<<

M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 1

BEFORE

Something unusual happened in and the Greek colonies of the some twenty-five hundred years ago. Whereas the previous great cultures of the Mediterranean had used mythological stories of the to explain the oper- ations of the and of the self, some of the began to discover new ways of explaining things. Instead of reading their into, or out of, ancient scriptures or poems, they began to use , contemplation, and sensory obser- vation to make sense of . The story, as we know it, began with the Greeks living on the coast of Asia Minor (present-day Turkey). These colonists, such as Thales, tried to find the one common element in the diversity of . Subsequent thinkers, such as Anaximenes, sought not only to find this one common element, but also to find the process by which one form changes into another. Other thinkers, such as , turned to the nature of form itself rather than the basic stuff that takes on a particular form. These lovers of , or , came to very dif- ferent conclusions and often spoke disrespectfully of one another. Some held the to be one, while others insisted that it must be many. Some believed that knowledge was capable of understanding virtually everything about the world, while others that it was not possible to have any knowledge at all. But despite all their differences, there is a thread of continuity, a continuing focus: the human attempt to understand the world, using human reason. This distin- guishes these philosophers from the great that preceded them. There are excellent for beginning a study of with these men and then proceeding to Socrates and . This, after all, is how Western

1 M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 2

2 BEFORE SOCRATES

The Kritos Boy (Statue from the attributed to Kritos.) Ca. 480 B.C. Just as the philosophers of focused on human reason and its ability to know, the artists of the same period examined the human body in its idealized form. (, Acropolis Museum. Photographer: Alison Frantz.)

philosophy did begin, and we can still recapture something of the excitement of this new way of thinking as we move from the bald statements of Thales to the all-embracing questions of Socrates, and thence to Plato’s efforts to fuse criticism with construction. If dissatisfaction with facile answers is the starting point of philosophic thought, the fragments of the Pre-Socratics are especially appropriate for a begin- ning. Not one of their works has survived complete—all we have are scattered quotations and reports from later writers. As a result, Pre-Socratic thought has a mysterious . Cryptic passages and forceful aphorisms, whose original con- text is lost, stimulate the imagination. Instead of looking for “the” answer, one is fascinated by a wealth of possible answers. And in the effort to show why some suggested answers are untenable, one develops critical faculties. Some fragments may remind readers of archaic statues—heads with broken noses, torsos without heads or arms—pieces so perfect in form that one has no M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 3

INTRODUCTION 3

regrets at the loss of the whole and may even believe that the complete work could not have been as fascinating. For all that, most interest in the Pre-Socratics is motivated by the fact that these thinkers furnish the backdrop for the thought of Socrates, Plato, and — this is why one lumps them together as the “Pre-Socratics.” But this magnificent succession of thinkers deserves more respect. Though often enigmatic and at oracular, the Pre-Socratics are distinguished above all by their appeal to reason. And through the appeal to reason, each thinker makes it possible for suc- cessors to exercise criticism, to amend, to develop alternatives, to move beyond. The Pre-Socratics’ influence on Plato was so great that a study of their thought is essential to understanding many passages in his and his ; many were suggested to him by , the , and the Pythagoreans— and, of course, by his originality. Aristotle studied the Pre-Socratics closely and - cussed them at length in the first book of his (reprinted in this volume). Of the later Greek philosophers, it has often been remarked that the Stoics were par- ticularly influenced by Heraclitus, and the Epicureans by . Elements of , an early Greek religious movement, also found their way into the ideas of the Pre-Socratics—most obviously, but by no means only, into — and hence into Plato and, later, into . In fact, a few of the fragments survived only as quotations in the works of early Christian writers.

