Plato and Hobbes: on the Foundations of Political Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Plato and Hobbes: on the Foundations of Political Philosophy Plato and Hobbes: On the Foundations of Political Philosophy Jan Dejnoñka May 1, 1992; edited for the Web, November 11, 2005 (new final paragraph of main text added July 22, 2006) There is a certain philosophia prima on which all other philosophy ought to depend... --Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan Jan Dejnoñka, Plato and Hobbes: On the Foundations of Political Philosophy (1992). A theory of the state based on theory of human nature and theory of value, with Hume’s is-ought inference problem solved. Philosophers and others discussed include Aristotle, Epicurus, G. W. F. Hegel, Immanuel Kant, Frances Hutcheson, Abraham Maslow, John Paul Scott, Richard E. Leakey, Raymond Dart, Robert Ardrey, Leo Strauss, Panayot Butchvarov, H. P. Grice, P. F. Strawson, C. D. Broad, W. T. Stace, Ernest Barker, Robert Lodge, Henry Teloh, Samuel Taylor Coleridge, C. B. MacPherson, Herbert W. Schneider, Richard, S. Peters, Mortimer Adler, Irving R. Copi, Alan Gewirth, Charles Hampden-Turner, Wilhelm Windelband, Stewart Umphrey, Miriam M. Reik, Martin A. Bertman, Ernest Nagel, Richard Taylor, A. E. Taylor, John Searle, John H. Hick, Joseph Raz, C. S. Lewis, Robert Nisbet, Russell Kirk, and James Bond Stockdale. Table of Contents Preface Introduction 1. The State A. A Pros Hen Theory of Politics B. Defining the State 2 C. Plato’s Definition of the State D. Hobbes’ Definition of the State E. Is the State a Fiction? 2. Values A. Values as Properties B. Against Radical Ethical Relativism C. Plato and Hobbes on Moral Relativism 3. Human Nature A. An Evolutionary Theory of Human Nature B. An Evolutionary Theory of Politics C. A Need-Hierarchy Theory of Values D. A Need-Hierarchy Theory of Personality E. Plato on Man’s Place in Nature F. Hobbes on Man’s Place in Nature 4. Why Obey the State? A. The Turn from Ancient Idealism to Modern Realism B. Resolving the Idealist-Realist Conflict C. Why Be Good At All? D. Transcending the Is-Ought Dichotomy 3 E. Theory of Justice F. The Foundation of Political Obligation G. The Ontological Foundation of Political Philosophy Notes Preface Hobbes began the study of geometry at the age of forty; I begin the study of Hobbes and political philosophy at forty. Rather than study a narrow topic, I have chosen to draw a big picture, a basis for further systematic thinking. But I have worked to deepen my view of the relationship of my fields of specialization, ontology and metaphysics, to the human things. Introduction I shall discuss the ontological and metaphysical foundations of political philosophy. This seems Quixotic, since political philosophy seems largely to rely on a common sense picture of the world. It seems especially foolish to ask whether things concerning politics exist or “really” exist. [As Nietzsche says, “What does a drowning sailor care for the chemical composition of the sea?”] Nonetheless, Plato is a star example of the opposite view, and the Hobbist alternative to Plato seems important to the extent that Hobbes’ metaphysic differs from Plato’s. What is there to be good or valuable except what you admit as having being? And does not what is good for us depend on our nature and on the nature of the world around us? For 4 instance, water is physically necessary to human life. Yet for obvious reasons, theft of water is reasonably punishable by death in desert cultures, while in our own culture it is not. Thus water seems both an absolute human good as fixed by human nature and a relative good shifting as human culture (or water scarcity) shifts.1 This interpenetration of real and relative values is no surprise. In general, real things must exist for there to be relativity to anything, just as real things must exist for there to be any distinctions in reason. Real distinctions and distinctions in reason (between aspects or collections of things) interpenetrate on every level of the world’s structure. Similarly, the real and relative values of water are distinct only in reason. The relative cultural value of water is a function of its absolute natural value to us. I omit the value of certain nonbeings: the utility of doughnut holes, the beauty of some musical pauses, the adventure of Conan the Barbarian, and the intellectual illumination of logical constructs or ideal cases. Even doughnut holes, musical pauses, and fictional heroes seem in some sense(s) both in the world around us and good for us. But then, in some sense, such items seem not absolutely nothing. This is much more important to political philosophy than one might think. Both Plato and Hobbes arguably assign the state a very low ontological status indeed. For Hobbes, the social contract is arguably like a doughnut hole: both seem mere logical constructs. For Plato, the state seems largely an imitative and illusory kingly art, having almost the lowest possible ontological status on the Divided Line-- almost as low as Conan the Barbarian. Yet despite the virtual nonbeing of the state, states are, in some sense, in the world around us, and they