Ethics and Invertebrates: a Cephalopod Perspective

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ethics and Invertebrates: a Cephalopod Perspective DISEASES OF AQUATIC ORGANISMS Vol. 75: 119–129, 2007 Published May 4 Dis Aquat Org OPENPEN ACCESSCCESS Ethics and invertebrates: a cephalopod perspective Jennifer A. Mather1,*, Roland C. Anderson2 1University of Lethbridge, Lethbridge, Alberta T1K 3M4, Canada 2Seattle Aquarium, Seattle, Washington 98101-4359, USA ABSTRACT: This paper first explores 3 philosophical bases for attitudes to invertebrates, Contractar- ian/Kantian, Utilitarian, and Rights-based, and what they lead us to conclude about how we use and care for these animals. We next discuss the problems of evaluating pain and suffering in inverte- brates, pointing out that physiological responses to stress are widely similar across the animal king- dom and that most animals show behavioral responses to potentially painful stimuli. Since cephalopods are often used as a test group for consideration of pain, distress and proper conditions for captivity and handling, we evaluate their behavioral and cognitive capacities. Given these capac- ities, we then discuss practical issues: minimization of their pain and suffering during harvesting for food; ensuring that captive cephalopods are properly cared for, stimulated and allowed to live as full a life as possible; and, lastly, working for their conservation. KEY WORDS: Invertebrates · Ethics · Cephalopods · Animal pain · Animal suffering Resale or republication not permitted without written consent of the publisher INTRODUCTION perhaps half the animal species in the world and are mostly land animals (Hardy 1988), but humans in Human attitudes towards and values placed on ani- general seem indifferent at best to animals unlike us mals are both varied and differential, depending on (Ponder et al. 2002). the animal evaluated. The fundamental anthropocen- trism of humans acts against consideration of inverte- brates and is a major factor in the present crisis in PHILOSOPHICAL APPROACHES invertebrate conservation—we are losing populations and species (New 1993). Even though they constitute It is useful to look at the philosophical bases of judg- 99% of all species on earth, invertebrates are not ments about animals to see how these beliefs might sufficiently understood or highly valued by people affect attitudes towards and treatment of marine in- (Ponder 1992, Kellert 1993, Nash 2004). Our belief in vertebrates. They can perhaps be grouped into 3 a ‘scala naturae’, an evolutionary continuum leading value systems: Contractarian/Kantian, Utilitarian, and inevitably to humans at its peak, is well explored by Rights-based (Nussbaum 2001). Each system looks at Eddy et al. (1993), who inadvertently demonstrated animals from a different viewpoint and each would this anthropocentrism by their choice of animal spe- treat invertebrates differently, depending on the cies to be evaluated—only 3 of 30 were invertebrates. circumstances. Both they and Bekoff (1994) found that animals The first system, Contractarian/Kantian, is perhaps judged to be more cognitively competent and those the ultimate in anthropocentrism and is based on older we could potentially bond with were presumed to be views, particularly those of Descartes, who said that worth more consideration. Sadly, many people con- animals were no better than automata and we ought tinue to show fear of and aversion towards inverte- not to consider their worth at all (quoted in Kellert brates (Kellert 1993, Nash 2004). This fear tends to be 1993). This view separates us completely from the nat- centered in particular on arthropods, which make up ural world, remains to some extent in Judeo-Christian *Email: [email protected] © Inter-Research 2007 · www.int-res.com 120 Dis Aquat Org 75: 119–129, 2007 philosophy (Bourdeau 2004), and denies what we all invertebrates, have the right to careful and respect- might call dignity to animals. Essentially, according to ful treatment (Regan 2003). Nussbaum (2001) suggests this philosophy we can do what we like to animals; this that we should care about an animal’s life, health, bod- view is fortunately no longer prevalent. The only ily integrity and emotional well-being. This approach redeeming aspect of this system is the viewpoint that raises many difficult questions, such as whether aquar- our humaneness is of value to us, and that we therefore iums, which deprive marine animals of their freedom, degrade or impoverish ourselves if we treat animals ought to exist. In its demands for rights for all animals, poorly (Rollin 1985) or ignore them. Kellert’s (1997) it leaves researchers with some difficult questions. For book reflects these attitudes as he emphasizes we must instance, one of my colleagues asked whether we encourage and develop our biophilia. He cites E. O. should consider the host or the parasite, when their Wilson, defining biophilia (Kellert & Wilson 1995) as an interests differ. And this viewpoint also requires that ‘inherent human affinity for life