Is Plato a Stoic?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Is Plato a Stoic? Méthexis X (/997) p. 23-38 Articu/os IS PLATO A STOIC? JULlAANNAS It is an honour to contribute this paper to a collection in memory of Conrado Eggers Lan, whose work has been so valuable in so many areas of ancient philoso­ phy, including the study of Plato. While 1 am not confident that he would have agre­ ed with the thesis of this paper, 1 hope that he would ascribe to it sorne value in ad­ ding to continuing discussion of and engagement with the great works of Plato. Conrado will be missed in many parts of the scholarly world for his work, and for his great courtesy and collegiality, as weil as for the vigour with which he supported the study of ancient philosophy in unpropitious times. His death is a great loss. Is Plato a Stoic? This may seem an absurd question. However, when we are con­ sidering Plato's ethics, which is my concem here, we do sometimes ask such ques­ tions as wh ether he is a utilitarian. Is this any less absurd? The questions reflect the fact that Plato chooses to write in the dialogue form, giving us arguments in plenty, but without providing us with a ready-made framework in which to put them. The quantity ofwork on the structure ofPlatonic ethics produced today shows that there is no consensus on what this framework is; there is still room for reasonable dis­ agreement over the form of ethical theory which best makes sense of what we find in Plato's works. It may still seem particularly unpromising to ask whether Plato is a Stoic in ethics; this does not look like a question that can bring us direct insight into his thinking. But it does promise to give us indirect insight. Once Greek eudaimonist ethical theory emerges explicitIy in AristotIe, its central problems are defined by their role in exposition and debate. When it tums out that it was a matter for contro­ versy what position Plato held on the central issue of ancient ethics - the relation of virtue to happiness - we may reflect that Plato's work is not just difficult for us to categorize, but is elusive in terms ofancient ethical debate also. Plato's position is a problematic one in ancient philosophical terms, notjust ours. Antipater, one of the heads of the Stoa, wrote three books on the theme that Plato held only virtue to be good. 1 ln this work he proved that according to Plato virtue is sufficient for happiness, as weil as c1aiming that many other Platonic ideas were in agreement with Stoicism. Antipater is claiming Plato for one side of a de­ bate about the central question of ancient ethical theory: Is virtue sufficient for hap­ piness, as the Stoics daim, or does happiness require, as AristotIe thought, a certain amount of 'extemal goods' such as health, wealth and success? Ooes the morally good person have everything that matters in life, or is she a failure if she ends up 1 H. von Arnim, Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta vol III, Antipater, fr. 56 (Clement of Alexandria, Stromateis V 14). Literally, the claim is that 'according to Plato only the fine is good', the fine being the aim of virtue. 24 Julia Annas poor and powerless? How far does morality demand that we revise our everyday in­ tuitive criteria for happiness? We can see why the Stoics might want Plato's authority to support them against AristotIe. It may seem at tirst more surprising that Plato's followers would see themselves as Stoics. But we tind that, after the end of Plato's own Academy (in the frrst century S.C.), when the people whom we cali Middle Platonists2 start interpre­ ting Plato as a philosopher with a system of positive doctrine (in the way that has been standard in the twentieth century) the main dispute over his ethics is precisely this: is he a Stoic or an Aristotelian? This is not really surprising: those were the contemporary categories available to philosophers interpreting Plato on what had now become the central theoretical question of ethics. As John Dillon puts it, '[N]o later Platonist... could be strictly "orthodox", since Plato does not leave a body of doctrine which can be simply adopted, but rather a series of guiding ideas, replete with loose ends and even contradictions, which require interpretation .... By the Se­ cond Century A.D., one in effect had the choice of adopting Aristotelian or Stoic terminology and concepts to give formaI structure to one's interpretation of what Plato meant, and there was no central authority such as a Platonic Academy, to ma­ ke ex cathedra pronouncements on how far one could go. Nor, 1 think was Plato­ nism any the worse for