<<

CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk

Provided by UCL Discovery 1

Schopenhauer's of German

Sebastian Gardner

Introduction

Arthur Schopenhauer occupies a central position in the narrative of nineteenth-century :

though first and foremost an idealist, Schopenhauer belongs also to its naturalistic current, and with

regard to many central tendencies of the age – including the turn towards the practical, at the

expense of the early modern image of man as -reflecting , the elevation of art to a

position of near parity with philosophy, and the exploration of proxies for traditional

Schopenhauer again occupies a pivotal role; in a way that deserves to be found puzzling,

Schopenhauer provides the key connecting link of Kant with Nietzsche.1 My aim here is to consider

1 The main broad feature of nineteenth-century not exhibited by Schopenhauer – and which

he in fact opposes vigorously – is its historical turn: see The World as and Representation [1st

edn. 1819; 2nd edn., revised and enlarged, 2 volumes, 1844], 2 vols., trans. E. F. J. Payne (New

York: Dover, 1969), Vol. I, pp. 273–274. Further references to this work are abbreviated WWR,

followed by volume and page number. References to other writings of Schopenhauer's are given by

the following abbreviations and are to the editions cited below:

BM Prize Essay on the Basis of Morals [1840], in The Two Fundamental

Problems of , trans. David E. Cartwright and Edward E. Erdmann

(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010).

FR On the Fourfold Root of the of Sufficient Reason [1st edn. 1813,

2nd edn. 1847], 2nd edn. trans. E. F. J. Payne (LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court,

1974).

FW Prize Essay on the Freedom of the Will [1839], in The Two Fundamental 2

Schopenhauer's philosophy from the perspective of , an approach which, I will try to show, takes us to the heart of his project and allows us to understand how a only one step removed from the philosophy of the Enlightenment could provide crucial impetus to late modern anti-.

Some preliminary remarks are needed concerning this contextualization. Schopenhauer's was not of course to provide simply a critique of German Idealism, but rather to present a

Problems of Ethics, trans. David E. Cartwright and Edward E. Erdmann

(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010).

MREM Manuscript Remains: Early Manuscripts (1804–1818), ed. Arthur Hübscher,

trans. E. F. J. Payne, Manuscript Remains in Four Volumes, Vol. 1 (New

York: Berg, 1988).

MRCD Manuscript Remains: Critical Debates (1809–1818), ed. Arthur Hübscher,

trans. E. F. J. Payne, Manuscript Remains in Four Volumes, Vol. 2 (New

York: Berg, 1988).

PP Parerga and Paralipomena: Short Philosophical [1851], 2 vols.,

trans. E. F. J. Payne (Oxford: Clarendon, 1974).

VgP Vorlesung über die gesammte Philosophie d.i. Die Lehre vom Wesen der

Welt und von dem menschlichen Geiste. In vier Theilen. Erster Theil: Theorie

des gesammten Vorstellen, Denkens und Erkennens, in Theorie des

gesammten Vorstellens, Denkens und Erkennens. Aus dem handschriftlichen

Nachlaß [1820], hrsg. u. eingeleitet von Volker Spierling (München: Piper,

1986).

WN On the Will in : A Discussion of the Corroborations from the

Empirical that the Author's Philosophy has Received Since its First

Appearance [1836], ed. David E. Cartwright, trans. E. F. J. Payne (Oxford:

Berg, 1991). 3 self-standing, independently intelligible system, the grounds of which are contained in basic facts of and accessible to anyone who is able and willing to reflect on these in the unobscured light of Kant's first Critique. Nor again is Schopenhauer's target – the world-view he intends his system to confute – identified narrowly with the positions of Fichte, Schelling, or Hegel: it comprises, much more broadly, the dominant tendency operative within all the major schools of

Western philosophy, namely, their directedness towards an optimistic solution to the riddle of the of the world.

It is possible, therefore, to detach Schopenhauer's philosophy from all consideration of

German Idealism, or to consider it, as much commentary does, only in relation to Kant and

Nietzsche, but there are sound for instead understanding his system abreactively – as in the first instance an attempt to simultaneously undermine, appropriate, and recast the legacy of German

Idealism. It is a of historical record that Schopenhauer in the earliest years of his philosophical formation had extensive exposure to the lectures and writings of Fichte and Schelling, with whom he engages more closely in his early notebooks than with any other figures in the history of philosophy with the exception of Kant.2 Approaching Schopenhauer with this in allows better to be made of Schopenhauer's than can be got simply by placing them directly alongside Kant's, Schopenhauer's departures from whom often seem oddly under- motivated:3 Schopenhauer's return to Kant is a return from German Idealism, conducted in light of

2 On Schopenhauer's early years, see Arthur Hübscher, The Philosophy of Schopenhauer in its

Intellectual Context: Thinker against the Tide, trans. Joachim T. Baer and David E. Cartwright

(Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen, 1989), Chs. 5–6, and David E. Cartwright, Schopenhauer: A

Biography (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), Ch. 4.

3 Christopher Janaway, in Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 1989), pp. 141–142, similarly affirms the need to Schopenhauer in historical context in order to understand his departures from Kant. For analyses of Schopenhauer's and , see, in addition to Janaway, Julian Young, Willing and Unwilling: A 4 its misconstrual (as he perceives it) of Kant's thought. It is of course in relation to Kant alone that

Schopenhauer asks for his system to be considered, but we can understand without difficulty the reasons why Schopenhauer would have wished to write German Idealism out of his philosophical ancestry.4 German Idealism represents for Schopenhauer the culmination of the optimistic tendency of and , which it equips with the most advanced modern articulation,5 its distinctive historical position consisting in its having recognized the profound and original advance made by yet perversely refused to grasp its anti-optimistic vector.6

Finally, Schopenhauer's central metaphysical claims allow themselves to be understood as negations of key claims in German Idealism.

Schopenhauer's philosophy represents, I therefore suggest, the result of an attempt to as it were re-run the post-Kantian development – the attempt beginning in the 1790s to fix Kant's problems – on the basis of a rejection of two crucial assumptions of Fichte and Schelling. The first of these is their reaffirmation of the Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR), to which they grant unrestricted scope and authority. The second concerns the of our existence and that of the world, which is held, following Kant, to be secured by the moral Fact of Reason, that value in general is grounded on freedom and enters the world primordially through the exercise of pure . On the basis of his controversion of these two fundamental assumptions,

Schopenhauer inverts the significance of the which he, completing his own extension of

Kant's philosophy, borrows from Fichte and Schelling.

Study in the Philosophy of (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1987) and Schopenhauer

(London: Routledge, 2005), and John E. Atwell, Schopenhauer on the Character of the World: The

Metaphysics of Will (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995).

4 As he does explicitly at WWR I, 416, and PP I, 132.

5 WWR II, 644–645: all German Idealism is Spinozistic, and therefore optimistic.

6 See MREM, 13: Kant exposed the contradictions in the lie which is life. 5

The net result is a system which has much of the formal structure and outward appearance of the German Idealist systems but a directly contrary import. Schopenhauer does not quite affirm the thoroughly disenchanted view of the world that the German Idealists attempted to show need not be accepted as the price of modernity, but the residue of enchantment which he allows to continue to attach to our existence is relocated outside the objectual world, in the form of its negation: the world itself inherits the 'nothingness', the 'lack of an ultimate purpose or ' and 'absence of all aim', of its metaphysical ground.7 Though Schopenhauer officially repudiates the Spinozistic that

F. H. Jacobi warns of as the inevitable upshot of Kantianism8 – on the somewhat thin basis that his doctrine of the negation of the world endows it with (inverted) moral-metaphysical significance9 – his proximity to it can hardly be exaggerated: Schopenhauer reaffirms Spinoza's anti-theism, , materialist tendency, naturalistic view of human motivation, and reductionist account of value.

I. Schopenhauer's strategy

1. Contraction of the Principle of Sufficient Reason

7 WWR I, 149, 164.

8 The ' that the world has merely a physical, and no moral, significance is the most deplorable error that has sprung from the greatest perversity of mind' (PP II, 102). Schopenhauer distinguishes his position from the 'Neo-' described by Jacobi at WWR II, 645–646.

9 See Schopenhauer's claim to have solved the age-old problem of demonstrating 'a moral world- order as the basis of the physical', WWR II, 590–591. 6

The first part of Schopenhauer's strategy is presented in The Fourfold Root of the Principle of

Sufficient Reason, his first publication and a work to which he frequently refers back, declaring its conclusions to be presupposed by the argument of WWR.10

Fourfold Root presents itself in the first instance as a historical review conjoined with a systematic analysis of PSR, but it is clear from the outset that it is not intended as a neutral account of the different ways in which PSR has been invoked or may be understood. The work's chief concern is to show, negatively, that confusions of different of ground or reason (Grund) have played a decisive role in metaphysical reasoning, and, positively, to offer a radically original, minimal account of the principle's content.11 Schopenhauer identifies PSR with the conjunction of four : (i) the law of , requiring changes in real objects to have efficient causes;

(ii) the condition on true judgement, that it have a ground outside itself; (iii) the mutual determination of all parts of and ; and (iv) the law of motivation governing acts of will.

Characteristically metaphysicians have confused the first two, especially in proofs of 's existence, reflecting their illicit conviction that the order of things is in that of thought.12

The full force of Schopenhauer's devaluation of PSR becomes clear in his nominalist answer to the question whether it constitutes one principle or many. Though drawn at to talk of a unitary Grund 'presenting itself in a fourfold aspect',13 ultimately Schopenhauer rejects the notion of a 'ground in general', einen Grund überhaupt,14 reducing PSR to an aggregate and leaving no scope

10 E.g. WWR I, xiv.

11 The critical intention becomes more pronounced in the amplified second edition of 1847, but is clear even in the first (1813).

12 FR 14–16, 18–19, 228–229.

13 FR, 162–163, 232.

14 FR, 234. See also FR, 2–4, 231; WWR II, 641; and VgP, 494. I discuss Fourfold Root in more detail in , 'Schopenhauer's Contraction of Reason: Clarifying Kant and Undoing

German Idealism', Kantian Review 17, 2012, 375–401, Section 3. 7 for the formation of a novel, non-empirical conception of Grund such as those freely employed by the German Idealists.15 The of reason in general or as such becomes a mere abstraction; what unifies the four principles is simply their fundamental character and epistemic immanence, i.e., our of them as constituting the form of objects within the world as representation. It follows that PSR extends only to the phenomenon, not to the thing in itself or 'inner essence' of things, to which it is entirely 'foreign'.16 The implications of its contraction are, as Schopenhauer at one place spells them out: that 'the laws of the faculty of reason are not laws'; that 'there is just as little unconditioned as conditioned, just as little God as world'; that the question how the world and nature have arisen can be likened to 'the talking of one who is still half in a dream'; and that in the realm beyond nature 'there is really no why and no wherefore'.17

Schopenhauer's contraction of PSR goes hand in hand with his concept , according to which concepts arise only from intuitive representations, formed by abstraction from immediately given data in much the way that British empiricism tells us.18 This avoids returning us to Hume's denial of all objective necessity, as an orthodox Kantian might object, because on

Schopenhauer's account itself – intuitive representation, in his terminology – contains seams of necessity, defined by the four sub-forms of PSR.19 Where Schopenhauer departs from

15 See FR, 234.

16 E.g. WWR I, 128, 163; WWR II, 579; PP II, 94.

17 MRCD, 430–431.

18 '[I]f we wish to call any concept objective, then it must be one which demonstrates its origin and object in sensuous feeling (the five senses)' (MRCD, 357); 'concepts have no meaning other than their relation to intuitive representations (whose representatives they are)' (MRCD, 471). See also

FR, 15, 146–148; WWR I, 39–42; and MRCD, 298–299, 468.