and lifelike processes’ we understand the basic physiology of the animals and emphasizes the values of exploitation. Aesthetics, themselves. How can we protect the rights of the clam, animals as metaphor, kinship with them, mastery and the brain coral or the euphausiid crustacean when we finding meaning in our relationship with them are understand very little about their lifestyle, behavior things we can get from invertebrates. and sensory ecology? Davis et al. (1999) point out the The second system is the Utilitarian, which dictates problem of our lack of understanding with ascidians as that we should act to get the best overall consequences an example. from our actions, and therefore that we must balance Since both the Utilitarian and Rights-based view- consequences for all involved. This viewpoint tends to points emphasize that we must make some assessment be narrow, as it requires us to balance total pleasure of pain, suffering, pleasure and thriving in order to and pain. This position then brings up the issue of what know how to act towards animals, it is these ap- animals ‘feel’ and whether we can ignore animals such proaches which are the basis of our evaluation of inver- as invertebrates with little cognitive ability; it also tebrates in order to best benefit them. Of all the marine looks at the wider view and not the value of the invertebrates, the cephalopod mollusks are best stud- individual. In practice, Utilitarianism seems to supply ied and most highly regarded in terms of their intelli- many of the arguments for those who would value gence and possible consciousness. Perhaps it is best to invertebrates more highly. They often point out their evaluate the following: what do we know about octo- ecological value (Kellert 1993, New 1993) and their puses and squid in terms of their ability to suffer, indi- important role in biological diversity; for example, viduality, cognitive capacity, consciousness and emo- coral reefs are important as the backbone of a major tionality? Understanding them and evaluating their marine ecosystem (Ponder et al. 2002). In addition, treatment in light of these abilities will be a place to mollusks as a group are the most seriously endangered start for the invertebrates. animals in North America (Nash 2004). Benkendoff (1999) takes this approach to the conservation of molluscan resources and Kellert (1993) expands on this ASSESSMENT OF SUFFERING approach by pointing out the value of invertebrates in waste decomposition, for food, as indicators of environ- Any discussion of consideration of animals’ lives has mental quality and as sources of drugs to treat our to first look at the issue of pain and suffering because illnesses. Presumably losses in terms of pain caused to these are what we want to avoid. Pain is a term coined the animals would be outweighed by our gains. This by humans and often presumed to apply only to us; also brings up a topic that will be evaluated below — pain is a sense but one in which emotions and cogni- how much pain and/or suffering do invertebrates tions are heavily involved (Matlin & Foley 1997). endure, and in what situations? Merskey’s (1986) definition underlines this evaluative The third philosophical system is the Rights-based capacity, as he defines it as ‘information about actual one. Regan (2003) proposes that both agent and or potential tissue damage, or interpreted in terms of patient have value and thus the right to respectful such damage’ to cover the central representation of treatment. This viewpoint focuses on the individual, pain signals. Human experiences are full of examples and extends the rights that animals ought to have to such as wartime wounds that are not painful until after include bodily integrity and bodily liberty, thus looking the battle, or Pain Disorder (American Psychiatric much more widely at what animals themselves are Association 2000) that is not associated with any actual experiencing. Although it values animals proportion- damage or is only triggered by it. Kavaliers (1988) sug- ate to their level of awareness, it assumes that the gests that one way to avoid the cognitive attribution is rights of an animal are not totally dependent on its to describe the sensory information as nociception and awareness and that all animals, presumably including the perceptual assumption as pain. Of course, just Mather & Anderson: Ethics and invertebrates 121 because an animal does not have the awareness of sit- ASSESSMENT OF LEARNING uations across time does not mean that nociceptive stimuli are not felt, and Bekoff (1994) points out that One necessity for the approach of evaluating ethics such stimuli might be less bearable (i.e. the suffering for invertebrates is to see animals as individuals. After might be greater) if an animal had no rich cognitive life years of lumping together all animals of the same spe- with which to remember the past or plan for and antic- cies or in the same situation, scientists have once again ipate the future. begun to take into account the individuality of their Stefano et al.
