapse 96 Scientific Constraint of Environmental Policy Choices and the Avoidance of Ecological Collapse 101 The Inferential Extrapolation of Science’s Correct Influence to Other Cases 106 v Conclusion 111 IV. THE REPRESENTATION OF SCIENTIFIC AUTHORITY BY INDIVIDUALS 113 Who Represent Scientific Explanations in Environmental Policy-making? 119 The Requirements for Individuals to Act as Political Representation of Scientific Authority within Policy-making 125 The Institutional Requirements for the Representation of the Authority of Science 132 Representation, Resemblance, and Respect 137 Conclusion 147 V. JUDGING CLAIMS TO REPRESENT THE AUTHORITY OF SCIENCE 149 The Importance of the Aim of Representative Claims and How They Are Judged 152 Judging the Rhetoric of Claims 156 Epistemological Grounds for Judgment 162 Ethical Grounds for Judgment 165 Provisional Judgments of Representative Claims—the Case of Climate Policy 168 The Third National Climate Assessment 169 G77+China Walkout at COP-19 174 A Protester in Manila 177 Conclusion 182 VI. CONCLUSION: THE AVOIDANCE OF THE POLITICIZATION OF SCIENCE 184 The Grounds and Scope of Scientific Authority in Environmental Policy-making 185 Scientific Authority as Remedy for the Politicization of Science 187 vi BIBLIOGRAPHY 192 vii FIGURES Figure 1. Causal relationships in Producing Scientific Knowledge and Policy Outcomes 20 2. Protester at U.S. Embassy in Manila 178 1 Introduction A number of biophysical phenomena currently threaten the continuation of existing human societies. For instance, current natural resource and energy use and waste production exceed levels that can be sustained by the biosphere (Boyden and Dovers 1992). Additionally, anthropogenic changes to the biophysical environment such as climate change, changes to land- use patterns and the deterioration of ecosystem services have caused an increased threat to public health through five mechanisms—exposure to infectious disease, water scarcity, food scarcity, natural disasters, and population displacement (Myers and Patz 2009). More specifically, the emergence of infectious disease has resulted from changes to human interactions with wildlife, such as the increase in overall interaction caused by human population expansion, (Daszak, Cunningham, and Hyatt 2000). Additionally, global agricultural output is threatened by the desertification of global drylands—primarily caused by the salinization of soil (Dregne and Chou 1992) and the decline in managed and wild pollinators (Meffe 1998). To understand the role of science in policy-making, we must consider how the relationship between human societies and the biophysical world should change in order to respond to these threats and produce societies whose biophysical relationships can be sustained by Earth systems. How to produce a sustainable society is a complex problem in two ways. First, many interrelated specific problems—such as climate change, water scarcity, net energy decline, etc.— need to be addressed in order to achieve sustainability and they must be resolved in a way that is compatible with sustainable resolutions to the others. Second, these problems are biophysical as well as sociopolitical, which further complicates attempts to address them. For instance, climate 2 change is both a biophysical phenomenon caused by increased greenhouse gas concentrations in the atmosphere and a sociopolitical problem requiring determination of a just distribution of energy resources, among other considerations1. Noting the existence of the biophysical and sociopolitical dimensions of sustainability means drawing attention to one of the most difficult and important tasks for designing a sustainable society—balancing the needs for a biophysically sustainable and a socio-politically desirable solution. Though leaving the resolution of these problems solely to scientific experts is likely to produce biophysically sustainable outcomes, such a solution would hinder the democratic self-rule of the people and the value of directing our collective lives by granting decision-making power to the scientific elite. However, leaving the resolution of these problems solely to the direction of the people is unlikely to lead to biophysical success because the people lack the knowledge of biophysical relationships of cause and effect necessary to identify biophysical problems and possible solutions. Thus, to design a sustainable society, we need to identify a way in which the people retain authority over the direction of their common lives, while also relying