19 To clarify their relation: Schopenhauer's account of PSR does not presuppose and is not argued for via his concept empiricism. Schopenhauer's concept empiricism, however, is not independent of his account of PSR, since this is presupposed by his account of the intuitive representations from 8

Kant is in his claim is that no independently originating concepts are brought to the data of or are required to make possible cognition of objects. And this denial of the pre-existence of concepts in any form, along with the impossibility of forming new concepts not already implicated in PSR-structured experience, is taken by Schopenhauer to entail the strict meaninglessness of any employment of concepts outside the domain of representation. The scope which Kant allowed to remain for employment of the unschematized categories – to provide the necessary foundation for our thought of problematic objects, Ideas of reason, and exercise of pure practical reason – is thereby eliminated: conceptuality and the world as representation are rendered co-extensive, and the

Kantian faculty of reason is collapsed into the understanding. Schopenhauer supports this conclusion by arguing that Kant's central argument for the necessity of differentiating Vernunft from Verstand, the Antinomy of Pure Reason, is bogus.20

What drove Schopenhauer to this major departure from Kantian doctrine – and indeed to focus, in his very first work, on an officially antiquated piece of philosophical apparatus with unmistakeable Leibnizian-Wolffian connotations – is his of what inevitably happens when PSR is allowed to remain in the partially deflated yet fundamentally intact state that Kant leaves it in: to wit, the spectacular reinflation which it receives at the hands of Fichte, Schelling, and

Hegel.21 After Kant had reduced the positive epistemic significance of PSR to (i) the principle of which concepts are formed. What concept empiricism adds to the contraction of PSR is the closing of a loophole which the transcendent post-Kantian might seek to exploit, viz., the possibility of novel conceptual construction.

20 The theses of all four antinomies are, Schopenhauer argues, groundless: dialectical illusion is purely one-sided, and the world infinite in all its dimensions. See MRCD, 480–485; WWR I, 492–

501; and VgP, 492–496.

21 'Just as though Kant had never existed, the principle of sufficient reason is for Fichte just what it was for all the scholastics, namely an aeternae veritas' (WWR I, 33). That Fichte alerted

Schopenhauer to the importance of PSR is suggested by his annotated lecture notes. In a lecture 9 causality and (ii) the regulative function of reason,22 the German Idealists reinstate the principle through their demand for absolute systematic completeness, and embark on the (in Schopenhauer's eyes, futile) business of formulating new conceptions of what may count as a Grund, their speculative innovations involving transcendent use of Kant's categories.23

The German Idealist reinflation and redeployment of PSR, as well as evincing the epistemic hubris that Kant sought to curb, has a substantive implication which makes it especially objectionable to Schopenhauer. PSR is connected closely in early modern rationalism with the ontological argument, which Schopenhauer sees the German Idealist systems as attempting to revive: Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre is 'Onto-theology',24 and Schelling 'venerates the ontological

transcript from 1811 Schopenhauer records Fichte's identification of Wissenschaft with 'the region of reasons or grounds', which is 'supernatural or spiritual', and of the Wissenschaftslehre with 'the reason or ground of all knowing' (MRCD, 22, 28). In WWR I, 33, Fichte is charged with construing the ego-world relation, on the basis of PSR, as a ground-consequent relation.

22 See Béatrice Longuenesse, 'Kant's Deconstruction of the Principle of Sufficient Reason', in Kant on the Human Standpoint (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).

23 Again and again Schopenhauer returns to the point that German Idealism rests on a transcendent and hence illegitimate employment of a priori concepts, especially that of causality: MRCD, 22,

359, 372, 376, 378–379, 384–386. In an annotation to lectures from 1811–12, Schopenhauer identifies Fichte's fundamental mistake with his 'failure to understand Kant's teaching' ('possibly due to a defect in Kant's doctrine') that explanation stops with immanent causes, and describes

Fichte's appeal to the I qua 'principle' as a concealed attempt to circumvent this restriction (MRCD,

64; see also 124 and 134). Note that Kant too, on Schopenhauer's account, fell victim to the illusion cast by PSR (MRCD, 463n.), and bears some responsibility for the German Idealist development

(MRCD, 64, 412; FR, 164, 176; VgP, 252–253).

24 MRCD, 111. 10 proof', of which Hegel's 'whole pseudo-philosophy' is really a 'monstrous amplification'.25

Schopenhauer views his situation and role in the history of philosophy as reproducing that of Kant: just as Kant pitted himself against the Leibnizian-Wolffian school, so Schopenhauer takes up arms against German Idealism, aiming to achieve a more decisive outcome by a more direct and far- reaching attack on PSR.26

2. Schopenhauer's axiological premise

The second ground floor assumption of German Idealism controverted by Schopenhauer, I said, is its endorsement of Kant's conception of the source of value, which represents in Schopenhauer's eyes yet another abortive attempt to optimize reality.

The that Schopenhauer famously advocates in opposition has, however, a more complex structure than his expositions of the doctrine allow readers to suppose, and this complexity is a consequence of his treatment of PSR.

Schopenhauer's argument often appears to be that the of the world derives from the negative hedonic balance sheet that necessarily characterizes human (and any other sentient) existence.27 However, in so far as its aim is to establish something about the metaphysical of the world, this argument fails to convince, relying as it does on a phenomenologically strained reduction of the objects of desire and valuation to hedonic states: that the satisfaction of every desire is followed immediately by the formation a new one does not mean that things are not better for its having been satisfied; and in any case there is value, by ordinary lights, simply in a

25 FR, 16; see also FR, 21–23.

26 See WWR I, 418, 510–511.

27 WWR I, §57, and Book IV, passim; PP II, Ch. 12. On this argument, see Christopher Janaway,

'Schopenhauer's Pessimism', in Christopher Janaway (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to

Schopenhauer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999). 11 creature that forms and acts on desires, beyond the of satisfaction that doing so may or may not procure. Schopenhauer's argument from the predominance of suffering is better viewed, however, not as the main point but merely as an auxiliary element in his case for pessimism, which has the following form.

Ultimately Schopenhauer considers the evil of existence an incontestable given, belonging to the physiognomy of the world and not open to debate.28 The problem for Schopenhauer is to articulate this insight within the parameters available to him. To be sure, the contraction of PSR undermines directly attempts such as Leibniz's to validate the world, and any other account (such as those of Schelling and Hegel) which rests on an appeal to final causes. It also cuts off the Kantian source of value in human freedom.29 But at the same time, the confinement of PSR to the interior of the world as representation appears to remove the basis for any rationally grounded negative assessment of the world or its contents considered collectively. Schopenhauer thus seems poised to embrace the sheer value-indifference of reality, in the manner of Spinoza, or any contemporary naturalist for whom talk of reality's having either positive or negative is nonsensical, but doing this would not give him what he wants, which is, to repeat, recognition of the positive

28 As Nietzsche recognizes: 'The ungodliness of existence was for him something given, palpable, indisputable ... unconditional and honest is simply the of the way he poses his problem' (, The Gay , 2nd edn. [1887], trans. Walter Kaufmann (New

York: Vintage, 1974), §357, 307). That it has axiomatic status is shown by the way in which it is invoked: see, e.g., MRCD, 391; and WWR II, 577, 581–584, 643. It is the original motor, and a condition of, philosophical reflection: see WWR II, 171, 579, and note 40 below.

29 Directly through its implication of psychological determinism, and indirectly through its elimination of Ideas of reason, undermining all of the special devices employed by Kant to conserve human freedom in face of the causal principle. 12 reality of evil, as an intrinsic, necessary feature of the world, inseparable from it.30 His task is to give sense to this .

Now Schopenhauer is quite clear that practical consciousness, including the whole domain of value, is orthogonal to the world as representation: it is what gives the world as representation its ponderousness, its non-illusory quality, but it has no grounds within it; practical and axiological significance shines through objects, weighing them down, but reflecting nothing of their mere object-being.31 If the evil of the world as representation is to be demonstrated, therefore, it can only be by attention to the way in which it manifests what lies beyond it, viz., Wille.32 The crux of

Schopenhauer's case for pessimism consists accordingly in showing (1) that the world as representation derives from a reality which is intrinsically and necessarily without purpose, (2) that the world as representation does not merely reflect that underlying reality or reproduce it in appearance – which would suffice only for Spinoza's conclusion of value-indifference – but reveals itself to be metaphysically defective in relation to it. Book II contains the demonstration of (1). The sections of WWR important for (2) are those in which Schopenhauer explains why, once we have achieved knowledge of Wille, the world as representation must be perceived as contradictory – an incoherent mis-expression in individuated form of a pre-categorial one, which moreover reproduces this incoherence within itself, in the form of the conflict of individuated wills with one another and

30 In his very earliest notes, from 1808–09, Schopenhauer describes the world as 'only an image of an actual evil existing in eternity ... the (Platonic) Idea of that real, inexplicable and unconditioned evil' (MREM, 9).

31 WWR I, 95 and 98–99.

32 Note that the mere 'emptiness' or nullity, Nichtigkeit, of the world as representation in the sense of its insubstantiality and illusoriness, Scheinbarkeit, consequent upon the purely relational constitution of phenomena (WWR I, 7, 366; VgP, 474–477), is not sufficient for pessimism (life's dream-likeness does not of itself make life a bad dream or a dream that ought not to be dreamt). 13 within themselves.33 The relevant discussions are those, chiefly in Book IV, of (i) natural

(concerning the conflictual structure of the organic realm, which exhibits the 'inner antagonism of the will'),34 (ii) sexual desire (the subordination of individual will to life to that of the species),35

(iii) eternal (which grasps individuation as a fault or 'sin', to be corrected),36 (iv) and ethical conduct (the error of affirming one's individuality, and its overcoming through higher knowledge),37 and (v) renunciation, resignation and asceticism (rationally necessary denial of the will to live, consequent upon higher knowledge).38 The general character of things in the world,

Schopenhauer says, is not imperfection but rather 'distortion', reflecting the fact that each thing is

'something that ought not to be'.39

Since the main work in substantiating pessimism has been done as soon as it has been established the world ought not to be, the role of the the argument from suffering is limited. What it adds, through its reminder that human life does not merit our good opinion on account of its hedonic quality, is an uncommonsensical re-interpretation of hedonic experience in light of the

33 This metaphysical contradiction, note, is to be distinguished from the actual contradiction which constitutes denial of the will to live (WWR I, 288, 301). The former, which obtains between the two worlds or world-aspects, is realized and becomes explicit in the latter, which obtains between the phenomenon and itself (as its self-renunciation) or between Wille and the phenomenon (WWR I,

402–403).

34 WWR I, 144–149, 161.

35 WWR II, Chs. 42 and 44, esp. 538–540.

36 WWR I, 331 and §63; WWR II, 580–582, 604; PP II, 301–302. See also the remarks on ,

WWR I, 252–255.

