A Nominalist's Dilemma and Its Solution
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
A Nominalist’s Dilemma and its Solution 2 Abstract Current versions of nominalism in the philosophy of mathemat- ics have the benefit of avoiding commitment to the existence of A Nominalist’s Dilemma and its Solution∗ mathematical objects. But this comes with a cost: to avoid com- mitment to mathematical entities, nominalists cannot take math- ematical theories literally, and so, they seem unable to accommo- Ot´avio Bueno date mathematical practice. In a recent work, Jody Azzouni has Department of Philosophy challenged this conclusion, by formulating a nominalist view that University of South Carolina doesn’t have this cost (Azzouni 2004). In this paper, we argue that, as it stands, Azzouni’s proposal doesn’t yet succeed. It faces Columbia, SC 29208 a dilemma to the effect that either the view isn’t nominalist or it [email protected] fails to take mathematics literally. So, in the end, it still doesn’t do justice to mathematical practice. After presenting the dilemma, we suggest a solution which the nominalist should be able to accept. and 1. Introduction Edward N. Zalta Center for the Study of Language and Information According to nominalism about mathematics, mathematical objects don’t Stanford University exist or, at least, they need not be taken to exist for us to make sense Stanford, CA 94305 of mathematics. While nominalism has the prima facie benefit of not [email protected] assuming the existence of mathematical objects, current nominalist in- terpretations face the problem of not being able to take mathematical theories literally. Typically, such theories have to be rewritten or, at least, reinterpreted in a nominalistically acceptable way, so as to avoid commitment to mathematical objects. For example, in Geoffrey Hellman’s modal-structural interpretation, a mathematical statement S has to be translated into a sentence of modal second-order language which (roughly) states that (i) if there were struc- tures of the appropriate kind, S would hold in such structures, and (ii) it’s possible that there are such structures (see Hellman 1989). In this way, the commitment to mathematical objects is avoided, and only the possibility of structures is asserted. But, clearly, mathematical language is not being taken literally. In Hartry Field’s version of nominalism, given that there are no math- ematical objects, existential mathematical statements are false (Field 1980). In particular, according to Field, given that there are no num- ∗ Copyright c 2005 by Ot´avio Bueno and Edward N. Zalta. This piece was pub- bers, the claim that “there are infinitely many prime numbers” is not lished in Philosophia Mathematica, 13, (2005): 297–307. The authors would like to thank Jody Azzouni, Mark Balaguer, Mark Colyvan, and Hartry Field for extremely true. But this simply flies in the face of the way mathematical discourse helpful discussions and comments about the material in this paper. is used. To preserve verbal agreement with mathematicians, Field can, of 1 3 Otavio´ Bueno and Edward Zalta A Nominalist’s Dilemma and its Solution 4 course, introduce a fictional operator, “According to arithmetic”, and, in commitment—that is, to be committed to the existence of a given object— this way, he can assert the true sentence “According to arithmetic, there a criterion for what exists needs to be met. There are, of course, various are infinitely many prime numbers” without violating nominalism (Field possible criteria for what exists (such as causal efficacy, observability, and 1989). But, once again, mathematical language wouldn’t have been taken so on). But the criterion Azzouni favors, as the one that we have all col- literally. lectively adopted, is ontological independence (2004, 99): what exist are The trouble of not taking mathematical discourse literally is that it the things that are ontologically independent of our linguistic practices makes it hard for the nominalist to make sense of mathematical practice. and psychological processes. The idea here is that if we have just made After all, instead of understanding what mathematicians are doing when something up through our linguistic practices or psychological processes, they are doing mathematics, the nominalist would have to be constantly there’s no need for us to be committed to the existence of the objects in rewriting mathematical discourse, and thus, changing a crucial part of question. And typically, we would resist any such commitment. the practice he or she is trying to understand. In its current forms, nom- Quine, of course, identifies quantifier and ontological commitments, inalism may provide a viable ontological alternative to those who worry at least in a crucial case, namely, for the objects that are indispensable about the existence of mathematical objects, but it’s unclear whether it to our best theories of the world. Such objects are those that cannot