*** What follows is only a selection. There is no such thing as a complete roster of the Pre-Socratics. The so-called were Socrates’ contemporaries, but and were older than he and had acquired reputations before he came along and challenged them; and they are included here. After all, it was partly in response to their teaching that Socrates’ thought was developed. Among the older writers, it is arguable who was, and who was not, a . Various poets, for example, are occasionally included among the Pre-Socratics. Not counting the Sophists, the present selection concentrates on eleven major figures. They might conveniently be arranged into four groups: (1) the three great Milesians (Thales, , and Anaximenes); (2) the three great independents—figures who came from different places and stood for quite different (Pythagoras, , and Heraclitus); (3) the two great monists ( and ); and, finally, (4) the three great pluralists (, , and Democritus). The only major name missing in this list is , founder of the atomistic philosophy, who is included with his better-known follower, Democritus. If we were to offer all the fragments of these figures, we would have to include such unhelpful items as the following, each given in its entirety: “The joint connects two things”; “as when fig juice binds white milk”; “having kneaded together barley-meal with ” (Empedocles, fragments 32, 33, 34). Instead, the following selections were chosen to give an of each thinker’s main teachings, as far as possible in his own words, and to provide some sense of his way of thinking and feeling. In short, the selections should give us the of thinkers who still have the power to astonish students across roughly twenty-five hundred years.

*** M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 4

4 BEFORE SOCRATES

For a comprehensive work on the Pre-Socratics, see Volumes I and II of W.K.C. Guthrie’s authoritative The of Greek Philosophy, six volumes, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962Ð1981). , Early Greek Philosophy (1892; reprinted New York: Meridian, 1960); John Mansley Robinson, An Introduction to Early Greek Philosophy (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1968); , The Pre-Socratic Philosophers (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1982); and Edward Hussey, The Presocratics (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1995) are standard secondary sources, while the rele- vant sections of W.T. Jones, The Classical (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1969); Frederick Copleston, A History of Philosophy: Volume I, Greece & , Part I (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1962); Friedo Ricken, Philosophy of the Ancients, translated by Eric Watkins (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1991); J.V. Luce, An Introduction to Greek Philosophy (New York: Thames and Hudson, 1992); Catherine Osborne, Presocratic Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: , 2004); and , : A New History of (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004) provide basic introductions. Robert S. Brumbaugh, The Philosophers of Greece (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1981), is an accessible intro- duction with pictures, charts, and maps. Francis MacDonald Cornford, Principium Sapientiae: The Origins of Greek Philosophical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1952), and Werner Jaeger, The of the Early Greek Philosophers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1947) are both classic works that discuss the movement from mythology to philosophy, while Kathryn Morgan, and Philosophy from the Presocratics to Plato (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000) is a more recent study on the . More recent works and refer- ences include Christopher C. Shields, ed., The Blackwell Guide to Ancient Philosophy (London: Blackwell, 2002); David Roochnik, Retrieving the Ancients (London: Blackwell, 2004); Nigel Wilson, ed., Encyclopedia of (London: New York: Routledge, 2005); and Patricia Curd and Daniel Graham, eds., The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008). For collections of , see David J. Furley and R.E. Allen, eds., Studies in Presocratic Philosophy, two volumes (New York: Humanities Press, 1970Ð1975); A.P.D. Mourelatos, ed., The Pre-Socratics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993); , ed., Studies in Greek Philosophy, Volume I: The Presocratics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995); Irwin, ed., Philosophy Before Socrates (Hamden, CT: Garland Publishing, 1995); Mary Louise Gill and Pierre Pellegrin, eds., A Companion to Ancient Philosophy (London: Blackwell, 2004); and Patricia F. O’Grady, Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece (Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2005). In addition to the general sources listed here, the articles in Paul Edwards, ed., The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1967) and Edward Craig, ed., Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (New York: Routledge, 1998) are frequently useful. Consult the following books for these specific thinkers: THALES: Patricia Frances O’Grady, Thales of : The Beginning of Western and Philosophy (Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2002). ANAXIMANDER: Charles H. Kahn, Anaximander and the Origins of Greek (New York: Columbia University Press, 1960). M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 5