seem in many ways good for us. If we knew the ultimate nature of reality, then presumably we would know the answer to every fundamental question, including how to live. If God were the ultimate reality, surely our 5 lives would be very different from what they would be if physical mass-energy were the ultimate reality. Yet there are at least three objections to this claim. First, many data of ethics seem so clear and specific (murder is bad, justice is good) that our theories of reality seem best judged adequate in part by their ability to conform to and elucidate the ethical data. To that extent it seems not to matter what our theory of reality is; we might all still remain in largely the same state under largely the same scheme of values. Indeed, each of the two theories of ultimate reality just mentioned is professed by many Americans, so the United States seems an actual case in point. Second, ultimate reality might be unknowable or theories about it might prove cognitively meaningless, yet ethics and political philosophy be feasible. Even the two “Bibles of logical positivism,” Ayer’s Language, Truth, and Logic and Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, perhaps self-defeatingly, professed some ethical views. Third, there is Hume’s problem of inferring values from matters of fact, or “ought” from “is”. As to the first two objections, my replies are these. First, our theory of reality should not be influenced by preconceptions of what reality “ought” to be like. That is question-begging. Ethical data are data like any others, and can be overruled. Second, if we do have a theory of reality, then the second objection becomes irrelevant. I shall resolve Hume’s problem in Part 4, sections D and G. Perhaps because they lived in philosophically simpler times, Plato and Hobbes based their ethics and politics on their theories of ultimate reality. Plato is not far from the “God” theory, and Hobbes is not far from the mass-energy theory. The differences between Plato and Hobbes must not obscure their striking similarities. Both are philosophers committed to the use of reason. Both are influenced by geometry as a model of reason, and both seek a justification of the state independent of religion. Both consider 6 ontology and metaphysics the basis of their political philosophies. Within metaphysics, both make theory of man basic to political philosophy. Both consider men as profitlessly going about in every individual direction if without suitable guidance. Also within metaphysics, both consider the problem of universals as especially important to political philosophy. Both have similar lists of virtues, such as courage and justice; both subscribe to the Golden Rule; and both find some ‘timeless or eternal’ aspect to their values. Both have naturalistic theories of values. Both value an anti-democratic strong ruler; both were influenced in this by war in their own time and by the Peloponnesian War (for Plato, these coincided). Finally, both make the state in some sense an “artificial man” which is a means to certain ends. The main differences are perhaps no less striking. Plato’s conception of reason as dialectical transcends Hobbes’ merely geometrical model. (I speak of explicit views; Hobbes does not fail to engage rival views dialectically.) Plato is a realist; Hobbes is a modified nominalist. For Plato, men are souls; for Hobbes men are machines. For Plato, men’s going about in every direction if without guidance is mainly due to their ignorance of the good. For Hobbes, it is mainly due to their self-interest and fear of domination by each other. For Plato, values are eternal natures to be grasped by the intellect. For Hobbes, it is the natural laws concerning sentiments which are eternal. For Plato, the ideal ruler is one who knows what goodness is. For Hobbes, the ideal ruler is one who has absolute power. For Plato, the end of the state is to promote the Good. For Hobbes, the ends of the state are prudential. The paper concerns four issues. (1) What is the state? (2) What are values? (3) What are human beings? (4) In light of (1)-(3), can we justify obeying the state? I discuss these four issues in the four sections to follow. In each section, I include my own views for perspective. 7 1. The State A. A Pros Hen Theory of Politics Like the word “being,” the word “political” is said in many ways. Whether or not the following are irreducibly political, we often speak of political: --entities, processes, events, structures --identities or essences --realities, appearances, constructions, or fictions --problems, puzzles, paradoxes,
Recommended publications
  • Generic Statements and Antirealism
