The Ancient Quarrel Between Art and Philosophy in Contemporary

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Ancient Quarrel Between Art and Philosophy in Contemporary 1 This is the accepted version of the following article: Jennifer A. McMahon, “The Ancient Quarrel Between Art and Philosophy in Contemporary Exhibitions of Visual Art” in Curator: The Museum Journal, Volume62, Issue1, Special Issue: Philosophical Intervention, January 2019: 7-17, which has been published in final form at https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/cura.12282. This article may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance with the Wiley Self-Archiving Policy [ http://www.wileyauthors.com/self-archiving]. See entire issue which is Gold Access at: https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/toc/21516952/2019/62/1 The Ancient Quarrel Between Art and Philosophy in Contemporary Exhibitions of Visual Art. Introductory Essay https://doi.org/10.1111/cura.12282 Jennifer A. McMahon ABSTRACT At a time when professional art criticism is on the wane, the ancient quarrel between art and philosophy demands fresh answers. Professional art criticism provided a basis upon which to distinguish apt experiences of art from the idiosyncratic. However, currently the kind of narratives from which critics once drew are underplayed or discarded in contemporary exhibition design where the visual arts are concerned. This leaves open the possibility that art operates either as mere stimulant to private reverie or, in the more contentful cases, as propaganda. The ancient quarrel between art and philosophy is that art influences surreptitiously while philosophy presents reasons that invite rational scrutiny. As such, in contrast to philosophy, art would undermine our agency. In July 2017, a group of philosophers gathered at the Art Gallery of NSW (AGNSW), in Sydney, Australia, in the presence of two AGNSW curators to explore the basis of their own experiences of selected artworks. Here, those commentaries are reproduced. Each reveal that objective grounds for an experience of art can be based in the community from which one draws one’s terms of reference. In our commentaries we see the expertise of the respective philosophical communities but other communities of culture or expertise might serve the same purpose and 2 hence resolve the ancient quarrel. Before hearing these commentaries, I explain what is at stake when the ancient quarrel between art and philosophy is understood in contemporary terms. This Issue of the Curator also includes an article on the community-based art criticism that emerges from these commentaries followed by an exhibition review which reveals the incorrigible impulse (also demonstrated in the commentaries) to find the basis for the most apt experience of an artwork. A response by the AGNSW curators completes this issue. Figure 1. Speakers and audience assemble for the Philosophical Intervention Symposium at the AGNSW on July 15, 2017 in front of Ai Weiwei, Forever 2003. © Ai Weiwei. Photo: © artsense.edu.au [Color figure can be viewed at http://artsense.edu.au/workshop-2017-photos/] WHATEVER HAPPENED TO ART CRITICISM? This discussion is limited to those institutions like the Art Gallery of N.S.W (AGNSW) which collect and preserve examples of visual art from various traditions with an emphasis on 3 understanding the visual-art-heritage of their citizens. European, Australian Indigenous, Asian and Middle Eastern, African and American traditions are all relevant to understanding Australian visual-art. It is important to note that this enquiry is not about visual culture generally but the narrower focus of visual art which is the purview of institutions like the AGNSW. Artworks take their place within a world of images. The twenty-first century has seen the artworld dissolve into a plethora of practices, where the art- gallery-museum takes its place as one of many public spaces which occasion experiences of entertainment, reflection, and communication about a range of topical issues (see Hein 2007: 79-81). A gallery visitor once might have felt it incumbent upon them to read about the art historical context of a work and the art critic’s view of its meaning and significance to the artworld. However, today art is often understood as a statement on a topical issue, while many visitors simply immerse themselves in images, videos or environments which strike them as evocative, not unlike the way they engage with music videos or the visual spectacle offered by a rock concert. The concepts through which an art-gallery visitor understands their experience might be drawn from popular culture rather than confined to professional art commentary (McMahon and Gilchrist 2017; and see Said 2005: 58-59). For example, many media outlets have dropped the art critic’s regular commentary. It has been suggested that this is because art critiques are relevant to only those who live in the vicinity of the relevant exhibition while online media outlets aim to capture much larger audiences.1 However, for the traditional art exhibition viewer, the art critique served as more than advertisement. The possibility of meaning-making requires a critical as well as receptive interface, and the art critic created this kind of context. The critic would defend an interpretation and a judgment with clear reasons in the form of metaphors, analogies and 4 prior examples; and when effective, the viewer could then approach the work with the configurations and construals with which the critic had equipped them. Some of the reasons for the demise of the art critic might also include a concern for diversity, multi-perspectives and inclusion. One would not want to exclude those not interested in art historical classifications and artworld theories from engaging with visual art. But