<<

Hegelian Phenomenology and the Critique of and Society Peter Osborne

Abhot Terrasson has rema~cked that if the size of a volume be measured not by the number of its pages but by the time required for mastering it, it can be said of many a book, that it would be much shorter if it were not so short. (Kant, Preface'to First Edition, Critique of Pure Reason)

Gillian Qnse's Hegel Contra Sociology (Athlone Press, of Hegel's thought which focuses on the socio­ 1981, £6.95 pb, 26lpp) would be much shorter were it political significance of his idea of speculative not so short. It is unashamedly, and sadly, an . extremely difficult book; not just in terms of the The argument is that Marx's critique of Hegel is complexity and subtlety of the position it puts for­ based on a Fichtean reading of his system which fails ward, but, primarily, in terms of the way in which to grasp the true meaning of his concepts of actual­ this position is presented. But it is, nonetheless, ity and spirit, and that in fact these concepts pro­ in many ways an important book. For it challenges, vide the theoretical basis for the conceptualisation at a fundamental level, the generally accepted frame­ of the subjective mediations of objective social work within which Hegel has been interpreted; and, forms. Marx's own conception of practical material­ in so doing, it challenges accepted beliefs not only ism is seen as theoretically incapable of.conceptual­ about the relationship between Marx and Hegel, but ising such mediations, since it involv~s abstract also about the philosophical adequacy of and dichotomies between and consciousness, and the redundancy of Hegelianism. It contains a densely theory and practice, which can only be unified argued and philosophically sophisticated piece of abstractly in an 'ought'. Without such mediations, Hegel scholarship which is mobilised against all the the relation between Capital and politics is seen to prevailing tendencies of contemporary social theory, be indeterminate. Capital gives an account of the and it be of particular interest to 'the mater­ objective determinations of social relations, but ialist friends of the idealist ' [1]. Marxism is seen to be theoretically incapable of In this essay my aim is two-fold: (i) to produce utilising this through a politics which an account of some central themes of the book, and, accounts for how these social relations may be prac­ in particular, of the reading of Hegel around which tically transformed on the basis of their objective it revolves; and (ii) to offer a provisional assess­ determinations, because it cannot develop adequate ment of the standpoint it adopts, not so much with concepts of subjectivity and culture [4]. regard to the textual credibility of the interpreta­ In what follows, I first give an account of Rose's tion of Hegel from which it derives, as with respect understanding of Hegel, contrasting it with that on to its immanent viability and more general implica­ which is based, since (i) this is a tions. For Rose treats the conception of Hegelian standard interpretation, and (ii) Rose's reading of phenomenology which she outlines as the only possible Hegel functions as a reformulation of the foundations coherent theoretical basis for the development of a of Critical Theory; then I discuss its implications critical theory of subjectivity, culture, and hence, for Marxism, and I discuss Rose's understanding politics. She wants to appropriate aspects of Hegel's of Harx. I conclude with a few comments of a general . The idea which the book develops is that on the overtly 'philosophical' character of the philosophical basis of Hegel's thought must be the project that Rose outlines. One of the most appropriated by Marxism if the latter is to be able interesting things about the book is that, while it to generate a critical politics. So it is the criticises existing formulations of Critical Theory, internal cogency of Rose's account of Hegel, rather it demonstrates and clearly endorses the explicitly than its historical veracity, which is important. 'philosophical' nature of its project. Hegel Contra Sociology announces itself as 'an attempt to retrieve Hegelian speculative experience Hegelian Phenomenology and the Radicalisation of Kant's for social theory' [2], and it concludes with a brief Critique of Reason outline of a projected Hegelian social theory (labelled 'critical Marxism' - I will come back to Hegel Contra Sociology is perhaps best understood as this) as 'the exposition of capitalism as culture', a response to Habermas's account of the development 'a presentation of the contradictory relations of from Kant to Marx, which prepares between Capital and culture' [3] in the phenomeno­ the ground for his formulation of Critical Theory as logical (speculative) mode. In the meantime, it a theory of knowledge-constitutive interests, and to develops a philosophical critique of sociology and the understanding of the idea of metacritique, as the of Harxism, and a strikingly original interpretation radicalisation of Kant's critique of reason, on which

8 that theory is based [5]. It is this interpretation Emphasising the specificity of Hegel's thought, of the idea of metacritique which determines the Rose restricts her usage of the term 'metacritique' meaning Habermas gives to the statement that 'a radi­ to refer to that particular form of reflection on cal critique of knowledge is possible only as social the of theory developed by those who theory' [6]. As we shall see, Rose's reading of rejected Hegel's philosophy; that is, quasi-transcend­ Hegel involves a reinterpretation of this fundamental ental reflection - inquiry into the ontological or axiom of Critical Theory, which changes its orienta­ sociological preconditions of critique by transcend­ tion from an, at least formal, directedness towards ental argument. Habermas's theory of knowledge­ Harx back towards Hegel. constitutive interests is established by an argument Habermas's understanding of the idea of meta­ of this kind. This kind of argument is quasi-trans­ critique has recently been elaborated by Garbis cendental because its results are both a priori (as Kortian in his book Metacritique: The Philosophical the ground of critique) and seemingly naturalistic Argwnent of Jurgen Habermas (Cambridge University (as external to the ). Consequently: Press, 1980). A brief examination of the different The status of the relation between the socio­ ways in which Kortian and Rose treat the concept of logical precondition and the conditioned becomes metacritique will serve to introduce Rose's position correspondingly ambiguous in all sociological and to situate it in relation to Critical Theory [7]. quasi-transcendental arguments. Kortian characterises 'metacritique' as an argument­ [14 ] ative strategy with reference to Hegel's Phenomenology In opposition to such an ambiguous form of argument, of Spirit, which is taken to provide its [7]. Hegelian phenomenology is presented as a form of He develops an account of the philosophical structure cognitive activity which successfully radicalises of Habermas's work in terms of the idea of meta­ the critique of reason, which presents its social pre­ critique, and he uses the in the form of conditions through a process of speculative self­ the arguments that Hegel and Habermas use to determine reflection in which the exposition