    GENERIC STATEMENTS AND ANTIREALISM Panayot BUTCHVAROV ABSTRACT: The standard arguments for antirealism are densely abstract, often enigmatic, and thus unpersuasive. The ubiquity and irreducibility of what linguists call generic statements provides a clear argument from a specific and readily understandable case. We think and talk about the world as necessarily subject to generalization. But the chief vehicles of generalization are generic statements, typically of the form “Fs are G,” not universal statements, typically of the form “All Fs are G.” Universal statements themselves are usually intended and understood as though they were only generic. Even if there are universal facts, as Russell held, there are no generic facts. There is no genericity in the world as it is “in-itself.” There is genericity in it only as it is “for-us.” KEYWORDS: Generic, General, Antirealism I shall take general statements to include those that logicians call universal, typically of the form “All Fs are G,” and particular, of the form “Some Fs are G,” but also those that linguists call generic, typically of the form “Fs are G.” The term ‘realism’ will be used for the metaphysical view that reality, the ‘world,’ is mind- independent, in particular, independent of our knowledge of it. ‘Antirealism’ will stand for the opposite view, including Kant’s transcendental idealism as well as recent positions such as Michael Dummett’s ‘antirealism,’ Nelson Goodman’s ‘irrealism,’ and Hilary Putnam’s ‘internal realism.’ According to antirealism, reality depends, insofar as it is known or knowable, on our ways of knowing it, our cognitive capacities – sense perception, introspection, intellectual intuition, imagination, memory, recognition, conceptualization, inductive and deductive reasoning, use of language and other symbolism.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Development of Spinoza's Account of Human Religion
    Intermountain West Journal of Religious Studies Volume 5 Number 1 Spring 2014 Article 4 2014 On the Development of Spinoza’s Account of Human Religion James Simkins University of Pittsburgh Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.usu.edu/imwjournal Recommended Citation Simkins, James "On the Development of Spinoza’s Account of Human Religion." Intermountain West Journal of Religious Studies 5, no. 1 (2014). https://digitalcommons.usu.edu/imwjournal/ vol5/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at DigitalCommons@USU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Intermountain West Journal of Religious Studies by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@USU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 52 James Simkins: On the Development of Spinoza’s Account of Human Religion JAMES SIMKINS graduated with philosophy, history, and history and philosophy of science majors from the University of Pittsburgh in 2013. He is currently taking an indefinite amount of time off to explore himself and contemplate whether or not to pursue graduate study. His academic interests include Spinoza, epistemology, and history from below. IMW Journal of Religious Studies Vol. 5:1 53 ‡ On the Development of Spinoza’s Account of Human Religion ‡ In his philosophical and political writings, Benedict Spinoza (1632-1677) develops an account of human religion, which represents a unique theoretical orientation in the early modern period.1 This position is implicit in many of Spinoza’s philosophical arguments in the Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect, the Short Treatise, and Ethics.2 However, it is most carefully developed in his Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (hereafter TTP).3 What makes Spinoza’s position unique is the fact that he rejects a traditional conception of religion on naturalistic grounds, while refusing to dismiss all religion as an entirely anthropological phenomenon.
    [Show full text]
  • Counterfactuals and Antirealism
    ISSN 2664-4002 (Print) & ISSN 2664-6714 (Online) South Asian Research Journal of Humanities and Social Sciences Abbreviated Key Title: South Asian Res J Human Soc Sci | Volume-1 | Issue-1| Jun-Jul -2019 | Short Communication Counterfactuals and Antirealism Panayot Butchvarov* The University of Iowa USA *Corresponding Author Panayot Butchvarov Article History Received: 12.07.2019 Accepted: 24.07.2019 Published: 30.07.2019 Abstract: There could be no causal connections in the world because if there were there would be counterfactual facts, and there are no such facts. Cognition of the world must employ counterfactual statements, roughly of the form “If p were true, then q would be true,” but obviously there are no counterfactual facts. Keywords: cognition, antirealism, causality, counterfactual The ways to antirealism Metaphysical antirealism is seemingly incredible but, paradoxically, also self-evident. It seems self-evident insofar as it says that if there is a world that we do not and cannot cognize (Kant‟s “things-in-themselves”) then we can ignore it, and if there is a world that we do or at least can cognize (Kant‟s “things-for-us”) then it can only be the world as we do or can cognize it. So the world we do cognize seems, in a sense, dependent on our cognition of it. (We may think of cognition as the capacity for knowledge, and of knowledge as the successful exercise of that capacity.) Metaphysical antirealism is not solipsistic – it‟s about what we, not what I, do or can cognize. For cognition of a world, unlike cognition of a toothache but like cognition of physics, mathematics, geography, or history, is inseparable from others‟ cognition – from the common language we speak to most of the views we espouse.