that.,3 It is natural that once Stoic and Aristotelian debate had formalized the central question of ethical theory, Plato's position should come to be seen in terms of that debate. We interpret Plato ourse Ives in terms of our own ethical debates, and the questions which they make central. ft is more interesting that there was disagree­ ment on this. Sorne people think that on the question of virtue and happiness Plato and AristotIe converge on a similar position.4 Others violently disagree, thinking Aristotle to be completely at odds with Plato where virtue and happiness are con­ cemed.5 What 1 want to focus on here is the point that so many Platonists con­ curred with Antipater: Plato agrees with the Stoics that virtue is the only good, and 2 Doubts can easily be raised about the adequacy or helpfulness of 'Middle Platonism' as a term picking out a coherent body of thought: see the helpful article by Pier Luigi Donini on a series of re­ cent publications, especially one by Michael Frede, 'Medioplatonismo e filosofi medioplatonici. Una raccolta di studi', Elenchos 1990,79-93. However, 1 do not think that these doubts matter for present purposes, since 1 am here interested exclusively with the understanding of Plato's ethics in Stoic and Aristotelian terms, a concem shared by writers traditionally labelled 'Middle Platonist' (and by sorne labelled 'neo-Pythagorean'); problems about the boundaries and nature of 'Middle Platonism' as a whole do not fundamentally affect this. 3 John Dillon, 'Orthodoxy and Eclecticism in Middle Platonism' in On and Off the Beaten Track, Studies in the History of Platonism, ed. Th. G. Sinnige, Nijmegen 1985,31-50, p. 44. 4 Arius Didymus, ap. Stobaeus, 51.15-17 says that Plato gives in different words the same defi­ nition of happiness as has just been described for Aristotle ('preferred use of complete virtue in a complete life') which makes reference to a crucial role for extemal goods. 5 Atticus has the strongest views here, insisting loudly that one should not argue to Platonist con­ clusions from Aristotelian premises. 'Aristotle's works [on ethicsJ, the Eudemian and Nicomachean Ethics and the Magna Moralia, think about virtue in a way which is petty and grovelling and vulgar' (fT. 2 des Places) and completely fails to grasp the nature of Plato's commitment to virtue. .
Recommended publications
  • The Little Book of Stoicism
    The Little Book of Stoicism Timeless Wisdom to Gain Resilience, Confidence, and Calmness Jonas Salzgeber Illustrations © 2019 Jonas Salzgeber. All rights reserved. Copyright © 2019 Jonas Salzgeber THE LITTLE BOOK OF STOICISM. All rights reserved. This book or any portion thereof may not be reproduced or used in any manner whatsoever without the express written permission of the publisher except for the use of brief quotations in critical articles or reviews. First paperback published 2019. FIRST EDITION. ISBN: 978-1791967284 www.njlifehacks.com Contents Introduction 1 PART 1: WHAT IS STOICISM 9 Chapter 1: The Promise of Stoic Philosophy 11 Practice the Art of Living: Become a Warrior- Philosopher 12 Promise #1: Eudaimonia 14 Promise #2: Emotional Resilience 17 Tame Restricting Emotions (≠ Unemotional) 19 Practice Stoicism and Become more Tranquil as a By-Product 23 Chapter 2: A Quick History Lesson 26 The Most Important Stoic Philosophers 29 Seneca the Younger (c. 4 BCE – 65 CE) 30 Musonius Rufus (c. 30 CE – c. 100 CE) 32 Epictetus (c. 55 CE – c. 135 CE) 33 Marcus Aurelius (121 CE – 180 CE) 34 Chapter 3: The Stoic Happiness Triangle 36 The Stoic Happiness Triangle in A Nutshell 38 1. Live with Areté: Express Your Highest Self in Every Moment 40 The Perfection of Our Natural Potential 43 The Four Cardinal Virtues 47 Character Beats Beauty 51 The Stoic Love of Mankind: Act for the Common Welfare 53 2. Focus on What You Control: Accept Whatever Happens and Make the Best Out of It 56 The Stoic Archer: Focus on the Process 60 Stoic Acceptance: Enjoy the Ride or Get Dragged Along 63 The Good, the Bad, and the Indifferent Things 67 In Poker as in Life, You Can Win with Any Hand 71 3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism and Cosmopolitanism