of critique and the theoretical specificity of Habermas's work. the derivation of its ground are united: Critical Theory generally, and Habermas's work in The exposition of abstract thinking and the particular, are presented as a response to the failure derivation of the social institutions which of Hegel's attempt at metacritique: 'Critical Theory determine it are completely integrated in the is intended as the experience and expression of the tracing of the education of self-consciousness failure of the Hegelian concept [8]. at specific historical moments. In agreement with Kortian's acceptance of a distinc· [15 ] tion between the epistemological structures of pheno­ The reason that Kortian does not distinguish menological and forms of metacritical argument, phenomenological and quasi-transcendental arguments but in opposition to his account of their difference, in this way is that his reconstruction of Habermas's Hegel Contra Sociology presents a reading of Hegel argument shares the presuppositions of Habermas's which is built upon a claim for the epistemological thought. In this sense, it is less a reconstruction superiority of the phenomenological form of Hegel's than a restatement. It presupposes the validity of argument. Hegel's thought is counter-posed to that the interpretation of Hegel from which Habermas of the advocates of Critical Theory, and of socio­ starts out. This interpretation (which is a standard logical thought generally (of which Critical Theory one) maintains that Hegel . is seen to be an instance, despite itself), as rep­ employs the radicalisation of critique, or this resentative of the only possible form of thought experience which he terms 'speculative', in the capable of superceding the dilemmas of , service of an absolute system of knowledge which are taken to be reproduced within all socio­ governed by the of the identity logical thought (and most strikingly in Habermas) of thought and being. because of its reliance upon Kantian forms of argu­ [16 ] mentation [9]. So while Habermas claims that his own The Phenomenology of Spirit is taken to be grounded work is genuinely metacritical, and that Hegel's is in idealist . Rejecting this metaphysic, metaphysical - in its failure to eliminate all Habermas separates the idea of the self-reflection 'absolute' presuppositions - Rose claims that only from the phenomenological form of its presentation. Hegel has achieved genuine metacritique, and that It is this abstraction which gives rise to the idea Habermas's work remains Kantian. The basis of this of metacritique which Kortian explicates. claim is that Hegel has been almost universally mis­ Now, from the point of view of Hegel's thought, understood. which Rose adopts, this abstraction of the idea of Kortian uses the term 'metacritical' to character­ metacritical argument from its original form appears ise the epistemological structure of a theory which as a regression to that Kantian form of argument is, broadly speaking, 'critical' in the sense in which separates off the subject from the object of which Horkheimer uses the term; that is, which critique, and defines their relation abstractly, in reflects upon the relation between the epistemic terms of a critical method. It was just this methodo­ subject engaged in critique and the object criticised; logical conception of refl~ction which Hegel sought to which reflects upon the presuppositions of critique overcome, because 'it takes for granted certain ideas [11]. Kortian distinguishes, none too clearly, about cognition as an instrwnent and as a medium, and between genuine or 'radical' metacritique - 'the assumes that there is a difference between ourselves movement associated with the "meta" is only radical and this cognition' [17]. The methodological appro­ so long as it resolutely refuses any ... absolute priation of the idea of the self-reflection of know­ position' [12] - and metacritique which fails to ledge robs it of its primary critical function. carry through the radicalisation of critique which is Metacritique, as opposed to phenomenology, is thus its task [13] because it rests on some absolute pre­ an essentially ambiguous enterprise which attempts to supposition, but which nonetheless presumably reveals reveal the presuppositions of critique through the some of the preconditions of critique. He places direction of the critical method towards previously Hegel's Phenomenology in the latter group. This is neglected aspects of human [18]. the source of a certain amount of conceptual confus­ In Kortian's terms, we can say that the ambiguity ion since it means that the paradigmatic example of of metacritically (quasi-transcendentallY) established metacritique is a failed instance of that which it preconditions constitutes a failure on the part of exemplifies. This is the result of defining it as an those theories which are grounded on them to overcome, intention. But I think it is clear what Kortian is or to 'radicalise', critique. For their combination getting at. of a priority and gives them just that

9 'absolute' character which defines the objects of metaphysical thought. However, although they are philosophically unsatisfactory, Rose acknowledges the fact that such metacritical arguments can be extremely fruitful sociologically. Indeed, she argues that they are the method by which the basic of socio­ logy were established. The first chapter of Begel Contpa Sociology, 'The Antinomies of Sociological Reason', gives a comprehensive, if condensed, historical account of the development of sociology in terms of its philosophical foundations in neo­ Kantianism, which shows how a variety of sociological enterprises were established by different meta­ critical arguments, each designed to uncover different preconditions of neo-Kantian . Neo­ Harxist sociology is also seen to exhibit this syn­ drome of reaction to, but incorporation within, neo­ Kantianism. Although both attempted to overcome the philosophical problems of traditional sociology, it is argued that Luk~cs and Adorno in fact represent different positions within neo-Kantianism [19]. And Althusser is seen to combine neo-Kantian epistemo­ logy (his conception of science) with sociological metacritique (his theory of structures of social formation), and so to make 'all the classic neo­ just that point at which it promises to become most Kantian moves solely within a project of rereading interesting. It leaves the question of the theoret­ Marx' [20]. ical value of the position outlined (which is always Rose's argument is that Hegelian phenomenology is also a practical question) unexplored, by implicitly the only way out of these philosophically inadequate assuming that it is the only way out of a certain forms of neo-Kantianism. The reason a way out is theoretical dilemma. The perspective within which needed (although this is never actually made explicit tHat-dilemma arises, and epistemology, which deter­ in the text - an example of its unnecessarily enig­ miRes-its form, is never itself que matic stance) is that, while neo-Kantian metacritique that dilemma arises, and which determines its form may be 'sociologically' (i.e. descriptively) ade­ (epistemology), is never itself questioned. The quate, its philosophical inadequacies make it ppact­ compositional structure of Begel Contpa Sociology, ically impotent, because it is incapable of generat­ which combines philosophical argument with textual ing a social theory in which the ground of critique, citation in a complex and often ambiguous manner, of theory generally - objective social determina­ and its terse, assertive style, which at times tions - is conceived other than as distinct from, borders on the cryptic, are the forma~ correlates and externally related to, consciousness. It is of this refusal to consider, concretely, the general incapable of giving rise to a social theory which significance of the position it puts forward (which grasps its object in terms of the subjective media­ is essentially a refusal to open a dialogue with the tions through which it is experienced and reproduced, reader). and through which it can be transformed. The argu­ Let us examine the argument put forward in defence ment for Hegelian phenomenology (as opposed to simply of the first premise (above) - the denial of any 'contra sociology') rests on two premises: (i) that, 'absolute' presuppositions in Hegel's thought. The despite almost universal to the contrary, bulk of Begel Contpa Sociology is devoted to its Hegel's philosophy does not rely on the metaphysical substantiation. presupposition of the identity of thought and being; Rose's reading of Hegel, in conscious opposition that 'the fact that the Absolute alone is true, or to Harxist appropriations of his thought, revolves the alone is absolute' [21] is not a ppe­ around her analysis of the roles played by that pair supposition of Hegel's thought at all: and (ii) that of concepts most often rejected, if not ridiculed, the philosophical foundations of Marxian by those appropriations as representative of its (as opposed to simply its sociological revisions) systematic, and so idealist and ultimately theo­ are themselves in some way Kantian or Fichtean inso­ logical, aspect. These are the concepts of the far as they are not Hegelian. absolute and of speculation (in all its various Although a demonstration of the validity of this forms as speculative thinking, speculative discourse, second premise is attempted, briefly, at the end of speculative experience, and, particularly important the book (to which I will return), it is assumed to Rose's interpretation, speculative rereading). from the beginning. For it is claimed, without Marxist sociology has mystified Hegel by making argumentation, that Kant's philosophy of conscious­ a distinction between a 'radical method' and a ness, with its theoretical and pract­ 'conservative system'. As a result of this ical moralism, 'can only be criticised if the infin­ artificial distinction, the centrality of those ite is knowable' [22]. We are offered an exclusive ideas which Hegel developed in order to unify choice between the possibility of Hegelianism and the theoretical and of Kant the impasse of an impotent Kantianism, since, accept­ and Fichte has been ignored. ing Kant's critical destruction of previous meta­ [23] physics, Rose, along with Hegel, recognises that the Rose sets out to reassert the centrality of these infinite can only be knowable in its unity with the ideas. Her thesi~ is that 'Hegel's philosophy has finite, i.e. as the absolute. no social import if the absolute cannot be thought' This doctrinaire insistence on the exclusive [24], since, as the unity of the finite and the theoretical option of Kant (and Fichte) op Hegel, infinite [25], it represents the unity, and hence reminiscent of the falsely exclusive choices offered the dif~erence, of actuality and possibility. So, by Luk~cs in his essays on in the thirties) how can the absolute be thought? What are the condi­ but lacking their possible political vindication, is tions of such a form of thought? And how can they a theoretical flaw which has the unfortunate effect be derived without being implicitly presupposed? of closing the discourse articulated by the text at i.e. how can the transcendental circle, which involves

10 the implicit presUpposItIon of that which is to be is present'. We cannot yet think the absolute. How deduced in the specification of that from which it is can this be done? to be deduced, be avoided? [26] How can the absolute The absolute can never be 'thought' or 'known' in be shown to be thinkable without this being pre­ the ordinary sense of being a determinate object for supposed in the form of the assumption of the identity consciousness (viz. Hegel's definition of knowledge, of thought and being? above), despite the title of the final chapter of The key to this of problems is the idea of the Phenomenology, because it is not a possible phenomenology. object of consciousness. It is not a possible object The only consistent way to criticise Kant's of consciousness because it is, by definition, beyond philosophy of consciousness is to show that the opposition of consciousness and its objects, and the which a methodological, or 'consciousness is always this opposition between any natural, consciousness falls into when it itself and its object' [34]. As 'implied' or considers the object to be external, can itself 'alluded to', it cannot so much be 'thought' or provide the occasion for a change in that con­ 'known' as experienced in a particular way. It can sciousness and in its definition of its object. be experienced negatively, or speculatively, as the [27] formal unity of the multiplicity of contradictory The only way to criticise Kant (within the problem­ or relations by which it is implied. It atic of modern epistemology, one might add) is thus is the production of such a form of experience of the through a phenomenology, which presents the forms of absolute, which Hegel calls speculative thought, knowledge according to their own methodological stand­ which Rose takes to be the purpose of a phenomenology. ards, as they appear to consciousness, and which In a phenomenology, a sequence of 'shapes of con­ thereby presents 'the realm of appearance as defined sciousness' is assembled 'in order to see the abso­ by limited forms of consciousness' [28]. Such a lute by presenting the series of its determinations, presentation is a genuine radicalisation of Kant's of its misapprehensions' [35], both historically and critique of reason because it involves no presupposi­ contemporaneously. Because no one set of determina­ tions about the nature of knowledge as it is presented tions, no one particular form of phenomenal knowledge, in a series of diverse forms, other than the bare can grasp the absolute, philosophy is necessarily axiom that knowing is 'the being of something for a systematic. 