Feminist Epistemology As a Local Epistemology Author(S): Helen E

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Feminist Epistemology As a Local Epistemology Author(S): Helen E Feminist Epistemology as a Local Epistemology Author(s): Helen E. Longino and Kathleen Lennon Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 71 (1997), pp. 19 -35+37-54 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4106954 Accessed: 26/04/2010 19:08 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The Aristotelian Society and Blackwell Publishing are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes. http://www.jstor.org FEMINISTEPISTEMOLOGY AS A LOCAL EPISTEMOLOGY Helen E. Longino and KathleenLennon I-Helen E. Longino I ntroductoryremarks. The very idea of feministepistemology throws some philosophers into near apoplexy. Partly this is social and psychological:an aversionto the revisionistchallenges of feminism abettedby a healthyif residualmisogyny. Partlythis is intellectual: how could a politically and intellectually partial form of inquiryhave anythingto say aboutepistemology, which is or ought to be about very generalquestions concerning the nature of knowledge?The formeris worthnoting, but not discussing;the second, however, goes to the heartof what feminist epistemology is. This essay pursuesone line of thoughtin feminist epistemology with a view to sorting out the relation between it and general epistemology, and between it and other approachesin feminist theory of knowledge. FirstI shouldnote whatfeminist epistemology is not. It is not the study or defence of feminine intuition, of 'women's ways of knowing', of subjectivism;it is not an embraceof irrationalityor of Protagoreanrelativism. Although feminist philosophers have celebratedthe female subject,have arguedfor the constructiverole of emotion in knowledge, and have criticizedstandard accounts of objectivity and rationality,attacks on feminist epistemology tend to ignore the argumentsfeminists offer and insteadgo after straw women. As they misrepresentthe feminist work they purportto criticize, they do not deserve any kind of detailedresponse, but do impose on feminists a burdenyet again to say what we mean.Also, contraryto the apparentview of many of its detractors,feminist epistemology encompasses a number of different directions of analysis some of which are,others of which arenot, mutuallycom- patible. In addition,themes andpositions in feministepistemology 20 I-HELEN E. LONGINO overlap with themes and positions in philosophy generally.Thus some of the tensions within feminist epistemological thought are mirroredby tensions in other areas of philosophy,while some are peculiar to it. For example, many commentatorstake feminist epistemology to be a species of naturalizedand social epistem- ology, but just as there are ways of naturalizingand ways of socializing epistemology, so there are ways of doing feminist epistemology. Feminist epistemology has both critical and constructive dimensions. Critical dimensions include the demonstration of forms of masculine bias at the heart of philosophicalanalyses of such topics as objectivity, reason, knowledge, and rationality. Constructive dimensions include carving out a space for specifically feminist programsof inquiry,identifying or defending epistemic guidelines of feminist inquiry. Among constructive programsfeminist standpointtheory and feminist empiricismhave been the most visible, but feminist forms of pragmatismare also findingfavour. (See Lloyd 1984, Code 1991, 1995, Harding1986, 1991, Rooney 1994, 1995, Anderson 1995, Solomon 1995, also Alcoff and Potter 1993, Lennon and Whitford1994.) Most feminist epistemologies (those named above) have been feminist adaptationsof extant philosophicalorientations. Another way to start thinking about feminist epistemology is to consider what feminists engagedin inquiry,in the productionof knowledge, have to say aboutknowledge, to investigatewhether and how they think feminist practices of inquiry might differ from standard practices. Feminists standing back from and reflecting on their practices have had quite a bit to say about moral dimensions of practices of inquiry; about the development of mutual respect among researchers, about the desirability of cooperation as opposed to competitionamong researchers,about the desirability of respect for, even love of, the objects of one's research,be these social or natural,about issues of responsibility.