37 WWR I, §61, §§64–66.

38 WWR I, §68.

39 PP II, 304. '[I]ndividuality is really only a special error, a false step, something that it would be better should not be' (WWR II, 490–491; see also WWR II, 579 and 604). 14 metaphysics of will: Schopenhauer directs us to grasp pleasure and not phenomenologically but as manifestations of a purposeless dynamic.40 The painfulness and ubiquity of pain are therefore, in themselves, not what establishes the of pessimism: suffering is probative in the case for Schopenhauer's doctrine only on account of what it displays regarding the irrational character of reality; his detailed portrait of man's misery provides a posteriori corroboration of the metaphysical claim.41

I will consider later whether this is cogent. For the present, the point is that Schopenhauer's contraction of PSR, and his axiological vision, are interrelated and mutually supporting. If evil has positive reality, then this testifies to the limitedness of PSR, and if PSR is limited, then theodical strategies for explaining away the manifest evil of the world, and hence denying its positive reality, are blocked. Moreover, through the reduction of PSR to a mere relational structure for phenomena,

40 We are to grasp the flow of hedonic experience, its repeated cyclical relapse into some or other mode of suffering, as it were formally (rather in the way that we, Schopenhauer supposes, apprehend Wille in music). Schopenhauer reformulates the idea interestingly in the assertion

(directed against Schelling) that I find myself necessarily 'not in an absolute state' but rather in 'a state from which I crave release', described as 'the motive of all genuine philosophical endeavour'

(MRCD, 360, 361, 365).

41 Just as natural science, according to Schopenhauer's argument in On the Will in Nature, corroborates the metaphysics of will. It is to be noted that Schopenhauer has also an axiological argument for his pessimistic metaphysics (mirroring Kant's claim that moral interest argues for the truth of ): his metaphysics are required – once the contraction of PSR has been accepted – in order to preserve the possibility of salvation in the face of our mortality (WWR

II, 643–644). More broadly, Schopenhauer offers the inducements that – again, given the results of

Kant's philosophy – no other way of endowing suffering with meaning, or of rescuing any truth in

Christianity, is available (MREM, 10; MRCD, 338; WWR I, §70; WWR II, Ch. 48). 15 the existence of evil is explained, as supervening on individuation: in Schopenhauer's brilliant reversal of Leibniz, PSR is not what saves us from evil but the source of evil itself.

3. Schopenhauer's inversion of Fichte: the blindness of Wille

Schopenhauer's contraction of PSR, and his axiological vision, underpin his inversion of Fichte's post-Kantian reconception of the as a primarily and essentially volitional conative being. In order to become clear about what exactly this comprises, it is necessary to look in some detail at the position Fichte develops in his System of Ethics.42

Fichte begins, in Cartesian style, with the thinking of oneself. The task is to determine what this involves and how it is possible. Fichte argues that originally, at the level of the facts of ordinary consciousness, the I must find itself not as thinking, i.e. as intellect, but as willing,43 and that to find

42 This is a clearer and much revised reworking of material in Part Three of the 1794–95 presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre: J. G. Fichte, Foundations of the Entire Science of

Knowledge, in The Science of Knowledge, with the First and Second Introductions, ed. and trans.

Peter Heath and John Lachs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 256–268.

Schopenhauer's critical comments on Fichte's System of Ethics are in MRCD, 399–406. It is in this text of Fichte's that , in his highly critical review of the first volume of

WWR ('Rezension, Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung von Arthur Schopenhauer. Leipzig, bei F. M.

Brockhaus. 1819', Hermes, oder, Kritisches Jahrbuch der Literatur 20, 1820, 131–148), claims to find already formulated Schopenhauer's thesis that will comprises the inner essence of the subject.

43 For the reason that thinking requires something objective set in opposition to it, if it is to become an object, whereas willing, at the level of facts of consciousness, stands necessarily in opposition to something objective: J. G. Fichte, The System of Ethics according to the Principles of the

Wissenschaftslehre [1798], ed. and trans. Daniel Breazeale and Günter Zöller (Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 2005), p. 26. 16 oneself more specifically as a willing from which all that is foreign has been abstracted, as the task at hand requires, is to find oneself as a tendency (Tendenz), or faculty or power (Vermögen), towards self-activity. Alternatively put: I find myself as a tendency to determine myself absolutely, without any external impetus, or again, as a tendency to self-activity for self-activity's sake.44

And since, in thus finding oneself, one finds oneself as (identical with) that which is found, and since, equally, that which does the finding brings what it finds under the sway of concepts, the I in finding itself as a Tendenz grasps itself also as an intellect. Consciousness of self, as having both power and freedom, arises therewith: the I grasps itself as capable of giving itself determinations through concepts.45 The problem which now arises, according to Fichte, is that the conception which has been provided so far remains that of a mere power without actuality.46 Alternatively stated, the problem is that we have got only as far as an intellect that intuits itself as pure activity, standing in opposition to all subsisting and being posited.47 The solution, Fichte argues, is for the

Tendenz to be thought to assume a more robust form, which he calls drive, Trieb, defined as 'a real, inner explanatory ground of an actual self-activity – a drive, moreover, that is posited as essential, subsisting, and ineradicable'.48 Fichte draws an analogy with the elasticity in a compressed steel spring as an inner ground of its activity.

44 That there is a 'sake' or aim – separating Fichte from Schopenhauer at the outset – is crucial.

Schelling, in his still Fichtean System of Transcendental Idealism (1800), trans. Peter Heath

(Charlottesville: University of Virginia, 1978), p. 35, considers and rejects the possibility that the self's activity is fundamentally 'blind'.

45 And only through concepts, Fichte, System of Ethics, p. 42.

46 The I's finding itself as a Tendenz has not, we now see, been sufficiently accounted for; Fichte,

System of Ethics, pp. 43–44.

47 See Fichte, System of Ethics, p. 42.

48 Fichte, System of Ethics, p. 44. 17

With this last shift, we are clearly approaching Schopenhauer's conceptual neighbourhood.

What should be emphasized for present purposes, however, are the features of this notion of drive which lock it into Fichte's project. As we have seen, it is introduced by Fichte in the context of a transcendental enquiry into the possibility of self-consciousness. The problem set by self- consciousness can also be viewed, Fichte explains, in terms of the demand that we, in philosophical reflection, construct a concept, which we are to suppose available to the I itself, of the of subject and object. Now this demand, Fichte affirms, cannot be met: one cannot think of oneself as that identity, since thinking introduces the very distinction that the identity is to exclude. The concept remains, consequently, 'a problem or task for thinking', an 'empty place' which we designate with an X.49 The drive to absolute self-activity which constitutes the being of the I is, it follows, a drive which aims at the I in its entirety, the unthinkable identity of subject and object.

Fichte's drive is, therefore, necessarily engaged with the space of reasons, inseparable from conceptuality, and constituted by a telos. It will come as no surprise to learn that it enjoys also a necessary connection with . The drive to self-activity, Fichte argues, manifests itself in and as a thought, which Fichte identifies with the , in the form of the principle of .50 Because the I in its entirety, the X of subject-object identity, cannot be grasped, the drive to self-activity must take the form of an approximation to it, consisting in 'a reciprocal determination of what is subjective by what is objective and vice versa'; and to proceed with this reciprocal determination, Fichte argues, is to act under the (self-given) law of self-sufficiency, which excludes determination of the I by the Not-I.

It is a consequence of this transcendental theory that Fichte can claim to have reconstructed

Kant's thesis of the equivalence of freedom and the moral law,51 and also to have effected a

49 Fichte, System of Ethics, pp. 45–46.

50 Fichte, System of Ethics, pp. 48–63.

51 Fichte, System of Ethics, pp. 55–56. 18 unification, not furnished by Kant, of practical and theoretical reason, finally putting beyond doubt the capacity of reason to be practical.52

Thus far, drive has been understood without any reference to the subject's phenomenology, but it is a general methodological requirement of the Wissenschaftslehre that its model be shown to accord with the facts of ordinary consciousness. Fichte adds accordingly an account of how, and in what form, drive shows up in ordinary consciousness, namely as a feeling of drive, called 'longing'

(Sehnen): an 'indeterminate sensation of a need' which is 'not determined through the concept of an object'.53 The feeling of drive is therefore the final manifestation of an underlying structure which has the character of a quintessentially rational task (Aufgabe), postulate (Postulat), or 'ought'

(Sollen).

If we now return to Schopenhauer, we can see immediately the various respects in which he, while endorsing Fichte's insight that the metaphysical core of the subject consists in drive, turns

Fichte's theory on its head.54 What Fichte takes as merely the most superficial manifestation of rational end-directed conation, the feeling of drive, is treated by Schopenhauer as primary, and as a sufficient basis for metaphysical extrapolation.55 Schopenhauer furthermore takes volitional feeling in isolation from representational consciousness, whereas it belongs to the central thrust of Fichte's argument that will and representation are reciprocally determining.56 On the basis of this isolated

52 Fichte, System of Ethics, p. 56, pp. 59–60.

53 Fichte, System of Ethics, pp. 101–103. Fichte denies that willing can be identified with, or that it originally manifests itself as, feeling (pp. 46–48 and p. 85), but nonetheless presents the connection as necessary.

54 See Schopenhauer's criticism of Fichte's theory of willing in MRCD, 406–408, 413–414; willing,

Schopenhauer counters, 'cannot be defined'.

55 See WWR I, 109–110.

56 Fichte, System of Ethics, pp. 81–87; in addition to the objects on which I act, my willing itself must be represented. 19 datum, Schopenhauer infers the essentially non-teleological and non-conceptual character of Wille.

Given Schopenhauer's contraction of PSR, the is indisputably valid: there is indeed nothing in the bare phenomenal feeling of drive or will which invites, or could possibly warrant, the complex and abstract structure which Fichte takes it to manifest; Fichte's interpretation of the facts of consciousness can get a purchase only because he assumes, as PSR entitles him to do, that there must be a reason for the existence of feeling, both in general and in this instance, as a type of mental state.57 Fichte's claim that 'the I itself has to be considered as the absolute ground of its drive', and that 'this drive appears as a freely designed concept of an end',58 is thus inverted:

Schopenhauer treats drive, impersonally conceived and directed to no end, as the ground of the I.59

57 Thus Fichte analyzes feeling as 'sheer determination', 'a mere determinacy of the intellect, without any contribution on the part of the intellect's freedom', System of Ethics, p. 102. Compare

Schopenhauer's brief definition of feeling in WWR I, 51. Karl Fortlage, in his 1845 review of the second volume of WWR (extracted in Volker Spierling (ed.), Materialen zu Schopenhauers »Die

Welt als Wille und Vorstellung« (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1984), pp. 119–126), defends

Fichte: Schopenhauer's concept of will without is, he argues, incoherent; in systematic terms, Schopenhauer represents merely an intermediation in the transition from Kant to Fichte (and

Schelling).

58 Fichte, System of Ethics, p. 103.

59 Even if Schopenhauer's non-Fichtean concept of will owes something to the Urwille posited in

Schelling's Freiheitsschrift as primal being, Ursein – Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom and Matters Connected Therewith [1809], trans. Jeff Love and Johannes

Schmidt (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2006), 350, p. 21 – Schelling does not invert Fichte's conception in the manner of Schopenhauer: the Urwille is without understanding yet not independent of it, because it is a yearning or desire for it, and is prescient, ahndend, of it; 'the understanding is really the will in will', and it joins with yearning to form God's omnipotent and freely creative will. Schopenhauer's low estimate of Schelling's essay, as a bad reworking of Jakob 20

Released from individuation, purposeless drive is ready to assume the role of substrate of the objectual world as such.

