A Bronze Statuette in the British Museum and the 'Aristotle' of the Palazzo Spada Author(S): Katharine A

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Bronze Statuette in the British Museum and the 'Aristotle' of the Palazzo Spada Author(S): Katharine A A Bronze Statuette in the British Museum and the 'Aristotle' of the Palazzo Spada Author(s): Katharine A. Esdaile Source: The Journal of Hellenic Studies, Vol. 34 (1914), pp. 47-59 Published by: Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/624475 Accessed: 05-02-2016 06:20 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies and Cambridge University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Hellenic Studies. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 05 Feb 2016 06:20:59 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions A BRONZE STATUETTE IN THE BRITISH MUSEUM AND THE 'ARISTOTLE' OF THE PALAZZO SPADA. [PLATES II.-VII.] AMONGthe most important bronzes in the British Museum is the statuette of a philosopher, said to have been found in dredging the harbour at Brindisi, which was acquired in 18651 (P1. II.). It measures 20 inches (50-8 cm.) in height, and represents a bearded man seated-though the original seat has disappeared-and resting his chin on his right hand; his left arm, muffled in his only garment, the himation that passes over his left shoulder, lies across his lap and supports the right arm; the right foot is drawn back behind the left, and he wears sandals elaborately tied. The thoughtful and interesting head (P1. III.) suggests in type and period the pleasanter portraits of Aeschines and the newly discovered Aristotle; hair and beard are cut close,2 the features are small and well shaped, the whole effect in singular harmony with the reflective pose of the figure. The surface has suffered from the action of water, and there is a large hole on the left shoulder, and a crack running down the arm. The statuette is compared by Michaelis, one of the very few writers to mention it, with the seated 'Demosthenes' of Petworth, a portrait statue of Attic origin to which a head of the orator has been wrongly affixed; 3 but though the composition is similar, the statue lacks the distinctive feature of the bronze, the hand wrapped in the himation and laid across the lap. A much closer parallel is to be found in one of the figures, that seated in front of the sundial, on the famous mosaic discovered some years ago at Pompeii, representing an assembly of philosophers or learned men,4 which is a variant of that in the Villa Albani from Sarsina in Umbria; in the latter, however, the distinctive left arm is placed in a different position, and it is obviously unsafe to generalise when the only known copies of a composition differ in an important point. Again, in the matter of dress the parallel is not exact, 1 B.AM.Catalogue of Bronzes, No. 848; 3 Wrongly, because the type of the seated Michaelis, Ancient Marbles in Great Britain, orator is without authority: Bernoulli, Grn p. 608; Encycl, Brit. ninth ed. vol. ii. p. 365, Ikon. ii. pp. 78-9 ; Studniczka, das Bildnis des Fig. 12, a poor cut which is so far the only Aristoteles, p. 7. published illustration of the figure. 4 Monum. d. Lincei, 1898, PI. XII.; Ber- 2 The figure is not beardless, as stated in the noulli, Gr. Ikon. ii. pp. 36-37 ; Helbig Fiihrer,3 Catalogue. ii. p. 46, and references. 47 This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 05 Feb 2016 06:20:59 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 48 KATHARINE A. ESDAILE as the figure on the mosaic wears a tunic, and so can hardly represent a truly Greek conception of the head of a philosophic -school; the coincidence of pose is worth noting, but there can be no question of a community of subject between the mosaic and the bronze. It is, however, not a little strange that the relation of the latter to a group of other works which includes three replicas on a small but varying scale and one life-size and world- famous statue, should have escaped notice, but this is partly due, no doubt, to the fact that not one of these replicas has the original head. In the combination of these with the British Museum bronze lies the solution of one of the famous enigmas of ancient art. The replicas are as follows:- (a) Bronze statuette in the British Museum. (The literature of this work is very scanty; the available references have been already given.) (b) Statuette in the Galleria dei Candelabri of the Vatican, P1. V., 'two palms high' (Welcker), often called Sophocles on the strength of the restored head; restored are also the bare feet, the right arm, the supports of the seat, and the plinth, and the figure struck me when I examined it in October, 1912, as having been worked over or at least much polished. (Clarac, P1. 