upon scientific expertise for explanations of biophysical relationships of cause and effect. In other words, in order to successfully design a sustainable society we must balance the normative desirability of democratic decision-making with the greater empirical success provided by the biophysical understanding of scientific expertise. The aim of my argument is to defend a balance between these normative and epistemic demands of environmental policies by arguing for a particular understanding of the authority scientific explanations should have within environmental policy-making. By clarifying the authority that science warrants as a particular type of explanation of biophysical relationships of 1 For a more detailed discussion of climate change and the importance of considering both the biophysical and sociopolitical dimensions of the problem, see Hulme (2009). 3 cause and effect, I contribute to our understanding of the role of scientific explanations within environmental policy-making in three ways. First, my account of the authority of scientific explanations, insofar as it is a theory of the authority warranted by scientific explanations, provides reasons for the exclusion of other sources of biophysical explanations within policy- making. Previous discussions of the political role of biophysical explanations begin by limiting the scope of their inquiries to scientific explanations without offering reasons for why other sources of biophysical explanation are not included (Brown 2009; Pielke Jr 2007). While the exclusion of other biophysical explanations is premised on exactly the authority of science I am arguing for, the act of assuming such authority opens up past theories to serious criticism for failing to justify their starting position—that science is the
Recommended publications
  • APA Newsletters
    APA Newsletters Volume 06, Number 2 Spring 2007 NEWSLETTER ON PHILOSOPHY AND LAW FROM THE EDITOR, STEVEN SCALET ARTICLES BRIAN H. BIX “Joseph Raz and Conceptual Analysis” JULES L. COLEMAN “Law and Political Morality” TIMOTHY ENDICOTT “Interpretation, Jurisdiction, and the Authority of Law” KENNETH EINAR HIMMA “Revisiting Raz: Inclusive Positivism and the Concept of Authority” LIAM MURPHY “Razian Concepts” STEPHEN PERRY “Two Problems of Political Authority” © 2007 by The American Philosophical Association ISSN: 1067-9464 APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy and Law Steven Scalet, Editor Spring 2007 Volume 06, Number 2 relating to such theories. In particular, I will look at the role of conceptual analysis in legal theory, focusing on some recent FROM THE EDITOR work by Joseph Raz.1 I. Overview Edition in Tribute to Joseph Raz It was a commonplace in the history of jurisprudence to focus on the inquiry, what is law? It is worth taking a few moments Joseph Raz is professor at Columbia University Law School to consider the question more closely. and research faculty at Oxford University. His writings influence generations of scholars and his many students are now among First and foremost, there is a potential confusion (heightened 2 the leading scholars in philosophy of law. in English more than in other major languages ), as “law,” even if focused on matters jurisprudential (and not speaking of physical For this edition of the Newsletter we invited leading political laws, the laws of games, social conventions, etc.), can refer to and legal philosophers to analyze some aspect of Professor a number of different, if related, matters: most prominently, Raz’s ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy (PHIL) 1
    Philosophy (PHIL) 1 PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) PHIL 3000 Plato's Metaphysics (4 Credits) A systematic study of Plato's Middle and Late Period Dialogues that focuses on his arguments for the existence of abstract objects and the development of Plato's theory of Forms. Prerequisite: At least Junior standing or permission of instructor. PHIL 3003 Plato's Theory of Knowledge (4 Credits) A systematic investigation of Plato's treatments of knowledge throughout the dialogues with a focus on the theory of recollection, Forms as objects of knowledge, the relationship between the Forms and perceptual experience, and the challenges posed by notions of true and false belief. Prerequisites: At least Junior standing or permission of instructor. PHIL 3005 Cosmopolitics (4 Credits) This class will be a close reading of Plato's dialogue Timaeus, with a special focus on the cosmological, theological, and political dimensions of the