4. Schopenhauer and the meta-Critical problem

The flat disagreement between Fichte and Schopenhauer concerning the nature of drive or will goes back to their philosophical starting points and widely divergent views of the problems that need to be solved. We see here what a large part is played in generating Schopenhauer's metaphysical conclusions by his prior refusal of the German Idealist agenda. In taking transcendental subjectivity as an unconditional basic element in his analysis of representation in Book I of WWR, and in asserting that it stands in a relation of bare Korrelation with objects,60 Schopenhauer rejects implicitly the Kantian idea, which Fichte preserves, that the subject's object-consciousness must be treated as an explanandum. Schopenhauer's discarding of Kant's theory of synthesis is closely connected with this rejection: on Schopenhauer's account, the subject is necessary for objects qua their correlate, but it is not involved in constituting the unity fundamental to objecthood in the way that Kant hypothesizes, just as the subject's unity of consciousness receives for Schopenhauer no explanation of its possibility by reference to the unity of objects. Again, when in Book II

Schopenhauer raises the question of how the subject of representation comes to cognize itself as an individuated content of the objective world,61 the question is understood – this we can infer from the way in which it is answered – as precisely not involving a solution to the problem of self-

Böhme, is in MRCD, 353–354, and FR, 22–23, and it is dismissed once again in PP I, 26. The substantial criticism made by Schopenhauer, reasserting once again the contraction of PSR, is that

Schelling interpolates the ground-consequent relation within God (FR, 22). In PP I, 132,

Schopenhauer denies Schelling's influence.

60 See WWR I, §5.

61 WWR I, 99 and 103. 21 consciousness as Kant and Fichte understand it: Schopenhauer simply lays it down that the subject of thought is able to grasp itself as one and the same in representing and willing, in other words, that the bare phenomenal having-of-feeling involved in volitional episodes suffices for a grasp of myself as willing.62 The question with which Fichte labours, concerning the very possibility of the

I's attributing efficacy to itself, is nowhere raised.63

All in all, then, a range of transcendental questions formulated and addressed in the

Transcendental Deduction and elsewhere in Kant, taken by Fichte and the later German Idealists to frame the task of post-Kantian philosophy, are set aside by Schopenhauer, whose form of post-

Kantian idealism is to that extent appropriately described as, in the strict sense, non- transcendental.64 Whether this implies a reversion to 'dogmatism' or otherwise constitutes a

62 In response to Fichte, Schopenhauer asserts that the I 'is merely intuitively perceivable': 'an I is something found merely as a fact, something simply given' (MRCD, 73). Schopenhauer's refusal to accept that there is a problem concerning how the I can become an object for itself is explicit in comments on Schelling, MRCD, 381 and 383.

63 To be fully clear, the transcendental question is not raised; what is raised is a question concerning the inter- of facts of consciousness, which Schopenhauer answers by reference to bodily awareness. The body cannot provide an answer to the transcendental question, since, even if awareness of embodiment provides an explanation of how volitional as opposed to representational consciousness is possible, as Schopenhauer asserts (WWR I, 100–101), the identification of oneself with one's body is presupposed and not accounted for. It is also noteworthy – as another aspect of the inversion that I have been pointing to – that Schopenhauer's assumption that the body explains volitional awareness reverses the order in Fichte, who derives the physical power of efficacy from the practical principle governing the I and the necessity of determining one's freedom: see Fichte,

System of Ethics, pp. 71–91.

64 See MRCD, 466–472, where Schopenhauer repudiates the task of transcendental , viewing it as rendered redundant by the appreciation that the understanding is a faculty of intuitive perception. 22 weakness is a separate matter, about which something will be said in the next section. For the present, it may simply be noted that a clear rationale for Schopenhauer's divergence from Kant and his rival post-Kantians can be located, once again, in his axiological commitments, in so far as the transcendentalist ambition of excogitating transparent foundations for knowledge and value implies a determination to discover the world to be rational through and through.

Support for this non-transcendentalist construal can be found in Schopenhauer's early notebooks, in which he works through major positions occupied in the early post-Kantian development. Included here are Schulze's skepticism, J. F. Fries' and Jacobi's Glaubensphilosophie,

Fichte's subjective , Schelling's and Real-Idealismus and all of the other innovations contained in Schelling's writings up to and including the Freiheitsschrift.

Schopenhauer had therefore a wide range of post-Kantian options at his disposal.65 What is striking

Schopenhauer's rejection of transcendental argumentation is explored in ,

'Schopenhauer, Kant, and the Method of Philosophy', in Christopher Janaway (ed.), The Cambridge

Companion to Schopenhauer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999). See however Rudolf

Malter's transcendental reconstruction of Schopenhauer, 'Schopenhauers Transzendentalismus',

Schopenhauer-Jahrbuch 66, 1985, 29–51, and Günter Zöller's comments in 'Schopenhauer and the

Problem of Metaphysics: Critical Reflections on Rudolf Malter's Interpretation', Man and World 28,

1995, 1–10.

65 The list is not complete. Reinhold is absent, and does not figure in Schopenhauer's published works, even though his own approach has similarity with Reinhold's conception of analysis the facts of consciousness. Fichte criticized this conception and to some degree, in rejecting Fichte,

Schopenhauer is returning to Reinhold's plainer view of Critical method. Hegel is also missing from

Schopenhauer's early notebooks. In later writings Schopenhauer focusses on the metaphysical results of Hegel's Logic, which he regards as a variant of Schelling's position (PP II, 27–28); nowhere (to the best of my knowledge) is the method of the Phenomenology discussed in any detail by Schopenhauer. 23 in the early notebooks, however, is the absence of any sustained constructive engagement with the meta-Critical issues thrown up by Kantian philosophy. Schopenhauer records his dissatisfaction with all of the positions on offer, availing himself of their mutual criticisms, but proposes no answer of his own to the question of how propositions about non-empirical matters can be known and their truth ascertained. Nor, as I indicated earlier in emphasizing Schopenhauer's non-, is this deficiency remedied in WWR. Arguably, the best construal of Schopenhauer's position on meta-Critical issues is as a kind of semi-skeptical return to naivety: Schopenhauer appears to suppose that, since none of the ambitious and innovative post-Kantian developments yield an improved account of Kant's position, the Critical method is best regarded as a practice of simply reading off metaphysical directly from the facts of consciousness.66 The Kantian task of proving transcendental propositions is eliminated, and the vital Kantian question of whether what we are necessitated to think corresponds to how things themselves must be, is overtaken by the metaphysical assertion of two worlds, one constructed within representation and the other unrepresentable.

5. The architecture of Schopenhauer's system

There is another respect, connected with the foregoing, in which Schopenhauer's project contrasts with that of the German Idealists. As we have seen, Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre has as one of its principal aims the exposure of a common root of Freedom and Nature, and of the practical and

66 They are 'seen and grasped a priori'; a priori laws are simply 'given to the understanding'

(MRCD, 335–336). The post-Kantian to whom Schopenhauer here comes closest is Fries. In comments on Schopenhauer asserts that 'there is no knowledge of knowledge' (MRCD,

454). Note the extremely minimal definition of transcendental philosophy at PP II, 9, as starting from consciousness rather than things; the fuller account at PP I, 82–84, identifies it merely with the thesis of the a priori origin ('rooted in our brain') of the essential laws of the world. 24 theoretical. The German Idealists' project of unification – their aim, taking its cue from the third

Critique (as they understood it) yet going beyond it, to comprehend Kant's dualities in a single system in such a way as to exhibit their common source as an essential unity – is not shared by

Schopenhauer.67 Schopenhauer does not, however, merely reaffirm the necessity of an incompletely unified, multi-component system of philosophy of the sort that Kant considers the most that human reason can achieve. His relation to the post-Kantian unificatory project is more complex.

Schopenhauer's distance from the project of unification arises in part from his avoidance of one of the key Kantian dualities: since Schopenhauer denies the existence of practical reason in the sense maintained by Kant,68 the doctrine of the primacy of pure practical reason – with all of the complications that it creates concerning the respective rights and interests, and the necessary strategies of integration, of practical and theoretical reason; issues of huge importance to Fichte and the early Schelling – does not figure at all for Schopenhauer, who instead straightforwardly identifies philosophy as such with , in Kant's sense.69

Within this context, however, Schopenhauer reasserts Kant's practical/theoretical duality in the form of the distinction of the world as Wille, which gives it, as noted, all of its practical significance, and the world as representation, which exists for the necessarily disinterested subject

67 The 'main tendency of the Kantian philosophy' is instead 'to demonstrate the complete diversity of and the ' (PP I, 86; see also 25).

68 See MRCD, 337–338; WWR I, 522–523; VgP, 418–420. For a concise statement of his anti-

Kantian, broadly Humean view, see MRCD, 351.

69 WWR I, 271, 285. Schopenhauer conserves Kant's idea of the special connection of ethical conduct with metaphysical truth (e.g. WWR I, 384; WWR II, 600), but without Kant's cognitive privileging of the 'practical point of view'. Ethical action is for Schopenhauer an enacting or acting out, a symbolization within the world as representation, of the reality of Wille, cognition of which is theoretical. 25 of knowing.70 Kant's practical/theoretical distinction is conserved, therefore, through its outright identification with another core Kantian duality, that of appearances and things in themselves. This has a major implication, which refers us back to Schopenhauer's rejection of Kantian practical reason and inversion of Fichte's account of the will: if practical consciousness is analyzed in terms of Wille, then Ought is reducible to Is; contrary to Fichte's view of the absolute primacy of the

Sollen, there can be nothing more to oughtness than awareness (in one mode or another) of the being of Wille.71 By of its dualist architecture, then, Schopenhauer's system stays closer to

Kant than do the German Idealists, but in so far as Schopenhauer resolves all dualities into the single one of Wille and Vorstellung, Schopenhauer follows at least part of the way the unificatory vector of German Idealism.

There is a further respect in which Schopenhauer takes the side of German Idealism against

Kant. Kant's reservations concerning the possibility of systematic completeness are grounded on his thesis of the inherent limitations of human reason. Schopenhauer's anti-, by contrast, is untethered from the idea of epistemic limitation. The distinction of Wille and representation is absolute in a sense not admissible for Kant: it represents a denial not just of the possibility of our forging a philosophical system with the strong unity sought by the German Idealists, but of the metaphysical possibility that Wille and the world as representation form a real unity. So, whereas

Kant leaves it open, and necessarily thinkable, that the dualities within human reason are united at some point which transcends our cognitive powers – indeed the third Critique teaches that beauty and natural teleology at least point to (if no more) a unitary ground of the sensible and supersensible

– Schopenhauer's position is that the several roads of philosophical reflection which we must go

70 WWR II, 499.

71 Schopenhauer celebrates Kant's notion of 'a point of view where the moral law appears not as an ought (Sollen) but as a being (Sein)' (MRCD, 326–327). See the criticism of the imperatival form of

Kantian ethics in §4 of BM, 136–143. The shift of idiom, from Sollen to Sein, is pursued in

Schopenhauer's account of human freedom, in terms of intelligible character: see FW. 26 down in our endeavour to solve the riddle of existence do not join up at any point.72 Again this is a direct implication of his contraction of PSR.

The next question to be considered is whether Schopenhauer succeeds in charting a clear course between Kant and Fichte-Schelling.