be can yield an insightful picture of mathematical activity. eliminated through paraphrase and over which we have to quantify when Jody Azzouni has recently developed a new way of conceptualizing we regiment the theories in question (in first-order logic). For Quine, nominalism in the philosophy of mathematics that is meant to overcome these are exactly the objects we are ontologically committed to. Azzouni this problem (Azzouni 2004). On his view, mathematical theories can be insists that we should resist this identification. Even if the objects in taken literally, and so one can do justice to mathematical practice, but our best theories are indispensable, even if we quantify over them, this there is no commitment to the existence of mathematical objects. The key is not sufficient for us to be ontologically committed to them. After all, idea is that mathematical theories should be taken to be (deflationarily) the objects we quantify over might be ontologically dependent on us— true, but their truth doesn’t entail the existence of mathematical entities. on our linguistic practices or psychological processes—and thus we might After all, on his view, an additional criterion of existence, which he calls have just made them up. But, in this case, clearly there is no reason ‘ontological independence’, has to be met. to be committed to their existence. However, for those objects that are In this paper, we argue that, as it stands, Azzouni’s proposal doesn’t ontologically independent of us, we are committed to their existence. yet succeed. It faces a dilemma to the effect that either the view isn’t As it turns out, on Azzouni’s view, mathematical objects are ontolog- nominalist or it ultimately fails to take mathematics literally, and so it ically dependent on our linguistic practices and psychological processes. still doesn’t do justice to mathematical practice. After presenting the And so, it’s not surprising that, even though they might be indispensable dilemma, we suggest a possible way out for the nominalist. to our best theories of the world, still we are not ontologically committed to them. Hence, Azzouni is a nominalist. 2. A New Form Of Nominalism But in what sense do mathematical objects depend on our linguistic practices and psychological processes? In the sense that, in mathematical According to Azzouni, two kinds of commitment should be distinguished: practice, the sheer postulation of certain principles is enough: “A mathe- quantifier commitment and ontological commitment (see Azzouni 2004, matical subject with its accompanying posits can be created ex nihilo by 127; see also 49–122). We incur a quantifier commitment whenever our simply writing down a set of axioms” (Azzouni 2004, 127). The only ad- theories imply existentially quantified claims. But existential quantifica- ditional constraint that sheer postulation has to meet, in practice, is that tion, Azzouni insists, is not sufficient, in general, for ontological com- mathematicians should find the resulting mathematics interesting. That mitment. After all, we often quantify over objects we have no rea- is, briefly put, the consequences that follow from mathematical principles son to believe exist, such as fictional entities. To incur an ontological shouldn’t be obvious, nor should they be intractable. Thus, given that 5 Otavio´ Bueno and Edward Zalta A Nominalist’s Dilemma and its Solution 6 sheer postulation is (basically) enough in mathematics, mathematical ob- (b) If ‘2’ refers to 2, then either Azzouni’s view is not nominalist (ac- jects have no epistemic ‘burdens’ and so Azzouni calls such objects, or cording to his own definition of ‘nominalism’), or it has a non- posits, as he uses term, ‘ultrathin’ (2004, 127). standard notion of reference (in which case the language is not taken The same move that Azzouni makes to distinguish ontological commit- literally). ment from quantifier commitment is also used to distinguish ontological commitment to F s from asserting the truth of “There are F s”. Although (c) If ‘2’ doesn’t refer to 2, then the proposal fails to take mathematical mathematical theories used in science are (taken to be) true, this is not language literally. sufficient to commit us to the existence of the objects these theories are Clearly, each option is problematic for Azzouni. But are the dilemma’s supposed to be about. After all, on Azzouni’s picture, it might be true premises true? Given that (a) is a logical truth, the crucial work is done F F that there are s, but to be ontologically committed to s, a criterion by premises (b) and (c), and we will motivate them in what follows. for what exists needs to be met. As Azzouni points out: Premise (b): Suppose that ‘2’ refers to 2. Now either it follows from I take true mathematical statements as literally true; I forgo this that there is something to which ‘2’ refers or that there is nothing to attempts to show that such literally true mathematical state- which ‘2’ refers.