Hegelianism and Christianity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hegelianism and Christianity Hegelianism and Christianity John H. Gerstner, Jr. John Oman has written : .. We God." are waiting today for some change in There was one thing more surpris philosophy away from Helegianism ing than the stupendousness of Hegel's and the process of thought as the key claim and that was that his contempor to the universe, corresponding to the aries believed it! But they did, and movement of science away from New- following a period of philosophical tonianism, with its assumption of the inebriation came the morning after laws of motion as the efficient cause and then the revulsion from which, it of things."^ This statement reveals seems, philosophers are still suttering. two : that Hegel is still things first, When this revulsion set in, the phi with that men who us, and, second, losophers not only threw out Hegel's think as Oman thinks wish he were with Hegel's wash, but they not. baby threw out Hegel too. And it is proving Hegel's influence has been greatly veiy difticult for him to get back again. under-rated precisely because his own Hence, we hear much disparagement claims were so greatly over-stated. and little appreciation. Xevertheless, Xever in the history of thought did though Hegel's name may be anath any man profess such exhaustive ema, many of his ideas, as Oman sug knowledge and practical omniscience. gests, have become sacred. F. L. that master of verbal Patton, Let us comment briefly on the : "When caricature, states it this way Hegelianism of two of the world's the Zopliar the Naamathite put ques outstanding philosophers, A. N. tion to his class, 'Who by searching Whitehead and John iJewey. Op can find out God?' an amid Hegelian, posed as each of these men is to tiie the silence of the school, courageously Absolute Idealism of Hegel, they held his hand."^ : as up Again "Here, nevertheless show striking alfinity for is a o- a witty writer suggests, catasti his fundamental viewpoint. The the reverse of that of the phe Korah; German philosopher was most char earth has not swallowed the up man, acteristically dissatisfied with any the man has swallowed the but up thing lurking behind phenomena. universe."-' Unfortunately, though Thus, he refuted the substance theory no one is Hegel explained everything of Spinoza, the thing-in-itself of Kant can It seems sure he explain Hegel. and the absolute of Schelling. As that a student a to brought passage Weber has stated : "In Hegel, the for and the Hegel explanation philos absolute is the process itself; it does : "When that opher replied passage not produce movement and life, it is was there were two who knew written, movement and life.""^ For Whitehead its �God and Xow, meaning myself. and Dewey also process is reality. In that is alas! there is but one, and the former's Process and Reality existence and the natural order are 1 Naturalism and Supernaturalism, (Macmillan. ultimate, and God, if anything, ap 1931), pp. 107-108. pears to be its product, certainly not 2 Fundamental Christianity, (Macmillan, 1926), p. 38. 3 Harris. Samuel The Self-Revelation of God, 4 Weber and Perry, History of Philosophy, 406. (Scribners, 1887), p. 260. (Scribners, 1925), p. HEGELIAXISM AND CHRISTIANITY 139 its producer. Dewey's Quest for Cer was the God-man in a unique sense.^ tainty is significant here. He deplores Biedermann supplemented Hegel by the philosophical endeavor to find teaching that religious faith was a abiding ideas and prefers to believe distinct element not to be equated in the world as flux or process. Thus with or dissolved by reason. But this Dewey finds uncertainty, and Hegel a faith presupposes revelation which it kind of certainty, but the important discerns immediately. H. R. Mac thing is that they look in the same intosh in Types of Modern Philosophy place. All of these philosophers find describes Biedermann as the philos- nothing behind phenomena. oi^her "who meant to be as Hegelian Hegel's influence is by no means as possible, but always found Christ restricted to philosophical circles. ianity breaking in.'"' The Rather, as Dr. Brightman says : radical wing found in Feuer- bach and Strauss their ablest and It speaks well for the power of reason today that most Feuer- Hegel is still an influence in the world of affairs. devastating exponents. No Hegel, no Marx-Engels-Lenin ; no commun bach reduced the absolute to man's ism and no socialist critique of communist dogma. size and ultimately, as a materialist, No Hegel, no Nazi theory of the state and no rejected all ideas including those of Liebert to indict it. No no Gentile to or Hegel, God which he called "Wunchwesen" ganize the Fascist system of education and no or wishful In Strauss's Croce to defy Mussolini. It is from Hegel that thinking. Royce received much of his inspiration ; from Leben Jesu, the pictures of Hegel have Hegel that Dewey took bis start, and to Hegel become the "myths'" of Christianity. he still looks as the of the greatest systematic In iilaiih^ nsleJirc, religion in general philosophers. 