INTRODUCTION 5

PYTHAGORAS: Walter Burkert, Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism, translated by Edwin L. Minar, Jr. (Cambridge, : Harvard University Press, 1972); and Arnold Hermann, To Think Like : Pythagoras and Parmenides— The Origins of Philosophy (Las Vegas, NV: Parmenides Publishing, 2004). HERACLITUS: G.S. Kirk, Heraclitus: The Cosmic Fragments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1954); and Charles H. Kahn, The and Thought of Heraclitus (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979). PARMENIDES: Leonardo Tarán, Parmenides: A Text with Translation, Commentary, and Critical Essays (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1965); A.P.D. Mourelatos, The Route of Parmenides (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1970); David Gallop, Parmenides of Elea (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1984); Patricia Curd, The Legacy of Parmenides (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998); Néstor-Luis Cordero, By , It Is: The Thesis of Parmenides (Las Vegas, NV: Parmenides Publishing, 2004); and Scott Austin, Parmenides and the History of (Las Vegas, NV: Parmenides Publishing, 2007). ZENO OF ELEA: Wesley C. Salmon, ed., Zeno’s (Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1970); Adolf Grünbaum, Modern Science and Zeno’s Paradoxes (Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press, 1967); and J.A. Faris, The Paradoxes of Zeno (Avebury, UK: Ashegate, 1996). EMPEDOCLES: Denis O’Brien, Empedocles’ Cosmic Cycle (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969); and M.R. Wright, Empedocles: The Extant Fragments (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1995). ANAXAGORAS: Malcolm Schofield, An on Anaxagoras (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980). DEMOCRITUS (): , The Greek Atomists and (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1928; reprinted New York: Russell and Russell, 1964). SOPHISTS: G.B. Kerferd, The Sophistic Movement (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Ugo Zilioli, Protagoras and the Challenge of : Plato’s Subtlest Enemy (Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2007). Much of the critical work on the Pre-Socratics is found only in journal articles. The Philosophers’ Index offers a way to locate such articles. (Please note that some of the books on specific thinkers assume some knowledge of and can be very technical.)

*** All of the fragments and most of the paraphrases in the following texts were collected by a nineteenth-century German scholar, Hermann Diels (and later modified by Walther Kranz), in Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (Berlin: Weidmann, most recent edition, 1967). Diels assembled the original Greek texts and furnished German translations for all the fragments. He also collected and printed, but did not translate, reports of ancient authors about the , works, and ideas of the Pre-Socratics. Kathleen Freeman published An Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers: A Complete Translation of the Fragments in Diels, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1947). Like Diels-Kranz, she trans- lated only the fragments, not the ancient paraphrases and reports about the philosophers’ lives and works. G.S. Kirk, J.E. Raven, and M. Schofield translated M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 6

6 BEFORE SOCRATES

many of these previously untranslated items in The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts, 2nd edition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983). Almost all the translations I have used are either those of Freeman (marked with an F) or those of Kirk, Raven, and Schofield (marked with a K). In a few cases the translation is Kaufmann’s (marked with a WK) or the older first edition (1957) of Kirk and Raven (so indicated in the notes). Some of the translations have been modified by Kaufmann or myself (and are marked with an *). After direct quotations, the symbols (K , F, and WK ) are preceded by the that the fragment bears in the fifth edition of Diels-Kranz’s standard work. (Freeman’s numbering is the same as that of Diels-Kranz.) After para- phrases, the ancient works in which the paraphrases occur are cited briefly (along with the abbreviation and number from one of the above sources). For discussions of the fragments and the paraphrases, see the Kirk, Raven, and Schofield’s work as well as Richard D. McKirahan Jr., Philosophy Before Socrates (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1994).