'This idea of a whole which cannot be consciousness' [29], which is a necessary condition grasped in one moment or in one statement for it must of all epistemology; a universally shared presupposi­ be experienced is the idea of the system' [36]. But tion. because the absolute is not a static totality, Such a presentation, Hegelian phenomenology, is neither is the system through which it is presented. possible, because of the unity of the processes of The essentially negative determination of the abso­ cognItIon and reflection within consciousness. As lute means that its systematic apprehension is never­ Hegel explains in the introduction to the ending; it involves the continual re-cognition of Phenomenology, phenomenal knowledge or prevailing forms of experi­ Consciousness examines its own self .... [It] ence (which may themselves be changing) as specula­ is, on the one hand, consciousness of the tive experience [37]. object, and on the other, consciousness of As I understand it from Rose's exposition, pheno­ itself; consciousness of what for it is the menal knowledge is re-cognised, specula'ti v"ely, by True, and consciousness of its knowledge of the observing (reading) consciousness of a phenomeno­ the truth. Since both are for the same con­ logy in the following way. The presentation of forms sciousness, this consciousness is itself of natural consciousness (that is, of forms of con­ their comparison; it is for the same conscious­ sciousness 'natural' to particular historical period~ ness to know whether its knowledge of the as forms of phenomenal knowledge (that is, as part of object corresponds to the object or not. determinate cultural configurations), leads the [30] observing consciousness to see their series as The series of contradictory experiences which the necessary, and to see them as determined. The observing (reading) consciousness undergoes as it experience this consciousness undergoes is speculat­ progresses through the different historical forms of ive, it is the experience of 'the transgression of knowledge recreated in their determinate series by a the limit between the positive and its condition' phenomenology, is seen by Rose to lead, by implica­ [38], because the recognition of determination which tion, to the concept of the absolute. It is argued it involves explodes the distinction between the that the experience of the contradictory nature of finite and the infinite which grounds the purely hitherto apparently valid forms of knowledge subverts contemplative attitude of ordinary thought, which the distinction between finite and infinite on which conceives of its objects as external to it [39]. It those forms - as different relations between con­ thus involves the concept of the absolute (as the sciousness and objects external to it - were based, unity of the conditions and the conditioned), in and implies a notion 'which does not divide con­ relation to which the prevailing form of phenomenal scious~ess or into finite and infinite' [31]: knowledge is revealed to be inadequate to its object the absolute. As implied, however, the absolute is (which is now conceived in its unity with, rather 'present but not yet known'. Only its concept is than as external to, consciousness). known. That it is present can be 'acknowledged but So, speculative thought is the re-thinking of not stated' [32], since to state that it is present phenomenal knowledge from the point of view of the would suggest that it is present to consciousness absolute, the re-thinking of phenomenal knowledge as (i.e. known), which it is not. This acknowledgement inadequate knowledge of the absolute. As such it is is not an abstract statement about the absolute, a form of thought which acknowledges a lack of but an observation to which we have now attained, identity between the subject and predicate of propo­ by looking at the experience of a consciousness sitions which represent phenomenal knowledge. which knows itself as an antithesis, as Propositions, ordinarily construed, are taken to negati ve ... posit a false identity between the concepts with [33] which they operate and the objects these concepts So, the concept of the absolute is derived, by are used to represent, insofar as the of implication, phenomenologically. It arises out of propositional grammar dictates that subject and pred­ Hegel's critique of Kant's epistemology. But the icate are conceived as independent prior to predica­ derivation of the concept is equivalent only to tion, and ~elated by predication. From the perspect­ 'the attainment of the observation that the absolute ive of the absolute, on the other hand, subject and

11 predicate are determinations which 'acquire their the Logic ends the Phenomenology rather than that meaning in a series of relations to each other' [40], the Phenomenology introduces the Logic. Whereas the and which are consequently not independent of each former is a phenomenology of natural consciousness, other, but in some way mutually constitutive. This the latter is taken to be a phenomenology of abstract, leads to the idea of speculative (re)reading; the philosophical consciousness - a form of consciousness reading of propositions as speculative identities. derived, historically, in the Phenomenology.) The In such 'speculative propositions', Aesthetics is read as a 'philosophy', as representat­ The subject of the proposition is no longer ive of the standpoint of the absolute, of the fixed and abstract with external, contingent collectivity. This is possible because the pheno­ accidents, but, initially, an empty name, menon it presents - - is taken by Hegel to be uncertain and problematic, gradually acquiring historically transcended, to be 'no longer a format­ meaning as the result of a series of contra­ ive, educative, political experience' [47]. The dictory experiences. lectures on the of and history [41 ] are read as methodologically mixed texts: Rose's interpretation of Hegel's system is thus In both lecture series there is no sustained that it is constituted by the phenomenological re­ phenomenology. Instead the 'standpoint of the presentation and speculative rereading of phenomenal absolute' is abstractly and repeatedly stated knowledge, and gives rise to 'knowledge' of the and contrasted with the standpoint of religious absolute through the speculative experiences which relation, difference, representation or conscious­ it provokes. And these experiences are 'critical'. ness. The two texts reveal the aporia of subject­ For example, in terms of moral and political con­ ivity: the subjective standpoint is criticised sciousness, its speculative apprehension involves by means of the exposition of its fonnation; experience of the fact that ethical life (Sittlich­ but the absolute is thought as subject. keit, a term used by Hegel to designate the unity of [48 ] the spheres of and legality, the practical Significantly, there is no discussion of the realm) is misrepresented by the prevailing cultural Encyclopaedia. forms through which it is experienced and reproduced. It is a feature of Rose's interpretation that .Although it is an essentially negative mode of Hegel's phenomenologies are taken to involve speculat­ cognition, which reveals the 'untruth' of phenomenal ive rereadings' of the propositions of phenomenal knowledge in all of its forms, speculative experience knowledge. Paradigmatically, these are the proposi­ is positive in three ways: (i) purely formally, inso­ tions of Kant and Fichte's philosophy which is taken far as it involves determinate negation [42], (ii) to by Hegel to be the philosophical articulation of the the extent that it reveals the determination of the prevailing forms of knowledge and experience, deter­ misapprehension which it uncovers (as we shall see, mined by the bourgeois property form. So 'speculative this is problematic), and (iii) insofar as the revela­ rereading' is an Hegelian or 'philosophical' equival­ tion of misapprehension contains, implicitly, the ent to Marxian critique (in the sense of the critique demand for a change in that which determines that of political economy - we can see here how Rose's misapprehension. I will examine the second and third reading of Hegel