Recommended publications
  • Chrysippus's Dog As a Case Study in Non-Linguistic Cognition
    Chrysippus’s Dog as a Case Study in Non-Linguistic Cognition Michael Rescorla Abstract: I critique an ancient argument for the possibility of non-linguistic deductive inference. The argument, attributed to Chrysippus, describes a dog whose behavior supposedly reflects disjunctive syllogistic reasoning. Drawing on contemporary robotics, I urge that we can equally well explain the dog’s behavior by citing probabilistic reasoning over cognitive maps. I then critique various experimentally-based arguments from scientific psychology that echo Chrysippus’s anecdotal presentation. §1. Language and thought Do non-linguistic creatures think? Debate over this question tends to calcify into two extreme doctrines. The first, espoused by Descartes, regards language as necessary for cognition. Modern proponents include Brandom (1994, pp. 145-157), Davidson (1984, pp. 155-170), McDowell (1996), and Sellars (1963, pp. 177-189). Cartesians may grant that ascribing cognitive activity to non-linguistic creatures is instrumentally useful, but they regard such ascriptions as strictly speaking false. The second extreme doctrine, espoused by Gassendi, Hume, and Locke, maintains that linguistic and non-linguistic cognition are fundamentally the same. Modern proponents include Fodor (2003), Peacocke (1997), Stalnaker (1984), and many others. Proponents may grant that non- linguistic creatures entertain a narrower range of thoughts than us, but they deny any principled difference in kind.1 2 An intermediate position holds that non-linguistic creatures display cognitive activity of a fundamentally different kind than human thought. Hobbes and Leibniz favored this intermediate position. Modern advocates include Bermudez (2003), Carruthers (2002, 2004), Dummett (1993, pp. 147-149), Malcolm (1972), and Putnam (1992, pp. 28-30).
    [Show full text]
  • Cephalopods and the Evolution of the Mind
    Cephalopods and the Evolution of the Mind Peter Godfrey-Smith The Graduate Center City University of New York Pacific Conservation Biology 19 (2013): 4-9. In thinking about the nature of the mind and its evolutionary history, cephalopods – especially octopuses, cuttlefish, and squid – have a special importance. These animals are an independent experiment in the evolution of large and complex nervous systems – in the biological machinery of the mind. They evolved this machinery on a historical lineage distant from our own. Where their minds differ from ours, they show us another way of being a sentient organism. Where we are similar, this is due to the convergence of distinct evolutionary paths. I introduced the topic just now as 'the mind.' This is a contentious term to use. What is it to have a mind? One option is that we are looking for something close to what humans have –– something like reflective and conscious thought. This sets a high bar for having a mind. Another possible view is that whenever organisms adapt to their circumstances in real time by adjusting their behavior, taking in information and acting in response to it, there is some degree of mentality or intelligence there. To say this sets a low bar. It is best not to set bars in either place. Roughly speaking, we are dealing with a matter of degree, though 'degree' is not quite the right term either. The evolution of a mind is the acquisition of a tool-kit for the control of behavior. The tool-kit includes some kind of perception, though different animals have very different ways of taking in information from the world.