5 seems to lose its savor. Finally Nevertheless, our concern in this Strauss asks himself, "Are we still paper is with Hegel's significance in Christians?" and answers: "If we the realm of religion. Himself always would have our yea yea and our nay an avowed Lutheran, Hegel's philos nay, in short, if we would speak as ophy of Christianity was Janus-faced. honest, upright men, we must acknowl His identification of the content of edge that we are no longer Christ religion and of philosophy could be ians."^ Pfleiderer points out Strauss' evaluated diversely. If one is im significance in the histoiy of Hegel pressed with the rational bulwark thus ianism. for as is provided religion, Hocking, Two previous works upon Immortality, the au is If one is the effect conservative. thors of which are Richter and Feuerbach, were impressed with the complete rational reckoned among the Hegelian school, had indeed, the izing of religion, the effect is radical. by radical negative conclusions therein reached by the application of this Ahnost after Hegel the philosophy, immediately shaken the confidence generally felt in Hegelian chose sides, . theologians up forming orthodoxy; but . produced no very important themselves into right and left wing effect. When, however, Strauss brouglit the Hegelians. heavy artillery of his criticism, distinguished equally by learning and penetration, to bear, first, the conservatives. Daub and Among on the historical foundations of the dogma itself Biedermann are especially examples. the unsubstantial fabric of Hegelian dogmatism Daub could write that the sig-nificance was within a few years completely destroyed.9 of ( hiist was that he exhibited the 6 The eternal incarnation of God and re Pfleiderer, Otto, Development of Theol ogy, (Macmillan, 1890), p. 132. of the world in his own demption 7 H. R. Macintosh, Types of Modern Philos- Thus he pei'son as a historical fact. ohpy. p. 133. 8 Quoted in Smith, H. B., Faith and Philosophy, S Amer In Wieman, H. N., and B. E. Meland, (Scribner, Armstrong & Co., 1877), p. 469. 9 ican Philfl'snphii's of Religion, (Willett, Clark & The Development of Theology. (Macmillan, Co., 1936), p. 319. 1890), p. 132. 140 JOHN H. GERSTNER, JJl. In England Hegelianism prevailed shall see, to overcome them by his in a pure form at Oxford, but was famous dialectical method�thesis and gradually watered down. In the class antithesis taken up into {aufgehohen) room, Dr, Brightman once gave his a higher synthesis. Kierkegaard was rating of some of the British thinkers the policeman who, as soon as he saw and this is the score if my notes do the philosophical machine begin to not fail me: Bradley and Bosanquet, grind its gears, blew his whistle, 100% Hegelian ; Pringle-Pattison, "Stop !" He was the champion of the 60%; Sorley, 40%; Ward, 0%. Dr, unresolved contradiction. For Hegel Ralph Barton Perry, rather more glee religion was whole thought; for Kier ful than sad, has a similar story to kegaard it was shattered thought. tell: Hegel relied on rationality; Kierke gaard cast himself upon the irrational. Thus the weakness of Hegel, from the later deified the intellect Kierke idealistic point of view, lies not in his general Hegel ; crucified it. For programme, but in the fact that he boldly set gaard Hegel religion about carrying it out. He made too many pos was a steady climb; for Kierkegaard itive assertions. The fact that Hegel did make it was a frantic leap.^^ assertions about about positive natural evolution, For all historical development, and about international Kierkegaard's earnestness, we doubt that he ever liberated politics, accounts for the fact that his philosophy truly was of vital consequence, and to many a source himself from rationalism. As John of inspiration. But today no one is more ready Wild has pointed out.^^ Kierkegaard than the idealist to point out that Hegel made asserts the good is unknowable and the mistake of forcing 'psychological' categories paradoxical. But this is belied upon nature and history. He tried to deduce the by two : he makes no actual cosmic process from the laws of spirit; things first, appeal and it is now generally conceded that he failed. to anything other than reason. Sec Everyone but the idealist explains his failure by ond, his three stages imply that man the falsity of the project itself; but he attributes naturally comes to a knowledge of the it to the fact that Hegel's categories of spin; were not purely logicalA^ good. The spiritual seed of Kierkegaard, Josiah H, Howison Royce, George Earth and Brunner, show the same and William E.