    Stoicism and Cosmopolitanism Although the term cosmopolitan (κοσμοπολίτης, literally, world-citizen ), was used by Greeks earlier than the Stoic philosophers (who started with Zeno [c. 335-263 BC]), it was these philosophers who took this term and gave it a genuine, “cosmopolitan” meaning, a meaning rather different from its modern usage. Prior to the Stoics Asked where he was from, Diogenes the Cynic (c. 390-323 BC) said, “I am a citizen of the world (in the Greek, kosmopolites ).” The atomist philosopher Democritus said, “To a wise man every land is accessible; for the entire world ( kosmos ) is a good soul’s native land.” Many Greek Sophists held cosmopolitan views. The Sophist Antiphon (d. 411 BC) wrote that “by nature we are all constituted alike in all things, both barbarians and Greeks. This can be seen by consideration of those things which are essential by nature to all men… In these things no barbarian is set apart from us, nor any Greek. For we all breathe into the air through mouth and nostrils…” Stoic Cosmopolitanism Zeno’s earliest and most famous work, Republic , was summarized by Plutarch: Moreover, the much-admired Republic of Zeno, the founder of the Stoic sect, may be summed up in this one main principle: that all the inhabitants of this world of ours should not live differentiated by their respective rules of justice into separate cities and communities, but that we should consider all men to be of one community and one polity, and that we should have a common life and an order common to us all, even as a herd that feeds together and shares the pasturage of a common field.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism a School of Thought That Flourished in Greek and Roman
    Stoicism A school of thought that flourished in Greek and Roman antiquity. It was one of the loftiest and most sublime philosophies in the record of Western civilization. In urging participation in the affairs of man, Stoics have always believed that the goal of all inquiry is to provide man with a mode of conduct characterized by tranquillity of mind and certainty of moral worth. Nature and scope of Stoicism For the early Stoic philosopher, as for all the post-Aristotelian schools, knowledge and its pursuit are no longer held to be ends in themselves. The Hellenistic Age was a time of transition, and the Stoic philosopher was perhaps its most influential spokesman. A new culture was in the making. The heritage of an earlier period, with Athens as its intellectual leader, was to continue, but to undergo many changes. If, as with Socrates, to know is to know oneself, rationality as the sole means by which something outside of the self might be achieved may be said to be the hallmark of Stoic belief. As a Hellenistic philosophy, Stoicism presented an ars vitae, a way of accommodation for people to whom the human condition no longer appeared as the mirror of a universal, calm, and ordered existence. Reason alone could reveal the constancy of cosmic order and the originative source of unyielding value; thus, reason became the true model for human existence. To the Stoic, virtue is an inherent feature of the world, no less inexorable in relation to man than are the laws of nature. The Stoics believed that perception is the basis of true knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Hellenistic Philosophy
    Hellenistic Philosophy drishtiias.com/printpdf/hellenistic-philosophy Introduction The Greek philosophy began as speculation into the nature of the cosmos or universe (Meta Physics). The early philosophers, in the Pre-Socratic era, like Sophists, Democritus, Pythagoras and others made bold speculations about the origins and nature of the universe. With the advent of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, the focus of philosophy also shifted towards morality, virtues and ethics. However, due to the sudden death of Alexander the Great (in 323 BC), the whole of Greece fell into a state of uncertainty & local wars and later it became a province of Rome. The empires that succeeded him, known as the Hellenistic empires, lasted for hundreds of years and spread Greek culture over huge territories. As the life of the average citizen was changing, the prevalent philosophical thought also underwent a change. Political, social and moral environment no longer sustained the creative impulses in philosophical thought and this gave rise to Hellenistic Age or post-Aristotelian philosophy. A common element of the philosophers in Hellenistic age was that the focus of Philosophy was shifting from general understanding of the universe to individual life and its perception as an “art of life”. Philosophy ends up being a driver of life and a source of relief, a healing art, a way to cope with a hostile world. This period saw the emergence of the three great schools of moral philosophy viz. Epicureanism, Stoicism and Skepticism. Epicureanism This school derives its name from its founder Epicurus, who founded his school on the outskirts of Athens and famously called it as the Garden (307 BC).
