<<

. Part 1. Pre-Socratic Greek . The pre-Socratic philosophers rejected traditional mythological explanations for the phenomena they saw around them in favor of more rational explanations. Many of them asked:  From where does everything come?  From what is everything created?  How do we explain the plurality of things found in ?  How might we describe nature mathematically? The Milesian was a founded in the 6th Century BC. The associated with it are exemplified by three philosophers from the Ionian town of , on the Aegean coast of Anatolia: Thales, , and Anaximenes. They introduced new opinions contrary to the prevailing viewpoint on how the world was organized. Philosophy of nature These philosophers defined all things by their quintessential substance (which calls the ) of which the world was formed and which was the source of everything. Thales thought it to be water. But as it was impossible to explain some things (such as ) as composed of this element, Anaximander chose an unobservable, undefined element, which he called . He reasoned that if each of the four traditional elements (water, , fire, and ) are opposed to the other three, and if they cancel each other out on contact, none of them could constitute a stable, truly elementary form of . Consequently, there must be another entity from which the others originate, and which must truly be the most basic element of all. The unspecified nature of the apeiron upset critics, which caused Anaximenes to define it as being air, a more concrete, yet still subtle, element. Anaximenes held that by its evaporation and condensation, air can change into other elements or substances such as fire, wind, clouds, water, and earth. is a term used for the esoteric and metaphysical beliefs held by and his followers, the Pythagoreans, who were much influenced by . Like Thales, Pythagoras is rather known for mathematics than for philosophy. His immediate followers were strongly influenced by him, and even until today Pythagoras shines through the mist of ages as one of the brightest figures of early Greek antiquity. Pythagoras founded a society of disciples which has been very influential for some . Men and women in the society were treated equally -an unusual thing at the time- and all was held in common. Members of the society practised the master’s teachings, a the tenets of which included the transmigration of and the sinfulness of eating beans. Pythagoras’ followers had to obey strict religious orders where it was forbidden to eat beans, to touch white cocks, or to look into a mirror beside a light. Pythagoras, like no other, embodied the contradistinctions of the mystical and rational world, which is woven into his personality and philosophy. In his , , spirits, souls, and the mystic connections between them formed one big picture. After Pythagoras introduced the of eternal recurrence into Greek thought, which was apparently motivated by his studies of earlier Egyptian scriptures, the idea soon became popular in . It was Pythagoras’ ambition to reveal in his philosophy the and structure of a higher order, the basis of the divine order, for which souls return in a constant cycle. This is how Pythagoras came to mathematics. It could be said that Pythagoras saw the study of mathematics as a purifier of the , just like he considered as purifying.