(See Hubbard1990, Martin1988, Birke 1984, Stanley 1990) Feministsin the course of working throughparticular research programs, whether empirical or analytical,have also defended,elaborated, or invoked a variety of cognitive or theoreticalvalues, desirablecharacteristics of the outcomesof inquiry.Thinking about these values and the roles they do or mightplay in inquiry,can initiatea chainof reflectionsleading FEMINISTEPISTEMOLOGY AS A LOCALEPISTEMOLOGY 21 to a somewhatunorthodox, but ultimately, I believe, quite fruitful, characterizationof epistemology.I will discusssome of thevalues thathave been endorsedby feministthinkers and their relation to traditionalepistemic values and move fromthis discussionto a considerationof therelation between an epistemologyfocused on feministcognitive values and general philosophical epistemology and betweenthis formof feministreflection on knowledgeand other,perhaps more familiar, directions in feministepistemology. II Feminist Values in Inquiry.In a series of earlier papers, I have exploreda set of values individuallyand severallyinvoked by feministresearchers (Longino 1994, 1996).They probably do not exhaustthe valuesthat feminist researchers do or couldendorse but they do exhibita suitablerange. To simplifymatters, I treat these as theoreticalvirtues, i.e. as characteristicsof theories, models,or hypotheses,that are taken as countingprima facie and ceterisparibus in favourof theiracceptance. The virtuesI have discussedin this capacityinclude empirical adequacy, novelty, ontologicalheterogeneity, complexity or mutualityof interaction, applicabilityto humanneeds, and decentralizationof power or universalempowerment. While empiricaladequacy is held in commonby feministand non-feminist researchers, the remaining five contrastintriguingly with morecommonly touted values of consistencywith theories in otherdomains, simplicity, explanatory powerand generality, fruitfulness or refutability. I shall briefly say somethingabout each of thefeminist virtues, excluding empirical adequacy. Feministsendorse the novelty of theoreticalor explanatory principleas protectionagainst unconscious perpetuation of the sexismand androcentrism of traditionaltheorizing or of theorizing constrainedby a desirefor consistencywith accepted explanatory models.The novelty envisioned is not thenovelty of discoveryof new entities(like the top quark)predicted by theorybut rather of frameworksof understanding.For example, some feminist scholarshave criticized the articulationof femalecentred models of evolutionby feministprimatologists as remainingtoo much withinthe framework of sociobiology,and thus, perpetuating other noxious values of that theoreticalapproach. Novelty, thus 22 I-HELENE. LONGINO understood,is contrary tothe value of conservatism aspropounded by Quineor of consistencywith theories in otherdomains as describedby Kuhn. The embrace of novelty may be conjoined with a hopeof ultimatelyseeing or engineeringan overturning of the theorieswith which a new viewis inconsistent,or withmerely makingsalient aspectsof experienceor realityhidden or marginalizedby presentlyaccepted theory. Feministswho endorseheterogeneity as a virtueindicate a preferencefor theories and models that preserve the heterogeneity inthe domain under investigation, orthat, at least, do not eliminate it on principle.An approachto inquirythat requires uniform specimensmay facilitate generalization, but it runsthe riskof missingimportant differences-so the maleof a speciescomes to be takenas paradigmaticfor the species (as in 'Gorillasare solitary animals;a typicalindividual travels only with a femaleand her/ theiryoung'). Or, via the conceptof male dominance,males are treatedas the only causallyeffective agents in a population.The embraceof heterogeneityextends beyond humanand animal behaviour,however, and is also invokedin the contextof genetic and biochemicalprocesses. Feminist researchers have resisted unicausalaccounts of developmentin favourof accountsin which quite differentfactors play causal roles. Heterogeneityis thus opposedto