***

Sources of the fragments: THALES: 1. Plato, 174a; K 72; 2. Aristotle, Politics A11, 1259a; K 73; 3. I, 75; K 66; 4. Aristotle, Metaphysics A3, 983b; W.D. Ross’s translation; 5. Heraclitus Homericus, Quaest. Hom. 22; K 87. These may not really have been Thales’ reasons; 6. Seneca, Qu. Nat. III, 14; K 88; 7. Aristotle, De Anima A2, 405a; K 89; 8. Aristotle, De Anima A5, 411a; K 91. ANAXIMANDER: 1. s.v.; K 95. Some of this has been disputed; 2. , Or. 26; K 96; 3. Simplicius, 24; K 101A and 119. Some scholars believe that the quotation begins earlier and comprises the whole ; 4. Ps.-, Strom. 2; K 121; 5. Ibid.; K 122A; 6. , Ref. I, 6, 3; K 122B; 7. Aetius II, 20; K 126; 8. Aetius V, 19; K 133; 9. Ps.-Plutarch, Strom. 2; K 134; 10. Plutarch, Symp. VIII, 730E; K 137. ANAXIMENES: 1. Laertius II, 3; K 138; 2. Augustine, City of God, VIII, 2; K 146; 3. Aristotle, Metaphysics, A3, 984a5; K 139; 4. Simplicius, Physics, 24, 26; K 140; 5. Ps.-Plutarch, Strom. 3; K 148; 6. Hippolytus, Ref. I, 7, 1; K 141; 7. , I, 10, 26; K 144; 8. Aristotle, Meteor. B7, 365b6; K159. PYTHAGORAS: 1. Herodotus IV, 95; K 257; 2. , V. P. 9; K 266; 3. Iustinus ap. Pomp. Trog. Hist. Phil. Epit. XX, 4, 14; K 272; 4. Aetius I, 3, 8; 1st edition K 280; 5. , In Eucl., p. 426 Friedl; 1st edition K 281; 6. Diogenes Laertius VIII, 36; Xenophanes, fragment 7; K 260; 7. Herodotus II, 123; 1st edition K 270; 8. Porphyry, Vita Pythagorae 19; 1st edition K 271; 9. ap. Simplic. Phys., 732, 30; 1st edition K 272. The doctrine of the eternal recurrence of the same events at gigantic intervals was revived in modern times by ; cf. Walter Kaufmann, Nietzsche (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1950; Cleveland, OH: Meridian Books, 1956), Chapter 11, “Overman and Eternal Recurrence”; 10–27. , Protr. 21; 1st edition K 275. These were some of the rules of the sect founded by Pythagoras. The of the rules in K are given in parentheses after each paragraph; 28. Procl., In Eucl., p. 65 Friedl.; 1st edition K 277; 29. Diogenes Laertius VIII, 8; 1st edition K 278. XENOPHANES: 1. Diogenes Laertius IX, 18; K 161; 2. 11; WK; 3. 14; WK; 4. 15; WK; 5. 16; WK; 6. 23; F*; 7. 24; F; 8. 25; F*; 9. 26; F; 10. 27; F*; 11. 34; K 186; 12. 18; WK. HERACLITUS: 1. Diogenes Laertius IX, 6; K 191; 2. Ibid., IX, 5; K 192. Some scholars have ques- tioned the claim about the three parts of his book; indeed, some have doubted that he wrote any book at all; 3. 89; WK; 4. 113; F; 5. 1; K 194; 6. 2; K 195; 7. 50; K 196; 8. 55; K 197; 9. 101a; F; 10. 7; F; 11. 107; K 198; 12. 60; K 200; 13. 6; F; 14. 49a; F*; 15. 91; F; 16. 12; K 214; 17. 61; K 199; 18. 111; K 201; 19. 8; F*; 20. 53; K 212; 21. 80; K 211; 22. 36; K 229; 23. 62; WK; 24. 27; F*; 25. 52; F; 26. 40; WK; 27. 42; WK; 28. 57; WK; 29. 5; F*; 30. 14; WK; 31. 96; WK. To appreciate the full measure of this heresy, one should recall ’ Antigone and ’s Iliad.; 32. 102; K 206; 33. 79; F; 34. 76; F*; 35. 66; F; 36. 30; K 217; 37. 9; F*; 38. 97; F; 39. 4; F*; 40. 110; F*; 41. 112; F*; 42. 116; WK; 43. 118; K 230; 44. 117; K 231; 45. 29; WK; 46. 44; K 249; 47. 49; F*; 48. 121; F*; 49. 101; WK; 50. 18; WK; 51. 119; WK; 52. 123; WK; 53. 92; F*; 54. 93; K 244. M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 7