1 Pythagoras and his disciples connected music with mathematics and found that intervals between notes can be expressed in numerical terms. They discovered that the length of strings of a musical instrument correspond to these intervals and that they can be expressed in numbers. The of the length of two strings with which two tones of an octave step are produced is 2:1. Music was not the only field that Pythagoras considered worthy of study, in he saw numbers in everything. He was convinced that the divine principles of the , though imperceptible to the , can be expressed in terms of relationships of numbers. He therefore reasoned that the secrets of the are revealed by pure thought, through deduction and analytic reflection on the perceptible world. This eventually led to the famous saying that “all things are numbers.” He associated numbers with form, relating to . of (ca. 535–475 BC) was a pre-Socratic Greek , a native of Ephesus, , on the coast of Minor. Heraclitus is known for his doctrine of change being central to the universe, and that the is the fundamental order of all. He became famous as the "flux and fire" philosopher for his proverbial utterance: "All things are flowing." In spite of the difficulties, Heraclitus was admired by his contemporaries for the of flux, which influenced many generations of philosophers after him. Let us look at the idea of flux and fire. Before Heraclitus, the world of the ancient had been fairly static. The Greeks before Heraclitus focused on the of things, its nature and being, which they deemed unchangeable. In contrast, Heraclitus said: "You cannot step into the same river twice, for fresh waters are ever flowing in upon you." This simple expresses the gist of his philosophy, that the river isn't actually the same at two different points in time. - He told people that nothing is the same now as it was before, and thus nothing what is now be the same tomorrow. With this he planted the idea of into Greek thought, and indeed, after Heraclitus Greek philosophy was not the same anymore. Heraclitus held that fire is the primordial element out of which everything else arises. Fire is the origin of all matter; through it things come into being and pass away. Fire itself is the of perpetual change because it transforms a substance into another substance without being a substance itself: "This world, which is the same for all, no one of gods or men has made; but it was ever, is now, and ever shall be eternal fire." When Heraclitus speaks of , he doesn't mean the Greek gods, neither a personal entity. Instead he thinks that God is living in every soul and even in every material thing on earth. The fiery element is the expression of God in everything, thus he is in every a pantheist. Another of Heraclitus' main teachings can be called the "". The unity of opposites means that opposites cannot exist without each other - there is no day without night, no summer without winter, no warm without cold, no good without bad. The were a school of pre-Socratic philosophers at Elea, a Greek colony in , . The group was founded in the early fifth century BCE by . Other members of the school included and Melissus of . Parmenides of Elea. His only known work is a poem which has survived only in fragmentary form. In it, Parmenides describes two views of . In the Way of , he explained how reality is

2 one; change is impossible; and is timeless, uniform, and unchanging. In the Way of Opinion, he explained the world of appearances, which is false and deceitful. The Way of Truth discusses that which is real, which contrasts in some way with the argument of the Way of Opinion, which discusses that which is illusory. Under the Way of Truth, Parmenides stated that there are two ways of : that it is, that it is not. He said that the latter argument is never feasible because nothing can not be: For never shall this prevail, that things that are not are. Thinking and the thought that it is are the same; for you will not find thought apart from what is, in relation to which it is uttered. For thought and being are the same. It is necessary to speak and to think what is; for being is, but nothing is not. Thus, he concluded that "Is" could not have "come into being" because "nothing comes from nothing". Existence is necessarily eternal. He was struggling with the of change, which is still a relevant philosophical topic today. Zeno of Elea was a pre-Socratic Greek philosopher of southern Italy and a member of the Eleatic School founded by Parmenides. Aristotle called him the inventor of the , and credited him with having laid the foundations of modern . He is best known for his . Zeno's paradoxes are a of problems generally thought to have been devised by Zeno of Elea to support Parmenides's doctrine that "all is one" and that, contrary to the evidence of our senses, the in plurality and change is mistaken, and in particular that motion is nothing but an illusion. Several of Zeno's eight surviving paradoxes (preserved in Aristotle's and Simplicius's commentary thereon) are essentially equivalent to one another; and most of them were regarded, even in ancient , as very easy to refute. Three of the strongest and most famous—that of and the tortoise, the argument, and that of an arrow in flight—are presented in more detail below. Zeno's arguments are perhaps the first examples of a method of proof called also known as proof by contradiction. The Paradoxes of Motion Achilles and the tortoise “In a race, the quickest runner can never overtake the slowest, since the pursuer must first reach the point whence the pursued started, so that the slower must always hold a lead.” In the of Achilles and the Tortoise, Achilles is in a footrace with the tortoise. Achilles allows the tortoise a head start of 100 feet. If we suppose that each racer starts running at some constant speed (one very fast and one very slow), then after some finite time, Achilles will have run 100 feet, bringing him to the tortoise's starting point. During this time, the tortoise has run a much shorter distance, for example 10 feet. It will then take Achilles some further time to run that distance, in which time the tortoise will have advanced farther; and then more time still to reach this third point, while the tortoise moves ahead. Thus, whenever Achilles reaches somewhere the tortoise has been, he still has farther to go. Therefore, because there are an infinite of points Achilles must reach where the tortoise has already been-- he can never overtake the tortoise. The arrow paradox “If everything when it occupies an equal is at rest, and if that which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment, the flying arrow is therefore motionless.”