    [Show full text]
  • Freedom and the State: the Social Contract This Course Aims To
    Freedom and the State: The Social Contract This course aims to introduce students to central questions in political philosophy, through engagement with the work of several significant political philosophers: Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Immanuel Kant and John Rawls. The topics with which we will be most deeply concerned include the legitimacy of the state; the limits of the state’s authority; the basis of rights of resistance or rebellion; the relevance of consent to political authority; the nature and value of freedom; the relationship between politics and human nature; and social justice. We will also, as often as we can, attempt to relate the views of these philosophers to contemporary debates. Program of lectures and reading Week 1 (15/01) Lecture 1: Political Legitimacy and the Social Contract Tradition Reading: Easy: Wolf (2006): 34-48. Easier: ‘Authority’ and ‘Political Obligation’ in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Harder: Boucher & Kelly (1994): ch. 1. Hampton (1997): Chapter 3. Week 2 (22/01) Lecture 2: Hobbes on Human Nature and the State of Nature Primary Reading: Leviathan, Part I, chs. 11, 13-16. Secondary Reading: Easy: Wolf (2006): 8-17. Easier: Levine (2002): 15-32. Newey (2008): ch. 4-5. Harder: Warburton, Pike and Matravers (2000): 100-105. Seminar question: If human nature is, or were, as Hobbes describes it, does it follow that life in the state of nature would be ‘solitary, poore, nasty, brutish and short’? Week 3 (29/01) Lecture 3: Hobbes on the Covenant, the Sovereign and the Right to Rebel Primary Reading: Leviathan, Part II, chs.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy.Pdf
    Philosophy 1 PHIL:1401 Matters of Life and Death 3 s.h. Contemporary ethical controversies with life and death Philosophy implications; topics may include famine, brain death, animal ethics, abortion, torture, terrorism, capital punishment. GE: Chair Values and Culture. • David Cunning PHIL:1636 Principles of Reasoning: Argument and Undergraduate major: philosophy (B.A.) Debate 3 s.h. Undergraduate minor: philosophy Critical thinking and its application to arguments and debates. Graduate degrees: M.A. in philosophy; Ph.D. in philosophy GE: Quantitative or Formal Reasoning. Faculty: https://clas.uiowa.edu/philosophy/people/faculty PHIL:1861 Introduction to Philosophy 3 s.h. Website: https://clas.uiowa.edu/philosophy/ Varied topics; may include personal identity, existence of The Department of Philosophy offers programs of study for God, philosophical skepticism, nature of mind and reality, undergraduate and graduate students. A major in philosophy time travel, and the good life; readings, films. GE: Values and develops abilities useful for careers in many fields and for any Culture. situation requiring clear, systematic thinking. PHIL:1902 Philosophy Lab: The Meaning of Life 1 s.h. Further exploration of PHIL:1033 course material with the The department also administers the interdisciplinary professor in a smaller group. undergraduate major in ethics and public policy, which it offers jointly with the Department of Economics and the PHIL:1904 Philosophy Lab: Liberty and the Pursuit of Department of Sociology and Criminology; see Ethics and Happiness 1 s.h. Public Policy in the Catalog. Further exploration of PHIL:1034 course material with the professor in a smaller group. Programs PHIL:1950 Philosophy Club 1-3 s.h.
    [Show full text]
  • Hobbes and the Theory of Social Contract As the Context for Kant's
    Hobbes and the theory of social contract as the context for Kant’s political philosophy Gorazd Korošec f we are to deal with Kant’s political theory, we must put it in the context I of social contract theories. The theory of social contract has a central place in Kant’s political theory and by placing it in this tradition, we shall be able to see where his theory is in accordance with the tradition, and where it differs from it. Social contract theory as a mode of political thought has dominated the Age of Enlightenment, but we can also see a revival of such theories in today’s political philosophy. We can trace the origins of social contract theory in ancient and medieval thought to Augustine, who built on Seneca and Cicero, to William of Ockham and Nicholas Cusanus, and find a number of basic elements for such a theory in Francisco Suarez, a Spanish writer who saw common political consent as necessary for people to be gathered together in one political body. Talking about its origins, we can also mention the tradition of natural law theory, developed by Grotius, Althusius, Lipsius and Seiden, which was subsequently included in a large part in theories of social contract by many of its greatest authors. The idea of individual moral autonomy, grown within the movements of Reformation and Protestantism and applied to politics, provided the intellectual basis for a social contract theory. At its heart is the idea that legitimate government is the artificial product of the voluntary agreement of free moral agents, and that there is no »natural« political authority.