Recommended publications
  • Hegelian Phenomenology and the Critique of Reason and Society Peter Osborne
    Hegelian Phenomenology and the Critique of Reason and Society Peter Osborne Abhot Terrasson has rema~cked that if the size of a volume be measured not by the number of its pages but by the time required for mastering it, it can be said of many a book, that it would be much shorter if it were not so short. (Kant, Preface'to First Edition, Critique of Pure Reason) Gillian Qnse's Hegel Contra Sociology (Athlone Press, of Hegel's thought which focuses on the socio­ 1981, £6.95 pb, 26lpp) would be much shorter were it political significance of his idea of speculative not so short. It is unashamedly, and sadly, an experience. extremely difficult book; not just in terms of the The argument is that Marx's critique of Hegel is complexity and subtlety of the position it puts for­ based on a Fichtean reading of his system which fails ward, but, primarily, in terms of the way in which to grasp the true meaning of his concepts of actual­ this position is presented. But it is, nonetheless, ity and spirit, and that in fact these concepts pro­ in many ways an important book. For it challenges, vide the theoretical basis for the conceptualisation at a fundamental level, the generally accepted frame­ of the subjective mediations of objective social work within which Hegel has been interpreted; and, forms. Marx's own conception of practical material­ in so doing, it challenges accepted beliefs not only ism is seen as theoretically incapable of.conceptual­ about the relationship between Marx and Hegel, but ising such mediations, since it involv~s abstract also about the philosophical adequacy of Marxism and dichotomies between being and consciousness, and the redundancy of Hegelianism.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Poststructuralism Understanding Movements in Modern Thought Series Editor: Jack Reynolds
    understanding poststructuralism Understanding Movements in Modern Thought Series Editor: Jack Reynolds Th is series provides short, accessible and lively introductions to the major schools, movements and traditions in philosophy and the history of ideas since the beginning of the Enlightenment. All books in the series are written for undergraduates meeting the subject for the fi rst time. Published Understanding Existentialism Understanding Virtue Ethics Jack Reynolds Stan van Hooft Understanding Poststructuralism James Williams Forthcoming titles include Understanding Empiricism Understanding Hermeneutics Robert Meyers Lawrence Schmidt Understanding Ethics Understanding Naturalism Tim Chappell Jack Ritchie Understanding Feminism Understanding Phenomenology Peta Bowden and Jane Mummery David Cerbone Understanding German Idealism Understanding Rationalism Will Dudley Charlie Heunemann Understanding Hegelianism Understanding Utilitarianism Robert Sinnerbrink Tim Mulgan understanding poststructuralism James Williams For Richard and Olive It is always about who you learn from. © James Williams, 2005 Th is book is copyright under the Berne Convention. No reproduction without permission. All rights reserved. First published in 2005 by Acumen Acumen Publishing Limited 15a Lewins Yard East Street Chesham Bucks HP5 1HQ www.acumenpublishing.co.uk ISBN 1-84465-032-4 (hardcover) ISBN 1-84465-033-2 (paperback) Work on Chapter 3 was supported by British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel and Chinese Marxism