    [Show full text]
  • "Higher" Cognition. Animal Sentience
    Animal Sentience 2017.030: Vallortigara on Marino on Thinking Chickens Sentience does not require “higher” cognition Commentary on Marino on Thinking Chickens Giorgio Vallortigara Centre for Mind/Brain Sciences University of Trento, Italy Abstract: I agree with Marino (2017a,b) that the cognitive capacities of chickens are likely to be the same as those of many others vertebrates. Also, data collected in the young of this precocial species provide rich information about how much cognition can be pre-wired and predisposed in the brain. However, evidence of advanced cognition — in chickens or any other organism — says little about sentience (i.e., feeling). We do not deny sentience in human beings who, because of cognitive deficits, would be incapable of exhibiting some of the cognitive feats of chickens. Moreover, complex problem solving, such as transitive inference, which has been reported in chickens, can be observed even in the absence of any accompanying conscious experience in humans. Giorgio Vallortigara, professor of Neuroscience at the Centre for Mind/Brain Sciences of the University of Trento, Italy, studies space, number and object cognition, and brain asymmetry in a comparative and evolutionary perspective. The author of more than 250 scientific papers on these topics, he was the recipient of several awards, including the Geoffroy Saint Hilaire Prize for Ethology (France) and a Doctor Rerum Naturalium Honoris Causa for outstanding achievements in the field of psychobiology (Ruhr University, Germany). r.unitn.it/en/cimec/abc In a revealing piece in New Scientist (Lawler, 2015a) and a beautiful book (Lawler, 2015b), science journalist Andrew Lawler discussed the possible consequences for humans of the sudden disappearance of some domesticated species.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cognitive Animal : Empirical and Theoretical Perspectives on Animal Cognition
    Contents Introduction ix 11 Learning and Memory Without a Contributors xvii Brain 77 James W. Grau THE DIVERSITY OF 12 Cognitive Modulation of Sexual COGNITION Behavior 89 Michael Domjan The Inner Life of Earthworms: Darwin's Argument and Us 13 Cognition and Emotion in Concert Implications 3 in Human and Nonhuman Animals 97 Eileen Crist Ruud van den Bos, Bart B. Houx, and Berry M. Spruijt 2 Crotalomorphism: A Metaphor for U nderstanding Anthropomorphism 14 Constructing Animal Cognition 105 by Omission 9 William Timberlake Jesús Rivas and Gordon M. 15 Genetics, Plasticity, and the Burghardt Evolution of Cognitive Processes 115 3 The Cognitive Defender: How Gordon M. Burghardt Ground Squirrels Assess Their 16 Spatial Behavior, Food Storing, and Predators 19 the Modular Mind 123 Donald H. Owings Sara J. Shettleworth 4 Jumping Spider Tricksters: Deceit, 17 Spatial and Social Cognition in Predation, and Cognition 27 Corvids: An Evolutionary Approach 129 Stim Wilcox and Robert Jackson Russell P. Balda and Alan C. 5 The Ungulate Mind 35 Kamil John A. Byers 18 Environmental Complexity, Signal 6 Can Honey Bees Create Cognitive Detection, and the Evolution of Maps? 41 Cognition 135 James L. Gould Peter Godfrey-Smith 7 Raven Consciousness 47 19 Cognition as an Independent Bernd Heinrich Variable: Virtual Ecology 143 Alan C. Kamil and Alan B. Bond 8 Animal Minds, Human Minds 53 Eric Saidel 20 Synthetic Ethology: A New Tool for Investigating Animal Cognition 151 9 Comparative Developmental Bruce MacLennan Evolutionary Psychology and Cognitive Ethology: Contrasting but 21 From Cognition in Animals to Compatible Research Programs 59 Cognition in Superorganisms 157 Sue Taylor Parker Charles E.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Consciousness: Beyond the Looking-Glass and What Dogs Found There
    Ethology Ecology & Evolution ISSN: 0394-9370 (Print) 1828-7131 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/teee20 Self-consciousness: beyond the looking-glass and what dogs found there Roberto Cazzolla Gatti To cite this article: Roberto Cazzolla Gatti (2015): Self-consciousness: beyond the looking-glass and what dogs found there, Ethology Ecology & Evolution, DOI: 10.1080/03949370.2015.1102777 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/03949370.2015.1102777 Published online: 13 Nov 2015. Submit your article to this journal View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=teee20 Download by: [Tomsk State University] Date: 19 November 2015, At: 20:36 Ethology Ecology & Evolution, 2015 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/03949370.2015.1102777 