846, No. 2132, 'Rome, Coll. Chablais'; Pistolesi vi. P1. 29; Monumenti Amaranziani 30; Welcker, A.D. i. p. 460; Helbig, Fiihrer 2 No. 370, omitted in Helbig ; Reinach, Repertoire i. p. 513.) (c) Statuette in the Museo Barracco, P1. VI., 201 in. ('515 m.) in height, unrestored: head and right hand missing, but the original seat with its curved and reeded legs preserved intact; on the seat is a cushion, treated with extreme realism, as are the forms of the lean and wrinkled body and the drapery, which is bolder and looser than in the other replicas; sandals elaborately tied, differing slightly in the details of the knot from those of (a). (' Vieux savant,' Collection Barracco, P1. LXIV.; 'formerly in the collection of the antiquary Scalambrini.') (d) Statuette formerly in Dresden (Fig. 1), 'anderthalb Ellen hoch' (Welcker), wrongly restored with the head of Euripides; the bare feet and right arm holding a scroll are clearly restorations; as to the seat, it is impossible to judge from the shaded drawing by which alone we know the work. (Le Plat, Recueil des Marbres Antiques, P1. III.; Clarac, P1. 841, No. 2093 D, after Le Plat; Welcker, A.D. i. p. 487; the latter, writing in 1867, notes that the statuette was omitted from contemporary guide- books; it has not since reappeared.) To sum up, (a) gives us the original head, but the surface of the bronze has suffered, as much in the head as elsewhere, and it cannot be relied on for minute details; (b) and (c) give us the form of the seat, a stool-a cushion worked with remarkable realism is added in the Barracco example- with delicately curved and reeded legs, and (c) is also noteworthy for the extreme care with which the wrinkled skin about the breast and armpits is rendered, shewing that the subject was an elderly man,5 and that the type is post-Lysippic. This is confirmed by the type of head in (a), which finds 5 (b) is a relatively poor copy, and has apparently been worked over; (d) cannot be judged of by the engraving. This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 05 Feb 2016 06:20:59 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions J.H.S. VOL. XXXIV. (1914). PL. II. ?r ?1~ ;ar? .~ ii i ;~ fL-- ,. IBi ?; r~RRI~'.~'~?%rUElsaF;~I;,~:? "r Z? d i ~B~i~?~?~Bl~pi~,~l~'7T "?r".lx~?`~~'~r~a~i~b~: Pil ?r: i- :I ?:?:ql ,:: ?, : I- -dELeCI~-` ~ ---~-CU~ ,t-?~ '1 I'i i* -::: $~8~~ r;i :iS?~ ,j t~ :' 5. ~: ?;~4 .?: e; a ~a~k~S ,ezr~,?y: ???; :~" -~ t "''1.~ This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 05 Feb 2016 06:20:59 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BRONZE STATUETTE OF ARISTIPPUS BRITISH MUSEUM. 1- j's At",t 3-4 41?7 4A?~Z`. 4 IwA 'Ar'-Af tLr Aid I r ARISTIPPUS: HEAD OF BRONZE STATUETTE BRITISH MUSEUM. This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 05 Feb 2016 06:20:59 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions : :i,:~-:,::;::i::i,:i:,-::::?i:l~~_~-~~~- :?:-:~--::'-::-~::::":--;-::::-::-'::~iii:?-:?:-~~:::;--:I-:-~-:-?:_--_:::::;:::::'::_:::i:a_:-:4:'~--:?i;:-'i"'"' :j; i:il:-::??:::::-: i-:::i:- i?::-:-C_:~_ : :i;- ;::-!i:: j:-; ?i;:-: ?1I:_:--~_i~:::r_ i::?i::-:~-:~---~ --1 :?:i:,--::::'i-,,,,,-~~-,~_::~~li'iiiii-s8~l~~-::-;:: ::::::::,:::i::;-:,:i:;:::~~::::1 i':;:::-?:-':-:='":-::;-: ;-i~i-: :,::i--?-?d-~_ ::i_~~~_:i~ :::-,:; i~-ii ~I~LB~I~B I :.::::-::~ :e ~a~ ? ~r CP ~-aBP I ? i:::::::::::i--:Jii_:i-i-:-:-:i-o--ii:6iiii:l_:-- -i:4ii~::*i~-;i~:-:::_:? iii I 34P~B~j~ii~ E:? C- I r x si x C< :":: •) ,1 v.. ARNDT-BRUCKMANN Griechische u. rimische Prlrdi'ts. ARISTIPPUS: MARBLE HEAD IN FLORENCE <I This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 05 Feb 2016 06:20:59 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions R9 JN Ne- NK? x 0,,:17?0 1?g N -'n A 'v- 40wow .5, M., 'x: 'MM IN, VN? om A ;K.- AM Wr >n ?A-Ma vw .:xom :?:::NMA'Mom gym on o"- A Al, K-A.K.
