1 Selection from Jonathan Dancy, Introduction to Contemporary

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 Selection from Jonathan Dancy, Introduction to Contemporary Selection from Jonathan Dancy, Introduction to Contemporary themselves. Our initial definition of direct perception may be Epistemology, Blackwell, 1985, pp. 144-174. vague, but it is not so vague as to be useless. We shall take it that a perceiver P directly perceives an object O if P perceives O without perceiving any intermediary I. P would be perceiving an intermediary I if, as things are, it is only in virtue of perceiving I that P perceives O. P’s relation to the intermediary I, if there is 10.2 THEORIES OF PERCEPTION one, need not for these purposes be exactly the same as P’s relation to O, and commonly will not be. The way in which P is There are three main families of theories of perception: direct aware of I need only be analogous to the way in which P is realism, indirect realism and phenomenalism. In this chapter we aware of O. So examples of indirect perception might be one’s will be doing a bit of philosophical geography and picking out perception of oneself in a mirror and one’s perception of an actor the main members of each family and the sorts of considerations on the television. There is in both cases a more immediate object used in their favour and against them. To avoid clutter, I have of awareness, in perceiving which one is said to perceive oneself avoided attributing positions to their main protagonists until the and the actor; the intermediary object, of which one is here references at the end of the chapter, where there is also a map of directly aware, perhaps, is the reflection in one case and the the positions to which it may be helpful to refer. image in the other. First, for an initial grasp of the differences between the three Indirect perception has been defined here in terms of families we need to get a preliminary view of what is meant by analogous sorts of awareness. There will be sorts of awareness realism in this context, and what the contrast is between the which are not perceptual, e.g. the awareness of pain, perhaps, or direct and the indirect. of the position of one’s own limbs. So when we speak of Realism in the theory of perception (which we shall call perception as awareness we must remember the existence of perceptual realism) can be initially but vaguely characterized as non-perceptual awareness. the view that the objects we perceive are able to and commonly Now the dispute between the direct realist and the indirect do exist and retain some at least of the properties we perceive realist concerns the question whether we are ever directly aware them as having, even when they are unperceived. This is to say of the existence and nature of physical objects. Both, as realists, that the existence of the objects we perceive and at least part of agree that the physical objects we see and touch are able to exist their nature is independent of the existence of any perceiver. and retain some of their properties when unperceived. But the This sort of realism looks different from that discussed in 1.4 and indirect realist asserts that we are never directly aware of 9.5, which we shall call metaphysical realism. We shall physical objects; we are only indirectly aware of them, in virtue eventually have to decide how the two sorts of realism are of a direct awareness of an intermediary object (variously related (11.6), but by then our account of perceptual realism will described as an idea, sense-datum, percept or appearance). The have been improved. direct realist denies this claim. The contrast between the direct and the indirect is notoriously Phenomenalism is a form of anti-realism; the phenomenalist slippery and difficult to pin down firmly, as we shall see. It is denies the existence of a physical world lying behind and able to sadly common for philosophers to inveigh against loose use of come apart from the world of experience. For him, the only this contrast in their opponents and then to do little better possible object of awareness is experience and complexes of 1 2 experiences; there is no reality apart from experience. If this is so, then to ‘most’ and so on, but it is simplest for us to view it in the the only objects of awareness are direct objects; there is nothing starkest and most extreme case. left over for us to perceive indirectly. The phenomenalist, then, Opposed to the naïve form of direct realism is scientific direct can be seen as agreeing with the direct realist about the realism. This scientific version takes it that science has shown directness of perception and the absence of intermediaries, but as that physical objects do not retain when unperceived all of the agreeing with