3 In the arrow paradox, Zeno states that for motion to be occurring, an object must change the position which it occupies. He gives an example of an arrow in flight. He states that in any one instant of time, for the arrow to be moving it must either move to where it is, or it must move to where it is not. It cannot move to where it is not, because this is a single instant, and it cannot move to where it is because it is already there. In other words, in any instant of time there is no motion occurring, because an instant is a snapshot. Therefore, if it cannot move in a single instant it cannot move in any instant, making any motion impossible. Whereas the first paradox presented divide space, this paradox starts by dividing time - and not into segments, but into points. (500 BC – 428 BC) was a Pre-Socratic Greek philosopher famous for introducing the cosmological of (mind), the ordering force. Cosmological theory All things have existed from the beginning. But originally they existed in infinitesimally small fragments of themselves, endless in number and inextricably combined. All things existed in this mass, but in a confused and indistinguishable form. Mind arranged the segregation of like from unlike. This peculiar thing, called Mind (Nous), was no less illimitable than the chaotic mass, but, unlike the logos of Heraclitus, it stood pure and independent, a thing of finer texture, alike in all its manifestations and everywhere the same. This subtle agent, possessed of all and power, is especially seen ruling in all the forms of . Mind causes motion. It rotated the primitive mixture, starting in one corner or point, and gradually extended until it gave distinctness and reality to the aggregates of like parts, working something like a centrifuge, and eventually creating the known cosmos. But even after it had done its best, the original intermixture of things was not wholly overcome. No one thing in the world is ever abruptly separated, as by the blow of an axe, from the rest of things. is considered the last Greek philosopher to write in verse and the surviving fragments of his teaching are from two poems, Purifications and . On Nature There are about 450 lines of his poem On Nature extant, including 70 lines which have been reconstructed from some papyrus scraps known as the Strasbourg Papyrus. It was this poem which outlined his philosophical system. In it, Empedocles explains not only the nature and history of the universe, including his theory of the four classical elements, but he describes on causation, perception, and thought, as well as explanations of terrestrial phenomena and biological processes. The four elements It was Empedocles who established four ultimate elements which make all the structures in the world - fire, air, water, earth. Empedocles called these four elements "roots", which, in typical fashion, he also identified with the mythical names of , , Nestis, and Aidoneus. According to the different proportions in which these four indestructible and unchangeable elements are combined with each other the of the structure is produced. It is in the aggregation and segregation of elements thus arising, that Empedocles, like the atomists, found the real process which corresponds to what is popularly termed growth, increase or decrease. Nothing new comes or can come into being; the only change that can occur is a change in the juxtaposition of element with element. This theory of the four elements became the standard for the next two thousand years.