    DOI: 10.4312/as.2019.7.1.55-73 55 Hegel and Chinese Marxism Tom ROCKMORE*1 Abstract China is presently embarking on the huge task of realizing what President Xi Jinping recently called the Chinese Dream. China is officially Marxist, and Marx thus inspires this dream in his assigned status as the “official guide” to the ongoing Chinese Revolution. This paper will focus on the crucial relation between Hegel and Chinese Marxism. Marx is a key Hegelian, critical of, but strongly dependent on, Hegel. Since the Chinese Dream is not Hegelian, but rather anti-Hegelian, it is unlikely, as I will be arguing, to be realized in a recognizably Marxian form. Keywords: Hegel, China, Marxism, Marx, Engels Hegel in kitajski marksizem Izvleček Kitajska se podaja na pot uresničitve projekta, ki ga je predsednik Xi Jinping pred kratkim imenoval »kitajske sanje«. Kitajska je uradno marksistična in Marx zaradi statusa »urad- nega vodiča« sedanje kitajske revolucije, ki so mu ga pripisali, navdihuje te sanje. Članek se bo osredotočil na ključno razmerje med Heglom in kitajskim marksizmom. Marx je ključni hegelianec, ki do Hegla ni le kritičen, ampak je tudi odvisen od njega. »Kitajske sanje« pa niso hegelianske, temveč prej antihegelianske, zato je, kot bo razloženo, malo verjetno, da se bodo uresničile v prepoznavno marksistični obliki. Ključne besede: Hegel, Kitajska, Marxism, Marx, Engels * Tom ROCKMORE, Department of Philosophy, Peking University, China. Email address: rockmore[at]duq.edu AS_2019_1_FINAL.indd 55 31.1.2019 10:48:34 56 Tom ROCKMORE: Hegel and Chinese Marxism On the Relation of Marx and Hegel Marx’s followers as well as his critics tend to approach him through Marxism.
    [Show full text]
  • Love and the Knowledge of God in Augustine's De Trinitate
    LOVE AND THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD IN AUGUSTINE'S DE TRINITATE LOVE AND THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD IN AUGUSTINE'S DE TRINITATE By MARTIN WESTERHOLM, B.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts McMaster University © Copyright by Martin Westerholm, August 2009 MASTER OF ARTS (2009) McMaster University (Religious Studies) Hamilton, ON TITLE: Love and the Knowledge of God in Augustine's De Trinitate AUTHOR: Martin Westerholm, B.A. (McMaster University) SUPERVISOR: Professor P. Travis Kroeker NUMBER OF PAGES: v, 130 11 Abstract: This thesis offers a close reading of Augustine's De Trinitate that is aimed at addressing the vexed question of the unity of the work. The most influential 20th century interpretation of De Trinitate holds that Augustine moves from a theological examination of the nature of the Trinity based on scripture to a philosophical investigation based on the structure of the human mind. This interpretation has led to the misconceptions that Augustine espouses a form of natural theology and separates theological doctrine from the concerns of the practical life. This thesis shows that De Trinitate is unified around the methodological rule that only the mind that loves God is capable of knowing him. This means, first, that Augustine's procedure is improperly characterized as natural theology; and, second, that, in making love a prerequisite for, and means to, knowledge of God, the ethical question of the ordering of love is inseparable from doctrinal concerns. This thesis shows that De Trinitate offers a coherent and compelling moral ontology in which the perceived tensions in Augustine'S theology of love can be reconciled.