when there is nothing to get wrong, there is nothing to get right either. There is scope for treating visual art as visual journalism but this does not speak to the way visual art can reflect ideas or norms emerging within the zeitgeist of our times. The artist often feels their way and it would take the art critic to articulate what was emerging in their work. This is what distinguished their work from propaganda. One had to be party to what one understood by the work. This crucial aspect of the artworld is traditionally what attracted many art gallery visitors. Richard Rorty discussed an issue in literary criticism along similar lines (Curthoys 2014). Literary criticism was seen by Rorty as an opportunity to draw the lines of ethical norms in new places and configure the shape of hope in new images. That is, it was not about the retrieval of what this or that author had in mind, but rather what was constructed by a community of readers at a particular time in history. Rorty argued that the progress of morality has had more to do with sentimentality, and opportunities to find objects worthy of our sentiments, than anything delivered up by clear analytic reasoned discourse, and that literature played a role in providing such opportunities.2 Could we ascribe this role to visual art also? The trouble with this view of things though is that sentiments can be dumb and fickle; and manipulating sentiment can be dangerous compared to persuading with reasoned argument. Aristotle recommended the politician or orator use rhetoric on a general audience because they would not be persuaded by reason alone. But rhetoric is manipulative. Unless 5 reason is brought to bear upon such persuasive meaning-making, people can be persuaded to beliefs that in more reasoned and less sentimental contexts they would reject. What does this mean for the diverse multi-voice all-inclusive engagement art-museums-galleries now foster? However, diversity is not necessarily a case of relativism as Paul Guyer’s aesthetic pluralism reveals in his commentary to follow. And as we will see in David Macarthur, Michael Newall and Mohan Matthen’s commentaries, art can be experienced in a way which is grounded in objective terms of reference other than art historical classifications and art theoretical knowledge. All the authors of the commentaries that follow, even those who do base their experiences at least in part on the art critic’s traditional concerns, such as Cynthia Freeland and Robert Sinnerbrink, explain the touchstone for their experience in their philosophical preoccupations. And the traditions and debates that ground these preoccupations constitute the philosophical communities from which they draw their terms of reference. While the communities of art historians and critics have less influence in the way art-gallery-museums attempt to engage their visitors, other communities have taken their place. So as we hope to demonstrate through the following commentaries, while the communicative capacity of art has arguably splintered according to the community in which one derives the concepts that shape one’s experience (McDowell 1996), this does not necessarily suggest that art acts upon us as rhetoric. Professional art criticism may have been overtaken by contemporary conditions such as social media and cultural diversity, but community-based practices may have filled the gap. THE ANCIENT QUARREL: ARISTOTLE AND KANT ON RHETORIC Before proceeding to the commentaries, it is worth examining how the practices associated with what we now consider the creative arts could have so threatened some in the ancient world, to see whether the conditions today are any different. Aristotle thought that art could 6 actually be exploited to achieve one’s goals. According to Aristotle, the substance of rhetorical persuasion works mainly by arousing prejudice, pity, anger and similar emotions. The modes of persuasion adopted by a rhetorician depend upon her personal character and a consideration of who her audience is, because she would need to put her audience into a certain frame of mind in order to effect change in their attitudes. By rhetoric, the audience is made to feel that the very proof of the position promoted is the rhetoric itself. In this sense, art has been thought of as an example of rhetoric.
Recommended publications
  • Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2014 Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy Bradley Taylor University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Taylor, Bradley, "Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy" (2014). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 1468. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1468 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1468 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy Abstract ABSTRACT HUMAN BEINGS AND THE MORAL LAW: MORAL PRECARIOUSNESS IN KANT'S ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY Bradley M. Taylor Dr. Paul Guyer This dissertation is an examination of human moral precariousness in Kant's ethics. Human beings are in a state of moral precariousness insofar as they are ever-capable of transgressing the moral law and are often uncertain of the moral worth of their actions. Put another way, in this dissertation I argue that the basic relationship between human beings and the moral law, in Kant's moral philosophy, is, most fundamentally, one of tenuousness and vacillation. This relation is the fundamental characteristic of the human moral condition because such a relation is built into Kant's account of human moral agency. We have a tenuous relation to the moral law because we always have at least the possibility of conflict between our desire for happiness (i.e. the satisfaction of our inclinations) and the requirements of the moral law.