INTRODUCTION 7

PARMENIDES: 1. 1 (Lines 1Ð32); K 288; 2. 2; K 291; 3. 3; K 292. K construes the literal as: “the same thing exists for thinking and for being”; Freeman’s “For it is the same thing to think and to be” is based on Diels’ Denn (das Seiende) denken und sein ist dasselbe. This much-discussed sentence seems to be continuous with the preceding two fragments; 4. 4; K 313; 5. 5; K 289; 6. 6; K 293. Freeman renders the final words: “in everything there is a way of opposing stress.” Either way, many interpreters believe that Parmenides here alludes to Heraclitus; 7. 7; K 294; 8. 8; F*; 9. 9; Kranz takes with the previous line and translates: “For is possible which does not come under either of the two” (i.e., everything belongs to one or the other of the two categories and night); F*; 10Ð14. 10Ð14; F. ZENO OF ELEA: 1. Plato, Parmenides 128c; F.M. Cornford’s translation; 2. Plato, 261d; R. Hackforth’s translation; 3. Simplicius, Physics 139, 18Ð19; WK; 4. Simplicius, Physics 109, 34; WK; 5. Simplicius, Physics 140, 30; WK; 6. Aristotle, Topics 160b 7; WK. Evidently the stage setting of the is a race course. On this ground it is better to call the argument by this name, instead of “The Dichotomy,” as is often done in the literature, keeping “The Stadium” as the generally accepted name of the fourth argument; 7. Aristotle, Physics 233a 21; WK; 8. Aristotle, Physics 239b 11; WK; 9. Aristotle, Physics 263a 5; WK; 10. Simplicius, Physics 1013, 4ff; WK; 11. Aristotle, Physics 239b 14; P.H. Wicksteed’s translation, edited by F.M. Cornford; 12. Aristotle, Physics 239b 1, 30; Wicksteed’s translation; 13. Aristotle, Physics 239b 33; Wicksteed’s translation; 14. Aristotle, Physics 209a 23; WK; 15. Simplicius, Physics 1108, 18; WK. EMPEDOCLES: 1. Simplicius, Physics 25, 19; K 335; 2. Aristotle, Metaphysics A3, 984a; 3Ð36. The fragments in this section are all from F. I have numbered them consecutively to make it easier to fol- low. The Diels-Freeman numbering follows each paragraph. ANAXAGORAS: 1. Diogenes Laertius II, 7Ð15; K 459; 2. 14, p. 645 Cas.; K 463; 3. Diogenes Laertius I, 16; K 466; 4Ð23. 1Ð19, 21 (Opening sentences from his book On ); F. DEMOCRITUS (AND LEUCIPPUS): 1. Simplicius, Physics 28, 4; 1st edition of K 539; 2. Diogenes Laertius X, 13; K 540; 3. Cicero, Academica pr. II, 37, 118; K 541; 4. Diogenes Laertius IX, 34; K 542; 5. Ibid., IX, 35; K 544; 6. Aristotle, De Gen. et Corr., A 8, 325a; K 545; 7. Simplicius, De Caelo 242, 18; K 557; 8. Dionysius ap. Eusebium P.E. XIV, 23, 3; K 561; 9. Hyppolytus Ref. I, 13, 2; K 565; 10. Diogenes Laertius IX, 45; K 566; cf. “the only extant saying of Leucippus himself,” K 569, Fr. 2, Aetius I, 25, 4: “Nothing occurs at random, but everything for a reason and by necessity”; 11. Aristotle, On Democritus ap. Simplicium De Caelo 295, 11; K 583; 12. Aristotle, De Anima, A2, 405a; K 585; 13. Aristotle, De Sensu 4, 442a; K 587; 14. Aetius IV, 8; K 588; 15. , De Sensu 50; R 589; 16. 7 (from “On the Forms”); F; 17. 8 (from “On the Forms”); F; 18. 9; F; 19. 10; F; 20. 11 (from “The Canon”); F; 21. 156; F; 22-27. The fragments in this section are all from F. I have num- bered them consecutively to make it easier to follow. The Diels-Freeman numbering follows each paragraph. PROTAGORAS: 1. 1 (from “” or “Refutatory ”); F; 2. 3 (from a treatise entitled “Great Logus”); F; 3. 4 (from “On the Gods”); F; 4. 6b; F; 5. 9; F; 6. 10; F; 7. 11; F. GORGIAS: 1. 3, Sextus, from On Not-being or ; F. : 1. , Selections 3.29.11, from Milton C. Nahm, Selections from Early Greek Philosophy (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1964); 2. Ibid., 3.37.15; 3. , translated as Against the Physicists 1.54, by R. C. Bury in Sextus Empiricus, 3.31 sq. (London: W. Heinemann, 1936). From The . Reprinted by permission of the President and Fellows of Harvard College; 4. Pseudo-, Art of 6.2.277.10, from Nahm, op. cit. M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 8