II. Schopenhauer's difficulties

1. Wille as ground of the world as representation

Schopenhauer denies that that the relation of the will or thing in itself to the phenomenon is a relation of causality.73 This follows from Schopenhauer's contraction of PSR. But Schopenhauer does not allow the realm of the thinkable to coincide with the boundaries of the world as representation, nor does he confine explanation to relations between worldly objects, for the world itself 'is to be explained solely from the will whose it is, and not through causality'.74

The problem is straightforward. So long as some element of explanation is involved in referring the phenomenal world to Wille – and Schopenhauer speaks readily of metaphysical

72 In a comment on Schelling, Schopenhauer complains of his forcing a false unity on the human subject, 'as a bridge to unite the two worlds': the genuine, critical philosopher by contrast is 'content to have ... recognized the twofold nature of his being', which 'appears to him as two parallel lines which he does not bend or twist in order to unite' (MRCD, 376–377). If they meet, it is in a sphere accessible only to the mystic. True philosophy, 'instead of uniting the two heterogeneous worlds into monstra ... will always try to separate them more completely' (MRCD, 412).

73 E.g. MRCD, 489, WWR I, 120, 140, 502–507.

74 MRCD, 489; see also WWR I, 507. 27

Erklärung75 – some employment of the categories of ground and consequent, as Kant would put it, must be present. The explanation may be non-causal, but it must nonetheless incorporate a 'because' relation. Without it, we are simply left with (at most) sub-propositional, non-conceptual awareness of the world as awash with a certain all-pervasive mental quality, the quality possessed by acts of will; and although this might provide the cue for some such metaphorical thought as that the world

'insists itself' or 'exerts pressure', obviously it will not provide Schopenhauer with a sufficient basis for any of the determinate discursive conclusions that he wants to extract from his grounding of phenomena on Wille.76

75 E.g. PP II, 91; contrary to his own explicit claim, in WWR I, 80, that Erklärung is the establishment of 'the relation of the phenomena of the world to one another according to the principle of sufficient reason'.

76 I do not know of any passage where Schopenhauer addresses this issue, and it may be asked why he does not do so. At one place Schopenhauer appears to address the similar though even more basic problem of how it is possible for us to think (form a concept of) will at all, given its heterogeneity with representation and non-conformity to PSR: '[T]he concept of will is of all possible concepts the only one that has its origin not in the phenomenon, not in the mere representation of perception, but which comes from within, and proceeds from the most immediate consciousness of everyone' (WWR I, 112). If Schopenhauer can be allowed this on the basis of his concept empiricism, then we can conceptualize features of or phenomena in the world not tied to

PSR. But what still cannot be accounted for is the relation between Wille and Vorstellung required by his metaphysical 'because' claim: there can be no 'immediate experience' of because-ness (or, if there can, then we have intellectual intuition after all). My conjecture is that Schopenhauer supposes implicitly that the 'because' relation, or all that he needs it to amount to, is given immediately in the experience of bodily willing. The relation of (i) my (subjective experience of my) willing my arm to rise, and (ii) the objective (in the world as representation) of my arm's rising, is declared to be a relation not of causation but identity (WWR I, §18). Schopenhauer may suppose that this intuition 28

Viewed from another angle, the problem lies in Schopenhauer's taking it for granted that the objectual world as such can pose a 'riddle' at all. In order to even form the thought of the world as constituting an explanandum which demands a metaphysical explanans – i.e., as not simply explicable, and adequately explained, in so far as its contents are interrelated in accordance with

PSR – it is necessary to suspend Schopenhauer's contraction of PSR.77

The problem shows itself also in Schopenhauer's . Schopenhauer's pessimism rests,

I suggested, on the perception of a metaphysical dissonance, for which it is essential that the world of representation be ontologically subordinated to, and measured in terms set by, the world as Wille; this is what allows Schopenhauer to strike down, as normative illusions, the ends that human set themselves. But it may be wondered if this strategy succeeds. The mere judgement that one layer of reality is dependent on another may be necessary, but is it sufficient, for the negative assessment of the world as representation, its condemnation as ontologically defective? There is no obvious of the will/body nexus – our immediate grasp of it as identity-like yet asymmetric, with body depending on will and not vice versa – provides what is needed for his metaphysical extrapolation.

This construal of his thinking gets support from his emphatic claim that we discover in self- consciousness a meeting point of subject and object, and of phenomenon and Wille (WWR I, 102;

WWR II, 497). But again – even granting this 'miracle par excellence' – this does not solve the problem of how we come to think this intuited ontological fact in the way Schopenhauer requires, namely as a quasi-causal quasi-identity. For this reason, Schopenhauer can get no mileage out of pressing a distinction between 'the subject of knowing' and the 'subject of representation': even if non-representational cognition is possible, its content must still be thought; else it is mystical (and

Schopenhauer denies that his metaphysics are 'illuminist': PP II, 10).

77 At WWR II, 640, Schopenhauer comes close to conceding that the further metaphysical questions which, he allows, his system does not answer, 'cannot be thought by means of the forms and functions of the intellect'. The question is why this is not true also of the metaphysical questions which, he maintains, his system does answer. 29 logical principle compelling us to take the stronger view, and there are grounds for thinking that in arriving at this verdict Schopenhauer relies on elements he is not entitled to. At key junctures

Schopenhauer appeals to what he calls our 'better consciousness',78 but in so far as its superiority is merely asserted, it is open to the Kantian, or German Idealist, to object that Schopenhauer faces a hard : either the superiority of the standpoint that he recommends, from which we condemn the world as a cosmic mistake, is merely stipulated (or, as the Nietzschean may suggest, a matter of motivated taste); or it has normative foundations, in which case Schopenhauer has betrayed his own contraction of PSR to the world as representation, and his 'better consciousness' is playing the role of affording a higher level of reflection which Vernunft plays in Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. To put the point another way: the problem is that we are required to understand the 'expression' of Wille in the world of representation in a normative sense, since we are to judge that the latter is a mis- expression of the former; but a normative understanding of the concept is inadmissible given the contraction of PSR.

2. Schopenhauer's two models

The foregoing points to a tension in Schopenhauer's metaphysics. Two ideas essential to

Schopenhauer's position are, first, that there is no properly intelligible relation between Wille and the world as representation, and second, that the latter must be regarded as a higher species of illusion, as the 'veil of Maya'.79 What this naturally suggests is that the expression of Wille in the world as representation consists in its objectification, Objektivation, in the sense of the subject's making an object of cognition, a Vorstellung, out of Wille. Though cognitively nothing is achieved

78 MREM, 23, 46, 72; MRCD, 19, 373, 374, 376, 416, 430, 431. It is exhibited in virtuous conduct, and associated with genius. Plausibly Schopenhauer's notion of better consciousness owes something to Fries' conception of Ahnung.

79 WWR I, 8, 17, 523. 30 thereby, since the PSR-defined formal structure of cognition falsifies Wille, the character of Wille as purposeless striving shows up in the concrete, non-formal features of the world as representation.

Here the relation of Wille to representation is grasped from the angle of the subject. This model, which we might call epistemic or perhaps 'Eastern', tallies of course with Schopenhauer's claim to be upholding Kant's insight into the ideality of empirical objects, and arguably provides a ground for pessimism, in so far as its derealization of the world as representation strips the objects of human valuation of genuine reality. It also agrees with the conception of ethics as founded on compassion,80 and it helpfully allows Schopenhauer to dismiss, as reflecting a misunderstanding of his position, the question of the nature of the overarching unity of the world(s) of Wille and representation.81 If the sphere of Vorstellung is an illusion, so too is its correlate, the transcendental subject, the 'existence' of which, along with the world of objects, can be attributed to epistemic error and held to be dissolved through its correction.

This model is however by no means consistent with everything in Schopenhauer's picture. It is doubtful in the first place that it fits with the reading of expression demanded by the idea that

Wille constitutes the inner Kern of the subject and other individuated entities,82 a conception underlined in Schopenhauer's philosophy of natural science, which demands metaphysical grounds

80 To amplify: it allows the apparently inchoate thought entertained by the virtuous agent – viz., that

I should act benevolently because I am the suffering other and do not exist as 'I' (see BM, 211–213)

– to be validated as tracking the incoherent shape of reality as presented to a subject who has grasped that the world as representation is mere illusion.

81 As it does the notion, which Schopenhauer allows to suggest itself, and which we will see is developed by Hartmann, that Wille gives birth to transcendental subjectivity in order to restore itself to tranquillity, and so is not blind after all.

82 In statements such as: 'The will appears in everything, precisely as it determines itself in itself ... all finiteness, all sufferings ... belong to the expression of what the will wills, are as they are because the will so wills' (WWR I, 351). 31 for natural phenomena.83 In particular, the epistemic model does not cohere with the claim that

Wille finally achieves cognition of itself. Some of Schopenhauer's statements suggest that attributing self-knowledge to Wille just means that one of its individuated products has self-knowledge (or perhaps: knows itself to be an individuated product of Wille), but the full story of denial of the will does require that Wille itself, not merely its individual human objectifications, achieve genuine cognitive (and, thereby, practical) reflexivity.84 The epistemic model thereupon gives way to a metaphysical (or 'Western') conception, familiar from Schelling, according to which reality undergoes a real transformation in so far as it assumes a new form in human subjectivity.85 The expression of Wille in the world as representation now amounts to Objektivation in the quite different sense of Wille's making itself into an object, by giving itself determinate form,86 and its being an object of cognition, an object for a subject, becomes secondary, a supervening consequence of the self-expressive activity of Wille. Here the relation of Wille to representation is grasped from the angle of Wille.

This shift of conception rationalizes the doctrine of denial of will, but it creates difficulties for all of the elements that the epistemic model makes sense of. In particular it interferes with the argument for pessimism. If Wille in fact becomes the world as representation, then there is scope for

83 See WWR I, §27; WWR II, Ch. 26; PP II, Ch. 6; and WN. Also relevant is Schopenhauer's endorsement of occasionalism, WWR I, 138.

84 This is required if Wille is to, as Schopenhauer says, 'freely abolish itself' by 'relating such knowledge to itself' (WWR I, 285, 288). It is also implied by the notion that, in the individual's denial of the will to live, the freedom which Wille alone can possess is manifest, 'immediately visible', in the phenomenon (WWR I, 402; see also 403 and 404).

85 See Schelling, Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom.

86 Thus Schopenhauer talks of Wille, reflexively, as 'objectifying itself' (sich objektivirenden

Willens), 'entering the form of representation' (in die Form der Vorstellung eingegangen ist) and thereby ' knowable' (WWR I, 115, 120, 506). 32 deeming the latter a transcendence of the former, a newly created, higher reality which sets its own terms of evaluation: if Wille has ceased to be blind and acquired a real teleology, then the ends projected by sentient beings cannot be cancelled as metaphysical errors.87

Thus, although the two versions of Objektivation – epistemic objectification by the subject, and Wille's metaphysical self-determination – are not inconsistent, and might be taken as complementary views of the same event, which is perhaps how Schopenhauer wishes to think of them, the two models have, as we have seen, contradictory implications for key theses in

Schopenhauer's philosophy. That Schopenhauer may indeed have granted both models a place in his metaphysics, invoking them in different contexts without appreciating their incompatibility, is rendered likely by his assertion of a grounding relation between Wille and representation not governed by PSR: in so far as the relation is indeed in reality one of ground and consequent, the metaphysical model is implied; in so far as it eludes PSR, it can consist only in epistemic error.