4 Love and Strife The four elements are, however, simple, eternal, and unalterable, and as change is the consequence of their mixture and separation, it was also necessary to suppose the existence of moving powers - to bring about mixture and separation. The four elements are eternally brought into union, and eternally parted from each other, by two divine powers, Love and Strife. Love explains the attraction of different forms of matter, and Strife accounts for their separation. If the elements are the content of the universe, then Love and Strife explain their variation and . Love and Strife are attractive and repulsive forces which the ordinary eye can see working amongst people, but which really pervade the universe. They alternately hold empire over things, - neither, however, being ever quite absent. Like Pythagoras, Empedocles believed in the transmigration of the soul, that souls can be reincarnated between humans, animals and even plants. was a pre-Socratic Greek materialist philosopher (born at Abdera in Thrace ca. 460 BC - died ca 370 BC). Democritus was a student of and co-originator of the belief that all matter is made up of various imperishable, indivisible elements which he called atoma (sg. atomon) or "indivisible units", from which we get the English word atom. Atoms and Democritus agreed that everything which is must be eternal, but denied that "the void" can be equated with nothing. This makes him the first thinker on record to argue the existence of an entirely empty "void". In order to explain the change around us from basic, unchangeable substance he created a theory that argued that there are various basic elements which always existed but can be rearranged into many different forms. Democritus' theory argued that atoms only had several properties, particularly size, shape, and (perhaps) weight; all other properties that we attribute to matter, such as color and taste, are but the result of complex interactions between the atoms in our bodies and the atoms of the matter that we are examining. Though intelligence is allowed to explain the organization of the world, according to Democritus, he does allow for the existence of a soul, which he contends is composed of exceedingly fine and spherical atoma (now called atoms, as mentioned above). He holds that, "spherical atoma move because it is their nature never to be still, and as they move they draw the whole body along with them, and set it in motion." In this way, he viewed soul-atoma as being similar to fire-atoma: small, spherical, capable of penetrating solid bodies and good examples of spontaneous motion. Democritus explained senses along these lines as well. He hypothesized that different tastes were a result of differently shaped atoms in contact with the tongue. Smells and sounds could be explained similarly. Vision works by the eye receiving "images" or "effluences" of bodies that are emanated. He stated that, "Sweet exists by , bitter by convention, color by convention; but in reality atoms and the void alone exist." This means that senses could not provide a direct or certain knowledge of the world. In his words, "It's necessary to realize that by this principle man is cut off from the real." Later philosophers use this to deny that any reliable knowledge can be obtained, but Democritus felt differently: There are two forms of knowledge: one legitimate, one bastard. To the latter form belong all the following: sight, hearing, smell, taste, touch. The legitimate is quite distinct from this. When the bastard form cannot see more minutely, nor hear nor smell nor taste nor perceive through touch, then another, finer form must be employed. - Democritus, Fragment 11, The of Life One view purports that this finer form is reasoning, although Democritus does not explain 's place in the atomistic view.

5 Classical period of Greek philosophy Greece called into existence a of teachers known as sophists. They wandered about Greece from place to place, gave lectures, took pupils, and entered into disputations. For these services they exacted large fees, and were, in fact, the first in Greece to take fees for teaching . The sophists were not, technically speaking, philosophers, but, instead taught any subject for which there was a popular demand. Topics included , , , , history, physics, and mathematics. Early on they were seen as teachers of in the sense that they taught people to perform their function in the state. of Abdera, of Leontini, of Ceos and of Elis. The aims of the young politicians whom they trained were to persuade the multitude of whatever they wished them to believed. The search for truth was not top priority. Consequently the sophists undertook to provide a stock of arguments on any subject, or to prove any position. They boasted of their ability to make the worse appear the better reason, to prove that black is white. Some, like Gorgias, asserted that it was not necessary to have any knowledge of a subject to give satisfactory replies as regards it. Protagoras is known primarily for three claims (1) that man is the measure of all things (which is often interpreted as a sort of radical ) (2) that he could make the "worse (or weaker) argument appear the better (or stronger)" and (3) that one could not tell if the gods existed or not. Protagoras' notion that judgments and knowledge are in some way relative to the person judging or knowing has been very influential, and is still widely discussed in .

A new period of philosophy opens with the Athenian (469-399 BCE). Perhaps his most important contribution to Western thought is his dialectic method of inquiry, known as the or method of "elenchus," which he largely applied to the examination of key moral such as the Good and . It was first described by in the Socratic . To solve a problem, it would be broken down into a of questions, the answers to which gradually distill the answer you seek. The influence of this approach is most strongly felt today in the use of the , in which hypothesis is the first stage. The development and practice of this method is one of Socrates' most enduring contributions, and is a key factor in earning his mantle as the father of , or moral philosophy, and as a figurehead of all the central themes in . Socrates often said his wisdom was limited to an awareness of his own ignorance. Socrates believed wrongdoing was a consequence of ignorance and those who did wrong knew no better. The one thing Socrates consistently claimed to have knowledge of was "the art of love" which he connected with the concept of "the love of wisdom", i.e., philosophy. He never actually claimed to be wise, only to understand the path a lover of wisdom must take in pursuing it. It is debatable whether Socrates believed humans could actually become wise. On the one hand, he drew a clear line between human ignorance and ideal knowledge; on the other, Plato's (Diotima's Speech) and ( of the Cave) describe a method for ascending to wisdom.