The Milesians THALES fl. ca. 585 B.C.

Thales lived in Miletus in (on the west coast of present-day Turkey) and is said to have been so scientifically skilled that he accurately predicted the eclipse of the on May 28, 585 B.C. He was a contemporary of the Hebrew prophet Jeremiah, of the Persian prophet , of the Indian Gautama Siddhartha (the Buddha), and of the Chinese philosophers and Lao-Tze. Thales has traditionally been considered the first Western philosopher (though some scholars now claim that this honor belongs to Anaximander). Thales was apparently the first to ask the question, “What is the basic ‘stuff’ of the universe?” According to Aristotle, Thales claimed that this basic stuff was water. This claim involves three vital assumptions: (1) that the fundamental explanation of the uni- verse must be one in number, (2) that this one reality must be a “thing,” and (3) that this one thing must have within itself the ability to move and change. Later thinkers disputed Thales’ of the universe’s basic “stuff,” but his bold theory encouraged them and helped them develop their own philosophical programs. Like many other Pre-Socratics, Thales was by no means a philosopher only. He was also a , an astronomer, a geometer, and a sage. The first three frag- ments that follow deal with Thales’ . Number one is probably the world’s oldest “absent-minded professor” story, while numbers two and three appear to be defenses designed to show how practical Thales could be. The remaining fragments are reports on Thales’ ideas. There are no known writings by Thales himself.

[1]* A witty and attractive Thracian servant-girl is said to have mocked Thales for falling into a well while he was observing the and gazing upwards; declaring that

*The numbers in brackets serve the purposes of this volume. See the “Sources of the Fragments” section on page 6 for the source of each fragment.

8 M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 9

THALES 9

Miletus, Ionia, in Asia Minor (present-day Turkey), was once an important port city at the mouth of the Maeander River. However, the slow-moving river (from which we get the term “”) carried silt from the interior mountains, moving the coastline five miles west. Today, the low-lying parts of the ruins are still flooded in the spring. It is not hard to see how Thales, who lived here, might think that “when water is compacted and changes into slime it becomes .” (Forrest E. Baird)

he was eager to know the things in the sky, but that what was behind him and just by his feet escaped his notice. [2] When they reproached him because of his poverty, as though philosophy were no use, it is said that, having observed through his study of the heavenly bodies that there would be a large olive-crop, he raised a little capital while it was still winter, and paid deposits on all the olive presses in Miletus and Chios, hiring them cheaply because no one bid against him. When the appropriate came there was a sudden rush of requests for the presses; he then hired them out on his own terms and so made a large profit, thus demonstrating that it is easy for philosophers to be rich, if they wish, but that it is not in this that they are interested. [3] When he came to the Halys river, Croesus then, as I say, put his army across by the existing bridges; but, according to the common account of the Greeks, Thales the Milesian transferred the army for him. For it is said that Croesus was at a loss how his army should cross the river, since these bridges did not yet exist at this period; and that Thales, who was present in the army, made the river, which flowed on the left hand of the army, flow on the right hand also. He did so in this way: beginning upstream of the army he dug a deep channel, giving it a crescent shape, so that it should flow round the back of where the army was encamped, being diverted in this way from its old course by the channel, and passing the camp should flow into its old course once more. The result was that as soon as the river was divided it became fordable in both of its parts.