reformulates the philosophical founda­ of these 'positive' aspects of speculative experience, tions of Critical Theory). It is at once a demonstra­ and the relation between them, in a moment, for this tion of the inadequacy of a particula~ theoretical is the issue on which the way in which Rose's form of perspective to a particular object, and a 'critique' Hegelianism can contribute to the development of a of the form of social relations which 'correspond' to critical Marxism rests. But first, I will quickly that perspective insofar as they determine it. How­ complete my account of Rose's position. ever, as we noted at the start of this essay, Rose's To sum up: according to Rose, the Phenomenology of claim for Hegelian phenomenology is much stronger Spirit, and any phenomenology for that matter, than this. It is that it is the only philosophically ... is not a teleological development towards adequate form of theory capable of critically concept­ the reconciliation of all oppositions between ualising subjectivity and culture. It is to this consciousness and its objects, to the abolition claim that I now want to turn. of natural consciousness as such, but a specu­ lative presentation of the deformations of natural consciousness; Hegelian Phenomenology and Marxism: The Critique of Society [43] [it is] not the experience of consciousness There is an ambivalence in Rose's attitude to Marxism recapturing its alienated existence, but the and to the question of the relationship between presentation of the formation of consciousness Hegelian phenomenology and ~~3.rxism, which reflects a as a determination of substance, and (or rather crucial and unresolved ambiguity in her conception through) consciousness' misapprehension of of phenomenology. This ambiguity is the result of a that determination; failure to resolve the tension within her account of [44 ] Hegel's thought between its philosophical and socio­ ... not a success, but a gamble. For the political aspects; the tension between its function perpetual occurrence of inversion and mis­ as critique of reason and its function as critique of . representation can only be undermined, or society. This, in turn, is a consequence of a failure 'brought into fluidity', by allusion to the to acknowledge the extremely limited sense in which a law of their determination ... phenomenology can be socially critical, which is an [45 ] effect of over-estimating the cognitive value of This open-ended interpretation of Hegelian pheno­ speculative experience. Perhaps the strangest thing menology, and its culmination in speculative experi­ about Hegel Contra Sociology is that while it gives ence of the absolute, which Rose develops primarily probably the clearest account in English of the through an examination of Hegel's Jena works, laying precise character of Hegelian speculation it fails to particular emphasis on the System of Ethical Life of grasp the significance of the limitations it so 1802 as the first phenomenology [46], is used to expertly delineates. As I suggested earlier, this produce critical reading of most of Hegel's mature is because it remains within the problematic of works. modern epistemology. The Philosophy of Right and the Logic are read as The ambiguity in Rose's conception of phenomenology phenomenologies, as representative of the 'standpoint (essentially an ambiguity in her conception of the of consciousness'. (Accordingly, one might say that sense in which it can lead to knowledge of the social 12 determination of consciousness) is displayed in the of the possibility of a new form of ethical life is, statement, that in phenomenologies, on Hegel's terms, epistemologically unjustifiable. the illusions and experiences of moral and The contradiction within Hegel's project registered political consciousness are presented in an here takes us to the heart of Rose's understanding, order designed to show how consciousness may and defence, of Hegel's concept of speculation. through them to comprehension of the The reason it is unjustifiable even to conceive of determination of ethical life. an alternative form of ethical life is that to remain [49] critical epistemologically, consciousness must posit On the basis of this claim it is further claimed that no form of relation between itself and its objects phenomenology is not only 'a presentation of political which does not arise 'naturally' out of its self­ experience', but itself 'the definitive political reflection upon the objects present to it in pheno­ experience' [50]. Harxism seems, very definitely, to menal knowledge. And, as we noted above [53], Rose's have been replaced. But does speculative experience 'materialist' appropriation of Hegel denies that the of the absolute really involve comprehension of the dialectic of consciousness is spontaneously self­ determination of ethical life? I think not. It generating, understanding it instead as the source involves only comprehension (in the politically of speculative experience. (Despite her description crucial form of 'experience', it is true) of the of Hegelian philosophy as 'the definitive political fact that ethical life is determined. And this is a experience', in fact in contradiction to it, Rose very different thing. A theory of this determination acknowledges the political impotence of philosophy is still required. Only by exploiting this ambiguity when she says that the 'possibility of in the phrase 'comprehension of the determination of ethical' depends on neither the recognition of deter­ ethical life' is Rose able to make such a strong case mination, nor on any moral decision, but on a 'trans­ for Hegel. formation of intuition' [54]. The determination of This brings us back to the second and third which is, of course, by definition, beyond the 'positive' aspects of speculative experience noted individual consciousness.) So 'absolute ethical above, to the question of the relation between the life' (the social ideal) is an 'unstatable' alternat­ kind of determination revealed in speculative ive [55]. What is more, even in this empty, abstract expe~ience and possibility of real . form it is unjustifiable. For it is Rose's belief that a phenomenological social Simply by of being an alternative, Rose theory ('the exposition of capitalism as culture') is argues, however unspecifiable, the concept of the 'the only way to link the analysis of the economy to absolute 'contains an abstract imperative', a moment comprehension of the conditions for revolutionary of Sollen ('ought') [56], despite itself, despite its practice' [51]. Such a theory is labeled 'critical purely negative derivation. For once it has been Marxism' because the 'analysis of the economy' derived it cannot but present itself to consciousness involved is to be Marx's. There are two problems as an alternative. Ironically, it is precisely the here: (i) the reduction of Harxism to 'the analysis need to avoid the 'abstractness' of a 'positive' of the economy', and (ii) the incorporation of any alternative (one which is 'posited' by consciousness, form of analysis, of theory, within a phenomenological and unrelated to the existing state of things) which 'presentation'. I will argue that an examination of leads Hegel to defend an unspecifiable alternative, the nature of speculative experience and its theoret­ that is ultimately equally 'abstract' insofar as it ical conditions reveals a fundamental incompatibility too presents itself to consciousness as an 'ought' (thoup,h not inconsistency) between He~elian pp.