    [Show full text]
  • Mature Kantians Mika Lavaque-Manty [email protected]
    Mature Kantians Mika LaVaque-Manty [email protected] Department of Political Science University of Michigan Philip Otto Runge, Hülsenbeck Children, 1805–6. © ARTstor. Prepared for delivery at the 2004 Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, September 2 – September 5, 2004. © American Political Science Association. Mature Kantians i INTRODUCTION: THE AUTONOMY PROBLEM One of the many problems facing Enlightenment thinkers was the question of how to reconcile their claim that all humans have equal dignity by virtue of their autonomous agency with the fact that many people neither enjoyed the respect their dignity warranted nor acted in ways that would have suggested they were meaningfully autonomous.1 If the 18th century was the age of the Enlightenment, many people didn’t act their age. Part of the problem was political in the institutional sense: absolutism, feudal vestiges and religious authoritarianism made it difficult, even impossible, for people to be autonomous. But these didn’t account for all the problems, and as Kant suggested, another part had to with ordinary people themselves: the people’s “immaturity” was also “self-incurred.” This was a real pickle, both theoretically and practically: If another person’s autonomous agency is your goal, you had better be careful about what and how much you do for her. There is a real tension, if not an outright conflict, between paternalism and respect for autonomy. There is also a risk of elitism in concerning yourself with others’ autonomy. In the absence of a shared summum bonum — and I take it that part of what modernity means is the absence of a shared summum bonum — the apparent end of a person’s action doesn’t always tell you whether she chose the action or the end.
    [Show full text]
  • 17TH-18TH CENTURY WESTERN PHILOSOPHY PHIL 318 (3 Hrs), Manchester College, Spring 2008
    17TH-18TH CENTURY WESTERN PHILOSOPHY PHIL 318 (3 hrs), Manchester College, Spring 2008 Instructor: Dr. Steve Naragon, Office: Ad Bldg., #231c (Phone — office: 982-5041; home: 982-6033) Required Texts: (1) Garrett Thomson, Bacon to Kant: An Introduction to Modern Philosophy, 2nd ed. (Waveland Press, 2002). [ISBN: 1-57766-201-6] (2) René Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, 3rd ed., translated by Donald A. Cress (Hackett, 1993), 72 pp. [ISBN: (0-87220-192-9)/(978-0-87220-192-7)] (3) John Locke, Essay Concerning Human Understanding, abridged and edited, with an introduction, by Kenneth P. Winkler (Hackett, 1996), 416 pp. [ISBN: (0-87220-216-X)/(978-0-87220-216-0)] (4) Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Discourse On Metaphysics and Other Essays, translated by Daniel Garber and Roger Ariew (Hackett, 1991), 96 pp. [ISBN: (0-87220-132-5)/(978-0-87220-132-3)] (5) George Berkeley, Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous, edited by Robert M. Adams (Hackett, 1979), 137 pp. [ISBN: (0-915144-61-1)/(978-0-915144-61-7)] (6) David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, 2nd ed., edited by Eric Steinberg (Hackett, 1993), 151 pp. [ISBN: (0-87220-229-1)/(978-0-87220-229-0)] (7) Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen Wood (Cambridge University Press, 1999), 800 pp. [ISBN: 0521657296)] Recommended Texts: (1) Robert Audi, ed., The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 2nd ed. Course Objective. We will read philosophers from the 16th through the 18th centuries (including Hobbes, Descartes, Locke, Spinoza, Leibniz, Berkeley, Hume, and Kant), with an emphasis on their epistemology and metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Metaphysics of the Self
    Philosophers’ volume 10, no. 8 ot many philosophers would turn to Kant for a positive view august 2010 about the metaphysics of the self (the referent of ‘I’). On the Imprint N contrary, most of Kant’s interpreters read him as warning that any attempt to give a positive account of the self’s nature is doomed to failure, and as building his theories without metaphysical assump- tions about the self.1 This broad interpretive approach, which I’ll call the “anti-metaphysical interpretation,” often sees Kant’s project as an- Kant’s Metaphysics ticipating Wittgenstein’s claims that the self or subject “doesn’t belong to the world, but is a limit of the world.”2 In some form or other, the anti-metaphysical interpretation is pres- ent in all major discussions of Kant’s views on the self. In a 1993 sur- of the Self vey of the literature, Günter Zöller stated that “[d]ifferences of method and philosophical approach aside, the interpretations … show a re- markable agreement in their understanding of Kant’s thinking self as a form or structure that eludes any attempt at reification.”3 The consen- sus now is similar — for instance, in the most recent book on the topic Arthur Melnick argues that in Kant’s theoretical philosophy the self should be understood as something like an activity precisely because this avoids construing it as an entity of any sort.4 In what follows, I argue that not only is the anti-metaphysical in- terpretation mistaken, but that Kant offers us a subtle, plausible meta- physical account of the self that has no direct analogue in the contem- porary literature.