text. PHIL 3010 Great Thinkers: Aristotle (4 Credits) A study of Aristotle's central theories and doctrines. Prerequisite: junior standing or instructor's permission. PHIL 3011 Great Thinkers: Virginia Woolf (4 Credits) In this course we will read Virginia Woolf as a philosopher. We will discuss her philosophy of nature, knowledge, art, politics, science, sensation, gender, and materialism throughout her fiction and non-fiction writings. PHIL 3023 Great Thinkers: Maimonides: Politics, Prophecy and Providence (4 Credits) Using "The Guide for the Perplexed" as our central text, we explore the complex philosophical ideas of Moses Maimonides (1135-1204), one of the central figures in medieval philosophy and Jewish thought. Our study includes analyses of his ideas on principles of faith, human perfection, intellectual vs.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosopher-Prophet in Avicenna's Political Philosophy
    The philosopher-prophet in Avicenna's political philosophy Author: James Winston Morris Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/4029 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Published in Political aspects of Islamic philosophy, pp. 152-198 Use of this resource is governed by the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons "Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 United States" (http:// creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/us/) The P~~losopher-Prophet in. AVic~nna's Political Philosophy. Chapter 4 of The PolItICal Aspects of IslamIc PhIlosophy, ed. C. Butterworth, Cambridge Harvard University Press, 1992, pp. 142-188. ' -FOUR- The Philosopher-Prophet in Avicenna~s Political Philosophy James W. Morris With time, human beings tend to take miracles for granted. Perhaps the most lasting and public of all miracles, those to which Islamic philosophers devoted so much of their reflections, were the political achievements of the prophets: how otherwise obscure figures like Moses, Jesus, and Muhammad came to shape the thoughts and actions of so much of civilized humanity. Within the high culture of Islamic civilization, the thought and writings of an itinerant Persian doctor and court administrator we know as Avicenna (370/980~28/1037) came to play a similarly central role: for almost a millenium, each of the tra­ ditions of Islamic thought claiming a wider, universal human validity has appealed either directly to his works or to logical and metaphysical disciplines whose Islamic forms were directly grounded in them. This study considers some of the central philosophic under­ pinnings of that achievement.
    [Show full text]
  • A Glossary of Terms and Concepts in Peace and Conflict Studies
    A GLOSSARY OF TERMS AND CONCEPTS IN PEACE AND CONFLICT STUDIES AUTHOR: CHRISTOPHER E. MILLER EDITOR: MARY E. KING A GLOSSARY OF TERMS AND CONCEPTS IN PEACE AND CONFLICT STUDIES SECOND EDITION A GLOSSARY OF TERMS AND CONCEPTS IN PEACE AND CONFLICT STUDIES AFRICA PROGRAMME © 2005 University for Peace Portions of this publication may be reproduced free of charge provided that the source is acknowledged. Views expressed in this publication are those of the author(s). They do not necessarily reflect the views of the University for Peace. ISBN 9977-925-36-4 A GLOSSARY OF TERMS AND CONCEPTS IN PEACE AND CONFLICT STUDIES The mission of the University for Peace is to provide humanity with an international institution of higher education for peace with the aim of promoting among all human beings a spirit of understanding, tolerance, and peaceful coexistence, to stimulate cooperation among peoples, and to help lessen obstacles and threats to world peace and progress in keeping with the noble aspirations proclaimed in the Charter of the United Nations. A GLOSSARY OF TERMS AND CONCEPTS IN PEACE AND CONFLICT STUDIES UNIVERSITY FOR PEACE AFRICA PROGRAMME Addis Ababa Office UPEACE Africa Programme Post Office Box 1176 Addis Ababa, Ethiopia Telephone: + 251 1 234 026 Email: [email protected] Web: www.africa.upeace.org Geneva Office 5 chemin du Rivage 1292 Chambésy / Geneva, Switzerland Telephone: +41 22 737 30 80 Fax: +41 22 737 30 90 Email: [email protected] Main Campus & Headquarters Post Office Box 138-6100 San José, Costa Rica Telephone: +506 205-9000
    [Show full text]
  • Islamic Philosophy and Politics (The Experience of Interpretation)