    [Show full text]
  • The Practical Turn' David G
    8 The Practical Turn' David G. Stern What is Practice Theory? What is a Practice? What is "practice theory"? The best short answer is that it is any theory that treats practice as a fundamental category, or takes practices as its point of departure . Naturally, this answer leads to further questions . What is meant by "practices" here? What is involved in taking practices as a point of departure or a fundamental category, and what does that commitment amount to? And what is the point of the contrast between a practice-based theory and one that starts elsewhere? Perhaps the most significant point of agreement among those who have taken the practical turn is that it offers a way out of Procustean yet seemingly inescap- able categories, such as subject and object, representation and represented, con- ceptual scheme and content, belief and desire, structure and action, rules and their application, micro and macro, individual and totality . Instead, practice the- orists propose that we start with practices and rethink our theories from the ground up. Bourdieu, for instance, insists that only a theory of practice can open up a way forward : Objective analysis of practical apprehension of the familiar world . teaches us that we shall escape from the ritual either/or choice between objectivism and subjectiv- ism in which the social sciences have so far allowed themselves to be trapped only if we are prepared to inquire into the mode of production and functioning of the practical mastery which makes possible both an objectively intelligible practice and also an objectively enchanted experience of that practice .
    [Show full text]
  • Hobbes, Aristotle, and Human Happiness
    Hobbes, Aristotle, and Human Happiness During his life in philosophy Thomas Hobbes engaged in several debates. Among his sparring partners the dearest to him was not a contemporary (such as Descartes, White, Bramhall, or Wallis) but Aristotle. This article explores the tension between Hobbes and Aristotle as it appears in metaphysics (including the study of nature), ethics (including psychology), and politics. The article will close with a comparison of their conceptions of human happiness. First impressions would suggest that Hobbes’s ridicule of Aristotle is thoroughly intended and his appreciation of the Philosopher sensationally low: And I beleeve that scarce any thing can be more absurdly said in natural Philosophy, than that which now is called Aristotles Metaphysics; nor more repugnant to Government, than much of that hee hath said in his Politiques; nor more ignorantly, than a great part of his Ethiques.1 Hobbes’s phrasing is certainly impressive, but if the claims he makes are left unspecified, they remain merely words. Having said that, when explicating Hobbes’s position toward Aristotle and Aristotelianism two issues must be taken into consideration: the exact target and the exact content of Hobbes’s criticism.2 The interrelations between Hobbes and Aristotle and Hobbes and Aristotelianism have been studied at great length and in detail.3 To summarise the major conclusion in Hobbes’s own words: vain-philosophy or spiritual darkness derive “partly from Aristotle, partly from Blindnesse of understanding”.4 It is fairly clear that Hobbes’s primary target is a combination of selected Aristotelian doctrines and their adaptation to the Catholic dogma, or, to follow his own coinage, “Aristotelity”.5 To be content with this, I think, is to overlook the nuances of Hobbes’s position.