    [Show full text]
  • Justice, Dissent, and the Sublime Canuel, Mark
    Justice, Dissent, and the Sublime Canuel, Mark Published by Johns Hopkins University Press Canuel, Mark. Justice, Dissent, and the Sublime. Johns Hopkins University Press, 2012. Project MUSE. doi:10.1353/book.15129. https://muse.jhu.edu/. For additional information about this book https://muse.jhu.edu/book/15129 [ Access provided at 29 Sep 2021 18:58 GMT with no institutional affiliation ] This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. Justice, Dissent, and the Sublime This page intentionally left blank Justice, Dissent, M and the Sublime N Mark Canuel The Johns Hopkins University Press Baltimore © 2012 The Johns Hopkins University Press All rights reserved. Published 2012 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 The Johns Hopkins University Press 2715 North Charles Street Baltimore, Maryland 21218-4363 www.press.jhu.edu Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Canuel, Mark. Justice, dissent, and the sublime / Mark Canuel. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-1-4214-0587-2 (hdbk. : alk. paper) — ISBN 978-1-4214-0609-1 (electronic) — ISBN 1-4214-0587-3 (hdbk. : alk. paper) — ISBN 1-4214- 0609-8 (electronic) 1. Aesthetics in literature. 2. English literature—18th century— History and criticism. 3. English literature—19th century—History and criticism. 4. Justice in literature. 5. Sublime, The, in literature. 6. Romanticism—Great Britain. I. Title. PR448.A37C35 2012 820.9Ј007—dc23 2011047314 A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Special discounts are available for bulk purchases of this book.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant and Modern Philosophy
    P1: JZP 052182303Xpre CB994B/Guyer 0 521 82303 X October 14, 2005 9:18 The Cambridge Companion to KANT AND MODERN PHILOSOPHY Edited by Paul Guyer University of Pennsylvania Cambridge Collections Online © Cambridge University Press, 2007 iii P1: JZP 052182303Xpre CB994B/Guyer 0 521 82303 X October 14, 2005 9:18 cambridge university press Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao˜ Paulo Cambridge University Press 40 West 20th Street, New York, ny 10011-4211, usa www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521823036 c Cambridge University Press 2006 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2006 Printed in the United States of America A catalog record for this publication is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data The Cambridge companion to Kant and modern philosophy / edited by Paul Guyer. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn-13: 978-0-521-82303-6 (hardback) isbn-10: 0-521-82303-x (hardback) isbn-13: 978-0-521-52995-2 (pbk.) isbn-10: 0-521-52995-6 (pbk.) 1. Kant, Immanuel, 1724–1804. 2. Philosophy, Modern. I. Guyer, Paul, 1948– II. Title. b2798.c365 2006 193 –dc22 2005029335 isbn-13 978-0-521-82303-6 hardback isbn-10 0-521-82303-x hardback isbn-13 978-0-521-52995-2 paperback isbn-10 0-521-52995-6 paperback Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of urls for external or third-party Internet Web sites referred to in this publication and does not guarantee that any content on such Web sites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
    [Show full text]
  • Values of Beauty: Historical Essays in Aesthetics Paul Guyer Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 0521844908 - Values of Beauty: Historical Essays in Aesthetics Paul Guyer Frontmatter More information Values of Beauty Historical Essays in Aesthetics In Values of Beauty, Paul Guyer discusses major ideas and figures in the history of aesthetics from the beginning of the eighteenth century to the end of the twentieth century. At the core of the book are Guyer’s most recent essays on the epochal contribution of Immauel Kant. The book sets Kant’s work in the context of predecessors, contemporaries, and successors, including David Hume, Alexander Gerard, Archibald Alison, Arthur Schopenhauer, and John Stuart Mill. All of the essays emphasize the complexity rather than the isolation of our aesthetic experience of both nature and art, and the intercon- nection of aesthetic values such as beauty and sublimity on the one hand and prudential and moral values on the other. Guyer asserts that the idea of the freedom of the imagination as the key to both artistic creation and aesthetic experience has been a common thread throughout the modern history of aesthetics, al- though the freedom of the imagination has been understood and connected to other forms of freedom in many different ways. Paul Guyer is Professor of Philosophy and Florence R. C. Murray Professor in the Humanities at the University of Pennsylvania. He is the author of five books on Kant, most recently Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness, and he is General Co-Editor of the Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, in which he has contributed to the translation of the Critique of Pure Reason, the Critique of the Power of Judgment, and Kant’s Notes and Fragments.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Response to the Problem of Induction by Curtis Sharp, BA A