the indirect realist that the direct objects of properties we perceive them as having; for some of those perception are not physical objects. This description is properties are dependent for their existence upon the existence of preliminary: it will be revised and, I fear, complicated in 10.6. ... a perceiver. Thus colour, taste, sound and smell, heat and roughness are not independent properties of the object which it [In this section Dancy also argues that even knowledge of our can retain unperceived. The object only has them in relation to own sensory states is fallible. For example, we might think than the perceiver. The scientific direct realist accepts the directness an object appears pink to us, when it actually appears orange. of our perception of the world, but restricts his realism to a Dancy recognises that this is controversial.] special group of properties. The distinction made here is a close relative of Locke’s distinction between primary and secondary qualities (see J. 10.3 DIRECT REALISM Locke, 1961, Bk 2 ch. 8). Locke held that the ‘primary’ qualities of shape, size, molecular texture and motion have a different Direct realism holds that in sense-perception we are directly status from that of the ‘secondary’ qualities such as colour, heat, aware of the existence and nature of the surrounding physical smell, taste etc. (we could call these the ‘sensory’ properties). world. All direct realists agree about this, the directness side of According to Locke, an object which we perceive as coloured things. They differ, however, in the degree of realism they are does not retain when unperceived any quality of the sort we willing to espouse. The realist, in our present sense, holds that perceive it as having. There is a sense in which it remains physical objects are able to exist and retain some at least of the coloured, of course; for its primary properties, which it does properties which we perceive them as having, even when retain, remain such that in suitable conditions it will look unperceived. The crucial phrase is ‘some at least’, and the coloured to the perceiver. An object retains the ‘primary quality question is which, exactly. We shall distinguish two types of ground’ for the secondary qualities it appears as having, then. direct realism, the naïve and the scientific; in the nature of the But colour-as-we-see-it, heat-as-we-feel-it and taste-as-we-taste- case, however, there must be many possible intermediate it are not properties which the object can be said to retain when positions. unperceived; and for that reason we cannot suppose that those The naïve direct realist holds that unperceived objects are able properties are independent properties of the object when it is to retain properties of all the types we perceive them as having. perceived. Colour-as-we-see-it is really more a property of our By this he means that an unperceived object may still have not way of being aware of the physical world than a property of that only a shape and size but also be hot or cold, have a colour, a world itself. taste and a smell, be rough or smooth and make a noise or keep Locke provided a miscellany of arguments for this position. silent. The naïveté of this position lies in the word ‘all’. The He suggested variously that experimental evidence forces it upon position becomes less naïve as ‘all’ retreats to ‘nearly all’ and us, and that the naïve alternative is inconceivable. A weaker 3 4 argument that the appeal to the inconceivability of any 10.4 INDIRECT REALISM alternative is an analogue of Ockham’s razor. This razor is the general principle that we should not multiply entities further than Indirect realism holds that in perception we are indirectly aware necessary; we should not, for instance, admit the existence of of the physical objects around us in virtue of a direct awareness numbers or of other putative sorts of entities unless we have of internal, non-physical objects. literally no alternative. The analogue of this argument in our This is the most straightforward form of indirect realism, and present case is that we should not admit the existence of a sort of it is the one with which this section is concerned. There are property if we can avoid it. Parsimony is always the right attitude further forms of indirect realism which will be mentioned (only in metaphysics, perhaps. And now the appeal to science can to be rejected) in chapter 11. They include the suggestion that we come in. For we can say that the sorts of explanation that are never aware of physical objects, but infer their presence from contemporary physics offers give us no need to suppose that the the nature of the internal objects of which we are (directly) secondary qualities are independent properties of physical aware.