6 Plato The In many of his dialogues, Plato mentions supra-sensible entities he calls "Forms" (or "Ideas"). Plato sometimes characterizes this participation in the Form as a kind of imaging, or approximation of the Form. The same may be said of the many things that are greater or smaller and the Forms of Great and Small, or the many tall things and the Form of Tall, or the many beautiful things and the Form of . When Plato writes about instances of Forms "approximating" Forms, it is easy to infer that, for Plato, Forms are exemplars. If so, Plato that The Form of Beauty is perfect beauty, the Form of Justice is perfect justice, and so forth. Scholars disagree about the scope of what is often called "the theory of Forms," and question whether Plato began holding that there are only Forms for a small range of properties, such as tallness, equality, justice, beauty, and so on, and then widened the scope to include Forms corresponding to every term that can be applied to a multiplicity of instances. He may have come to believe that for any set of things that shares some property, there is a Form that gives unity to the set of things (and univocity to the term by which we refer to members of that set of things). and In the early transitional , the , Plato has Socrates introduce the Orphic and Pythagorean idea that souls are immortal and existed before our births. All knowledge, he explains, is actually recollected from this prior existence. Several arguments for the immortality of the soul, and the idea that souls are reincarnated into different life forms, are also featured in Plato's . In the Symposium, which is normally dated at the beginning of the middle period, and in the , which is dated at the end of the middle period or later yet, Plato introduces his theory of erôs (usually translated as "love"). Also in that dialogue, we are told of the "ladder of love," by which the lover can ascend to direct cognitive contact with (usually compared to a kind of vision of) Beauty Itself. In the Phaedrus, love is revealed to be the great "divine madness" through which the wings of the lover's soul may sprout, allowing the lover to take flight to all of the highest aspirations and achievements possible for humankind. In both of these dialogues, Plato clearly regards actual physical or sexual contact between lovers as degraded and wasteful forms of erotic expression. Because the true goal of erôs is real beauty and real beauty is the Form of Beauty, what Plato calls Beauty Itself, erôs finds its fulfillment only in Platonic philosophy. Unless it channels its power of love into "higher pursuits," which culminate in the knowledge of the Form of Beauty, erôs is doomed to frustration. For this reason, Plato thinks that most people sadly squander the real power of love by limiting themselves to the mere pleasures of physical beauty. Plato's greatest and most enduring work was his lengthy dialogue, The Republic. This dialogue has often been regarded as Plato's blueprint for a future society of . I do not accept this opinion. Instead, I would like to suggest that The Republic is not a blueprint for a future society, but rather, is a dialogue which discusses the education necessary to produce such a society. The Republic discusses a number of topics including the nature of justice, statesmanship, ethics and the nature of politics. It is in The Republic that Plato suggests that was little more than a "charming form of government." And this he is writing less than one hundred years after the brilliant age of Periclean democracy. After all, it was that convicted Socrates. For Plato, the citizens are the least desirable participants in government.