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy in Biology and Medicine: Biological Individuality and Fetal Parthood, Part I
    Oslo, Norway July 7–12, 2019 ISHP SS B BOOK OF ABSTRACTS 2 Index 11 Keynote lectures 17 Diverse format sessions 47 Traditional sessions 367 Individual papers 637 Mixed media and poster presentations A Aaby, Bendik Hellem, 369 Barbosa, Thiago Pinto, 82 Abbott, Jessica, 298 Barker, Matthew, 149 Abir-Am, Pnina Geraldine, 370 Barragán, Carlos Andrés, 391 D’Abramo, Flavio, 371 Battran, Martin, 158 Abrams, Marshall, 372 Bausman, William, 129, 135 Acerbi, Alberto, 156 Baxter, Janella, 56, 57 Ackert, Lloyd, 185 Bayir, Saliha, 536 Agiriano, Arantza Etxeberria, 374 Beasley, Charles, 392 Ahn, Soohyun, 148 Bechtel, William, 259 El Aichouchi, Adil, 375 Bedau, Mark, 393 Airoldi, Giorgio, 376 Ben-Shachar, Erela Teharlev, 395 Allchin, Douglas, 377 Beneduce, Chiara, 396 Allen, Gar, 328 Berry, Dominic, 56, 58 Almeida, Maria Strecht, 377 Bertoldi, Nicola, 397 Amann, Bernd, 40 Betzler, Riana, 398 Andersen, Holly, 19, 20 Bich, Leonardo, 41 Anderson, Gemma, 28 LeBihan, Soazig, 358 Angleraux, Caroline, 378 Birch, Jonathan, 22 Ankeny, Rachel A., 225 Bix, Amy Sue, 399 Anker, Peder, 230 Blais, Cédric, 401 Ardura, Adrian Cerda, 380 Blancke, Stefaan, 609 Armstrong-Ingram, Tiernan, 381 Blell, Mwenza, 488 Arnet, Evan, 383 Blute, Marion, 59, 62 Artiga, Marc, 383 Bognon-Küss, Cécilia, 23 Atanasova, Nina, 20, 21 Bokulich, Alisa, 616 Au, Yin Chung, 384 Bollhagen, Andrew, 402 DesAutels, Lane, 386 Bondarenko, Olesya, 403 Aylward, Alex, 109 Bonilla, Jorge Armando Romo, 404 B Baccelliere, Gabriel Vallejos, 387 Bonnin, Thomas, 405 Baedke, Jan, 49, 50 Boon, Mieke, 235 Baetu,
    [Show full text]
  • Robert Klee and the Latest Face of Scientific Realism P. Kyle Stanford
    Pergamon Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci., Vol. 30, No. 2, pp. 367–375, 1999 1999 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved Printed in Great Britain 0039-3681/99 $ - see front matter Essay Review Preaching to the Choir? Robert Klee and the Latest Face of Scientific Realism P. Kyle Stanford* Robert Klee, Introduction to the Philosophy of Science: Cutting Nature at its Seams (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), xi ϩ 258 pp., ISBN 0- 19-5106113, paperback. Perhaps the most important point to make about Robert Klee’s recent Introduc- tion to the Philosophy of Science: Cutting Nature at its Seams is that we need many more books like it: it is an engaging, accessible and comprehensive introduc- tory text in the philosophy of science which manages to avoid sailing over the head of the beginner philosophy student without talking down to the working pro- fessional. I suspect that many teachers of the philosophy of science will, along with their students, find something in this book to stimulate their own thinking about the subject. Despite its many strengths, however, the book’s central strategy of argument is, as we shall see, compromised by a fundamental weakness. One particularly impressive feature of the text is its effective use of immunology as a case study. Klee’s first chapter presents the basics of immunological science, and it serves him well as a constant source of illustration throughout the text. As Klee notes, this pedagogical strategy avoids the traditional exclusive focus on the (sometimes idiosyncratic) features of physics. Far more importantly, however, it avoids the classic philosopher’s mistake of testing accounts of science against a high-school textbook reconstruction of scientific activity, rather than the sophisticated, complex, richly detailed and messy business in which real science consists.
