Causal Parameters and Policy Analysis in Economics
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
CAUSAL PARAMETERS AND POLICY ANALYSIS IN ECONOMICS: ATWENTIETHCENTURY RETROSPECTIVE* JAMES J. HECKMAN Themajor contributions of twentiethcentury econometricsto knowledge were thede nition of causal parameters within well-de ned economic models in which agentsare constrained by resourcesand markets and causes are interrelated, the analysisof what isrequired to recover causal parameters from data (the identication problem), and clari cation of the role of causal parameters in policy evaluationand in forecasting the effects of policies never previously experienced. Thispaper summarizes the development of these ideas by theCowles Commission, theresponse to their work bystructural econometriciansand V AReconometri- cians,and the response to structural andV AReconometricsby calibrators, advocatesof natural and social experiments, and by nonparametric econometri- ciansand statisticians. I. INTRODUCTION Thispaper considersthe de nition and identication of causal parametersin economicsand theirrole in econometric policyanalysis. It assessesdifferent researchprograms designed torecovercausal parametersfrom data. Atthebeginning of this century,economictheory was mainly intuitive,and empiricalsupport forit was largelyanecdotal. At theend of thecentury ,economicshas aricharray offormalmodels and ahigh-quality database. Empirical regularitiesmotivate theoryin manyareas of economics,and data areroutinely used to testtheory .Many economictheories have been developed as measurementframeworks to suggest what data should becol- lectedand howthey should beinterpreted. Econometrictheory was developedto analyze and interpret economicdata. Mosteconometric theory adapts methodsorigi- nally developedin statistics. Themajor exception to this ruleis theeconometric analysis ofthe identi cation problem and the companionanalyses ofstructural equations, causality ,and eco- nomicpolicy evaluation. Although an economistdid notinvent the phrase,‘ ‘correlationdoes not imply causation,’’1 economistsclari- *Thisresearch was supported by NSF 97-09-873to the University of Chicago.I havebene ted from comments received in discussions with Jeff Biddle, JenniferBoobar ,Ray Fair,Edward Glaeser,ClaudiaGoldin, Lars Hansen, LawrenceKatz, StevenLevitt, Costas Meghir ,JudeaPearl, Jose ´Scheinkman, ChristopherSims, and Edward Vytlacil.For historical background on the Cowles Commission,I haverelied on Christ{1952}, Epstein {1987}, and Morgan {1990}. 1.The phrase is generallyattributed to Karl Pearson. r 2000by thePresident and Fellowsof Harvard Collegeand theMassachusetts Institute of Technology. The Quarterly Journal ofEconomics, February2000 45 46 QUARTERLY JOURNALOF ECONOMICS ed themeaning of causation within well-specied models,the requirementsfor a causal interpretationof an empiricalrelation- ship, and thereasons why acausal frameworkis necessaryfor evaluating economicpolicies. 2 Thefundamental workwas doneby economistsassociated with theCowles Commission. 3 Thelasting legacyof this research programincludes the concepts of exogenous(external) and endoge- nous(internal) variables,and thenotions of ‘ ‘policyinvariant parameters’’ and ‘‘structuralparameters’ ’ whichhave entered everydayparlance inside and outsideof economics. Just as theancient Hebrews were ‘ ‘thepeople of the book,’ ’ economistsare ‘ ‘thepeople of themodel.’ ’ Formaleconomic models arelogically consistent systems within whichhypothetical ‘ ‘thought experiments’’ can beconducted to examine the effects of changes inparametersand constraintson outcomes. Within a model,the effectson outcomes of variationin constraintsfacing agentsin a marketsetting are well de ned. Comparative statics exercises formalizeMarshall’ s notionof a ceterisparibus changewhich is what economistsmean by acausal effect.In his ownwords, Itis sometimessaid that the laws of economicsare ‘ ‘hypothetical.’’ Of course,like every other science, it undertakes to study theeffects which will beproduced by certain causes, not absolutely ,butsubject to the condition thatother things are equal and that the causes are able to work outtheir effectsundisturbed. Almost every scienti c doctrine,when carefully and formallystated, will be found to contain some proviso to the effect that other thingsare equal; the action of the causes in question is supposed to be isolated;certain effects are attributed to them, but only on the hypothesis thatno cause is permitted to enter except those distinctly allowed for {Marshall,1961, p. 36}. The‘ ‘otherthings areequal’ ’ orceteris paribus clauseis a cornerstoneof economicanalysis. Dening causality within amodelis relativelystraightfor- 2.For example, the arti cial intelligence community has just begunto appreciatethe contributions of econometrics to the de nition and identi cation of causalrelationships. See the papers in Glymourand Cooper {1999} and the paper byPearl{1998}. 