Forum Self-consciousness: beyond the looking-glass and what dogs found there The state of the art of animal cognition and awareness studies Self-recognition, that is, the recognition of one’s own self, has been studied mainly by examining animals’ and children’s responses to their reflections in mirrors (Gallup et al. 2002). The definitive test is whether or not a subject is capable of using the reflection to notice and respond to a mark on the face, head or other parts of the body by touching the mark (Bard et al. 2006). The mark, which is placed on the subjects when they are distracted or under anaesthesia, is only visible to the subject when they look at themselves in a mirror. The basic idea behind the test is that the subject who understands the concepts of “self” and “others” can differentiate between the two, and can recognize himself in the reflection (Swartz et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Housing, Husbandry and Welfare of a “Classic” Fish Model, the Paradise Fish (Macropodus Opercularis)
    animals Article Housing, Husbandry and Welfare of a “Classic” Fish Model, the Paradise Fish (Macropodus opercularis) Anita Rácz 1,* ,Gábor Adorján 2, Erika Fodor 1, Boglárka Sellyei 3, Mohammed Tolba 4, Ádám Miklósi 5 and Máté Varga 1,* 1 Department of Genetics, ELTE Eötvös Loránd University, Pázmány Péter stny. 1C, 1117 Budapest, Hungary; [email protected] 2 Budapest Zoo, Állatkerti krt. 6-12, H-1146 Budapest, Hungary; [email protected] 3 Fish Pathology and Parasitology Team, Institute for Veterinary Medical Research, Centre for Agricultural Research, Hungária krt. 21, 1143 Budapest, Hungary; [email protected] 4 Department of Zoology, Faculty of Science, Helwan University, Helwan 11795, Egypt; [email protected] 5 Department of Ethology, ELTE Eötvös Loránd University, Pázmány Péter stny. 1C, 1117 Budapest, Hungary; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected] (A.R.); [email protected] (M.V.) Simple Summary: Paradise fish (Macropodus opercularis) has been a favored subject of behavioral research during the last decades of the 20th century. Lately, however, with a massively expanding genetic toolkit and a well annotated, fully sequenced genome, zebrafish (Danio rerio) became a central model of recent behavioral research. But, as the zebrafish behavioral repertoire is less complex than that of the paradise fish, the focus on zebrafish is a compromise. With the advent of novel methodologies, we think it is time to bring back paradise fish and develop it into a modern model of Citation: Rácz, A.; Adorján, G.; behavioral and evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo) studies. The first step is to define the Fodor, E.; Sellyei, B.; Tolba, M.; housing and husbandry conditions that can make a paradise fish a relevant and trustworthy model.
    [Show full text]
  • Imported Food Risk Statement Bivalve Molluscs and Domoic Acid
    Imported food risk statement Bivalve molluscs and domoic acid Commodity: Bivalve Molluscs. This includes whole or portions of bivalve molluscs that are fresh, frozen, dried or canned, such as cockles, clams, mussels, oysters and scallops. The following products are excluded and therefore not covered by this risk statement: cephalopod molluscs (e.g. squid, octopus, cuttlefish) and jelly fish marinara mix. Analyte: Domoic acid (DA) Recommendation and rationale Is DA in bivalve molluscs a medium or high risk to public health: Yes No Uncertain, further scientific assessment required Rationale: Consumption of seafood containing DA has resulted in human poisoning incidents and deaths. DA is a potent neurotoxin that causes amnesic shellfish poisoning (ASP) within 24-48 hours following ingestion. There is no antidote for ASP. DA is not destroyed by cooking, freezing or other food processing. General description Nature of the analyte: DA is a water-soluble, non-protein amino acid. It is produced by some marine diatoms of the genus Pseudo- nitzschia spp., which are likely to be present to some extent in most coastal marine environments. Isomers of DA are less toxic. Domoic acid is not reliably destroyed by common cooking methods (Vidal et al. 2009) or by autoclaving (McCarron and Hess 2006). Adverse health effects: DA is a potent neurotoxin that causes amnesic shellfish poisoning (ASP) within 24-48 hours following ingestion. There is no antidote for ASP. Clinical signs of acute DA toxicity (or ASP) are mild gastrointestinal symptoms (vomiting, diarrhoea, and abdominal pain) from an oral dose ranging between 0.9 and 2 mg DA/kg bw.