    [Show full text]
  • Objectivity in the Feminist Philosophy of Science
    OBJECTIVITY IN THE FEMINIST PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requisites for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Karen Cordrick Haely, M.A. ***** The Ohio State University 2003 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Louise M. Antony, Adviser Professor Donald C. Hubin _______________________ Professor George Pappas Adviser Philosophy Graduate Program ABSTRACT According to a familiar though naïve conception, science is a rigorously neutral enterprise, free from social and cultural influence, but more sophisticated philosophical views about science have revealed that cultural and personal interests and values are ubiquitous in scientific practice, and thus ought not be ignored when attempting to understand, describe and prescribe proper behavior for the practice of science. Indeed, many theorists have argued that cultural and personal interests and values must be present in science (and knowledge gathering in general) in order to make sense of the world. The concept of objectivity has been utilized in the philosophy of science (as well as in epistemology) as a way to discuss and explore the various types of social and cultural influence that operate in science. The concept has also served as the focus of debates about just how much neutrality we can or should expect in science. This thesis examines feminist ideas regarding how to revise and enrich the concept of objectivity, and how these suggestions help achieve both feminist and scientific goals. Feminists offer us warnings about “idealized” concepts of objectivity, and suggest that power can play a crucial role in determining which research programs get labeled “objective”.
    [Show full text]
  • Fehr, “What Is in It for Me? the Benefits of Diversity in Scientific
    Chapter 7 What Is in It for Me? The Benefits of Diversity in Scientific Communities Carla Fehr Abstract I investigate the reciprocal relationship between social accounts of knowledge production and efforts to increase the representation of women and some minorities in the academy. In particular, I consider the extent to which femi- nist social epistemologies such as Helen Longino’s critical contextual empiricism can be employed to argue that it is in researchers’ epistemic interest to take active steps to increase gender diversity. As it stands, critical contextual empiricism does not provide enough resources to succeed at this task. However, considering this view through an employment equity lens highlights areas where such theories need to be further developed. I argue that views such as Longino’s ought to attend to nuances of community structure and cultural features that inhibit critical social interactions, if we are to maximize the epistemic as well as the ethical improvements associated with a social approach to knowing. These developments advance these epistemic theories for their own sake. They also help develop these theories into a tool that can be used by those calling for increased diversity in the academy. Keywords Feminist philosophy of science • Social epistemology • Implicit bias • Employment equity • Workplace environment issues 7.1 What Is in It for Me? A while ago I gave a lecture to science faculty members and university administrators regarding the underrepresentation of women and minorities in science, technology, engineering and mathematics (STEM) fields.1 After my talk, an administrator, with 1 In this paper I am primarily focusing on gender diversity.
    [Show full text]
  • Toward an Engaged Account of Objectivity: Contributions from Early Phenomenology
    Toward an Engaged Account of Objectivity: Contributions from Early Phenomenology Author: Amanda Gibeault Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/730 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2009 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. ! ∀# ∃%∃&∋ ∃! ∃∀( )&∗ ( ) & + ( ∃ !) + , −../ 0 +( ∃ !) −../ ! ∀# ∃%∃&∋ ∃! ∃∀( )&∗ ( ) & + ∃ 1∃2 +321 45 6∃ 45 +1 ++ 72 1 18 +426∃ 8 6∀1∃ 54 2+326∃ 72+321 45 61∃ 1 +326 5 5 + 2+ 9215 5+ +326 1∃ 2 ∗) :815 +32 ,6∗ 1+, 2 6∃2 54 ;15 ∃∗ 6∀1∃+ +81 22251 +326 251 ,+325 2214 281+121 ,6∃ 1∃ + 5 +326 ! ∀ #∃ % ∀ &∋( ) ∗ ∀ %+ ∀ %, %∀ % ∃ %− +∀ + +% ,∀ . +, /∀ 0 +− ∀ 1 23 +4 %∀ . 5 . 6 +! +∀ ∃ 7 8 8 9 ,: ,∀ 3 3; , −∀ 3 6 < 3 ,% /∀ / ,+ ∀ & 3 ,+ %∀ 6∋ . ,∗ +∀ = ∃ >1 2 −% 3 ∀ ( ∃ −, ∀ −∗ ,∀ / −! /∀ 4% % 3 4, ∀ 6 & 4∗ ∀ ? 4∗ %∀ 6 4≅ +∀ 0 . ∗: ,∀ 6∃ 3 6 ∗ ∀ 1 ? 0 & ∗, ∀ ? !− /∀ 7 <∃ 8> 8& ≅, /∀ :+ + ; 3 :4 ∀ ; 3 0 :∗ ∀ Α . ∃ . :! ∋ %∀ 76;1 81 8 % 1 ∀ ; 3 − ∀ ∋ 8∃85 − %∀ 7 5 ∃ ∗ +∀ ; 3 %∗ ,∀ +: ∀ 1 6 +− ∀ 6 +4 %∀ 6 ,: +∀ =3 , ,∀ 6 ; 3 ,% /∀ ,4 ,∃?(6 −: ∀ 6 6 −% ∀ 4: ∀ ∗: ∀ ∗: %∀ ∗− /∀ = ∗≅ ∀ = ∗≅ %∀ = ! +∀ & = !− /∀ 3) 3 !! ∀ 6 ≅% /∀ 6 ≅, /∀ ≅∗ − 6 ≅! ∀ 0 %: ∀ .∃ %:− ∀ %:− %∀ % +∀ = 6∃ %+ ,∀ 66 %≅