7 Instead, a philosopher-king or guardian should hold the reigns of power. An aristocracy if you will – an aristocracy of the very best. Plato's Republic also embodies one of the clearest expressions of his theory of knowledge. In The Republic, Plato asks what is knowledge? what is illusion? what is reality? how do we know? what makes a thing, a thing? what can we know? These are epistemological questions – that is, they are questions about knowledge itself. He distinguishes between the reality presented to us by our senses – sight, touch, taste, sound and smell – and the essence or Form of that reality. In other words, reality is always changing – knowledge of reality is individual, it is particular, it is knowledge only to the individual knower, it is not universal. The unphilosophical man – that is, all of us – is at the mercy of sense impressions and unfortunately, our sense impressions oftentimes fail us. Our senses deceive us. But because we trust our senses, we are like prisoners in a cave – we mistake shadows on a wall for reality. This is the central argument of Plato's which appears in Book VII of The Republic. Plato realized that the Athenian state, and along with it, Athenian direct democracy, had failed to realize its lofty ideals. Instead, the citizens sent Socrates to his death and direct democracy had failed. Plato wanted to rescue from degeneration by reviving that sense of community that had at one time made the great. The only way to do this, Plato argued, was to give control over to the Philosopher-Kings, men who had philosophical knowledge, and to give little more than "noble " to everyone else. The problem as Plato saw it was that power and wisdom had traveled divergent paths -- his solution was to unite them in the guise of the Philosopher-King. Aristotle Plato's most famous student was ARISTOTLE (384-322 B.C.). His father was the personal physician to Philip of Macedon and Aristotle was, for a time at least, the personal tutor of . At the age of eighteen, Aristotle became the student at the of Plato (who was then sixty years of age). Aristotle also started his own school, the in 335 B.C. It Aristotle was a "polymath" – he knew a great deal about nearly everything. Very little of Aristotle's writings remain extant. But his students recorded nearly everything he discussed at the Lyceum. Regardless, Aristotle lectured on , physics, logic, , music, , , , , ethics and politics. The one field in which he did not excel was mathematics. As a scientist, Aristotle's is perhaps closer to our own. For Aristotle did not agree with Plato that there is an essence or Form or behind every object in the phenomenal world. Or, as one historian has put it: "The point is, that an elephant, when present, is noticed." In other words, whereas Plato suggested that man was born with knowledge, Aristotle argued that knowledge comes from . And there, in the space of just a few decades, we have the essence of those two philosophical traditions which have occupied the western intellectual tradition for the past 2500 years. – knowledge is a priori (comes before experience) and – knowledge is a posteriori (comes after experience). , The Four Causes  The material cause is that from which a thing comes into existence as from its part, constituents, substratum or materials. This reduces the explanation of causes to the parts (factors, elements, constituents, ingredients) forming the whole (system, structure, compound, complex, composite, or combination), a relationship known as the part-whole causation. Simply put it is the influence of the material substances on the . So imagine two dominos,