    [Show full text]
  • Miscellaneous Mollusc Resources of Pacific Islands
    SPC/lnshore Fish. Res./WP2 29 February 1988 ORIGINAL : ENGLISH ( Noumea, New Caledonia, 14-25 March 1988) HISCELLANEOUS MOLLUSC RESOURCES OF PACIFIC ISLANDS BY Dr A.D. Lewis Introduction l Molluscs (Phylum Molluscs) we a diverse array of "shellfish", which include bivalves (clams, cockles, oysters, mussels - Class Pelecypoda) ,gastropods ( snails, abalone, seahares- Class Gastropods) and cephalopods (squids, octopus, cuttlefish - Class Cephalopoda). These support large marine fisheries, world landings of molluscs exceeding 6 millions tonnes in 1985 (Anon, 1987) and dominated by cephalopods ( 1.67 million mt,), clams, cockles and arkshells ( 1.6 1 million mt.) and oysters ( 1.03 million mt). 2. Previous sessions at the workshop have considered in detail the molluscs of major commercial importance to Pacific Islands. This include molluscs harvested primarily for Industrial purposes (eg. trochus, green snail and pearl shell, for their nacreous shell interiors) as well as those harvested primarily for human consumption (giant clams). 3. There is in addition, however a wide range of molluscs harvested throughout the Pacific Islands for subsistence purposes and in some cases small scale commercial exploitation. Many are gleaned from a variety of inshore habitats, including mud flats, mangrove roots, sandy beaches, reef flats and rubble areas. These molluscs are commonly collected by women, and have traditionally served as important reserve food sources during times of bad weather or poor line fishing. In (tensely populated atolls, they may become a primary fooAsource, Zann ( 1985) noting that in South Tarawa (Kiribati), landings of three lagoon bivalves exceed that of all finfish combined. 4. Othermoreactivemolluscsaretakenwithluresorbaits(cephalopoda).whilstothers are trawled (scallops).
    [Show full text]
  • Veganism: a New Approach to Health Miljana Z
    Chapter Veganism: A New Approach to Health Miljana Z. Jovandaric Abstract The word vegan was given by Donald Watson in 1944 in Leicester, England, who, together with several other members of the Vegetarian Society, wanted to establish a group of vegetarians who did not consume milk or dairy products. When the proposal was rejected, Watson and like-minded people founded The Vegan Society, which advocated a complete plant-based diet, excluding meat, fish, eggs, milk and dairy products (cheese, butter) and honey. Vegans do not wear fur items, wool, bone, goat, coral, pearl or any other material of animal origin. According to surveys, vegans make up between 0.2% and 1.3% of the US population and between 0.25% and 7% of the UK population. Vegan foods contain lower levels of cholesterol and fat than the usual diet. Keywords: veganism, health, supplements 1. Introduction Veganism is a philosophy and lifestyle that seeks to exclude the use of animals for food or clothing and includes all other forms of diet of non-animal origin. Vegan diet is based on cereals, legumes, fruits and vegetables. Vegans do not eat meat, fish, seafood, eggs, milk, dairy products, honey threads carry things made of fur, wool, bones, leather, coral, pearls or any other materials of animal origin. Within the commitment to a vegan lifestyle, there is a group of people who eat exclusively fresh raw fruits, vegetables without heat treatment. This group of vegans is called a row food diet. Veganism differs from vegetarianism in that it is reduced entirely to a plant-based diet, while vegetarians also eat some products of animal origin, when animals are not killed when obtaining these products, e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Insights from a Case Study of a Highly Social Animal That Failed the Mirror Self-Recognition Test