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Adventures
    Philosophical Adventures Elisabeth A. Lloyd INDIANA UNIVERSITY John Dewey lecture delivered at the one hundred tenth annual Central Division meeting of the American Philosophical Association in New Orleans, Louisiana, on February 21, 2013. I had the lovely opportunity of being introduced by Alison Wylie, to whom I owe a large thank you, and thank you especially to Anne Jacobson, and the whole program committee, for this chance to share a bit of my life and career with you. This invitation charged that I was to give an “autobiographical sort” of talk. Specifically, it required the speaker to provide “an intellectual autobiography, with perhaps some account of the way in which [she] was shaped by or shaped the profession, how the profession seems to have changed over the years, etc. The lecturer might reflect on the people and issues that led [her] into philosophy and provide a personal perspective on the state of the field today.” I tried to stick pretty closely to this mandate. Over the course of my career, which is now—although I find this astounding—over thirty years long, I have had the great pleasure of seeing my primary field of research grow and establish itself as a serious field of thought and activity in philosophy. When I was in graduate school at Princeton in the early 1980s, I was told, and I quote, “there is no such thing as Philosophy of Biology. You can’t write a dissertation on that.” And John Beatty wrote that same year: “In the world of academic specialties and subspecialties, philosophy of biology certainly counts as a self-respecting, if not otherwise respected, field of study.”1 It is impossible to imagine anyone saying that now! Five years later, I was also told that feminist philosophy of science was hopeless, that there were no good cases of male bias in science worth discussing, and that since science was self- correcting, those sorts of bias couldn’t have any long-term significance.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Aspects of Scientific Knowledge
    1 Social Aspects of Scientific Knowledge Ilkka Niiniluoto ABSTRACT. From its inception in 1987 social epistemology has been divided into analytic (ASE) and critical (CSE) approaches, represented by Alvin I. Goldman and Steve Fuller, respectively. In this paper, the agendas and some basic ideas of ASE and CSE are compared and assessed by bringing into the discussion also other participants of the debates on the social aspects of scientific knowledge – among them Raimo Tuomela, Philip Kitcher and Helen Longino. The six topics to be analyzed include individual and collective epistemic agents; the notion of scientific community; realism and constructivism; truth-seeking communities; epistemic and social values; science, experts, and democracy. KEYWORDS. democracy, epistemic values, experts, scientific community, scientific realism, social epistemology, truth-seeking, Introduction: Analytic and Critical Social Epistemology Social epistemology studies knowledge from a social point of view. As a complement to empirical studies, such as the sociology of knowledge and the sociology of science, social epistemology aims to provide a normative philosophical account of knowledge as a collective achievement. Even though the term dates from the 1950s, the work in this field started in 1987 with a special issue of Synthese, edited by Frederick Schmitt, and the new journal Social Epistemology – A Journal of Knowledge, Culture, and Policy, founded by Steve Fuller. In the next year Fuller published a monograph with the title Social Epistemology. Alvin I. Goldman, who published in the 1987 Synthese issue an article on “Social Epistemics”, developed his reliabilist epistemology in the direction of social practices in his Knowledge in a Social World (1999).