    Kant’s Response to the Problem of Induction by Curtis Sharp, BA A Thesis In PHILOSOPHY Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Texas Tech University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS Approved Francesca DiPoppa Thesis Committee Chair Sungsu Kim Fred Hartmeister Dean of the Graduate School August 2008 Texas Tech University, Curtis Thorburn Sharp, August 2008 Table of Contents Abstract iii I. Introduction 1 II. The Causal Law in the Second Analogy 2 III. The Causal Law in the Critique of Judgment 10 IV. Kant’s Externalist Solution to the Problem of Induction 15 Bibliography 23 ii Texas Tech University, Curtis Thorburn Sharp, August 2008 Abstract In this paper, I examine Immanuel Kant’s response to David Hume’s problem of induction. I pay particular attention to Kant’s main writings on causation: the Second Analogy in The Critique of Pure Reason and the Introduction to The Critique of Judgment. I agree with Paul Guyer that Kant does not provide a solution to the problem in the Critique of Reason. I disagree with Guyer, however, that Kant also does not provide a solution in the Critique of Judgment: whereas Guyer concludes that Kant tells us that we merely assume – and cannot prove - that induction is justified, I conclude that Kant argues for an externalist justification of induction. iii Texas Tech University, Curtis Thorburn Sharp, August 2008 Chapter I Introduction In this paper, I will examine Kant’s solution to Hume’s problem of induction. In particular, I will examine Kant’s treatment of causation, and how it would allow us to be justified in our causal – and hence inductive – inferences.
    [Show full text]
  • On Exceeding Determination and the Ideal of Reason
    On Exceeding Determination and the Ideal of Reason On Exceeding Determination and the Ideal of Reason: Immanuel Kant, William Desmond, and the Noumenological Principle By Christopher David Shaw On Exceeding Determination and the Ideal of Reason: Immanuel Kant, William Desmond, and the Noumenological Principle, by Christopher David Shaw This book first published 2012 Cambridge Scholars Publishing 12 Back Chapman Street, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2XX, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2012 by Christopher David Shaw All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-4438-3748-2, ISBN (13): 978-1-4438-3748-4 To William Desmond in passio essendi TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction ................................................................................................. 1 Part I: The Ideal of Reason Chapter One................................................................................................. 7 Thinking the Transcendent Chapter Two .............................................................................................. 11 Confronting the Unconditioned: Self, World, and God Chapter Three ............................................................................................ 17 Conceptualizing the
    [Show full text]
  • 1 April, 2006 Vita Allen W. Wood Academic Address: Philosophy
    April, 2006 Vita Allen W. Wood Academic Address: Philosophy Department, Bldg 90 Stanford University Stanford, CA 94305-2155 Telephone 650-723-2587 Fax 650-723-0985 E-mail: [email protected] Education: B. A., Reed College, 1964; Major: Literature and Philosophy (Thesis: "Nietzsche and Christianity"). M. A., Philosophy, Yale University, 1966. Ph. D., Philosophy, Yale University, 1968 (Thesis: "Kant's Moral Religion"). Academic Employment: Teaching Assistant in Philosophy, Yale University, 1966-1967. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Cornell University, 1968-1972. Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Michigan, 1973. Associate Professor of Philosophy, Cornell University, 1973-1980. Professor of Philosophy, Cornell University, 1980-1996. Visiting Professor of Philosophy, University of California at San Diego, 1986. Professor of Philosophy, Yale University, 1996-1999 Visiting Professor of Philosophy, Yale University, 1999-2000. Professor of Philosophy, Stanford University, 1999-2001 Ward W. and Priscilla B. Woods Professor, Stanford University, 2001-present. Isaiah Berlin Visiting Professor, Oxford University, 2005 Academic Honors: William F. Stout Scholarship, Reed College, 1960-64 Woodrow Wilson Fellowship, Yale University, 1964 Yale-Wilson Fellowship, Yale University, 1965-66 Woodrow Wilson Dissertation Fellowship, 1967 Sterling Fellowship, 1967 Cornell Society for the Humanities Summer Fellowship, 1970 John Simon Guggenheim Fellowship, 1983 Fulbright Fellowship, 1983 (declined) Alexander von Humboldt Fellowship, 1983 (declined) National Endowment for the Humanities Fellowship, 1992 American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 2002 Publications: 1 Books: Kant's Moral Religion. Ithaca: Cornell University Press,1970. Kant's Rational Theology. Ithaca, Cornell University Press, 1978. Karl Marx. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1981. Hegel's Ethical Thought. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant+(Guyer).Pdf
    Kant ‘Kant is an absolutely first-rate general introduction to Kant’s Critical Philosophy. Paul Guyer’s interpretations are extremely well-supported, carefully and crisply argued, and highly insightful.’ Robert Hanna, University of Colorado ‘An impressive overview of the various strands of Kant’s philosophy.With great skill Guyer manages to compress Kant’s critical thought into a few hundred pages. This book will provide an excellent introduction to Kant’s thought.’ Philip Stratton-Lake, University of Reading ‘The book is impressive in very many ways. It demonstrates a mastery of the Kantian corpus and an ability to explain exceedingly complex argu- ments in a clear and accessible fashion. I think it will become essential reading for students wanting to grasp the broad sweep of Kant’s thought without losing much by way of depth.’ Andrew Chignell, Cornell University ‘That Guyer is able to cover this much material, clearly and without over- simplification, in a single, reasonably sized volume represents a unique accomplishment, which should prove to be extremely useful to a broad audience.’ Eric Watkins, University of California, San Diego Routledge Philosophers Edited by Brian Leiter University of Texas, Austin Routledge Philosophers is a major series of introductions to the great Western philosophers. Each book places a major philosopher or thinker in historical context, explains and assesses their key arguments, and considers their legacy. Additional features include a chronology of major dates and events, chapter summaries, annotated suggestions for further reading, and a glossary of tech- nical terms. An ideal starting point for those new to philosophy, they are also essential reading for those interested in the subject at any level.
    [Show full text]
  • 255 Paul Guyer. a History of Modern
    Philosophy in Review XXXVI (December 2016), no. 6 Paul Guyer. A History of Modern Aesthetics. 3 Vols. Cambridge University Press 2014. 1752 pp. $355.00 USD (Hardcover ISBN 9781107643222). Aesthetics has sometimes seemed a poor relation in the family of philosophical specialties. This has been the attitude, perhaps predictably, of non-aesthetician philosophers. The history of aesthetics has seemed an even poorer thing, and I suspect that many aestheticians might join the party, at least to judge from the number of attempts made to set out that history. In English, we have Katharine Everett Gilbert’s and Helmut Kuhn’s A History of Esthetics (1939), and, earlier, Bernard Bosanquet’s more obviously monumental A History of Aesthetic (1892), but not much else, apart from specialized articles and anthologies of historical texts that go proxy, as it were, for histories. It is against this background that we can begin to appreciate Paul Guyer’s achievement in this three-volume survey of modern aesthetic theory—one volume each on the eighteenth, nineteenth, and twentieth (and early twenty-first) centuries. Guyer’s history outshines Bosanquet’s, in clarity of style and in wealth of concrete detail, if not in scope, inasmuch as Guyer confines himself, as his title indicates, to modern times (though he does get the historical ball rolling with a stimulating treatment of Plato’s concerns and challenges, to which he returns, sympathetically, in his remarks on Alexander Nehamas in the Epilogue to Volume Three). Undoubtedly, Guyer’s book will be the standard reference on its subject for the remainder of this, our still relatively new, century.
    [Show full text]