Recommended publications
  • The Polemical Practice in Ancient Epicureanism* M
    UDK 101.1;141.5 Вестник СПбГУ. Философия и конфликтология. 2019. Т. 35. Вып. 3 The polemical practice in ancient Epicureanism* M. M. Shakhnovich St. Petersburg State University, 7–9, Universitetskaya nab., St. Petersburg, 199034, Russian Federation For citation: Shakhnovich M. M. The polemical practice in ancient Epicureanism. Vestnik of Saint Petersburg University. Philosophy and Conflict Studies, 2019, vol. 35, issue 3, pp. 461–471. https://doi.org/10.21638/spbu17.2019.306 The article explores the presentation methods of a philosophical doctrine in Greek and Ro- man Epicureanism; it is shown that for the ancient, middle, and Roman Epicureans a con- troversy with representatives of other philosophical schools was a typical way of present- ing their own views. The polemical practice, in which the basic principles of Epicureanism were expounded through the criticism of other philosophical systems, first of all, Academics and Stoics, was considered not only as the preferred way of presenting the own doctrine, but also as the most convenient rhetorical device, which had, among other things, didac- tic significance. The founder of the school, Epicurus, often included in his texts the terms used in other philosophical schools, giving them a different, often opposite, content. While presenting his teaching in the treatise “On Nature” or in letters to his followers, Epicurus pushed off the opinions of Democritus, Plato, and the Stoics, but resorted mainly to implicit criticism of his opponents, often without naming them by name. His closest students and later followers — Metrodorus, Hermarchus, Colotes, Philodemus, Lucretius, Diogenes of Oenoanda — continuing the controversy with the Academics and the Stoics, more frank- ly expressed their indignation about the “falsely understood Epicureanism” or erroneous opinions.
    [Show full text]
  • Freed from Desire1 Countering Consumerism with Critical Epicureanism
    Freed From Desire1 Countering Consumerism with Critical Epicureanism Master Thesis Philosophy by Robin Habbé, written under guidance of Johan Hartle ABSTRACT: Consumer society has the consumer in a tight hold; due to the cyclical nature of desire the consumer is manipulated to keep on consuming with disastrous ecological and social problems as a result. In my thesis I will elucidate the rise and the workings of contemporary consumer societies, more specifically the element of hedonism, because the organization of consumer society can be categorized as hedonistic. I will discuss hedonism and happiness as understood by Marcuse, as well as tactics for liberation from the imposed desires to consume. I will discover what room we have for emancipating the consumer by providing an alternative form of hedonism, based in Epicureanism. This thesis will show that Marcuse and Epicurus have very similar ideas as to how we should live happily, but most importantly on how to distinguish between true and false desires in order to live a more free and happy life, and to not destroy the planet while living. Keywords: Consumerism, Liberation, Hedonism, Emancipation, Epicureanism, Desire, Happiness, Marcuse, Aesthetic Revisioning, Critical Hedonism 1 This title is a reference to the 1996 dance song by Gala, a Belgian performer. The lyrics seem to be very much aligned with the teachings of Epicurus: condemning money, power and fame and the desire for them as something we should liberate ourselves from through strong beliefs. I would certainly recommend listening to them. ~ 1 ~ Introduction We live in strange times: most of the affluent inhabitants on our beautiful planet are consuming away an immense proportion of the scarce resources we have left.