3. Between Kant and German Idealism

In addition to the doubling of Eastern/epistemic and Western/metaphysical models, a separate tension can also be identified in Schopenhauer, occurring at a more fundamental, metaphilosophical level, and which is consequent upon the complex movement of his philosophy away from German

Idealism and back to Kant, and then again forward from Kant to reoccupy the territory of German

Idealism. I claimed earlier that Schopenhauer asserts an absolute distinction of will and

87 The Western model does not therefore cohere with the abolition of Wille itself (in addition to the world as representation), which Schopenhauer seems to say follows from denial of the will to live

(WWR I, 410–411). This claim appears to demand both models: in order for quieting of Wille, as opposed to mere dissolution of illusion, to ensue from the denial, it is necessary that Wille be genuinely present in the phenomenon; but if it is so present, then Wille has genuinely become a sphere of individuated objective entities, and it is unclear how it can retract its self-transformation. 33 representation, entailing the impossibility of a real unity of Wille and the world as representation.

Such a claim, not hedged by any Kantian epistemic qualification to the effect that dualism is simply the best that our cognitive powers can manage, is what Schopenhauer needs in order to counter

German Idealism's monism at its own level. But such absolute dualism, as it may be called, sits ill with Schopenhauer's avowed commitment to immanence and the standpoint of ordinary empirical consciousness.88

It is consequently fair to describe Schopenhauer as seeking to negotiate a way between two opposed positions:89 on the one hand, Kant's view that only perspectival conclusions, judgements about the nature of things relativized to our cognitive capacities and having only the status of necessities of representation, are licensed; and on the other, the non-perspectival absolutism of the

German Idealists, which rejects Kant's separation of mere necessities of representation from the true necessities governing things as they really are.90 Schopenhauer internalizes both approaches to metaphysics, and seeks to combine them in a novel way. The product is a conception of two worlds, which are not so much ontologically unequal in virtue of their possessing a different degree of reality according to a single measure, as ontologically heterogeneous in so far as each is associated with and defined by a different conception of what being consists in: in the case of Wille, being is conceived as intrinsically antithetical to cognition, and in that of Vorstellung, it is identified with it.91 Though we must treat the two conceptions as bearing on the same world, their heterogeneity entails that the relation between them cannot be grasped.92 This feature is present also, to some

88 WWR I, 272–273; WWR II, 640; PP II, 6–9.

89 Reflected in his (semi-paradoxical) statement that philosophy is 'conditioned knowledge of the absolute' (MRCD, 358–359).

90 Schopenhauer lays claim to 'absolute truth' ('in so far as such a truth is in general attainable'),

WWR II, 472; will is 'that which is absolutely real in every being', PP II, 95.

91 '[T]he word being means ''being known through the senses and the understanding''' (MRCD, 421).

92 WWR II, 497, 'the two heterogeneous sides of the world ... are absolutely incommensurable'. 34 degree, in Kant's account – in so far as Kant denies that the relation of appearances and things in themselves is open to theoretical cognition – but it becomes problematic in Schopenhauer in a way that it is not in Kant, in virtue of the fact that, as we have seen, Schopenhauer eliminates the basis supplied by Kant for the co-thinkability of the two worlds, namely the categories.

Schopenhauer's accommodation of fits into this picture in the following way.93 In so far as Schopenhauer counters German Idealism's monism with an absolute dualism,

Schopenhauer appears exposed to charges of incompleteness: a whole range of questions is, he acknowledges frankly, left unanswered.94 Mysticism provides a solution: Kant's modest, epistemically qualified, perspectival conception of philosophical knowledge is re-invoked at the outer limit of Schopenhauer's system as a ground for legitimating mystical claims, allowing

Schopenhauer to acknowledge his system's explanatory limitations while reaffirming its philosophical completeness.

One final observation may be made, concerning the way Schopenhauer recasts Kant's distinction of appearances and things in themselves. As noted previously, Schopenhauer's contracted PSR differs from Kant's principles of experience in not owing its truth to any normatively defined epistemic function (of 'making experience possible') that it performs for us.

The knowledge we have of PSR is instead of a kind that, in Kant's terms, belongs (like the claims of the German Idealists) to dogmatic metaphysics: it specifies the entire intrinsic constitution of a type of object (albeit a very special type, which includes cognition within its constitution). Our knowledge of the sphere defined by PSR is thus not mere perspectival knowledge, in the way that for Kant knowledge of appearance counts as a mere perspective on something (unknown) that is not itself appearance. Furthermore, although knowledge of the world as representation is not knowledge of a substance – since it does not contain the condition of its own existence – its (unique and

93 WWR I, 410; WWR II, 610–614.

94 As he acknowledges: WWR II, 640–641. WWR II, 579: 'even the most perfect philosophy will always contain an unexplained element, like an insoluble precipitate or remainder'. 35 sufficient) ontological requisite, viz. Wille, is known to us. We know, therefore, both the essence and the ground of the world as representation. Now, just as Schopenhauerian Vorstellung is not

Kantian Erscheinung, so Schopenhauer's thing in itself is not Kant's, and in Kant's terms,

Schopenhauer's claims to knowledge of the world as representation – viz., as constituted internally by PSR and grounded externally on Wille – is already knowledge of a thing in itself: though

Schopenhauer's contraction of PSR restricts its domain, PSR enjoys with respect to that domain the same kind of absolute metaphysical validity as it enjoyed (with respect to being in general) for

Spinoza and Leibniz. In this unexpected way, Schopenhauer's development of Kant's transcendental idealism, which he intended as a radical alternative to the Fichte-Schelling form of post-

Kantianism, ends up, in the respect indicated, firmly on their side.95

If the difficulties I have indicated are genuine, then Schopenhauer's deconstruction of German

Idealism does not succeed. To press the point home: It is a consequence of the foregoing that the very charges that Schopenhauer lays against Schelling can be levelled against his own system.

Schopenhauer repudiates the intellectually intuited 'indifference point' of Schelling's identity philosophy, claiming that Schelling's positing of an absolute unity of the subjective and the

95 This result is not so surprising, when we recall Schopenhauer's alignment of Kant's idealism with that of Berkeley (WWR I, 434–435, 444; WWR II, 8), whose idealism is by Kant's lights a form of transcendental realism. The point can thus be put as follows. Schopenhauer makes clear that his understanding of Erscheinung takes an extra, Berkeleyan step beyond Kant's (VgP, 482–489), and because for Schopenhauer the subject-object relation is one of bare Korrelation, and the object's existence consists in its relatedness to the subject (as it does for Berkeley), our mode of cognition,

Erkenntnisart, is for Schopenhauer not a (merely formal) condition to which objects are subject and hence relativized in so far as they are cognized (as it is for Kant), but an (unrelativized) ontological component of those objects (as they are an sich). 36 objective violates the principle of contradiction and results in mere pseudo-concepts.96 But if

Schopenhauer requires us to think the world as a superimposition of two dissociated conceptions, then he puts us in the same position as that which he criticizes in Schelling. The 'either-or, neither- nor, both-and' character of Schelling's point of indifference is reproduced in the structure of

Schopenhauer's system, which hinges on a supposition of the very same order – namely, that Wille can both be and not be the world as representation. The same combination of conjunction and exclusive disjunction is involved. The from Schelling is only that Schopenhauer has not made the supposition formally explicit, and chooses to describe our knowledge of the coming together of Wille and the world as representation as mere 'negative knowledge'.97 But again it does not look as if the negative character of our knowledge creates a real difference: Schopenhauer may not talk of a faculty of intellectual intuition, or develop a theory of construction in concepts, but still he must posit a capacity to grasp in some manner the nexus of Wille and representation, on pain of foregoing the claim that philosophical knowledge is involved here at all.98

III. The post-Schopenhauerian development

96 E.g., MRCD, 342, 359–360, 371–373, 391, and WWR I, 26. Schopenhauer is on weak ground here, in so far as his own claim to possess the concepts of object, subject, and Korrelation, which define the sphere within which PSR operates, appears to assume intellectual intuition or its equivalent.

97 WWR I, 410; WWR II, 612.

98 It is highly significant in this context that Schopenhauer describes Kant's account of intellectual intuition in §76 of the Critique of the Power of Judgement – passages inspirational for the German

Idealists, and which, one might think, Schopenhauer ought to have dismissed as one of Kant's regrettable errors – as 'the pith of the Kantian philosophy' (MRCD, 326–327). 37

I want now to look at the post-Schopenhauerian development, with a view to showing how it bears witness to the problem created by his contraction of PSR, and to charting Schopenhauer's influence on late nineteenth-century philosophy. Distinguished below are five systematic possibilities, mapped onto actual historical developments.99 Each represents a different move that, it may be thought, Schopenhauer may or should make in response to the difficulties generated by his attempt to persevere with substantive metaphysical claims while contracting reason. In each case I will note very briefly its arguable limitation from Schopenhauer's perspective or a problem that it encounters.

1. Modifying German Idealism from within: late Schelling

Schelling's late philosophy is of course not a development of Schopenhauer's philosophy but an independent development within German Idealism, which was already underway, though it had not come to completion, by the time Schopenhauer came on the German philosophical scene.100 It merits consideration here nonetheless, in so far as the late Schelling may be regarded as attempting to modify German Idealism in a way that incorporates the conviction at the root of Schopenhauer's project: Schelling had in clear view from 1804 onwards the very problem that appears to mark the limit of Schopenhauer's philosophical system, namely how to express and explain, in discursive terms and with reasoned justification, the failure of the real to be the rational.

In his Essay on Human Freedom of 1809 Schelling tries to revise the system of idealism in a way that will accommodate the possibility of evil, something which, he argues, Kant, Fichte and by implication his own earlier forms of idealism had precluded. This involves Schelling in rethinking the Absolute, or God, as primordially will, without conceptual form or understanding, 'blind

99 I provide only selective coverage; for a comprehensive view of Schopenhauer's influence and successors, see Fabio Ciracì, Domenico M. Fazio, and Matthias Koßler (eds.), Schopenhauer und die Schopenhauer-Schule (Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann, 2009).

100 See note 59 above. 38 longing'. Reason, on this account, is something that comes to be, in and through God's volitional self-realization. The pattern mirrors Schopenhauer: first there is will, then there is the space of reasons; and the possibility of evil derives from the 'excess' of reality over reason, the residue of non-rational will carried over into rationally formed reality.101 What might be claimed therefore is that, though Schopenhauer's reassertion of the unsolved problem of evil poses a challenge which the incurably optimistic systems of Fichte and Hegel cannot meet, the challenge is eventually met by

Schelling.