    ISSN 2039-2117 (online) Mediterranean Journal of Social Sciences Vol 6 No 6 S1 ISSN 2039-9340 (print) MCSER Publishing, Rome-Italy November 2015 Islamic Philosophy and Politics (The Experience of Interpretation) Viktor Vasilievich Zheltov Maxim Viktorovich Zheltov Sergey Vladimirovich Birukov Kemerovo State University, Russian Federation, 650043, Kemerovo, Krasnaya Street,6 Doi:10.5901/mjss.2015.v6n6s1p537 Abstract The article highlights the historical background of the diversity of Islam related to the influence of pre-Islamic culture in different countries, as well as the impact of socio-economic cooperation of Islamic countries with the West. It analytically reveals the phenomenon of Islamization of ancient Greek philosophy as a phenomenon of its adaptation to the realities of the Islamic world showing opportunities of philosophy as a science in the Islamic world, and the role of the Qur'an in the development of philosophy and politics in the Muslim countries. The article touches upon the questions of the role of Islam in the Muslim countries` politics, trans-prospects and building democracy in the Arab world analyzing “The Arab Spring” political legacy and future perspectives of its influence. Keywords: ancient Greek philosophy, Islamic philosophy, Islam, Moslem world, the Koran, Revelation, politics, democracy, pluralism 1. Introduction As a rule, the philosophical and political literature says about Islam, as they say in general terms, i.e. as a single doctrine. Meanwhile, there is no single Islam. Political scientists and religious-WIDE Islamic thinkers rightly speak of the existence of: Sunni-ray and Shia Islam; Islam, which are practiced in Riyadh (Saudi Arabia) and Bamako (Mali); version of Islam in Morocco and Indonesia.
    [Show full text]
  • The Analytical-Continental Divide: Styles of Dealing with Problems
    Haverford College Haverford Scholarship Faculty Publications Political Science 2016 The analytical-Continental divide: Styles of dealing with problems Thomas J. Donahue Haverford College, [email protected] Paulina Ochoa Espejo Haverford College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.haverford.edu/polisci_facpubs Repository Citation Donahue J. Thomas, Espejo Ochoa Paulina, (2016). "The analytical-Continental divide: Styles of dealing with problems." European Journal of Political Theory, 15(2):138-154 This Journal Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Political Science at Haverford Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Haverford Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. XML Template (2015) [12.5.2015–3:37pm] [1–17] //blrnas3.glyph.com/cenpro/ApplicationFiles/Journals/SAGE/3B2/EPTJ/Vol00000/150024/APPFile/SG- EPTJ150024.3d (EPT) [PREPRINTER stage] Article EJPT European Journal of Political Theory 0(0) 1–17 ! The Author(s) 2015 The analytical–Continental Reprints and permissions: divide: Styles of dealing sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/1474885115585324 with problems ept.sagepub.com Thomas J. Donahue and Paulina Ochoa Espejo Haverford College, USA Abstract What today divides analytical from Continental philosophy? This paper argues that the present divide is not what it once was. Today, the divide concerns the styles in which philosophers deal with intellectual problems: solving them, pressing them, resolving them, or dissolving them. Using ‘the boundary problem’, or ‘the democratic paradox’, as an example, we argue for two theses. First, the difference between most analytical and most Continental philosophers today is that Continental philosophers find intelligible two styles of dealing with problems that most analytical philosophers find unintelligible: pressing them and resolving them.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Politics 9503A/Philosophy 9119A: Central Problems in Political Theory
    Politics 9503A/Philosophy 9119A: Central Problems in Political Theory September-December 2020 Tuesday Zoom meetings 3:30-5:20 Charles Jones, 661-2111 x85060, [email protected], SSC 4129 Zoom Office Hours: Wednesdays 1:30-3:00 & by appointment This course examines some central problems in political theory: political authority, property and the market, distributive justice and equality, liberty, and democracy. We will study both classic works and recent scholarship on these issues. By the end of the course, students will be able to: (1) Describe the problem of political authority and explain (and evaluate) the main arguments in its favour, (2) Assess the case for and against private property rights, (3) Explain the pros and cons of markets in goods and services as a means of organizing an economy, (4) Describe the problem of distributive justice (‘who should get what?’) and