    [Show full text]
  • Lucretius on Creation and Evolution: a Commentary on De Rerum Natura 5.772--1104 by Gordon Campbell Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, 2003
    Lucretius on Creation and Evolution: A Commentary on De rerum natura 5.772--1104 by Gordon Campbell Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, 2003. Pp. xii + 385. ISBN 0--19--926396--5. Cloth $114.80 Reviewed by Brooke Holmes University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill [email protected] If survival of the fittest is a principle as relevant to ideas as it is to species, Darwinism has proved to be a hardy breed, especially if we judge provocation to be a sign of life. Last November alone, voters in Pennsylvania ousted school board members who had instated poli- cies that gave Intelligent Design a hearing alongside Darwin in ninth- grade biology, while the Kansas Board of Education removed obsta- cles to teaching both perspectives. The Austrian Cardinal Christoph Schoenborn felt obliged to go on the record once again about the Church’s views on the debate over evolution in America. And an am- bitious exhibition simply entitled Darwin opened at the American Museum of Natural History in New York. One reviewer [Rothstein 2005], citing an 1844 letter in which Darwin says that writing about his ideas was like confessing a murder, takes the curator to task for domesticating a bizarre and shocking idea. What is so unnerving about Darwinism? The Cardinal is blunt: It’s all about materialism, that’s the key issue [Heneghan 2005]. It is the idea that matter is the only reality. Epicureanism is Antiquity’s most infamous promoter of mate- rialism, as well as the attendant horrors outlined by the Kansan Board—secular humanism, atheism, and the idea that life is acciden- tal, both in the everyday and in its genesis.1 Nowhere, perhaps, is the defense of these tenets more vivid and calculated than in the fifth book of Lucretius’ De rerum natura, in which our gaze is shifted from the primordia rerum, the imperishable first-beginnings of things, to 1 Of course, strictly speaking, the Epicureans are not atheists; but their gods inhabit another world and care not a whit for humankind, which is to say that their brand of humanism is aggressively secular.
    [Show full text]
  • Index of Names
    Index of Names Akbar 81, 85, 86, 90, Attenborough, David Biruni, Abu Rayhan 93 99 (Alberonius) 275, Abolkhayr, Abusa’id Aurangzeb 87, 93–94, 276, 280 (Abu-Sa’id Abul- 140 Boethius 72, 73 Khayr) 283 Austin, John Bosanquet, Bernard al-Baqillani, Abu Longshaw 124 31, 34 Bakr 272 Ayer, Alfred Jules 124 Bradley, Francis al-Jabri, Muhammaed Herbert 31, 34, Abid 317 Bacon, Francis 76, 78– 223–224, 235, 236 al-Kindi, Abu Yusuf 79, 93 n.20 Ya’qub ibn Ishaq Badawi, Abd al- Braiterman, Zachary 274, 277, 278–280, Rahman 317 167–169 287 Badiou, Alain 41 Broad, Charlie Alexander (the Great) Bahaei’ (Sheikh) 298, Dunbar 235 45 299 Brunschwig, Jacques Allen, Woody 156 Bajjah, Ibn 54 Amadiume, Ifi (Avempass) 285 Buber, Martin 117–120 Baker, Osman 290 149–154, 160, 162, Amoli, Javadi Balkhi, Jalal al-Din 166, 168 (Ayatollah) 315 Muhammad Buddha 127, 184, 202 Ammonius 72 (Rumi) 294 Burnett, Charles 279 Anaxagoras 289 Barnes, Simon 102 Burnyeat, Miles 64 Aristotle 35–36, 65, Basso, Sebastien 66–68, 71–74, 78–79, 93 Caesar, Julius 47 77–79, 93, 228, 274, Benjamin, Mara Caitanya 85, 93 276, 279, 285, 288, 158–159, 160 n.35 Camus, Albert 28 291, 296, 313 Bennett, Jonathan 32 Candrakīrti 131 Aristoxenus 64 Ben-Ze’ev, Aaron 213 Carneades 47 Ashtiyani, Seyyed Bergson, Henri 8, 30 Cato 47 Jalal ad-Din 315, Berkeley, George 35, Chaucer, Geoffrey 73 316 124 n.4, 125, 128, Chomsky, Noam 191 Aurelius, Marcus 46, 131 Christ (Jesus) 58, 257, 53, 66 n.79 Berkovits, Eliezer 168 260 Arabi, Ibn (Muhi Berlin, Isaiah 51 Chrysippus 48, 54 al-Din al-Arabi) 86, Bernier, François 86– Cicero 46–48, 53 n.28, 294–296, 301 89, 95 55 n.35, 56–57, Ardibili, Safi al-Din Bhattạ̣Nārāyanaạ93 238 296 Bhattacharya, Sibesh Cleombrotus 63 Asada, Akira 22 195 Code, Lorraine 211 323 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophical and Rhetorical Concept of Enargeia at Work in Latin Poetry Robert E