The notion that Schelling takes the wind out of Schopenhauer's sails encounters, however, the following obstacle. True to Kant, Schelling identifies evil as such with human moral evil – and this allows Schopenhauer to grant for the sake of argument that Schelling's revision to German

Idealism might account for the evil that enters the world through human action, while denying that it does anything to acknowledge the evil which is written into the fabric of the world (the evil

101 The details of the later Schelling's view of reason do not belong here, but it is worth indicating the basic difference between his and Schopenhauer's respective contractions of PSR. This may be viewed in terms of their different attitudes to the thesis of the absolute identity of being and knowing maintained in Schelling's identity philosophy of 1801–02. This Schopenhauer simply negates by asserting its antithesis, i.e., that being (in itself) and knowing are absolutely alien to one another. Schelling by contrast thereafter continues to regard the identity thesis as containing truth, but not as ontologically primary, the important point being that, though the domain conforming to

PSR is ultimately restricted, Schelling regards it as intelligibly continuous with its pre-rational ground. Thus in the Freiheitsschrift, Schelling locates the birth of reason in God's self-grounding, to which it is related teleologically (Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom, p. 30). In his later philosophy of revelation, the relation between PSR and what lies outside it is formulated in terms of the (again intelligible and ultimately complementary) relation of negative to positive philosophy: see The Grounding of Positive Philosophy: The Berlin Lectures [1842–43], trans. Bruce Matthews (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2007), esp. pp. 127–154. 39 which, to take an example from a relevant context, incites Adrian Leverkühn to take back the Ninth

Symphony).102

The following four neo-Schopenhauerian developments divide into two groups, according to whether they either approach Schopenhauer from the angle of German Idealism and attempt to resolve the tension in his system by working it into that context, or on the contrary propose to cut him loose from it. The pair comprising the first group can be described as 'metaphilosophically realist', in the sense that they regard Schopenhauer's metaphysical claims as aiming at plain theoretical truth (in accord with Schopenhauer's own view of their logical character) and as having immodest, non-Kantian, absolutist import. They subscribe accordingly to what I called

Schopenhauer's 'Western'/metaphysical model, eschewing the illusionistic dimension of

Schopenhauer's treatment of empirical reality.

2. Union with Hegel: Eduard von Hartmann's Philosophy of the Unconscious

Eduard von Hartmann regards Schopenhauer's attempt to annex a metaphysics of will to empirical reality as essentially correct, but as suffering principally from the defect that Schopenhauer fails to explain how conceptual structure enters the picture. The teleological metaphysics of Hartmann's

Philosophy of the Unconscious, published in 1869, grounds natural phenomena in a manifold of unconscious acts of will, unified ultimately under the single act of will which he calls the (All-One)

Unconscious. Thus far Hartmann is following, and developing, Schopenhauer's line in On the Will in Nature. Hartmann departs from Schopenhauer, however, by interpreting the teleological metaphysics of nature as revealing the existence of an original synthesis of Hegel's Idee and

102 Whether the objection succeeds depends on whether Schelling's suggestion that man's moral evil infects creation at large can be sustained: see Michelle Kosch, Freedom and Reason in Kant,

Schelling, and Kierkegaard (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 103–104. 40

Schopenhauer's alogical Wille, the dual equiprimordial constituents of reality. Nature falls out of their union: the Idee furnishes natural kinds and the order of nature, while Wille gives these actual existence, bringing to life and imparting movement to Hegel's ghostly edifice.

The broad philosophical significance of his Philosophy of the Unconscious, Hartmann explains, is that it comprises an overcoming of the antinomy formed by Hegel and Schopenhauer, yielding a super-system in which their respective deficiencies are corrected: the Schopenhauerian element allows Hegel to answer the familiar charge of panlogicism, while Hegel provides the ideational structure which Schopenhauer is unable to account for.103

The crucial, striking element in Hartmann's neo-Schopenhauerian metaphysics is the notion of an absolutely original, unconditioned union of Idee and Wille. This presents the following difficulty. The union is either rational or not, but if it is not, then it is impossible to understand how

Idee can be affected by Wille, while if it is, then Wille must lie already within the space of reasons.

It seems that, if the union is possible, then Wille must be proto-ideational and Idee must be proto- volitional; in which case their union amounts to the actualization of each through the other, their mutual realization in a hylomorphic relationship (suggesting, perhaps, that Idee and Wille cannot after all be absolutely primitive). This might be counted an interesting new addition to the neoplatonic canon, and it is arguably the position that Hartmann ought to have taken, but it is not, in fact, how he wishes to conceive matters: the Idee-Wille synthesis, Hartmann maintains, is indeed

103 For a selection of Hartmann's criticisms of Schopenhauer, see Eduard von Hartmann, Philosophy of the Unconscious: Speculative Results According to the Inductive Method of Physical Science [1st edn., 1869], trans. William Chatterton Coupland (from the 9th edn, 1882) (London: Kegan Paul,

1931), Vol. I, pp. 29–31, pp. 117–119; Vol. II, pp. 101–102, pp. 339–343; and Vol. III, pp. 149–

151. Hartmann reads the Hegel-Schopenhauer relation through the lens of Schelling's distinction of negative and positive philosophy, Hegel supplying the Was or Wie of things and Schopenhauer the

Daß. To that extent, Hartmann's manoeuvres may be viewed as an exploration of the first option, i.e., as resolving Schopenhauer into late Schelling. 41 unintelligible; we must regard it as an error or wrong,104 that can be characterized only in quasi- mythic terms (on the model of sexual union).105 And with this it becomes clear that, contrary to the expectations raised by talk of a Hegel-Schopenhauer synthesis, Hartmann has not eased the tension present in Schopenhauer concerning the relation of Wille to PSR, nor has he intended to do so: rather he has singled it out, theorized it explicitly, and reaffirmed it at the apex of his system. The gain in explicitness is however offset – from Schopenhauer's point of view – by the way in which

Hartmann's reconfiguration appears to remove irrationality from the world and relocate it outside, in its mere ontological antecedents.

3. Schopenhauer in the of Hegel: 's Realdialektik

Whereas Hartmann aims to fortify Schopenhauer's system by melding it with Hegel's, his contemporary Julius Bahnsen recasts Schopenhauer's central ideas in the terms of Hegel's .

According to Bahnsen, there are, as Hegel says, contradictions in reality – the blame for antinomy falls on the object, not the thinking subject – but these are, as per Schopenhauer, functions of its character as Wille, not of an autonomous dynamic of the Begriff. The contradictions arise because will inherently contradicts itself – to will is to will not-to-will: every desire aims at its own extinction. The space of reasons just is the appearing (Schein) of the self-contradicting activity of Wille, and PSR the 'law' which governs it.106 Because conceptuality is nothing over and above

Wille's manifestation of its self-negating essence, there is nothing within it, no potential for autonomy, that could lead to an overcoming of the world's constitutive contradictions. Whereas

Hartmann marries Wille with reason, its ontological equal, Bahnsen's more authentically

104 Hartmann, Philosophy of the Unconscious, Vol. II, p. 273, and Vol. III, pp. 124–125.

105 Hartmann, Philosophy of the Unconscious, Vol. II, Ch. XV, Sect. 2.

106 Julius Bahnsen, Der Widerspruch im Wissen und Wesen der Welt. Princip und Einzelbewährung der Realdialektik (Berlin: Grieben, 1880), p. 206. 42

Schopenhauerian approach reduces reason to Wille; again, whereas Hartmann concedes to Hegel the genuinely rational character of reality as given to us, Bahnsen follows Schopenhauer in ascribing an irrational character to the conceptually formed world. Pessimism, the defence of which

(as noted above) presents Hartmann with a difficulty, is thus firmly reinstated.107

Bahnsen's metaphysics lacks nothing in strangeness, yet may be regarded as again a consistent development from Schopenhauerian premises. Bahnsen's original contribution to neo-

Schopenhauerianism lies in his substitution for the antagonism of PSR with Wille a primordial antagonism within Wille itself. This facilitates what Schopenhauer denied to be possible, viz., a grounding of PSR, thereby converting Schopenhauer's absolute dualism into an absolute monism. In a supreme reversal of Wolff, PSR is derived from a principle of self-contradiction.

Of greatest importance for present purposes, however, is Bahnsen's novel articulation of

Schopenhauer's core thesis. Bahnsen takes from Hartmann a term that is absent from Schopenhauer, antilogisch, in order to characterize the essence of Wille.108 He does so because he wishes to conceive Wille not as merely outside reason in the familiar and innocuous sense in which for bald naturalists nature and efficient natural causality lie outside the space of reasons, but as contrary or antagonistic to reason.109 This notion makes sense, however, only if Wille's opposition to reason is a

107 Bahnsen, Der Widerspruch im Wissen und Wesen der Welt, p. 210. Hartmann's case for pessimism is made in Philosophy of the Unconscious, Vol. III, Ch. XIII.

108 Hartmann denies that the will as such is anti-logical; it is merely alogical, and becomes anti- logical only in its act (Philosophy of the Unconscious, Vol. III, pp. 124–125).

109 This is made clear in Bahnsen, Der Widerspruch im Wissen und Wesen der Welt, p. 6: In

Objektivdialektik 'it is a matter not just of the conflict of the laws of thought with one another, but of a conflict of the laws of reality on the one hand with one another and on the other with the laws of thought'; the dialectical character of the relation between elements in reality (gedachten Realen)

– not insofar as they are contained in subjective thought but insofar as they stand in objectivity – is the same as that which can obtain between , 'namely one of contradiction'. It is on this basis 43 relation distinct from opposition in the material sense of conflicting causality, e.g., the clash of physical forces, which is merely alogical or non-logical. The relation must instead comprise, or have a character akin to, logical opposition. The only thing that can be thought to stand opposed to logic as such is contradiction, the Contradictory. Bahnsen's Antilogische provides for this not through dialetheism, the true conjunction of contradictory assertoric propositions, but through contradiction in will: performative, as opposed to constative, contradiction. Bahnsen's Wille thus opposes reason in the mode of refuting or falsifying it, by dint of the fact that reality as a whole and in all of its individual forms – all possible candidates for satisfying or exemplifying reason – has in essence the nature of an impossible undertaking (a striving with the incoherent content: 'to will-not- to-will').

Bahnsen's Realdialektik unpacks and sharpens Schopenhauer's claim that Wille is 'foreign' to

PSR, but makes no advance with the problem that we have been tracking in Schopenhauer.

According to Realdialektik, the relation of thought to reality too must exhibit contradiction, meaning that no philosophical system which grasps reality adequately can give a full and complete account of its capacity to do so; Bahnsen's claim to knowledge of the self-contradictory essence of

Wille is no less precarious than Schopenhauer's claim to knowledge of the grounding of the world in

Wille.110

Hartmann and Bahnsen give a fair idea of what can be done with Schopenhauer by reworking his thought in the terms of German Idealism. The alternative is to abandon the aspiration to plain theoretical truth. This may be buttressed by the suggestion that just as, according to Schopenhauer, that Bahnsen differentiates his Realdialektik from Hegel's merely subjective, 'verbal', 'pseudo' dialectic.

110 Which is not to say that Bahnsen fails to engage with epistemology: in the first part of Volume I of Der Widerspruch im Wissen und Wesen der Welt, 'Das antilogische Princip: Einleitung in die

Realdialektik', Bahnsen tries to show that his system avoids self-refutation. 44

Kant allowed the Leibnizian-Wolffian philosophy which comprised his proximate target to condition and compromise his own system,111 so Schopenhauer, too much under the spell of the idea of Philosophy-as-System, made the same mistake with respect to German Idealism. Two such

'metaphilosophically anti-realist' construals of Schopenhauer's philosophy suggest themselves. They are independent but not exclusive, and both are associated with Nietzsche.

4. 'Aestheticist' reconstrual of Schopenhauer

If Schopenhauer's system cannot lay claim to theoretical truth, it may still be construed expressively or aesthetically, or perhaps as a case of 'showing' what cannot be said, and in such terms a species of validity claimed for it. Whether or not such an approach counts as a poor second best, or entails a complete abandonment of cognitive ambition, will depend upon what general view is taken of the significance of aesthetic presentations and of the capacity of philosophical thought to attain theoretical truth; in the case of Wittgenstein's rendering of Schopenhauer's insights in the Tractatus, for example, it is not at all clear that cognitive inferiority is implied.