8 the first of which is lighter. The first is knocked over into the second but does not have enough power to knock it over, this is Material cause.  The formal cause tells us what a thing is, that any thing is determined by the definition, form, pattern, essence, whole, synthesis or archetype. It embraces the account of causes in terms of fundamental principles or general , as the whole (i.e., macrostructure) is the cause of its parts, a relationship known as the whole-part causation. Plainly put it is the influence of the form (essence) of the things on the event. So take the two dominos again except this time the second is shaped to prevent it from falling *eg. triangular.* this is formal cause.  The efficient cause is that from which the change or the ending of the change first starts. It identifies 'what makes of what is made and what causes change of what is changed' and so suggests all sorts of agents, nonliving or living, acting as the sources of change or movement or rest. Representing the current understanding of causality as the relation of cause and effect, this covers the modern definitions of "cause" as either the agent or or particular events or states of affairs. More simply again that which immediately sets the thing in motion. So take the two dominos this time of equal weighting, the first is knocked over causing the second also to fall over. This is effectively efficient cause.  The final cause is that for the sake of which a thing exists or is done, including both purposeful and instrumental actions and activities. The final cause or is the purpose or end that something is supposed to serve, or it is that from which and that to which the change is. This also covers modern ideas of mental causation involving such psychological causes as volition, need, motivation, or motives, rational, irrational, ethical, all that gives purpose to behavior. Metaphysics Aristotle defines metaphysics as "the knowledge of immaterial being," or of "being in the highest degree of abstraction." He refers to metaphysics as "first philosophy", as well as "the theologic ." Substance, potentiality and actuality Aristotle examines the concept of substance in his Metaphysics, Book VII and he concludes that a particular substance is a combination of both matter and form. As he proceeds to the book VIII, he concludes that the matter of the substance is the substratum or the stuff of which it is composed, e.g. the matter of the house are the bricks, stones, timbers etc., or whatever constitutes the potential house. While the form of the substance, is the actual house, namely 'covering for bodies and chattels' or any other . The formula that gives the components is the account of the matter, and the formula that gives the differentia is the account of the form. The coming to be is a change where nothing persists of which the resultant is a property. In that particular change he introduces the concept of potentiality (dynamis) and actuality (entelecheia) in association with the matter and the form. Referring to potentiality, this is what a thing is capable of doing, or being acted upon, if it is not prevented by something else. For example, the seed of a in the soil is potentially (dynamei) plant, and if is not prevented by something, it will become a plant. Potentially can either 'act' (poiein) or 'be acted upon' (paschein), which can be either innate or learned. For example, the eyes possess the potentiality of sight (innate - being acted upon), while the capability of playing the flute can be possessed by learning (exercise - acting). Actuality is the fulfillment of the end of the potentiality. Because the end (telos) is the principle of every change, and for the sake of the end exists potentiality, therefore actuality is the end. Referring then to our previous example, we could say that actuality is when the seed of the plant becomes a plant.

9 In conclusion, the matter of the house is its potentiality and the form is its actuality. The formal cause (aitia) then of that change from potential to actual house, is the reason (logos) of the house builder and the final cause is the end, namely the house itself. Then Aristotle proceeds and concludes that the actuality is prior to potentiality in formula, in time and in substantiality. With this definition of the particular substance (i.e., matter and form), Aristotle tries to solve the problem of the unity of the beings, e.g., what is that makes the man one? Since, according to Plato there are two Ideas: animal and biped, how then is man a unity? However, according to Aristotle, the potential being (matter) and the actual one (form) are one and the same thing.

Hellenistic Philosophy Both and sought to give , or peace of mind. For the aim of life was pleasure; the highest pleasure was absence of ; pleasure of the mind was preferable to that of the body. The soul with the body, so we must not fear death or ; the gods exist but do not concern themselves with humanity or natural phenomena (all of which can be explained scientifically); we should avoid public life and emotional commitments in order to escape the pains likely to be caused by them. The physical world was explained by the adapted from Democritus. Stoicism. Stoic ideas appear in the greatest work of Roman literature, Vergil's , and later the philosophy was adopted by Seneca (c. 1-65 A.D.), (39-65; poet and associate of the Emperor ), (c. 55-135; see passages from the Enchiridion ), and the Emperor Aurelius (born 121, Emperor 161-180; author of the ). Stoicism is perhaps the most significant philosophical school in the , and much of our contemporary views and popular mythologies about Romans are derived from Stoic principles. Sceptisism. This is actually not a philosophical school, but one could generally group a number of Hellenistic under this rubric, including the Second Academy (Hellenistic Platonists), the Second Sophistic, the Cynics, the Skeptics, and so on, and, for the most part, the Stoics as well. What is important for our purposes is that all these schools to some degree or another espoused the idea that human beings cannot arrive at certain truth about anything (not all denied was impossible, only that human beings could never be certain). Basically, life became this great guessing game: the lot of humanity is to be cast into a twilight world in which all that we know and think is either false or occupies some middle position between the false and the true (which was called the "probable," "readily believable," or the "verisimilar"). This comes to dominate thought in late antiquity; the first philosophical attacks levels against the thought of antiquity are refutations of sceptical principles. Of all the of antiquity, this is perhaps the most familiar to you: the skeptic principle of doubting everything became, in the modern era, the fundamental basis of the scientific method.

10