    2020, 33 Heather M. Hill Editor Peer-reviewed Fish Out of Water: Insights from a Case Study of a Highly Social Animal that Failed the Mirror Self-Recognition Test Shannon Michelle Barber-Meyer1 and Lori Jean Schmidt2,3 1U.S. Geological Survey, Northern Prairie Wildlife Research Center, U.S.A. 2International Wolf Center, U.S.A. 3 Natural Resources Program Coordinator, Vermilion Community College, U.S.A. Mirror self-recognition (MSR) tests have been conducted in a variety of species to assess whether these animals exhibit self-awareness. To date, the majority of animals that have convincingly passed are highly social mammals whose wild counterparts live in complex societies, though there is much debate concerning what constitutes “passing” and what passing means in terms of self-awareness. Amid recent reports that a fish (cleaner wrasse, Labroides dimidiatus) passed, it is intriguing that a mammal as highly social, tolerant, attentive, and cooperative as the gray wolf (Canis lupus) has reportedly failed the test. Given the many possible reasons for failure, we were interested in reexamining wolves as a case study of MSR in socially complex mammals as part of a broader overview of the MSR test. We aimed to elucidate the wolves’ responses at various stages of the MSR test to pinpoint potential problem areas where species- specific modifications to the test may be needed. We evaluated 6 socialized, captive gray wolves during July 2017. At a minimum, wolves did not respond to their reflection as an unfamiliar conspecific. Unfortunately, the wolves rapidly lost interest in the mirror and were uninterested in the applied marks.
    [Show full text]
  • Husbandry Manual for BLUE-RINGED OCTOPUS Hapalochlaena Lunulata (Mollusca: Octopodidae)
    Husbandry Manual for BLUE-RINGED OCTOPUS Hapalochlaena lunulata (Mollusca: Octopodidae) Date By From Version 2005 Leanne Hayter Ultimo TAFE v 1 T A B L E O F C O N T E N T S 1 PREFACE ................................................................................................................................ 5 2 INTRODUCTION ...................................................................................................................... 6 2.1 CLASSIFICATION .............................................................................................................................. 8 2.2 GENERAL FEATURES ....................................................................................................................... 8 2.3 HISTORY IN CAPTIVITY ..................................................................................................................... 9 2.4 EDUCATION ..................................................................................................................................... 9 2.5 CONSERVATION & RESEARCH ........................................................................................................ 10 3 TAXONOMY ............................................................................................................................12 3.1 NOMENCLATURE ........................................................................................................................... 12 3.2 OTHER SPECIES ...........................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Giant Pacific Octopus (Enteroctopus Dofleini) Care Manual
    Giant Pacific Octopus Insert Photo within this space (Enteroctopus dofleini) Care Manual CREATED BY AZA Aquatic Invertebrate Taxonomic Advisory Group IN ASSOCIATION WITH AZA Animal Welfare Committee Giant Pacific Octopus (Enteroctopus dofleini) Care Manual Giant Pacific Octopus (Enteroctopus dofleini) Care Manual Published by the Association of Zoos and Aquariums in association with the AZA Animal Welfare Committee Formal Citation: AZA Aquatic Invertebrate Taxon Advisory Group (AITAG) (2014). Giant Pacific Octopus (Enteroctopus dofleini) Care Manual. Association of Zoos and Aquariums, Silver Spring, MD. Original Completion Date: September 2014 Dedication: This work is dedicated to the memory of Roland C. Anderson, who passed away suddenly before its completion. No one person is more responsible for advancing and elevating the state of husbandry of this species, and we hope his lifelong body of work will inspire the next generation of aquarists towards the same ideals. Authors and Significant Contributors: Barrett L. Christie, The Dallas Zoo and Children’s Aquarium at Fair Park, AITAG Steering Committee Alan Peters, Smithsonian Institution, National Zoological Park, AITAG Steering Committee Gregory J. Barord, City University of New York, AITAG Advisor Mark J. Rehling, Cleveland Metroparks Zoo Roland C. Anderson, PhD Reviewers: Mike Brittsan, Columbus Zoo and Aquarium Paula Carlson, Dallas World Aquarium Marie Collins, Sea Life Aquarium Carlsbad David DeNardo, New York Aquarium Joshua Frey Sr., Downtown Aquarium Houston Jay Hemdal, Toledo
    [Show full text]