~~o­ despite its phenomenological derivation. menology and Marxian critique. And that, consequent­ But rather than rejecting the standpoint of con­ ly, phenomenology is incapaule of tulfilling the sciousness as a starting point because of this contra­ theoretical expectations which Rose has of it. But, diction, Rose acknowledges it and accommodates it first, let us see how phenomenology is socially within her exposition. It is here that the original­ critical, in its own right. ity of her interpretation lies. Rejecting both Rose takes speculative experience to be 'critical' 'right-' and 'left-wing' Hegelianism as attempts to not just epistemologically, in its independence from resolve the contradiction by unjustifiably adopting presuppositions, but also, and consequently (and this one of its sides and neglecting the other, she is the problem), politically, in its orientation embraces the contradiction as definitively character­ towards other philosophies and to society. It is istic of Hegel's thought, calling it 'the paradox of critical in this latter, dual, sense because it Hegel's philosophy of philosophy' [57], and taking it involves the recognition of a form of mediation to show that an element of Sollen, of 'ought', of between consciousness and its objects which is not epistemologically unjustifiable striving for an acknowledged either by other philosophies, or by the alternative state of affairs, must be present in existing forms of law and property relations to which philosophy, and that this is quite consistent with these philosophies correspond. This recognition is Hegel's critique of Kant. This element of Sollen taken to subvert both the validity of these philo­ is taken to appear as a subjective limitation on sophies and the legitimacy of the forms of social speculative experience. relation which condition them and sustain their The argument is that once it has been acknowledged credibility. Now, as we noted above, such negative that the ?~solute cannot be thought (c8Dnot become criticism has a positive function, and it is here present to consciousness through its objects [58] that a new problem arises which demonstrates quite while the dichotomies which its concept transcends clearly how limited is a social critique grounded in remain a feature of the world which our consciousnesses epistemology. inhabit, 'we can think the absolute by acknowledging One of the positive functions of speculative the element of Sollen in such a thinking' [60], experience is speculatively. This restatement of the idea of to make a different form of ethical life speculative experience from the point of view of its possible by providing insight into the dis­ practical aspect reveals the unity of theoretical placement of actuality in those dominant and in the unity of the epistemo­ philosophies which are assimilated to and logical and practical limitations from which speculat­ reinforce bourgeois law and property relations. ive experience suffers. Such experience is presum­ [52] ably only subjectively limited in the sense that its The problem is: (i) that this insight can contribute objectively determined limitations appear as limita­ to the development of a new form of ethical life only tions of the subject. in a minimal sense, and (ii) that merely to conceive So, 'thinking the absolute' speculatively is some-

13 thing of a Pyrrhic victory, both sociologically and It does not involve a social theory. 'Theory' is practically. For while the acknowledgment and explan­ precisely what it rejects. ation of an unjustifiable element of Bollen in Rose's ambivalence towards Marxism centres on this speculative experience reasserts its theoretical problem of the status of theory, and of the theoreti­ consistency, it also serves to emphasise both its cal status of Marxism. It is the result of her theoretical and practical impotence [60]. This is strident critique of the philosophical foundations of particularly clear from a comparison of Rose's Marxism, as they are presented in Marx's early writ­ description of Hegel's idea of the vocation of ings. Her argument is that because of the inadequacy philosophy with her understanding of his philosophy. of his conceptualisation of the theory-practice Philosophy, we are told, has the vocation 'to relation, Marx 'misunderstood the relation between present a notion of law to our abstract consciousness his own (later) discourse and the possibility of a which will re-form ethical life without being re­ transformed politics' [65]; that he misunderstood the formed by it' [61]. It 'urges us to transform meaning of his own discourse. She does not object to ethical life by re-cognising the law of its determina­ the analysis in Capital, but to 'any presentation of tion' [62]. This re-cognition, it is argued, that analysis as a comprehensive account of capital­ 'commends a different way of transforming [it]' [63] ism, ... any pre-judged, imposed "realisation" of from that of the arbitrary and tyrannical imposition that theory, any using it as a theory~ as Marxism' of a new form without regard to determinations of the [66] . existing form - a mode of transformation paradigmatic­ Now, it seems to me that what we have here is a ally represented by the Terror of the French Revolu­ straightforward confusion, and false identification, tion, and taken to be theoretically articulated in of the realms of theory and practice, in the idea of the categorical imperatives of Kant's and Fichte's 'theory' which is presented. The idea of Marxism in practical philosophies. But philosophy cannot the above quotation quite unjustifiably, and almost specify concretely what this new mode of transforma­ incomprehensibly, identifies the theorisation of an tion is. And so, I would argue, it cannot bring object, as opposed to its 'presentation', with the about such a transformation. A 'notion of law' 'pre-judged, imposed realisation' of some theory of will not transform anything. how that object ought to be. No allowance is made Rose describes Hegel's new mode of transformation for mediations between social theory and politics. as 'transforming the specific determination in rela­ And it is assumed that the theoretical structure of tion to the totality of its real possibilities' [64]. Capital is such that it takes to be an No further specification is possible, because of the 'object' and ignores the subjective aspect of its law of the determination of ethical life whose formal reproduction. recognition is seen to lead to recognition of the Rose's problem is that she has no other conception necessity of such transformation, the specific form of theory. Marx is placed within the Kantian problem­ of which would determine the mode of transformation, atic on the basis of a cursory reading of a few early is, by definition, unknowable in any ordinary sense texts, in which his philosophical position is neither of the word 'know'. It can only be known as the fully developed nor discussed at any length [67]. negation of all forms of determination which pre­ But this negligent treatment of Harx (compare it to suppose the independence of condition from condi­ the care lavished on the details of Hegel's most tioned. Hegel thus 'commends' an 'unstatable' alter­ obscure works!) is