explain the relative merits of competing approaches to this problem, (5) Evaluate the value of equality and sufficiency as competing goals of just distribution, (6) Explain the arguments on both sides of the debate between distributive egalitarians and relational egalitarians in their answers to the question, ‘What is the point of equality?’, (7) Identify the competing conceptions of liberty in the history of political theory and adjudicate between them, (8) Evaluate the case for and against ‘libertarian paternalism’ as an approach to public policy, and (9) Outline the most important arguments against and for democracy as a form of public and private decision-making. Texts Course readings will be posted on the OWL site. There is one book to purchase: Elizabeth Anderson, Private Government: How Employers Rule Our Lives (and Why We Don’t Talk about it), Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2017.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Authority and Its Critics
    EPISTEMIC AUTHORITY AND ITS CRITICS LINDA ZAGZEBSKI University of Oklahoma The purpose of Epistemic Authority1 is to defend the rationality of belief on authority from the modern assumption that the ultimate authority over the self is the self. More specifically, the strategy is to show that traditional epistemic authority, including the teaching authority of institutions such as the Catholic Church, can be justified even if we accept the modern value of autonomy. The book begins with a brief historical and philosophical investigation of the rejection of epistemic authority, particularly as it is arises from the ideal of epistemic self-reliance. I argue that although that ideal dominates much of contemporary discourse, it cannot be defended from the work of Plato, Descartes, Locke, or Kant, and that the epistemological and moral arguments for self-reliance are weak. I then turn to an extended argument that the conscientiously self-reflective person is committed to authority in the realm of belief. I argue that epistemic (and emotional) self-trust is both rational and inescapable, that consistent epistemic self- trust commits us to trust in others, and that some of those others satisfy conditions for epistemic authority modelled on Joseph Raz’s well-known theses of political authority. I apply epistemic authority to authority in communities, defend epistemic authority in the domains of morality and religion, and argue that the account of epistemic authority I give shows that epistemic authority is compatible with intellectual autonomy. Believing on authority is a demand of conscientious self-governance. It is not only compatible with autonomy, but follows from it.
    [Show full text]
  • Authority, Legitimacy and Epistemic Accounts of Democratic Law
    Authority, Legitimacy and Epistemic Accounts of Democratic Law: Estlund vs. Habermas Jonathan Trejo-Mathys ABSTRACT: David Estlund has recently articulated the most sophisticated form of epistemic proceduralism available in Anglophone legal and political philosophy, one that grants that there are normative political truths and that some possess superior knowledge of them but defeats the claim that superior knowledge can successfully confer legislative authority. In the course of his argument, he charges Habermas’ rival version of proceduralism with ‘political nihilism’. The first two sections of this paper show that this charge is false and based upon a misunderstanding of Habermas and that it obscures the fact that Habermas provides a potentially stronger form of epistemic proceduralism that defeats the claim that those who know should rule by undermining the very idea that there could be some who possess superior normative political knowledge. The third section discusses a weak point in Habermas’ justification of coercive democratic law that is revealed in the course of the defense and suggests a Kantian way of remedying it. Trejo-Mathys 1 Epistemic Accounts of Democratic Authority and Legitimacy: Estlund vs. Habermas1 Epistemic views of democracy defend its legitimacy, or stronger, its authority in light of the epistemic virtues that the democratic process displays with respect to tracking some normative standard such as justice or the common good, however those are understood. They involve the belief that the truth about such matters, and in particular a sufficiently strong and effective tendency to pursue and discover it, is a necessary part of the justification of political authority and the legitimacy of the norms issued by such authority.