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Chemistry
    Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Chemistry Jaap van Brakel Abstract: In this paper I assess the relation between philosophy of chemistry and (general) philosophy of science, focusing on those themes in the philoso- phy of chemistry that may bring about major revisions or extensions of cur- rent philosophy of science. Three themes can claim to make a unique contri- bution to philosophy of science: first, the variety of materials in the (natural and artificial) world; second, extending the world by making new stuff; and, third, specific features of the relations between chemistry and physics. Keywords : philosophy of science, philosophy of chemistry, interdiscourse relations, making stuff, variety of substances . 1. Introduction Chemistry is unique and distinguishes itself from all other sciences, with respect to three broad issues: • A (variety of) stuff perspective, requiring conceptual analysis of the notion of stuff or material (Sections 4 and 5). • A making stuff perspective: the transformation of stuff by chemical reaction or phase transition (Section 6). • The pivotal role of the relations between chemistry and physics in connection with the question how everything fits together (Section 7). All themes in the philosophy of chemistry can be classified in one of these three clusters or make contributions to general philosophy of science that, as yet , are not particularly different from similar contributions from other sci- ences (Section 3). I do not exclude the possibility of there being more than three clusters of philosophical issues unique to philosophy of chemistry, but I am not aware of any as yet. Moreover, highlighting the issues discussed in Sections 5-7 does not mean that issues reviewed in Section 3 are less im- portant in revising the philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • C.S. Peirce's Abduction from the Prior Analytics
    Providence College DigitalCommons@Providence Community Scholar Publications Providence College Community Scholars 7-1996 C.S. Peirce's Abduction from the Prior Analytics William Paul Haas Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.providence.edu/comm_scholar_pubs Haas, William Paul, "C.S. Peirce's Abduction from the Prior Analytics" (1996). Community Scholar Publications. 2. https://digitalcommons.providence.edu/comm_scholar_pubs/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Providence College Community Scholars at DigitalCommons@Providence. It has been accepted for inclusion in Community Scholar Publications by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Providence. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WILLIAM PAUL HAAS July 1996 C.S. PEIRCE'S ABDUCTION FROM THE PRIOR ANALYTICS In his Ancient Formal Logic. Professor Joseph Bochenski finds Aristotle's description of syllogisms based upon hypotheses to be "difficult to understand." Noting that we do not have the treatise which Aristotle promised to write, Bochenski laments the fact that the Prior Analytics, where it is treated most explicitly, "is either corrupted or (which is more probable) was hastily written and contains logical errors." (1) Charles Sanders Peirce wrestled with the same difficult text when he attempted to establish the Aristotelian roots of his theory of abductive or hypothetical reasoning. However, Peirce opted for the explanation that the fault was with the corrupted text, not with Aristotle's exposition. Peirce interpreted the text of Book II, Chapter 25 thus: Accordingly, when he opens the next chapter with the word ' Ajray (¿y-q a word evidently chosen to form a pendant to 'Errctyuyrj, we feel sure that this is what he is coming to.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Visual Motion Perception Shows Hallmarks of Bayesian Structural Inference Sichao Yang1,2,6*, Johannes Bill3,4,6*, Jan Drugowitsch3,5,7 & Samuel J
    www.nature.com/scientificreports OPEN Human visual motion perception shows hallmarks of Bayesian structural inference Sichao Yang1,2,6*, Johannes Bill3,4,6*, Jan Drugowitsch3,5,7 & Samuel J. Gershman4,5,7 Motion relations in visual scenes carry an abundance of behaviorally relevant information, but little is known about how humans identify the structure underlying a scene’s motion in the frst place. We studied the computations governing human motion structure identifcation in two psychophysics experiments and found that perception of motion relations showed hallmarks of Bayesian structural inference. At the heart of our research lies a tractable task design that enabled us to reveal the signatures of probabilistic reasoning about latent structure. We found that a choice model based on the task’s Bayesian ideal observer accurately matched many facets of human structural inference, including task performance, perceptual error patterns, single-trial responses, participant-specifc diferences, and subjective decision confdence—especially, when motion scenes were ambiguous and when object motion was hierarchically nested within other moving reference frames. Our work can guide future neuroscience experiments to reveal the neural mechanisms underlying higher-level visual motion perception. Motion relations in visual scenes are a rich source of information for our brains to make sense of our environ- ment. We group coherently fying birds together to form a fock, predict the future trajectory of cars from the trafc fow, and infer our own velocity from a high-dimensional stream of retinal input by decomposing self- motion and object motion in the scene. We refer to these relations between velocities as motion structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction Meta-Ethical Speculations About Rights and Obligations
    NON-NATURALISM REVISITED; RIGHTS/OBLIGA TIONS AS EMERGENT ENTITIES Eike-Henner W. KLUGE University of Victoria Introduction Meta-ethical speculations about rights and obligations. as indeed meta-ethical speculations in general, are characterized by profound disagreement over the nature of the relevant terms. I Broadly spea­ king, we can distinguish three general types of approaches: realism, nominalism and non-cognitivism.2 Each of these occurs in several variations. For instance, realism may be naturalistic - which is to say, it may attempt to reduce the relevant expressions to claims dealing with ordinary properties; or it may be non-naturalistic - which is to say, it may claim that wh at ultimately grounds such expressions are properties sui generis: distinct from ordinary ones but ontologically on a par with them. 3 Nominalism, in turn, may analyze right/obligation locutions as statements about (explicit or implicit) contractual agreements, or as reportive of custom, convention or habit - but in any case will view their meanings as a matter of pure convention.4 Non-cognitivism, finally, may be either emotive, attitudinal or performative in focus - or any combination of these- 1. Cf. W.K. Frankena, Ethies (Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, 1963) pp. 4 ff. and "Recent Conceptions of Morality" in H.-N. Castaöeda and George Nakhnikian, eds. Morality and the Language 0/ Conduet (Wayne State U. Press, Detroit, 1965) pp. 1-24, and R.ß. Brandt, Ethieal Theory (Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N.J. 1959) pp. 7-10 et passim. Brandt also refers to it as "critical ethics". 2. This nomenclature is not quite that currently in vogue.