    [Show full text]
  • In Defense of Stoicism
    In Defense of Stoicism by ALEX HENDERSON* Georgetown University Abstract This article employs Cicero’s assault on Stoic philosophy inPro Murena as a point of departure to engage three critical aspects of Stoicism: indifference to worldly concerns, the sage as an ideal, and Stoic epistemology. It argues that Cicero’s analysis fails to clearly distinguish between these elements of Stoic philosophy and, therefore, presents Stoicism in a misleadingly unfavorable light. harges of bribery were brought against Lucius Licinius Murena in 62 bce. Despite entrenched opposition from the popular Cparty, Murena was able to enlist the aid of the famed orator and presiding consul Marcus Tullius Cicero. His prosecutor was the most conservative of senators—Marcus Porcius Cato, famed for his rectitude and his unbending adherence to Stoic philosophy. In order to defend Murena, who was almost certainly guilty, Cicero chose to go on the offensive and discredit his opponent by undermining Stoic philosophy in the eyes of the jury. Cicero portrays Stoicism as follows: A wise person never allows himself to be influenced… Philosophers are people who, however ugly, remain handsome; even if they are very poor, they are rich; even if they are slaves, they are kings. All sins are equal, so that every misdemeanor is a serious crime… The philosopher has no need to offer conjectures, never regrets what he has done, is never mistaken, never changes his mind.1 Cicero’s portrayal seems to argue that (1) the Stoics’ commitment to remain indifferent to worldly influence causes them to lack compassion for the circumstances of other people, (2) Stoics are too severe when * [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism and Anti-Stoicism in Qoheleth
    STOICISM AND ANTI-STOICISM IN QOHELETH by JOHN G. GAMMIE The University of Tulsa, Tulsa, Oklahoma 74104 It is a distinct pleasure to submit this comparative and linguistic study to a volume in honor of Shlomo Dov Goitein whose scholarly work did so much to illumine the life of Jewish communities in the Arab world. The present study seeks to probe the impact of one particular Hellenistic philosophy on a Jewish intellectual of the third century B.C.E. whose work was destined to become part of the sacred scripture of his own people as well as of the people of a daughter religion. Over fifty years ago Galling (1932, p. 276) identified four mam questions among researchers in Qoheleth: (I) How should one read the theme of the book and understand its arrangement? (2) Are the "I-sayings" signs of an autobiography, and can they be coordinated with "historical allusions"? (3) Do there exist con­ nections between Qoheleth's wisdom and the wisdom literature of the ancient near East? and (4) Has Greek philosophy been worked into the book? (My translation) By and large the same basic questions have continued to dominate in the research since Galling. A fairly thorough survey of research on Qoheleth by James Crenshaw may be found in a recent issue of the Hebrew Annual Review (1983, pp. 41-56). Accordingly, a selective update in response to the questions in Galling's earlier essay may serve as an introduction to the present inquiry. (I) On the issue of arrangement, Zimmerli (1974) has convincingly shown there is a greater coherence among the various sentences than Galling was inclined to accept; Loader (l 979) has identified "polarities" within the book and has demonstrated its dynamic unity on the basis of their presence, whereas Wright (1968) and Murphy (1981) have focused on key phrases as a means of establishing its formal unity.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Greek Philosophy. Part 1. Pre-Socratic Greek Philosophers