    [Show full text]
  • The Outcome of Classical German Philosophy History 71600/CL
    The Outcome of Classical German Philosophy History 71600/CL 85000/PSC Prof. Wolin (GC 5114) Fall 2019 [email protected] Mon. 6:30-8:30 Room: GC ?? In 1886, Friedrich Engels wrote a perfectly mediocre book, Ludwig Feuerbach and the Outcome of Classical German Philosophy, which nevertheless managed to raise a fascinating and important question that is still being debated today: how should we go about evaluating the legacy of German Idealism following the mid-nineteenth century breakdown of the Hegelian system? For Engels, the answer was relatively simple: the rightful heir of classical German philosophy was Marx’s doctrine of historical materialism. But, in truth, Engels’ response was merely one of many possible approaches. Nor would it be much of an exaggeration to claim that, in the twentieth century, there is hardly a philosopher worth reading who has not sought to define him or herself via a confrontation with the legacy of Kant and Hegel. Classical German Philosophy – Kant, Fichte, Hegel, and Schelling – has bequeathed a rich legacy of reflection on the fundamental problems of epistemology, ontology and aesthetics. Even contemporary thinkers who claim to have transcended it (e.g., poststructuralists such as Foucault and Derrida) cannot help but make reference to it in order to validate their post- philosophical standpoints and claims. Our approach to this very rich material will combine a reading of the canonical texts of German Idealism (e.g., Kant and Hegel) with a sustained and complementary focus on major twentieth-century thinkers who have sought to establish their originality via a critical reading of Hegel and his heirs: Alexandre Kojève, Martin Heidegger, Michel Foucault, Theodor Adorno, and Jürgen Habermas.
    [Show full text]
  • 210 the Genesis of Neo-Kantianism
    SYNTHESIS PHILOSOPHICA Book Reviews / Buchbesprechungen 61 (1/2016) pp. (207–220) 210 doi: 10.21464/sp31116 of his book is that the movement’s origins are to be found already in the 1790s, in the Frederick Charles Beiser works of Jakob Friedrich Fries, Johann Frie- drich Herbart, and Friedrich Eduard Beneke. They constitute “the lost tradition” which pre- The Genesis of served the “empiricist-psychological” side of Neo-Kantianism Kant’s thought, his dualisms, and things-in- themselves against the excessive speculative idealism of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel who Oxford University Press, tried to rehabilitate the dogmatic rationalist Oxford 2014 metaphysics of Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff after Kant’s critical project. Frederick Charles Beiser, professor of phi- The first chapter of the first part (pp. 23–88) losophy at Syracuse University (USA) whose is concerned with the philosophy of Fries field of expertise is the modern German phi- who tried to base philosophy on empirical losophy, is one of the most erudite historians psychology, and epistemology on psychol- of philosophy today. His first book The Fate ogy which could recognize the synthetic a of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant priori but not prove it. His book Reinhold, to Fichte (1987) didn’t only present a fresh Fichte und Schelling (1803) saw the history account of German philosophy at the end of of philosophy after Kant as the “struggle of th the 18 century, but it also introduced a new rationalism to free itself from the limits of method of historical research. His more re- the critique”. In his political philosophy Fries cent works, starting with The German His- was an anti-Semite, but gave the leading role toricist Tradition (2011) until the most recent to public opinion which could correct even Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philoso- the ruler, although he encountered problems phy, 1860–1900 (2016), have focused on the in trying to reconcile his liberal views with th main currents of the 19 century German the social injustice that liberalism created.
    [Show full text]
  • Religion and Representation in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 11-2017 The perversion of the absolute: religion and representation in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit Thomas Floyd Wright DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Wright, Thomas Floyd, "The perversion of the absolute: religion and representation in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit" (2017). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 240. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/240 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PERVERSION OF THE ABSOLUTE Religion and Representation in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit A Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2017 BY Thomas Floyd Wright Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, Illinois Contents 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Hegel contra Theology . 1 1.2 Marx, Ante-Hegel . 5 1.3 Hegel, post Hegel mortum . 11 1.4 Speculation and perversion . 16 2 The perversion of identity 22 2.1 The evil of ontotheology . 22 2.2 The perversion of desire: Augustine . 26 2.3 The perversion of speech: Hobbes . 30 2.4 The perversion of reason: Kant .
    [Show full text]
  • Subjectivity and Critique : a Study of the Paradigm Shift in Critical Theory.”