An anti-realist understanding of Schopenhauer underlies Nietzsche's non-committal use of his metaphysics in The Birth of Tragedy, where the Schopenhauerian dissolution of nature into a trans-phenomenal will is compared to a 'light-image [Lichtbild] that healing nature holds up to us after we have glimpsed the abyss'.112 Though Schopenhauer himself barely wavers in his commitment to the unqualified truth of his system, there are moments when his concept empiricism may seem to draw him in such a direction – philosophy is described as merely depositing in concepts 'a reflected image [reflektirtes Abbild]' of the inner nature of the world.113

111 MRCD, 310; WWR I, 418; WWR II, 582.

112 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy Out of the Spirit of Music [1872], trans. Shaun

Whiteside, ed. Michael Tanner (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1993), §9, 47.

113 WWR I, 384. Or, again, as an 'Abspiegelung der Welt, in abstrakten Begriffe', VgP, 571. 45

One way of developing this line in Schopenhauer's own terms would be to claim that his philosophical system stands in the same sort of relation to man, or the human condition, as a work of art does to the Idea that it realizes. Since tragedy is for Schopenhauer the form of art that expresses most perfectly the Idea of man,114 Schopenhauer's metaphysics would count as a theorization not essentially different from a tragic work but simply more abstract. The measure of the success of his system would consist, at least in part, in the application of criteria appropriate to a work of art – verisimilitude, resonance, hermeneutic traction, and so on. That Schopenhauer's philosophy lends itself readily to such a perspective is testified by its extraordinary track record of literary inspiration.

The essential point at any rate is that if Schopenhauer's metaphysics of Wille are viewed aesthetically, then they are discharged from the task of explanation: the distinction between answering and simply evoking the 'riddle of the world' disappears, and with it the tension created by his contraction of PSR. Also affected, however, is Schopenhauer's axiological conviction: that the world is intrinsically and positively evil must now be regarded as something other than a straightforward fact about its nature.

5. 'Practicalist' reconstrual of Schopenhauer: Nietzsche

Nietzscheans may welcome the earlier conclusion that Schopenhauer fails in his endeavour to deconstruct German Idealism as showing the necessity of taking a greater initial distance from the legacy of idealism in order to overcome it. Nietzsche's own deconstruction of Schopenhauer's pessimism is well-known and needs only brief rehearsal. According to Nietzsche, what it means for the will or the practical to have primacy is not just for the intellect to be, as a factual matter, causally subordinate to the will, à la Freud. Certainly it entails that philosophical thought should reflect on its own motivation, but more deeply it means, metaphilosophically, that values, taken to

114 WWR I, 252. 46 be themselves non-metaphysical, replace metaphysical truth-claims in our understanding of the practical, and that philosophical reflection makes legitimate appeal to values in determining how to conceptualize the world. Practical orientation is understood with indifference to metaphysical questions (thus to some extent in a more Kantian way), and henceforth depth replaces metaphysics in providing practical and axiological guidance. And this practical turn can be given a

Schopenhauerian justification: Nietzsche's contention is that if the contraction of PSR is carried through consistently (and on his account there is further to go in dethroning reason) then practical and axiological concerns cannot be regarded any longer as topics in, or as subject to the authority of, metaphysics.

In this light, Nietzsche argues, Schopenhauer's own ground floor conviction that evil has positive reality must be re-examined, from which it emerges that this metaphysical judgement is a mere symptom of a defective constitution, lacking in truth and expressive of a stance towards the world which has no privileged . Nietzsche thus converts Schopenhauer's categorical judgement that the world is evil, is such that it ought not to be, into an act of will, a bare imperative of world-rejection. The respective claims of optimism and pessimism, keenly debated in the late nineteenth century, form for Nietzsche an antinomy resting on a false presupposition, and its dissolution opens up new horizons.

Both the realist and the anti-realist developments can claim to stay true to the spirit of

Schopenhauer's project; Hartmann and Bahnsen may be regarded as restoring it to its terminus ad quo, and Nietzsche as articulating its terminus ad quem. The latter is doubtless more congenial to us now, but its limitation – again, from Schopenhauer's point of view – is worth noting. What holds

Schopenhauer within metaphysics is not a failure to grasp the possibility of saying farewell to the whole business of trying to say something about the essence of the world: the basis for that post- metaphysical option is set out clearly in Fourfold Root. The reason why Schopenhauer does not take it is that the evil of existence is, for him, a hard fact, a fact so hard that only the thing in itself can do 47 justice to its reality. From this angle, the primary task, the difficulty of which was not lost on

Nietzsche, is to persuade Schopenhauer out of his conviction of the theoretical character of his insight; in other words, to demonstrate that the anti-realist reconstrual does not – as it will appear to

Schopenhauer – amount to a loss of reality and betrayal of his insight.

References

Abbreviations employed in reference to Schopenhauer's works:

BM Prize Essay on the Basis of Morals

FR On the Fourfold Root of the Principle Sufficient Reason

FW Prize Essay on the Freedom of the Will

MREM Manuscript Remains: Early Manuscripts (1804–1818)

MRCD Manuscript Remains: Critical Debates (1809–1818)

PP Parerga and Paralipomena, Vols. I–II

VgP Vorlesung über die gesammte Philosophie

WN On the Will in Nature

WWR The World as Will and Representation, Vols. I–II

Atwell, John E. (1995), Schopenhauer on the Character of the World: The Metaphysics of Will

(Berkeley: University of California Press).

Bahnsen, Julius (1880), Der Widerspruch im Wissen und Wesen der Welt. Princip und

Einzelbewährung der Realdialektik (Berlin: Grieben).

Cartwright, David E. (2010), Schopenhauer: A Biography (Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press).

Ciracì, Fabio, Domenico M. Fazio, and Matthias Koßler (eds.) (2009), Schopenhauer und die

Schopenhauer-Schule (Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann). 48

Fichte, J. G. (1982 [1794–95]), Foundations of the Entire Science of Knowledge, in The Science of

Knowledge, with the First and Second Introductions, ed. and trans. Peter Heath and John Lachs

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Fichte, J. G. (2005 [1798]), The System of Ethics according to the Principles of the

Wissenschaftslehre, ed. and trans. Daniel Breazeale and Günter Zöller (Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press).

Gardner, Sebastian (2012), 'Schopenhauer's Contraction of Reason: Clarifying Kant and Undoing

German Idealism', Kantian Review 17, 1–27.

Herbart, Johann Friedrich (1820), 'Rezension, Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung von Arthur

Schopenhauer. Leipzig, bei F. M. Brockhaus. 1819', Hermes, oder, Kritisches Jahrbuch der

Literatur 20, 131–148.

Guyer, Paul (1999), 'Schopenhauer, Kant, and the Method of Philosophy', in Christopher Janaway

(ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Hartmann, Eduard von (1931 [1869]), Philosophy of the Unconscious: Speculative Results

According to the Inductive Method of Physical Science, trans. William Chatterton Coupland (from the 9th edn, 1882) (London: Kegan Paul).

Hübscher, Arthur (1989), The Philosophy of Schopenhauer in its Intellectual Context: Thinker against the Tide, trans. Joachim T. Baer and David E. Cartwright (Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen).

Janaway, Christopher (1989), Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford

University Press).

Janaway, Christopher (1999), 'Schopenhauer's Pessimism', in Christopher Janaway (ed.), The

Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Kosch, Michelle (2006), Freedom and Reason in Kant, Schelling, and Kierkegaard (Oxford:

Oxford University Press).

Longuenesse, Béatrice (2005), 'Kant's Deconstruction of the Principle of Sufficient Reason', in Kant on the Human Standpoint (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). 49

Malter, Rudolf (1985), 'Schopenhauers Transzendentalismus', Schopenhauer-Jahrbuch 66, 29–51.

Nietzsche, Friedrich (1993 [1872]), The Birth of Tragedy Out of the Spirit of Music, trans. Shaun

Whiteside, ed. Michael Tanner (Harmondsworth: Penguin).

Nietzsche, Friedrich (1974 [1887]), The Gay Science, 2nd edn., trans. Walter Kaufmann (New

York: Vintage).

Schelling, F. W. J. (1978 [1800]), System of Transcendental Idealism, trans. Peter Heath

(Charlottesville: University of Virginia).

Schelling, F. W. J. (2006 [1809]), Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom and Matters Connected Therewith, trans. Jeff Love and Johannes Schmidt (Albany, NY: State

University of New York Press).

Schelling, F. W. J. (2007 [1842–43]), The Grounding of Positive Philosophy: The Berlin Lectures, trans. Bruce Matthews (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press).

Schopenhauer, Arthur (1969 [1819/1844]), The World as Will and Representation, 2 vols., trans. E.

F. J. Payne (New York: Dover).

Schopenhauer, Arthur (1974 [1847]), On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason,

2nd edn., trans. E. F. J. Payne (LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court).

Schopenhauer, Arthur (1974 [1851]), Parerga and Paralipomena: Short Philosophical Essays, 2 vols., trans. E. F. J. Payne (Oxford: Clarendon).

Schopenhauer, Arthur (1986 [1820]) Vorlesung über die gesammte Philosophie d.i. Die Lehre vom

Wesen der Welt und von dem menschlichen Geiste. In vier Theilen. Erster Theil: Theorie des gesammten Vorstellen, Denkens und Erkennens, in Theorie des gesammten Vorstellens, Denkens und Erkennens. Aus dem handschriftlichen Nachlaß, hrsg. u. eingeleitet von Volker Spierling

(München: Piper).

Schopenhauer, Arthur (1988 [1804–18]), Manuscript Remains: Early Manuscripts (1804–1818), ed.

Arthur Hübscher, trans. E. F. J. Payne, Manuscript Remains in Four Volumes, Vol. 1 (New York:

Berg). 50

Schopenhauer, Arthur (1988 [1809–18]), Manuscript Remains: Critical Debates (1809–1818), ed.

Arthur Hübscher, trans. E. F. J. Payne, Manuscript Remains in Four Volumes, Vol. 2 (New York:

Berg).

Schopenhauer, Arthur (1991 [1836]), On the Will in Nature: A Discussion of the Corroborations from the Empirical Sciences that the Author's Philosophy has Received Since its First Appearance, ed. David E. Cartwright, trans. E. F. J. Payne (Oxford: Berg).

Schopenhauer, Arthur (2010 [1839]), Prize Essay on the Freedom of the Will, in The Two

Fundamental Problems of Ethics, trans. David E. Cartwright and Edward E. Erdmann (Oxford:

Oxford University Press).

Schopenhauer, Arthur (2010 [1840]), Prize Essay on the Basis of Morals, in The Two Fundamental

Problems of Ethics, trans. David E. Cartwright and Edward E. Erdmann (Oxford: Oxford University

Press).

Spierling, Volker (ed.) (1984), Materialen zu Schopenhauers »Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung«

(Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp).

Young, Julian (1987), Willing and Unwilling: A Study in the Philosophy of Arthur Schopenhauer

(Dordrecht: Kluwer).

Young, Julian (2005), Schopenhauer (Young: Routledge).

Zöller, Günter (1995), 'Schopenhauer and the Problem of Metaphysics: Critical Reflections on

Rudolf Malter's Interpretation', Man and World 28, 1–10.