    Florida State University Libraries Electronic Theses, Treatises and Dissertations The Graduate School 2015 Seeing the Unseeable: The Philosophical and Rhetorical Concept of Enargeia at Work in Latin Poetry Robert E. (Robert Edward) Hedrick Follow this and additional works at the FSU Digital Library. For more information, please contact [email protected] FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF ARTS AND SCIENCES SEEING THE UNSEEABLE: THE PHILOSOPHICAL AND RHETORICAL CONCEPT OF ENARGEIA AT WORK IN LATIN POETRY By ROBERT E. HEDRICK, III A Dissertation submitted to the Department of Classics in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Degree Awarded: Spring Semester, 2015 Robert Hedrick defended this dissertation on March 16, 2015. The members of the supervisory committee were: Timothy Stover Professor Co-Directing Dissertation Svetla Slaveva-Griffin Professor Co-Directing Dissertation John Roberts University Representative Nathaniel Stein Committee Member Francis Cairns Committee Member The Graduate School has verified and approved the above-named committee members, and certifies that the dissertation has been approved in accordance with university requirements. ii This manuscript is dedicated to two people who have deeply influenced me and who, in fact, share my name: my grandfather, Robert E. Hedrick (1920-1997), and my father, Robert Hedrick, Jr. My grandfather was a truly great person. He served his country as a captain in the U.S. Army during World War II and saw combat throughout Europe. After returning home, he went on to become the first “Doctor” in the family and was the director of the Orlando location of Florida Southern College. Without him, I would not be the man I am today.
    [Show full text]
  • The Book of Dead Philosophers
    Praise for Simon Critchley's THE BOOK OF DEAD PHILOSOPHERS "A provocative and engrossing invitation to think about the human condition and what philosophy can and can't do to illuminate it." —Financial Times "Concise, witty and oddly heartening." —New Statesman (A 2008 Book of the Year) "Full of wonderful absurdities.... Extremely enjoyable." —The Independent (London) "Simon Critchley is probably the sharpest and most lucid philosopher writing in English today." —Tom McCarthy, author of Remainder "Ingenious. Packed with great stories." —Time Out London "A tremendous addition to an all too sparse literature. Brilliant, entertaining, informative." —New Humanist (UK) "A fabulous concept. [Critchley writes] with dash, humour and an eye for scandalous detail." —The Vancouver Sun "[Critchley is] among the hippest of (living) British philosophers." —The Book Bench, newyorker.com "Surprisingly good fun. Worthy of the prose writings of Woody Allen. .. Not the least of the pleasures of this odd book, lighthearted and occasionally facetious as it is, is that in surveying a chronological history of philoso• phers it provides a sweep through the entire history of philosophy itself." —The Irish Times "Critchley has a lightness of touch, a nimbleness of thought, and a mocking graveyard humour that puts you in mind of Hamlet with a skull." —The Independent on Sunday (London) Simon Critchley "The Book of Dead Philosophers is something of a magic trick: on the surface an amusing and bemused series of blackout sketches of philosophers' often rather humble THE BOOK OF and/or brutal deaths, it actually is an utterly serious, DEAD PHILOSOPHERS deeply moving, cant-free attempt to return us to the gor- geousness of material existence, to our creatureliness, to our clownish bodies, to the only immortality available to us (immersion in the moment).