    Ancient Greek Philosophy. Part 1. Pre-Socratic Greek philosophers. The pre-Socratic philosophers rejected traditional mythological explanations for the phenomena they saw around them in favor of more rational explanations. Many of them asked: From where does everything come? From what is everything created? How do we explain the plurality of things found in nature? How might we describe nature mathematically? The Milesian school was a school of thought founded in the 6th Century BC. The ideas associated with it are exemplified by three philosophers from the Ionian town of Miletus, on the Aegean coast of Anatolia: Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes. They introduced new opinions contrary to the prevailing viewpoint on how the world was organized. Philosophy of nature These philosophers defined all things by their quintessential substance (which Aristotle calls the arche) of which the world was formed and which was the source of everything. Thales thought it to be water. But as it was impossible to explain some things (such as fire) as being composed of this element, Anaximander chose an unobservable, undefined element, which he called apeiron. He reasoned that if each of the four traditional elements (water, air, fire, and earth) are opposed to the other three, and if they cancel each other out on contact, none of them could constitute a stable, truly elementary form of matter. Consequently, there must be another entity from which the others originate, and which must truly be the most basic element of all. The unspecified nature of the apeiron upset critics, which caused Anaximenes to define it as being air, a more concrete, yet still subtle, element.
    [Show full text]
  • The Meaning of Voluntas in Augustine
    Augustinian Studies 37:2 (2006) 171–189 The Meaning of Voluntas in Augustine Sarah Byers Ave Maria University Augustine uses the term voluntas for dispositional and occurrent forms of hormê of a rational being, hormê being the Stoic concept of ‘impulse’ toward action.1 In what follows I shall first demonstrate this, using mainly books twelve and fourteen of the De Civitate Dei. There is need of such a demonstration, for although much ink has been spilt over the sense of “will” in Augustine’s texts, interpretations have varied greatly. Next I shall draw attention to a num- ber of corroborating texts from works spanning thirty years of his writing career, highlighting how this Stoic concept, together with Stoic epistemology, makes sense of the uses of voluntas in book eight of the Confessiones and of ‘free will’ (libera voluntas, liberum arbitrium voluntatis) in the De Libero Arbitrio. I conclude with suggestions about specific texts and authors influ- encing Augustine’s usage. Recent Interpretations Gerard O’Daly has sometimes seemed very close to identifying Augustine’s voluntas with Stoic hormê, but has not actually done so. In Augustine’s Phi- losophy of Mind, he once calls will “impulse,”2 but nowhere mentions the Stoic concept of “impulse” as a psychic prompt toward action. Moreover, he does 1. See B. Inwood, Ethics and Human Action in Early Stoicism (Oxford: Clarendon, 1985), 20, 53, and passim. 2. G. O’Daly, Augustine’s Philosophy of Mind (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1987) 26. Again he comes close to identifying appetitus (which he identifies with “im- pulse,” p.