    [Show full text]
  • Austin & Hempel Lectures 1991-1995
    Austin & Hempel Lectures 1991-1995 Dr. Hilary Putnam, Cogan University Professor, Harvard University October 20, 1995: “Wittgenstein & Philosophy of Mathematics” October 19, 1995: “The Importance of Nonscientific Knowledge” Dr. James Tully, McGill University March 23, 1995: "The Quebec Referendum and the Future of Canada" (In cooperation with the Political Science Department at Dalhousie University) March 24, 1995: "Problems of Cultural Recognition" (In cooperation with the Political Science Department at Dalhousie University) Dr. Sandra Harding, Delaware University and UCLA October 6, 1994: "Is Western Science and Ethno-Science? Feminist and Post-colonial Issues" (In cooperation with the Women's Studies Programme of Dalhousie University) October 7, 1994: "Strong Objectivity: After the Neutrality Ideal" (In cooperation with the Women's Studies Programme of Dalhousie University) Dr. Daniel Dennett, Tufts University September 29, 1994: "Some Confusions about Evolution" September 30, 1994: "Consciousness of Time - and Time of Consciousness" Dr. Naomi Scheman, University of Minnesota February 10, 1994: "On Waking Up One Morning and Discovering We Are Them" (In cooperation with the Women's Studies Programme at Dalhousie University) February 11, 1994: "Closets, margins, and Forms of Life" (In cooperation with the Women's Studies Programme at Dalhousie University" Dr. Barbra Partee, University of Massachusetts Amherst November 4, 1993: "Quantification in Natural Languages and Some Questions for Semantic Typology" November 5, 1993: "Generalized context-Dependence in Quantified Structures" Dr. Paul Horwich, MIT October 14, 1993: "Is Time Travel Possible" October 15, 1993: "What is it Like to be a Deflationary Theory of Meaning?" Dr. Ian Hacking, University of Toronto September 30, 1993: "Memoro-Politics: Trauma and the Soul" (In cooperation with the Political Science Department at Dalhousie University) October 1, 1993: "Reasoning and Realism" (In cooperation with the Political Science Department at Dalhousie University) Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
    The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T.
    [Show full text]
  • Objectivity and the Values and Science Debate Sean Boivin A
    The Likelihood Principle: Objectivity and the Values and Science Debate Sean Boivin A Major Research Paper in the Department of Philosophy Under the supervision of Dr. Matthew J. Barker Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts (Philosophy) at Concordia University Montreal, Quebec, Canada February 2018 © Sean Boivin ABSTRACT The Likelihood Principle: Objectivity and the Values and Science Debate Sean Boivin This paper focuses on the debate of underdetermination in science, and asks the descriptive question: is objectivity possible in science? I introduce the problem of underdetermination in science and articulate a related argument presented by philosopher Helen Longino against the possibility for objectivity (traditionally understood) in science. In opposition to Longino, I aim to salvage the possibility of important objectivity. I begin from Likelihoodism – a normative view about the form that evidential reasoning should take. After presenting different defenses of that view, I show how it implies a descriptive claim – the Likelihood Principle – that opposes Longino’s cynicism about the descriptive possibility of objectivity in science. The Likelihood Principle compares the likelihoods of two hypotheses in relation to a body of evidence and says which hypothesis (if any) is consequently favored. I argue that “favours” be interpreted as “objectively favours”, implying it is possible for some evidence to objectively favour one hypothesis over another without appeal to values. In addition to arguing that we should then infer a descriptive objectivism from this, I interpret a case-study using the Likelihood Principle to illustrate how applications of it can be objective. I discuss what follows for the debate in the values and science literature, including what follows with respect to Longino’s views.