    [Show full text]
  • Pre-Lecture Notes I.4 – Measuring the Unobservable Think About All of The
    Pre-lecture Notes I.4 – Measuring the Unobservable Think about all of the issues that psychologists are interested in – these include depression, anxiety, attention, memory, problem-solving abilities, interpersonal attribution, etc. Notice how many of these cannot be directly observed; they are characteristics of the mind, not behavior, and, as of now, we don’t have a way of reading people’s minds. Given that psychology is an empirical science and, therefore, relies upon objective and replicable data, this is a problem. One option, of course, is to disallow any discussion of anything that cannot be directly observed. Under this approach, you would never talk about something like depression, since it cannot be observed. Instead, you would only talk about the behavioral manifestations (or symptoms) of depression, because these can be observed. This is the approach taken by behaviorists and some neo-behaviorists. The other approach, which is taken by a large majority of psychologists, is to create ways to convert or translate unobservable constructs, such as depression, into observable behaviors, such as responses on a questionnaire. In some cases, this translation is almost too obvious to discuss, such as defining the amount of time that it takes a person to mentally solve a problem as the lag or delay between the moment when they were given the problem and the moment when they give the (correct) answer. In other cases, however, which includes the definition of depression as the condensed score on a specific questionnaire, quite a bit of discussion and background research is needed. This brings us to the first of the four types of validity that determine the value or quality of psychological research.
    [Show full text]
  • On Entanglement of Fact and Value in the Views of Hilary Putnam , "Kultura I Wartości" 2018, No
    Rosiak-Zi ęba, E., On Entanglement of Fact and Value in the Views of Hilary Putnam , "Kultura i Wartości" 2018, No. 25, pp. 69-84; 31 July 2018 (ISSN 2299-7806). doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.17951/kw.2018.25.69. Available at: <https://journals.umcs.pl/kw/article/download/6389/5425>. Retrieved: 01 August 2018. On Entanglement of Fact and Value in the Views of Hilary Putnam Ewa Rosiak-Zi ęba https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9090-7308 Pobrane z czasopisma http://kulturaiwartosci.journals.umcs.pl Data: 01/08/2018 10:06:27 Kultura i Wartości ISSN 2299-7806 Nr 25/2018 http://dx.doi.org/10.17951/kw.2018.25.69 On Entanglement of Fact and Value in the Views of Hilary Putnam Ewa Rosiak-Zięba https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9090-7308 The subject of this paper is the analysis of Hilary Putnam’s thesis on the fact/value entanglement along with some of his arguments meant to corroborate this stance. One of his main objectives of putting forward this thesis is reconciliation of science and values, bringing an end to the picture of the former as a ‘value-free zone’. While Putnam’s polemics with standpoints conflicted with his own one are carried out in quite a comprehensive way, the way he formulates some of his constructive arguments meant to augment his own stance are a bit enigmatic. The goal of this paper is to clarify some of them. The first part of this paper briefly outlines Putnam’s arguments aiming to undermine the fact/value dichotomy, which is contradictory to the thesis title.