    [Show full text]
  • Empedocles, Epicurus, and the Failure of Sacrifice in Lucretius By
    Empedocles, Epicurus, and the Failure of Sacrifice in Lucretius by Zackary P. Rider A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the Department of Classics. Chapel Hill 2011 Approved by: James O’Hara James Rives Robert Babcock ABSTRACT ZACKARY P. RIDER: Empedocles, Epicurus, and the Failure of Sacrifice in Lucretius (Under the direction of James O’Hara.) In this thesis, I examine sacrificial ritual as it is portrayed in Lucretius’ De Rerum Natura, focusing on its role in Lucretius’ polemic against religion. In the first chapter, I engage in a detailed analysis of sacrificial scenes in the DRN, showing that sacrifice is regularly shown to have deleterious effects on social relationships. I argue that such a representation renders sacrifice incompatible with Epicurean philosophy as practiced prior to Lucretius because of Epicurus’ known approval of the practice, and that such a discrepancy suggests a rift in thought between Lucretius and his school. In the second chapter, I argue that Lucretius instead uses an Empedoclean model for his portrayal of sacrifice, presenting it and religion as the social analogues to the Empedoclean force Strife, while presenting his Epicurean philosophy as analogous to the Empedoclean force Love, co-opting the earlier poet’s cosmology to his own Epicurean ends. ii TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction ...…………………………………………………………………………... 1 1 Lucretius and Epicurus ...……………………………………………………… 3 1.1 Empedocles at Aulis ...…………………….…………………………….. 6 1.2 Sacrifice in the DRN ...……………………………………………….… 12 1.3 Sacrifice and the (un?)Epicurean Poet .........….....…………………...... 16 2 Lucretius, Epicurus, and Empedocles ...……………………………………..
    [Show full text]
  • Attila Németh, Epicurus on the Self
    Attila Németh, Epicurus On the Self di PAMELA ZINN Attila Németh’s engaging new study, Epicurus On the Self, analyzes Epicurus’ notion of the self and its significance for our understand- ing of Epicurean ethics and philosophy of mind. Németh (= N.) seeks to show that, for Epicurus, the self began at the cradle. The process of developing as a desiring agent occurred largely through the πάθη and self-reflection. In order to accommodate the self as responsible agent, Epicurus held a «non-reductive physicalist position» (p. xiii and passim) on the relationship between the mind and its atoms. This self was constantly developing in relation to the external world, to causation – both internal, like bodily and mental states, and external, like social interactions – and to memory. The book thus aims to con- tribute to our understanding of the relationship between Epicurean ethics and Epicurus’ account of the psychological development of living beings. N. draws primarily on the evidence of the fragments of Book XXV of Epicurus’ On Nature (Περὶ Φύσεως), as published by Simon Laursen. These correspond to the following Herculaneum papyri, as N. groups them: PHerc. 419/1634/697, PHerc. 1420/1056, and PHerc. 1191. The Appendix on pp. 201–202 shows the way that these correspond to N.’s somewhat idiosyncratic relabeling. N. offers new translations of the fragments discussed and, occasionally, new readings. He also draws on related evidence from Epicurus, Lucretius, and — to a less- er extent — Philodemus, Diogenes of Oenoanda, Hermarchus, and Polystratus, as well as from non-Epicurean witnesses, such as Cicero and Alexander of Aphrodisias.
    [Show full text]
  • Epicurean Justice and Law
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2016 Epicurean Justice and Law Jan Maximilian Robitzsch University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Classics Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Robitzsch, Jan Maximilian, "Epicurean Justice and Law" (2016). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 1976. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1976 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1976 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Epicurean Justice and Law Abstract This dissertation concerns a cluster of related issues surrounding the Epicurean conception of justice. First, I show that the Epicureans defend a sophisticated kind of social contract theory and maintain a kind of legal positivism, views that are widely held today and so are of continuing interest for contemporary readers. In doing so, I argue that thinking about justice and law forms an integral part of Epicurean philosophy (pace the standard view). Second, I take up some neglected issues regarding justice and so provide detailed accounts of the metaphysics of moral properties in Epicureanism as well as of Epicurean moral epistemology. After the introduction in chapter 1, I set out the main features of the Epicurean view of justice and law in chapters 2-4. In chapter 2, I explain the basics of the Epicurean conception of justice as an agreement and relate it to Epicurean ethics as whole. In chapter 3, I examine Epicurean culture stories and I point out in what way the Epicurean view is a kind of social contract theory.