not contingent. For "Rose's main­ native, and 'urges' us to seek it through the trans­ tenance of the subject-object problematic of modern formation of determinations which are 'unspecifiable'! epistemology, while it allows her to conceptualise This is where Marxism comes in. the mediation of the objective within the subjective The attempted incorporation of Marxist theory (phenomenologically), rules out the possibility of a within Hegelian phenomenology which Rose undertakes theoretical mode in which the subjective is mediated is necessitated by the fact that, despite indications within the objective, and this is the only possible to the contrary, Hegelian phenomenology is incapable form of a materialist theory of subjectivity, culture of generating knowledge of the concrete determinations and politics, which aims to go beyond the mere recog­ which give rise to the correlation between forms of nition of the 'deformation' of existing forms of consciousness and forms of social relations which it phenomenal knowledge to theorise their real determina­ presents, and by the fact that such knowledge is tions and possible modes of transformation. The necessary If speculative experience of the deforma­ Hegelian approach which Rose adopts excludes the tions of natural consciousness is to lead to a possibility of an understanding of Marx. transformative practice based on (rather than simply against) objective social determinations. But there is a fundamental contradiction here. For the absence Conclusion: The End of Philosophy? from Hegelian phenomenology of a theory of objective social determination is no accident. It is a conse­ If Capital is not 'a comprehensive account of capital­ quence of a particular epistemological argument, the ism', or at least the beginnings of, and basis for, one from which the phenomenological form is itself such an account, what is it? And how can it be of derived. use to a theory which aims to present the contradic­ This argument maintains that to avoid the ambigu­ tions between capital and culture, to expose capital­ ity, and practical impotence, of quasi-transcendent­ ism as a culture? I do not think that there are ally established, Kantian, metacritical theories of answers to these questions which do not involve the the social determination of consciousness, the stand­ abuse of basic hermeneutic standards in the reading point of consciousness must be criticised immanently. of Capital. But where does this leave Hegel and In a phenomenology, the critique of the standpoint of Hegelian phenomenology? consciousness is achieved, exclusively, through its The short answer to this question is 'outside adoption; through its 'presentation' in a form Marxism'. Rose's' cri tical Marxism' is incoherent. designed to reveal its limitation. Such an adoption But her idea of Hegelian phenomenology is not. It is of the standpoint of consciousness is theoretically merely limited. It represents the end-point of mod­ incompatible with any social theory. It involves the ern philosophy; a point at which the self-critique of presentation of social forms (forms of social rela­ epistemology has reached its limit, and from which it tion) in a form designated to provoke the reading can progress no further, condemned to eternal repeti­ consciousness into experiencing their determination tion, the never-ending production of a speculative of the forms of consciousness to which they corres­ experience of society which remains trapped within pond and along with which they have been 'presented'. the confines of the perspective it knows to be false

14 [68]. For through her critical reading of Hegel, But while the reiteration of such a position may clear Rose has arrived at just that point at which Adorno, our philosophical , and represents a timely whose path was more tortuous, came to rest: recogni­ reminder of the fallacy of epistemological absolutism, tion of the fact that the essential negativity of the it remains impotent in the face of contemporary dialectic of consciousness means that it can have no r0ality. resting place, can secure no 'true' knowledge [69].

Footnotes 40 HCS p.49. 41 HCS, p.49. This 'Hegelian' semantics hardly seems as original as Rose An earl ier version of this essay was read to the Philosophy Society at appears to suggest. By referring to the 'purely formal' positive aspect Cambridgeshire College of and Technology in February 1982. I would 1 ike of determinate negation, I mean that it is positive insofar as it offers to thank those present on that occasion, and Chris Arthur, for their comments the limited truth about an object, that it is not some particular thing. on the draft. I do not mean to imply that I agree with Hegel that a new form immediately arises, i.e. that the dialectic of consciousness is spontaneously self­ generating (cf. Hegel, G.W.F., op.cit., p.5l). Nor is Rose committed to The strangeness of this phrase when taken outside of its strictly pedagogical this position. By construing spirit as a 'structure of recognition' context is particularly appropriate here, since it locates Rose's project rather than a metaphysical entity, she is absolved from the sin of making most precisely while at the same time questioning its coherence. (For while the Idea the subject of history. However, as we shall see, this undermines historical materialists may be friends of the dialectic - practitioners, her claim for the political significance of phenomenology. hopefully - are they 'friends' of the idealist dialectic?) The phrase at 42 By referring to the 'purely formal' positive aspect of determinate once asserts and subverts the idea of materialisJ11 .. It raises the problem negation, I mean that it is positive insofar as it offers the limited of subjectivity. By reconstructing the idealist dialectic as a dialectic truth about an object, that it is not some particular thing. I do of consciousness in the interests of materialism, Rose too raises the not mean to imply that I agree with Hegel that a new form immediately problem of sUbjectivity. However, as I hope to show below, by accepting 43 HCS, p.150. the construction of such a dialectic exclusively from the standpoint of 44 HCS, p.152, parthenthese added. consciousness, despite the fact that material determinations are acknow­ 45 HCS, p.159, first emphasis added. ledged, the phenomenological dialectic which Rose sanctions is incapable of 46 HCS, pp.59-73. sol ving this problem which it so acutely poses. 47 HCS, p. 121. O'ne of the implications which can be drawn from such an understanding of 48 HCS, p.l06. It is not clear to me how Rose can account for those texts Rose's text is that while the phrase 'materialist friends of the idealist which 'think the absolute as subj ect' or 'adopt the standpoint of the dialectic' registers a central philosophical problem of materialism - the collectivity' since they transgress the 'critical' rule of relentless problem of subjectivity - it does so in terms of categories which give rise negati vi ty. It is for this reason that it only seems possible to under­ to it, but through which it cannot be solved. In this sense, Joe HcCarney stand her reading of Hegel as 'revisionist', for it seems to invalidate a is right to use the phrase to define a particular theoretical task, but number of his mature texts. Not that this is a bad thing, of course; to wrong to suggest that it can be used to define a problematic. The construc­ attempt to render all of Hegel' s texts consistent with each other, and to tion of a problematic within which the problem of which it is an index can defend them, would be a bizarrely ahistorical, and futile, enterprise. RP be coherently posed is the task! I would therefore suggest that becomes, 49 HCS, p.50, emphasis added. not 'the house ;ournal of "the materialist friends of the idealist dialectic", 50 He'S, p.209. and then reconstruct but the house j~urnal of those concerned to deconstruct 51 HCS, p.220. the enigma of which that phrase is the mark. (Cf. J. HcCarney' s correspond­ 52 HCS, p. 208. Indeed, Rose describes this as 'the overall intention of ence, RP30, pp. 51-52.) Hegel 's thought'. HCS, p.l. 53 See note 42 above. HCS, p.220. 