    [Show full text]
  • AFRREV STECH, Vol
    AFRREV STECH, Vol. 1 (2) April-July, 2012 AFRREV STECH An International Journal of Science and Technology Bahir Dar, Ethiopia Vol.1 (2) April-July, 2012:32-44 ISSN 2225-8612 (Print) ISSN 2227-5444 (Online) The Woes of Scientific Realism Okeke, Jonathan C. Department of Philosophy University of Calabar, Calabar, Cross Rivers State, Nigeria [email protected] & Kanu, Ikechukwu Anthony Department of Philosophy University of Nigeria, Nsukka, Enugu State, Nigeria [email protected] Phone: +2348036345466 Abstract This paper investigated the disagreement between Realists and Anti-realists on the observable and unobservable distinction in scientific practice. While 32 Copyright © IAARR 2012: www.afrrevjo.net/stech AFRREV STECH, Vol. 1 (2) April-July, 2012 the realists maintain that machines and gadgets can simulate the human act of perception there-by making all realities under the screen of science observable, the anti-realists or the instrumentalists insist that what cannot be observed with the human senses even if detected with gadgets are not observable. This paper contended against the realist position which says that machines can simulate the human activity of perception. Hence the distinction between what is observable and unobservable is shown to be indisputable. Introduction In metaphysics there is a long standing argument between followers of realism (the view that the physical world exists independently of human thought and perception) and the apologists of idealism (the view that the existence of the physical world is dependent on human perception) (Ozumba, 2001). Realism is further broken down to three different types: ultra or transcendental realism which Plato represents, and which holds that the real things exist in a realm other than this physical one (Copleston, 1985).
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Realism and Phenomenology Through the Case Study of Autism
    Scientific Realism and Phenomenology Through the Case Study of Autism Themistoklis Pantazakos UCL Submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy January 2019 1 Declaration I, Themistoklis Pantazakos, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. 2 Acknowledgements Acknowledgements is the graceful place within a philosophy doctorate where one does not have to provide sustained argument for absolutely anything. I will then take it for granted that we live in a culture celebrating individual achievement while displaying profound illiteracy on the topic of relating collectively. Ironically, it is also true that no achievement has one owner, especially so in the case of intellectual achievement. If anything of value is to be found in the following dissertation, it should be attributed to many authors. First, to pretty much everyone within the STS department at UCL for creating such a collaborative and accommodating atmosphere to work in. Especially so to Julia Sánchez- Dorado, who kept showing me the ropes from my first day until her graduation, and who repeatedly provided company in times of inevitable academic awkwardness. Moreover, to my intellectual centre in Athens, the pop culture and critical studies magazine SKRA- punk, for providing both a stimulating and cosy space to work in, the invaluable companionship of its members, and a sense of belonging in times when the fear of being constantly left out of an elusive ‘we’ is at its social highest. This dissertation should also be attributed to my friends, double so to those doubling as commenters and editors.
    [Show full text]
  • Causality Causality Refers to the Relationship
    Causality Causality refers to the relationship between events where one set of events (the effects) is a direct consequence of another set of events (the causes). Causal inference is the process by which one can use data to make claims about causal relationships. Since inferring causal relationships is one of the central tasks of science, it is a topic that has been heavily debated in philosophy, statistics, and the scientific disciplines. In this article, we review the models of causation and tools for causal inference most prominent in the social sciences, including regularity approaches, associated with David Hume, and counterfactual models, associated with Jerzy Neyman, Donald Rubin, and David Lewis, among many others. One of the most notable developments in the study of causation is the increasing unification of disparate methods around a common conceptual and mathematical language that treats causality in counterfactual terms---i.e., the Neyman- Rubin model. We discuss how counterfactual models highlight the deep challenges involved in making the move from correlation to causation, particularly in the social sciences where controlled experiments are relatively rare. Regularity Models of Causation Until the advent of counterfactual models, causation was primarily defined in terms of observable phenomena. It was philosopher David Hume in the eighteenth century who began the modern tradition of regularity models of causation by defining causation in terms of repeated “conjunctions” of events. In An Enquiry into Human Understanding (1751), Hume argued that the labeling of two particular events as being causally related rested on an untestable metaphysical assumption. Consequently, Hume argued that causality could only be adequately defined in terms of empirical regularities involving classes of events.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume on Unobservable Entities
    Hume on unobservable entities Silvio Seno Chibeni Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, State University of Campinas (UNICAMP), Campinas, SP, Brazil [email protected] Abstract: It is generally acknowledged by both philosophers of science and by Hume scholars that Hume’s classic analysis of perceptions and knowledge of matters of fact push strongly toward scepticism about unobservable entities, such as those typically postulated in theories of the natural sciences. Intriguingly, though, Hume has not only written approvingly of certain scientific theories referring to unobservable objects, but also introduced himself several hypotheses about unobservable entities and processes in his own “science of man”. This article aims to pinpoint and comment some of the main passages of his works in which Hume appears to take a positive stance toward unobservables, in certain particular instances. If correct, this analysis would constitute a piece of evidence against the usual belief that the empiricist epistemological theory developed by Hume would constitute an impeditive framework for any form of scientific realism. Key-words: David Hume; empiricism; scientific hypotheses; scientific realism; unobservable entities; natural philosophy. Hume sobre entidades inobserváveis Resumo: Constitui opinião comum entre filósofos da ciência e historiadores da filosofia moderna que a clássica análise de Hume da percepção e do conhecimento de questões de fato que escapam ao testemunho dos sentidos aponta fortemente para o ceticismo quanto ao conhecimento de entidades inobserváveis, como as que são tipicamente postuladas por teorias das ciências naturais. Não obstante, Hume não apenas expressou aprovação a certas teorias científicas que putativamente se referem a itens inobserváveis como também introduziu, ele próprio, diversas hipóteses sobre entidades e processos inobserváveis em sua “ciência do homem”.