*** M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 10

10 THE MILESIANS

[4] Thales . . . says the is water (for which reason he declared that the earth rests on water), getting the perhaps from seeing that the nutriment of all things is moist, and that heat itself is generated from the moist and kept alive by it..., and from the fact that the seeds of all things have a moist nature, and that water is the origin of the nature of moist things. [5] Moist natural substance, since it is easily formed into each different thing, is accustomed to undergo very various changes: that part of it which is exhaled is made into , and the finest part is kindled from air into , while when water is com- pacted and changes into slime it becomes earth. Therefore Thales declared that water, of the four elements, was the most active, as it were, as cause. [6] He [Thales] said that the world is held up by water and rides like a ship, and when it is said to “quake” it is actually rocking because of the water’s movement. [7] Thales, too, seems, from what they relate, to have supposed that the was something kinetic, if he said that the [Magnesian] stone possesses soul because it moves iron. [8] Some say that it [soul] is intermingled in the universe, for which reason, per- haps, Thales also thought that all things are full of gods.

ANAXIMANDER ca. 610–ca. 546 B.C.

Anaximander was born in Miletus about 610 B.C., and he died around 546 B.C. During his lifetime, Nebuchadnezzar conquered Jerusalem and the prophet Ezekiel was exiled to . Anaximander traveled extensively and was so highly regarded by his fellow Milesians that he was honored with the of a new colony. He may have been the first Greek to write a book of prose. Anaximander seems to have accepted Thales’ three basic assumptions (summed up in the that the universe must be one changeable thing), but he differed with Thales on the nature of the “stuff” underlying the “many” that we observe. In place of Thales’ water, Anaximander introduced the of the —the unlimited, boundless, infinite, or indefinite—as the fundamental principle of the world. This notion was a step up in philosophical sophistication— a metaphysical principle rather than an empirically observed material thing. This idea of a basic “stuff,” with properties different from anything in the observable world, has survived to the present. Anaximander also developed a rudimentary concept of natural —the idea that all growing things in the natural world develop according to an identical . He invented the idea of models, drawing what is considered to be the first geographical map. But what has fascinated all subsequent students of philosophy, M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 11

ANAXIMANDER 11

more than anything else, is the one sentence, or half-sentence, quoted by Simplicius in fragment [3] which follows. This remark, the oldest known piece of Western philosophy, has elicited a large body of literature, including a forty-eight-page essay by .

[1] Anaximander son of Praxiades, of Miletus, philosopher, was a kinsman, pupil, and successor of Thales. He first discovered the equinox and solstices and hour-indicators, and that the earth lies in the center. He introduced the gnomon [a vertical rod whose shadow indicates the sun’s direction and height] and in general made known an outline of geometry. He wrote On Nature, Circuit of the Earth and On the Fixed Stars and a Celestial Globe, and some other works. [2] [Anaximander] was the first of the Greeks whom we know who ventured to produce a written account on nature.

*** [3] Of those who say that it is one, moving, and infinite, Anaximander, son of Praxiades, a Milesian, the successor and pupil of Thales, said that the principle and ele- ment of existing things was the [indefinite, or infinite], being the first to introduce this name of the material principle. He says that it is neither water nor any other of the so-called elements, but some other nature, from which come into being all the heavens and the in them. And the source of coming-to-be for exist- ing things is that into which destruction, too, happens “according to necessity; for they pay penalty and retribution to each other for their injustice according to the assessment of time,” as he describes it in these rather poetical terms. It is clear that he, seeing the changing of the four elements into each other, thought it right to make none of these the substratum, but something else besides these; and he produces coming-to-be not through the alteration of the element, but by the separation off of the opposites through the eternal . [4] He says that that which is productive from the eternal of hot and cold was separated off at the coming-to-be of this world, and that a kind of sphere of flame from this was formed round the air surrounding the earth, like bark around a tree. When this was broken off and shut off in certain circles, the sun and and stars were formed. [5] He says that the earth is cylindrical in shape, and that its depth is a third of its width. [6] Its shape is curved, round, similar to the drum of a column; of its flat surfaces we walk on one, and the other is on the opposite side. [7] Anaximander [says the sun] is a circle twenty-eight times the size of the earth, like a wheel, with its [rim] hollow and full of , and showing the fire at a certain point through an aperture as though through the nozzle of a bellows. [8] Anaximander said that the first living creatures were born in moisture, enclosed in thorny barks; and that as their age increased they came forth on to the drier part and, when the bark had broken off, they lived a different kind of life for a short time. [9] Further he says that in the beginning man was born from creatures of a dif- ferent kind; because other creatures are soon self-supporting, but man alone needs prolonged nursing. For this reason he would not have survived if this had been his original form. M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 12