    [Show full text]
  • Justification of Political Authority in Theological(Islamic) Epistemology
    JISMOR 5 JISMOR 5 Justification of Political Authority in Theological(Islamic) Epistemology Mojtaba Zarvani Abstract The political views of the speculative theologians have been more abstraction and justification of the events of the age rather than an issue resulting from their scholastic theological geometry. “In other words, in the field of politics, the speculative theology [not only today, but also always] has been a sort of filling the gap and resurfacing the work”. In order to prove this argument, we will show a process during which from the early days of Islam up to Ghazzali, gradually the monitoring elements which challenge the authority of the Islamic ruler became fade. Moreover, the speculative theologians in their political views gradually reach to a point in which they consider a ruler with no specific features qualified to serve as a judge. That is to say, the authoritative nature of the Abbasid government, which according to many thinkers is the heritage of imitation from the Iranian and Sāsānid traditions made a situation that even the Ash’arits thinker who used to consider the return to the age of The rightly Guided Caliphs as a Utopia, mutilated and made a selection out of the traditions of the holy prophet and the caliphs. Keywords: political authority, kalām, epistemology Foreword This research has taken form round a problem rather than a subject. Therefore, the appropriate statement of the issue and faithfulness to it has been emphasized. The difficulty of conducting research by a researcher who is so naive in such kind of experiences is clear to everybody.
    [Show full text]
  • Utilitarianism and Beyond: Contemporary Analytical Political Theory David Miller
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Political Science Faculty Publications Political Science 2006 Utilitarianism and Beyond: Contemporary Analytical Political Theory David Miller Richard Dagger University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/polisci-faculty-publications Part of the Political Theory Commons Recommended Citation Miller, David, and Richard Dagger. "Utilitarianism and Beyond: Contemporary Analytical Political Theory." In The Cambridge History of Twentieth-Century Political Thought, edited by Terence Ball and Richard Bellamy, 446-70. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Political Science at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Political Science Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 21 Utilitarianism and beyond: contemporary analytical political theory david miller and richard dagger General features In this chapter we sketch a body of political thought that became predom- inant in the second half of the twentieth century among academic politi- cal philosophers, primarily in the English-speaking world, but increasingly elsewhere, too. To call this type of political thought ‘analytical’ may not be particularly revealing, but no other term better describes the movement in question. Sometimes ‘liberal political theory’ is used, and there is in- deed a close connection between analytical theory and liberalism. But that label is in one way too broad and in another too narrow for this kind of political thinking: too broad because liberalism has assumed many different philosophical guises in the course of a history much longer than that of our subject; and too narrow because those who engage in this kind of political theory use methods of analysis and techniques of argument that are not confined to liberals.
    [Show full text]
  • Conclusion. a Research Agenda for Political Pragmatism
    Conclusion. A Research Agenda for Political Pragmatism Throughout this book I have contended that, in its broadest terms, a wide view of democracy can help us revive and advance the democratic project, insofar as it reconnects the political phase of democracy to its social roots. Such a theory provides us with precious theoretical resources to tackle some of the most pressing challenges of our time, such as the rise of popu- lism, democratic deficits, the ongoing crisis of formal political institu- tions, and the emergence of new forms of discrimination. By including the whole of social life in the concept of democracy, the wide view is better suited not only to the critical task of identifying the cracks and tensions that threaten the democratic project, but also, and especially, to the recon- structive task of providing concrete guidance for reform projects, whether for democratizing the workplace and other social institutions, for extend- ing the scope of the associational principle to new production practices, for reducing global inequality by politicizing consumerism, or for achiev- ing greater degrees of accountability in global politics. Indeed, it seems to me that it is only by radically broadening our conceptual framework that we can hope to overcome the practical and theoretical deadlocks that democracy faces today, precisely because this enlargement allows us to come closer to the true reasons that render the democratic project so important and so inescapable, even when its political performances appear © The Author(s) 2019 395 R. Frega, Pragmatism and the Wide View of Democracy, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18561-9 396 Conclusion.
    [Show full text]