54 HCS, p.65. HCS, p.2l4-220. 55 HCS, p.202. Knowledge and Human Interests, Cf. Habermas, J., 2nd edition, H. E. B., London, 56 HCS, p.78, parentheses added. 1978, Part One, 'The Crisis of the Critique of Knowledge', pp.1-63. 57 RCS, p.78. . Habermas, J., op.cit., p.vii. 58 While the absolute cannot ever be an object of consciousness, it is Rose does not discuss Kortian' s book, though she does refer to it in a foot­ suggested that it could be 'known', 'naturally' in a society that was note as 'an excellent discussion of Habermas' (HCS, ft.18l to ch.l, p.228). socially transparent insofar as each 'obj ect' of consciousness, each Elsewhere, it has been described as 'too static and one-sided' because of piece of phenomenal knowledge, would contain and display its mediation its attempt to 'thoroughly Hegelianise Habermas' (Kellner, D. and Roderick, of every other aspect of phenomenal knowledge, thereby giving the absolute R., 'Recent Literature on Critical Theory', pp.14l-l70, New German Critique in full, in a certain sense. This is the (purely formal) idea of absolute 23, p.165). But it is for just this reason that it is useful here. It ethical li fe. highlights the originality of Rose's reading of Hegel and demonstrates its 59 HCS, p.204. effect on the philosophical foundations of Critical Theory. 60 The, at least formal, theoretical consistency of Rose's position has not 8 Kortian, G., Metacritique, Cambridge University Press, 1980, p.29. been grasped by other reviewers, who have accused her of fall ing back upon 9 ibid., p.32. a left-Hegelian reading, and have then noted the inconsistency between such 10 Cf. HCS, Chapter 1, pp.1-47. a position and other claims made for her reading. Such readings of Rose's 11 Cf. Horkheimer, M., 'Traditional and Critical Theory', pp.188-243, Critical text fail to get to grips with its central point, because they under­ Theory: Selected Essays, trans. ~I.J. O'Connel, New York, 1972. estimate its subtlety. Berki, for example, thinking that he is arguing 12 Kortian, G., op.cit., pp.29-30. against Rose, concludes his review with the statement that Hegel 'emanates 13 'Metacritique is true critique, or rather, it is what critique becomes only "restlessness" but no direction', inferring from this, 'he is not when it is made radical' - Kortian, G., op.cit., p.29. "contra sociology"'. But the whole point of Rose's reading is to show 14 HCS, p.14. the compatibil ity of Hegel' s 'restlessness' with his contrariness to 15 HCS, p.185. sociology, and thereby to specify ppecisely the way in which Hegel' s thought 16 Kortian, G., op.cit., p.30. is restless. Berki ignores rather than refutes Rose. 17 Hegel, G.W.F., Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Hiller, Oxford, 1979, This kind of misunderstanding is compounded by Rose's use of the p.47. . expression 'speculative thought', and her, at times unqualified, insistence 18 Kortian expresses this distinction very clearly when he says: 'It is pre­ that such 'thought' is thought of the absolute. It is most clearly revealed cisely by virtue of what is articulated through speculative experience that in the 'Yes, I did', 'No, you didn't' character of the exchange between Rose the discourse of the speculative proposition is to be distinguished from and Hawthorn on the question of whether Rose actually shows the absolute to theoretical enterprises which are content to bring together different be thinkable. As I argue here, Rose seems not to fully grasp the signific­ positive fields, and to pass from one to another by a transference (meta­ ance of her own position. (Cf. Berki, R.N., 'Thinking the Absolute', TLS, phopa) which produces a synthesis in the metaphor and not in the concept.' 23/10/81, p.1242; Hawthorn, G., London Review of Books, Vo1.3, No.21, and Kortian, G., op.cit., p.28. the exchange of letters between Rose and Hawthorn, LRB, Vo1.3, No.24. 19 HCS, pp.27-33. 61 HCS, p.184. 20 HCS, p.37. 62 HCS, p.187. 21 Hegel, G.W.F., op.cit., p.47. 63 HCS, p. 201, parentheses added. 22 HCS, p.44. 64 HCS, p.191. 23 HCS, p.42. 65 HCS, p.2l9. 24 HCS, p. 42 . 66 HCS, p.2l9. 25 HCS, p.47 67 The section on ~larx, 'The Culture and Fate of Harxism', is only six pages 26 For an account of the expositional, rather than strictly deductive, struct­ in length. Apart from a reference to the GpundPisse to support the mis­ ure of transcendental arguments, cf. S. Kl:frner, 'On the Impossibility of leading claim that 'Marx saw the appeal of art as eternal and ahistorical' Transcendental Deductions', Monist 51, 1967. (HCS, p.2l6), the latest text referred to is the 'Theses on Feuerbach', 27 HCS, pp.45-46. which is treated, quite unjustifiably, as if it were a definitive statement 28 HCS, p.46. of Marx' s philosophical position. In general, the issue of the 'philo­ 29 Hegel, G.W.F., op.cit., p.52. sophical' status of Marxism is treated as if it were quite unproblematic. 30 Hegel, G.W.F., op.cit., p.54. (For a detailed, and brill iant, reading of Marx' s texts up to 1848, which 31 HCS, p.46. addresses the dual question of the meaning of philosophy for Marxism, and 32 HCS, p.158. its fate within Marxism, see Labica, G., M=xism and the Status of 33 RCS, p.181. Philosophy, Harvester Press, 1980, trans. Soper, K. and Ryle, M.. Labica's 34 RCS, p.153. insistence on peading Marx, in the fullest sense of that term, produces an 35 HCS, p.181. account of his early writings which emphasises the fact, and complexity, of 36 HCS, p.182. the conceptual development they embody. Rose, on the other hand, both 37 'Absolute knowledge is a path which must be continually traversed', HCS, treats these texts as homogeneous, and considers that they represent the p.182. philosophical framework in relation to which the later, 'economic' works 38 The phrase is Kortian's. Kortian, G., op.cit., p.28. acquire their meaning.) 39 Rose's claim is that 'to see the determination in the act is to see beyond 68 Cf. HCS, p.182: 'Absolute knowledge is a path which must be continually the dichotomy between act and non-act'. HCS, p.205. The claim is crucial, traversed. ' for it is the experience of 'seeing the determination in the act', which it 69 Cf. Adorno, T., Negative , Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973, trans. is claimed that only a phenomenology can give rise to, that is the basis of E. B. Ashton. Rose's own account of Adorno' s thought (The MeZancholy Rose's idea of political (educative) experience, which in turn is the basis Science, Macmillan, 1978) provides an interesting point for a comparison of her critique of Marxism. of Adorno with Rose's Hegel.

15