    “Subjectivity and Critique : A Study of the Paradigm Shift in Critical Theory.” by Alexander Reynolds A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Government Department of the London School of Economics, February 1995. UMI Number: U079B09 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Dissertation Publishing UMI U079B09 Published by ProQuest LLC 2014. Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 F 720 2_ 2 Abstract of thesis. The German social-philosophical tradition of Critical Theory has recently undergone what its current practitioners have themselves described as a “paradigm shift”. Writers like Jurgen Habermas and Kari-Otto Apel are today attempting to reformulate the socially-critica! insights of Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno in new terms. Where Horkheimer and Adorno had tried to articulate their critique of existing social relations in a language of “subjectivity” and “objectivity” drawn largely from the classical German philosophical tradition, Habermas and Apel are trying to formulate an - ostensibly - similar critique in a language of “a priori intersubjectivity” drawn from the “ordinary language” and “speech-act" theory which has emerged since the Second World War in the Anglo-American philosophical sphere.
    [Show full text]
  • Traveling Theory: Fredric Jameson's Interpretations of the Cultural Revolution and Maoism
    CLCWeb: Comparative Literature and Culture ISSN 1481-4374 Purdue University Press ©Purdue University Volume 20 (2018) Issue 3 Article 5 Traveling Theory: Fredric Jameson’s Interpretations of the Cultural Revolution and Maoism Xian Wang University of Notre Dame Follow this and additional works at: https://docs.lib.purdue.edu/clcweb Part of the American Studies Commons, Chinese Studies Commons, Comparative Literature Commons, and the European Languages and Societies Commons Dedicated to the dissemination of scholarly and professional information, Purdue University Press selects, develops, and distributes quality resources in several key subject areas for which its parent university is famous, including business, technology, health, veterinary medicine, and other selected disciplines in the humanities and sciences. CLCWeb: Comparative Literature and Culture, the peer-reviewed, full-text, and open-access learned journal in the humanities and social sciences, publishes new scholarship following tenets of the discipline of comparative literature and the field of cultural studies designated as "comparative cultural studies." Publications in the journal are indexed in the Annual Bibliography of English Language and Literature (Chadwyck-Healey), the Arts and Humanities Citation Index (Thomson Reuters ISI), the Humanities Index (Wilson), Humanities International Complete (EBSCO), the International Bibliography of the Modern Language Association of America, and Scopus (Elsevier). The journal is affiliated with the Purdue University Press monograph series of Books in Comparative Cultural Studies. Contact: <[email protected]> Recommended Citation Wang, Xian. "Traveling Theory: Fredric Jameson’s Interpretations of the Cultural Revolution and Maoism." CLCWeb: Comparative Literature and Culture 20.3 (2018): <https://doi.org/10.7771/1481-4374.3271> This text has been double-blind peer reviewed by 2+1 experts in the field.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel After Augustine, an Essay on Political Theology Geoffrey J.D
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations (2009 -) Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Projects Transcending Subjects: Hegel After Augustine, an Essay on Political Theology Geoffrey J.D. Holsclaw Marquette University Recommended Citation Holsclaw, Geoffrey J.D., "Transcending Subjects: Hegel After Augustine, an Essay on Political Theology" (2013). Dissertations (2009 -). Paper 303. http://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/303 TRANSCENDING SUBJECTS: HEGEL AFTER AUGUSTINE, AN ESSAY ON POLITICAL THEOLOGY by Geoffrey J. D. Holsclaw, B.A., M.Div. A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Milwaukee, Wisconsin December 2013 ABSTRACT TRANSCENDING SUBJECTS: HEGEL AFTER AUGUSTINE, AN ESSAY ON POLITICAL THEOLOGY Geoffrey J. D. Holsclaw, B.A., M.Div. Marquette University, 2013 From where do political reformers and radicals come who are willing and prepared to challenge the status quo? Where are people formed who are capable of initiating change within a political system? Some worry belief in transcendence closes off authentic political engagement and processes of transformation. Others think that a transcendent orientation is the only means to protect and promote a more free and just society. Some see a positive commitment to transcendence as inimical to democratic practices, while others see such a commitment as indispensible for such a project. These general issues concern transcendence, immanence, and subjectivity as they bear on the question of political transformation. Explaining the differences between these fundamental orientations prompts an investigation of the philosophical and theological systems of Hegel and Augustine. Examining Hegel and Augustine around the issues of transcendence and freedom offers a way to understand these more localized disagreements between political philosophers and theologians, and even between theologians.