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    CURRICULUM VITAE Philip Stuart Kitcher February 2018 Date of Birth: February 20 1947 Place of Birth: London, England Citizenship: British by origin, naturalized American citizen (May 1995). Home address: 454 Riverside Drive, Apt. 6B, New York, NY 10027 Home phone: (212)-662-5812 Office phone: (212)-854-4884, (212)-854-3196 (department) E-mail: [email protected] Higher Education Christ's College, Cambridge; 1966-1969, B.A. 1969, (M.A. 1996). (First class honours in Mathematics/History and Philosophy of Science) Princeton University; 1969-1973; Ph.D. 1974 (Department of Philosophy/Program in History and Philosophy of Science) Honorary Degree Doctor, honoris causa Erasmus University Rotterdam November 2013 (on the occasion of the University centennial; awarded for “outstanding contributions to philosophy of science”) Honors and Awards Henry Schuman Prize (awarded by the History of Science Society, for the best essay by a graduate student), 1971 University of Vermont Summer Research Grant, 1975 University of Vermont Summer Research Grant, 1979 NEH Summer Research Grant, 1979 ACLS Study Fellowship, 1981-82 University of Vermont Distinguished Scholar in Humanities and Social Sciences, 1983 NEH Fellowship for College Teachers, 1983-84 NEH Grant for Institute to Investigate a Possible New Consensus in Philosophy of Science (Joint Principal Investigator with C. Wade Savage) 1 Imre Lakatos Award (co-winner with Michael Friedman) 1986. Awarded for Vaulting Ambition. NEH Fellowship for University Teachers 1988-89 (declined) John Simon Guggenheim Fellowship 1988-89 Principal Investigator, five-year NSF Research and Training Grant for the development of a Science Studies Center at UCSD. (Awarded Fall 1990). Revelle College (UCSD) Distinguished Teaching Award, 1990.
    [Show full text]
  • 2021 APA Eastern Division Meeting Program
    The American Philosophical Association EASTERN DIVISION ONE HUNDRED SEVENTEENTH ANNUAL MEETING PROGRAM VIRTUAL MEETING JANUARY 7 – 9, 2021 AND JANUARY 14 – 16, 2021 Use Coupon Code ZAPE21 to Save 30% (PB)/50% (HC) THROUGH FEBRUARY 16, 2021 ORDER ONLINE AT WWW.SUNYPRESS.EDU Critique in German Philosophy The Aesthetic Clinic From Kant to Critical Theory Feminine Sublimation in Contemporary María del Rosario Acosta López and Writing, Psychoanalysis, and Art J. Colin McQuillan, editors Fernanda Negrete The Primary Way The Disintegration of Community Philosophy of Yijing On Jorge Portilla’s Social and Political Chung-ying Cheng Philosophy, With Translations Foreword by Robert Cummings Neville of Selected Essays Carlos Alberto Sánchez and Jouissance Francisco Gallegos, editors A Lacanian Concept Néstor A. Braunstein Endangered Excellence Translation and Introduction by On the Political Philosophy of Aristotle Silvia Rosman Pierre Pellegrin Translated by Anthony Preus Epistemic Responsibility Lorraine Code A World Not Made for Us Topics in Critical Environmental Philosophy Manufactured Uncertainty Keith R. Peterson Implications for Climate Change Skepticism Recovering the Liberal Spirit Lorraine Code Nietzsche, Individuality, and Spiritual Freedom On Metaphysical Necessity Steven F. Pittz Essays on God, the World, Morality, and Democracy Adult Life Franklin I. Gamwell Aging, Responsibility, and the Pursuit of Happiness Carl Schmitt between John Russon Technological Rationality and Theology Modernity as Exception The Position and Meaning and Miracle
    [Show full text]