3.The Cowles Commission was founded by Alfred Cowles to promote the synthesisof mathematics and economics. Cowles and the Cowles Commission playeda leadingrole in creating the Econometric Society .Itwas originally based in ColoradoSprings andhad a looseorganizational arrangement with Colorado College.It relocated to the University of Chicago from 1939 to 1955. See Christ {1952,reprinted 1995}, Epstein {1987}, and Morgan {1990} for valuable histories of econometricsand the role of the Cowles Commission in de ning modern econometrics. CAUSALP ARAMETERSAND POLICY ANALYSIS 47 ward whenthe causes can be independently varied. 4 Dening causality whenthe causes are interrelated is lessstraightforward and is amajorachievement of econometrics. Recovering causal parametersfrom data is notstraightforward. An important contributionof econometric thought was theformalization of the notiondeveloped in philosophy that manydifferent theoretical modelsand hencemany different causal interpretationsmay be consistentwith thesame data. In economics,this is called the problemof identication. The econometric analysis ofthe identi - cationproblem clari es thelimits of purelyempirical knowledge. It makesprecise the idea that correlationis notcausation by using fully specied economicmodels as devicesfor measuring and interpretingcausal parameters.It presentsconditions under whichthe hypothetical variations mentioned in thequotation fromMarshall, orthe structural parameters of well-speci ed economicmodels, can in principle beidenti ed fromdata. Differ- enta prioriassumptions can identify thesame causal parameter oridentify different causal parameters.The key insight in the literatureof twentieth century econometrics was thediscovery of theconditional nature of empirical knowledge. The justi cation forinterpreting an empiricalassociation causally hingeson the assumptionsrequired to identify thecausal parametersfrom the data. Thispaper proceedsin thefollowing way .(1) Theconcept of a causal parameterwithin awell-posed economicmodel is dened in an economicsetting that respectsthe constraints imposed by preferences,endowments, and socialinteractions through mar- kets.By awell-posed economicmodel, I meana modelthat species all ofthe input processes,observed and unobservedby theanalyst, and theirrelationship to outputs. My denition of causal parametersformalizes the quotation from Marshall. This formalizationis amoreappropriate frameworkfor economic causal analysis than otherframeworks developed in statistics that donot recognize constraints, preferences, and socialinterac- tions(i.e., are not based onformal behavioral models). The conceptof identi cation of acausal parameteris discussed using themarket demand-supply examplethat motivatedthinking aboutthe identi cation problem through the rsthalf ofthe twentiethcentury .Thisexample emphasizes the consequences of 4.Marini and Singer {1988} present a valuablesummary of therancorous and confusingdebates about the nature of causallaws developed in model-free elds. 48 QUARTERLY JOURNALOF ECONOMICS interdependenceamong economic agents, but has somespecial featuresthat arenot essential for understanding thefundamental natureof theidenti cation problem. A moregeneral statement of theidenti cation problem is giventhan appears in thepublished literature.The role of causal parametersin policy analysis is claried. (2) Thepaper thenassesses the response in thelarger economicscommunity to the Cowles Commission research pro- gram.The Cowles group developed the linear equation simulta- neousequations model (SEM) that is still presentedin most econometricstextbooks. It extensivelyanalyzed oneform of the identication problem that mosteconomists still thinkof as the identication problem. It focusedattention on estimation of Keynesianmacro models and onthe parameters of market-level supply and demand curves.By themid-1960s theCowles research programwas widely perceivedto be an intellectualsuccess but an empiricalfailure. Thisled totwo radically different responses.The rstwas the VARor‘ ‘innovationaccounting’ ’ programmost often associated with thework of Sims{1972,1977,1980,1986} that objectedto the ‘‘incredible’’ natureof the identifying assumptionsused in the CowlesCommission models and advocated application ofmore looselyspeci ed economicmodels based ondevelopments in the multivariatetime series literature. This research program system- atically incorporatedtime series methods into macroeconometrics and producedmore accurate descriptions of macrodata than did its Cowlespredecessors. Its useof economic theory was less explicit,but it drewon the dynamic economicmodels developed in theseventies and eightiesto motivate its statistical decompositions.