    [Show full text]
  • Hobbes's Thucydides
    Histos () XXXI–XXXVII REVIEW–DISCUSSION HOBBES’S THUCYDIDES Luca Iori, Thucydides Anglicus: Gli Eight Bookes di Thomas Hobbes e la ricezione inglese delle Storie di Tucidide (–). Pleiadi . Rome: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, . Pp. xx + . Paperback, €.. ISBN ----. obbes’s translation of the Eight Bookes of the Peloponnesian Warre () was the first made into English from the Greek text; it was preceded by that of T. Nicolls (), made from the French translation of C. H 1 de Seyssel () which was itself made from the Latin translation of L. Valla, and was followed in England by an edition of the Greek text with Latin notes by J. Hudson (). This book begins with four chapters on Greek studies and the knowledge of Thucydides in England between and (but despite the dates on the title page has little to say of –), and then proceeds to four chapters on Hobbes and his translation. After the Conclusion there are a catalogue of sixty manuscript and printed versions of Thucydides acquired by Oxford and Cambridge libraries up to , a bibliography, and indexes of names of persons and of passages in Thucydides. In ch. i Iori stresses that, if England could not match continental countries for works of classical scholarship until after the Restoration of , from the beginning of the sixteenth century study of the classics was widespread. Crucial were the foundation of St. John’s College, Cambridge (), Corpus Christi College, Oxford (), and at a more junior level the refoundation of St. Paul’s School, London (), while about the same time the nobility who did not send their sons to school took to employing tutors of Latin and Greek, and some of the leading clergy attracted scholars to their households.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Hobbes's "Leviathan": a Study in Interpretation
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 1962 Thomas Hobbes's "Leviathan": A study in interpretation John Anthony Long The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Long, John Anthony, "Thomas Hobbes's "Leviathan": A study in interpretation" (1962). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 5590. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/5590 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THOMAS HOBBES*S LEVIATHAN: A STUDY IN INTERPRETATION by JOHN ANTHONY LONG B*A., Montana State University, 1961 Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts MONTANA STATE UNIVERSITY 1962 Approved by: hairman, Board of Examiners Dean, Graduate School SEP 1 8 1962 Date UMI Number: EP41054 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Dissertation Publishing UMI EP41054 Published by ProQuest LLC (2014). Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author.
    [Show full text]
  • "Leviathan"? He Wanted an Image of Strength and Power to Stand Metaphorically for the Commonwealth and Its Sovereign
    Leviathan as Metaphor SAMUELI. MINTZ Why did Hobbes name his masterpiece "Leviathan"? He wanted an image of strength and power to stand metaphorically for the commonwealth and its sovereign. So much is clear. Nevertheless the title seems odd. Why didn't he call the book by its subtitle, "The Matter, Forme and Power of a Common- wealth" ? This subtitle, precise and denotative, like a description in a book catalogue, would have been a title in the hands of almost any other political philosopher of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. We think of Bodin's Six Books of the Republic, of Locke's Two Treatises of Government. Doubt- less there were exceptions: Harrington's Common-Wealth of Oceana is one; but Harrington belongs also to the genre of utopian romance. It is Hobbes who stamped his book with the name of a myth, rich in traditional associa- tions ; also, in a sense I hope to make clear, it is a 'poetic' name; and, what no one can dispute, it is memorable. Leviathan was the great sea-beast of the Book of Job whom only God could tame and whose power was contrasted by God with Job's weakness. In Isaiah 27 : 1, Leviathan is referred to as "the piercing serpent," "that crooked serpent... and dragon in the sea" who is dispatched by God's mighty sword. Hobbes chose the Jobian Leviathan, an image of neutral or benign power, over the figure of evil in Isaiah. The two Biblical Leviathans, from Job and from Isaiah, became objects of mythical accretion, interpretation, and etymological speculation in a long tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • William of Ockham and Thomas Hobbes – on the Nature of General Concepts
    STUDIES IN LOGIC, GRAMMAR AND RHETORIC 8 (21) 2005 Katarzyna Doliwa Białystok University WILLIAM OF OCKHAM AND THOMAS HOBBES – ON THE NATURE OF GENERAL CONCEPTS William of Ockham and Thomas Hobbes are three centuries away, each of them created in different social and political situation, and based on different paradigms and scientific standards. Ockham times is the end of the Middle Ages, the period when religion ruled every domain of life, the ages of the scholastic rule. The period when Hobbes lived, the great crisis of 17th century, when the fundaments of the old order collapsed, new science was in creation and the struggle with scholastic methods was the anthem of many thinkers. It seems however that the two philosophers have a lot in common – nationality and studies at Oxford – great polemic temperament and en- gagement in politics. They were both contestants of contemporary social order, they did not hesitate to speak their disagreement and both had a lot of trouble because of unpopular views they propagated (Ockham was judged at the pontifical Court at Avignon from where he resorted to flight, Hobbes almost perished at the stake). Common to both philosophers is their attitude in the argument over universals which engaged the greatest thinkers of all ages, starting with Plato and lasting until today 1 especially on the grounds of philosophy of mathematics. From the classical point of view the argument divides philo- sophers into partisans of realism recognizing the existence of generalities 2, 1 See Spór o uniwersalia a nauka współczesna, (ed.) M. Heller, W. Skoczny, J. Życiński, Cracow, 1991 2 Plato, architect of theory of ideas – forms existing beyond time and space, saw in generalities the elements of the real world, the only object of knowledge.
    [Show full text]