12 THE MILESIANS

[10] Therefore they [the ] actually revere the fish as being of similar race and nurturing. In this they philosophize more suitably than Anaximander; for he declares, not that fishes and men came into being in the same parents, but that originally men came into being inside fishes, and that, having been nurtured there—like sharks— and having become adequate to look after themselves, they then came forth and took to the land.

ANAXIMENES fl. 546 B.C.?

Very little is known about the life of Anaximenes, except that he was a Milesian and a younger contemporary of Anaximander. Anaximenes proposed air as the basic world principle. While at first this thesis may seem a step backwards from the more comprehensive (like Anaximander’s unlimited) to the less comprehen- sive particular (like Thales’ water), Anaximenes added an important point. He explained a process by which the underlying one (air) becomes the observable many: By rarefaction, air becomes fire, and, by condensation, air becomes, suc- cessively, wind, water, and earth. Observable qualitative differences (fire, wind, water, earth) are the result of quantitative changes, that is, of how densely packed is the basic principle. This view is still held by scientists.

[1] Anaximenes, son of Eurystratus of Miletus, was a pupil of Anaximander....He said that the material principle was air and the infinite; and that the stars move, not under the earth, but around it. He used simple and unsuperfluous Ionic speech. He was active, according to what says, around the time of the capture of Sardis [by Cyrus in 546/5 B.C.?], and died in the 63rd . [2] He [Anaximander] left Anaximenes as his and successor, who attributed all the causes of things to infinite air, and did not deny that there were gods, or pass them over in silence; yet he believed not the air was made by them, but that they arose from air.

*** [3] Anaximenes and Diogenes make air, rather than water, the material principle above the other simple bodies. [4] Anaximenes, son of Eurystratus, of Miletus, a companion of Anaximander, also says, like him, that the underlying nature is one and infinite, but not undefined as Anaximander said but definite, for he identifies it as air; and it differs in its substantial nature by rarity and density. Being made finer it becomes fire, being made thicker it becomes wind, then , then (when thickened still more) water, then earth, then M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 13

ANAXIMENES 13

stones; and the rest come into being from these. He, too, makes motion eternal, and says that change, also, comes about through it. [5] And all things are produced by a kind of condensation, and again rarefaction, of this [air]. Motion, indeed, exists from everlasting; he says that when the air melts, there first of all comes into being the earth, quite flat—therefore it accordingly rides on the air; and sun and moon and the remaining heavenly bodies have their source of gen- eration from earth. At last, he declares the sun to be earth, but that through the rapid motion it obtains heat in great sufficiency. [6] Anaximenes...said that infinite air was the principle, from which the things that are , and that are, and that shall be, and gods and things divine, all come into being, and the rest from its products. The form of air is of this kind: whenever it is most equable it is invisible to sight, but is revealed by the cold and the hot and the damp and by movement. It is always in motion; for things that change do not change unless there be movement. Through becoming denser or finer it has different appearances; for when it is dissolved into what is finer it becomes fire, while winds, again, are air that is becoming condensed, and cloud is produced from air by felting. When it is condensed still more, water is produced; with a further degree of condensation earth is produced, and when condensed as far as possible, stones. The result is that the most influential components of generation are opposites, hot and cold. [7] Afterwards, Anaximenes determined that air is a god, and that it comes into being, and is measureless and infinite and always in motion; as though either formless air could be a god . . . or mortality did not attend upon everything that has come into being. [8] Anaximenes says that the earth, through being drenched and dried off, breaks asunder, and is shaken by the peaks that are thus broken off and fall in. Therefore earth- quakes happen in periods both of drought and again of excessive rains; for in droughts, as has been said, it dries up and cracks, and being made over-moist by the it crumbles apart.