    [Show full text]
  • To Tell the Truth: Zizek and the Real Hegel
    Žižek and Hegel - IJŽS Vol 2.2 Žižek and the Real Hegel David J. Gunkel, Northern Illinois University (USA) Žižek and Hegel, the terms and conditions of this relationship are, if anything, complicated and contentious. On the one hand, Žižek—or more precisely Žižek's writings and publications—attempt to affect "a return to Hegel" (Žižek 1989: 7). This return, it seems, responds to and takes account of Michel Foucault's rather ominous warning: "We have to determine the extent to which our anti-Hegelianism is possibly one of his tricks directed against us, at the end of which he stands, motionless, waiting for us" (Foucault 1972: 235). According to Foucault's characterization, the general movement of contemporary philosophy (in post-war France in particular) may be characterized as an attempt to escape from Hegel and the influence exerted by Hegelianism. This endeavor is, however, immediately complicated by the possibility that such an escape may itself be something already comprehended and anticipated by the Hegelian system. This is precisely the kind of argument Žižek mobilizes in Organs without Bodies, where he endeavors to demonstrate that the anti-Hegelianism of Gilles Deleuze, for all its concentrated and concerted efforts, remains thoroughly comprehended and controlled by Hegelian dialectic: "Deleuze equals Hegel" (Žižek 2004: 49). It is also evident in his encounters with other well-known poststructuralist readings of Hegel, like that proffered by Jacques Derrida. "What the Derridean deconstruction brings out," Žižek (2008a) argues, "after a great struggle and declares to be the inherent limit of dialectical mediation—the point at which the movement of Aufhebung necessarily fails—Hegel posits directly as the crucial moment of this movement" (85).1 For Žižek, this inescapable "Hegelian remainder" does not (as Foucault's comment seems to imply) so much come back around to bite us on the ass as it always and already is clinging to or hanging off the ass of the poststructuralist or anti-Hegelian project, unable to be effectively eliminated to begin with.
    [Show full text]
  • Slavoj Žižek's
    A Lacanian Hegelianism: Slavoj Žižek’s (Mis-)Reading of Hegel Anders Burman When reading Slavoj Žižek, it does not take long to realize that Hegel’s philosophy is one of his most important theoretical points of departure. Unlike most other contemporary political theorists and thinkers, he does not even hesitate to call himself a Hegelian. In an interview from 2002, he says, for example, “even when I sometimes try to be critical of Hegel, I remain a Hegelian”.1 Like many other political radical Hegelians, Žižek is also in some way influenced by the theories of Marx as well as by Lenin and other later Marxist thinkers. Nevertheless, it would be incorrect to regard him as an orthodox or traditional Marxist. Ian Parker is therefore right when he writes: “Žižek does indeed see traditional Marxism as out of date, no longer applicable to new conditions of global capitalism”, with the important addition, “and this does lead him back to Hegel”.2 Žižek’s readings of Hegel’s texts are based on Jacques Lacan’s theories of the subject and the unconscious, and less on Marx. Indeed, Žižek explicitly defends a psychoanalytically impregnated Hegelianism. With an implicit but obvious reference to Marx’s eleventh thesis on Ludwig Feuerbach, he writes in The Plague of Fantasies that the motto of such a Lacanian reading of Hegel could be: “Philosophers have hitherto only interpreted Hegel; but the point is also to change him.”3 This article examines Žižek’s way of understanding and interpreting Hegel, but also how in different ways he changes the Hegelian philosophy in 1 Slavoj Žižek & Glyn Daly, Conversations with Žižek (Cambridge & Malden: Polity, 2004), p.
    [Show full text]