    [Show full text]
  • Manual of Reformed Stoicism
    Manual of Reformed Stoicism Piotr Stankiewicz Series in Philosophy Copyright © 2020 Vernon Press, an imprint of Vernon Art and Science Inc, on behalf of the author. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Vernon Art and Science Inc. www.vernonpress.com In the Americas: In the rest of the world: Vernon Press Vernon Press 1000 N West Street, C/Sancti Espiritu 17, Suite 1200, Wilmington, Malaga, 29006 Delaware 19801 Spain United States Series in Philosophy Library of Congress Control Number: 2019957903 ISBN: 978-1-62273-648-5 DISCLAIMER This is a philosophical book – it’s purpose is to educate. It is not intended as a substitute for psychological counseling. If you need help, please do not hesitate to see a mental health professional. The author and publisher disclaim any responsibility or liability resulting from the actions advocated or discussed in this book. The purchaser of this book assumes the responsibility for the decisions they take during and/or after reading the book, based on the information in the book. Product and company names mentioned in this work are the trademarks of their respective owners. While every care has been taken in preparing this work, neither the authors nor Vernon Art and Science Inc. may be held responsible for any loss or damage caused or alleged to be caused directly or indirectly by the information contained in it. Every effort has been made to trace all copyright holders, but if any have been inadvertently overlooked the publisher will be pleased to include any necessary credits in any subsequent reprint or edition.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism, Scepticism, & Epicureanism
    Stoicism, Scepticism, & Epicureanism: Philosophies of Life Final Exam Duration: 2 Hours Note: All questions are of equal value. Scoring Each of the following six questions is worth a total of 5 points. Answers will be graded according to the following rubric: 5 Clear, careful, accurate, nuanced & insightful answer, supported by multiple pieces of evidence that are thoughtfully woven together and balanced against each other 4 Clear, careful, & accurate answer, supported by multiple pieces of evidence 3 Clear, accurate, but simplistic answer, supported by a minimal amount of evidence 2 Clear but inaccurate answer, which misrepresents or misunderstands the view in question 1 Unclear or extremely inaccurate answer 0 No answer PART I: Creative applications For each of the following three questions, write a short essay answering one of the available prompts. Remember that there is no single “right” answer to any of these prompts; the key is how you develop and support your answer. Wherever possible, explain your answers with reference to the specific ideas and principles of the relevant philosophical school. Question 1: Epicureanism Answer one of the following three prompts. (1A) Dating advice You’ve been single for a while now and are wondering whether you should start dating. What would an Epicurean tell you to do? (How should you date? Whom should you date? Why should you date? Or should you not bother dating at all?) (1B) Why recycle? Let’s face it: recycling is a nuisance. It’d much easier and more convenient just to throw everything in the garbage. What would an Epicurean think about recycling? Would an Epicurean go through the hassle of recycling, or would they not bother? Why? (1C) Free massages It’s your lucky day! You’ve just won a lifetime of free massages at your local spa.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism in Early Christianity
    STOICISM IN EARLY CHRISTIANITY Edited by Tuomas Rasimus, Troels Engberg-Pedersen, and Ismo Dunderberg K Tuomas Rasimus, Troels Engberg-Pedersen and Ismo Dunderberg, Stoicism in Early Christianity Baker Academic, a division of Baker Publishing Group, © 2010. Used by permission. _Rasimus_Stoicism_BB_djm.indd 3 9/29/10 3:29 PM © 2010 by Tuomas Rasimus, Troels Engberg-Pedersen, and Ismo Dunderberg Published by Baker Academic a division of Baker Publishing Group P.O. Box 6287, Grand Rapids, MI 49516-6287 www.bakeracademic.com Printed in the United States of America All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Stoicism in early Christianity / edited by Tuomas Rasimus, Troels Engberg- Pedersen, and Ismo Dunderberg. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and indexes. ISBN 978-0-8010-3951-5 (alk. paper) 1. Stoics. 2. Philosophy and religion—Rome. 3. Church history—Primitive and early church, ca. 30–600. 4. Bible. N.T.—Philosophy. I. Rasimus, Tuomas. II. Engberg-Pedersen, Troels. III. Dunderberg, Ismo. BR128.A2.S76 2010 261.2—dc22 2010021683 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Tuomas Rasimus, Troels Engberg-Pedersen and Ismo Dunderberg, Stoicism in Early Christianity Baker Academic, a division of Baker Publishing Group, © 2010. Used by permission. _Rasimus_Stoicism_BB_djm.indd 4 9/29/10 3:29 PM Contents Preface vii Abbreviations ix 1. Setting the Scene: Stoicism and Platonism in the Transitional Period in Ancient Philosophy 1 Troels Engberg-Pedersen 2.
    [Show full text]