    [Show full text]
  • Defending Phenomenalism
    Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/pq/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/pq/pqy064/5266887 by National University of Singapore user on 28 February 2019 The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 00,No.02018 ISSN 0031-8094 doi: 10.1093/pq/pqy064 DEFENDING PHENOMENALISM By Michael Pelczar According to phenomenalism, physical things are a certain kind of possibility for experience. This paper clarifies the phenomenalist position and addresses some main objections to it, with the aim of showing that phenomenalism is a live option that merits a place alongside dualism and materialism in contemporary metaphysical debate. Keywords: metaphysics, idealism, phenomenalism. I. THE MILLIAN PICTURE We all have perceptual experiences, which, taken together, present a subjective appearance of objects and events existing in a common time and space. In Leib- niz’s famous image, our experiences are like different perspective-drawings of the same landscape. They are, John Foster puts it, world-suggestive.1 Ordinarily, we attribute the world-suggestiveness of our experiences to the fact that we all inhabit the same world, encounter objects in a common space, and witness events in a common time. J.S. Mill thought that this way of thinking, while correct as far as it goes, misses out on a deeper truth. Yes, we have bodies with such-and-such physical features, embedded in such-and-such physical environments, and, yes, there’s an explanation for the regularities in our experience to be found in all that. But, at a more basic level, the world we perceive doesn’t explain the world-suggestive quality of our experiences: it is the world-suggestive quality of our experiences, or rather: it’s the tendency for experiences to occur in a world-suggestive way, given that they occur at all.
    [Show full text]
  • Causal Inference in Statistics: an Overview∗†‡
    Statistics Surveys Vol. 3 (2009) 96–146 ISSN: 1935-7516 DOI: 10.1214/09-SS057 Causal inference in statistics: An overview∗†‡ Judea Pearl Computer Science Department University of California, Los Angeles, CA 90095 USA e-mail: [email protected] Abstract: This review presents empirical researcherswith recent advances in causal inference, and stresses the paradigmatic shifts that must be un- dertaken in moving from traditional statistical analysis to causal analysis of multivariate data. Special emphasis is placed on the assumptions that un- derly all causal inferences, the languages used in formulating those assump- tions, the conditional nature of all causal and counterfactual claims, and the methods that have been developed for the assessment of such claims. These advances are illustrated using a general theory of causation based on the Structural Causal Model (SCM) described in Pearl (2000a), which subsumes and unifies other approaches to causation, and provides a coher- ent mathematical foundation for the analysis of causes and counterfactuals. In particular, the paper surveys the development of mathematical tools for inferring (from a combination of data and assumptions) answers to three types of causal queries: (1) queries about the effects of potential interven- tions, (also called “causal effects” or “policy evaluation”) (2) queries about probabilities of counterfactuals, (including assessment of “regret,” “attri- bution” or “causes of effects”) and (3) queries about direct and indirect effects (also known as “mediation”). Finally, the paper defines the formal and conceptual relationships between the structural and potential-outcome frameworks and presents tools for a symbiotic analysis that uses the strong features of both. Keywords and phrases: Structuralequation models, confounding,graph- ical methods, counterfactuals, causal effects, potential-outcome, mediation, policy evaluation, causes of effects.
    [Show full text]