    [Show full text]
  • 4Reek Philosophy
    OUTLINES OE THE HISTORY OF 4reek philosophy BY Dr. EDWARD ZELLER TRANSLATED WITH THE AUTHOR'S SANCTION BY SARAH FRANCES ALLEYNE AND -ABBOTT tJNlVEBSITi t NEW YORK HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY 1S86 IN' MEMORIAM SARAH FRANCES ALLE7NE AUTHOR’S PREFACE. F or some years it has been my intention to respond to a request arising from various quarters, and add to my larger work on the Philosophy of the Greeks a short sketch of the same subject. But until the third edition of the History was brought to a conclusion I had not the leisure for the work. Sketches of thi3 kind will proceed on different lines according to the aim which is held in view. My object has been primarily to provide students with a help for academical lectures, which would facilitate preparation, and save the time wasted in writing down facts, without interfering with the lecturer’s work or imposing any fetters upon it. Hence I have made it my task to give my readers a pic­ ture of the contents of the philosophical systems, and the course of their historical development, which should contain all the essential traits— and also to put into their hands the more important literary references and sources. But as in the last points I have not gone beyond what is absolutely necessary, so in the historical account I have as a rule indicated the parts very briefly with which historical considerations of a general kind or special explanations and inquiries are connected, or in viii AUTHOR'S PREFACE. which, it seemed proper to supplement my earlier work.
    [Show full text]
  • Hedonism Before Bentham
    UCL Bentham Project Journal of Bentham Studies, Vol. 17 (2015) Hedonism Before Bentham OLE MARTIN MOEN University of Oslo [email protected] The hedonistic theories of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill are both widely known. Hedonism before Bentham, however, is much less known and, hitherto, no systematic presentation of hedonism’s early history has been written. In this paper I seek to fill this gap in the literature by providing an overview of hedonism in early Indian and ancient Greek thought (Sections 1-4), in Roman and Medieval thought (Section 5), and from the Renaissance until the Enlightenment (Section 6). Keywords: Aristippus, Aristotle; Hedonism; History of Ethics; Plato 1. Early Indian and Greek Hedonism Where does the history of hedonism begin? The answer hinges, naturally, on how we define ‘hedonism’. If we use the term in its popular sense, to mean a way of life where one seeks to promote pleasure and avoid pain, hedonism is no doubt very old, for pleasures and pains attract and repel us irrespective of our philosophical views. If we require something more, however, like philosophical reflection about value and disvalue—and the idea that pleasure and pain are the end points in such matters—the oldest example of hedonism is arguably Cārvāka, a materialist, empiricist, and hedonistic intellectual tradition in early Indian philosophy (5th–6th Centuries BC) from which we now only have fragments. Some of these fragments are poetical: While life is yours, live joyously None can escape Death's searching eye When once this frame of ours they burn How shall it ever again return?1 Other fragments are more practical: By doing only what is considered practical, such as farming, 1 M.
    [Show full text]
  • A Study in Epicurean Poetics: Virgil's Eclogues by David Douglas B. A
    A Study in Epicurean Poetics: Virgil’s Eclogues by David Douglas B. A., McGill University, 2017 A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of Greek and Roman Studies © David Douglas, 2020 University of Victoria All rights reserved. This dissertation may not be reproduced in whole or in part, by photocopy or other means, without the permission of the author. ii A Study in Epicurean Poetics: Virgil’s Eclogues by David Douglas B. A., McGill University, 2017 Supervisory Committee Dr. Cedric Littlewood, Supervisor Department of Greek and Roman Studies Dr. Clifford Roberts, Committee Member Department of Philosophy iii Abstract In this thesis I propose a reading of Virgil’s Eclogues which draws heavily on the author’s background in Epicurean philosophy. My aims are twofold: firstly to illuminate the literary complexities of Virgil’s bucolic poetry, a poetry which is highly allusive and whose meaning rests on knowledge of a wide range of both literary and philosophical sources; and secondly to substantiate a more general theory of Epicurean poetics by observing how such a theory can be seen to unfold in Virgil’s poetic practice. Beginning with the available biographical sources on Virgil’s life, I review the evidence for his adherence to Epicureanism and attempt to provide a rough chronology of his philosophical conversion and early literary output, including the Eclogues. In addition to this historical context I give an overview of Epicurean ethical teachings as they relate to poetry and literature, in order to arrive at a better understanding of the discursive and ideological milieu which would have informed the Eclogues’ composition.
    [Show full text]