The Epistemological Ties That Bind: a Pragmatist Case Against Fewist Theories of Truth and Knowledge and the Implications for Feminet Science

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Epistemological Ties That Bind: a Pragmatist Case Against Fewist Theories of Truth and Knowledge and the Implications for Feminet Science THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL TIES THAT BIND: A PRAGMATIST CASE AGAINST FEWIST THEORIES OF TRUTH AND KNOWLEDGE AND THE IMPLICATIONS FOR FEMINET SCIENCE by Shaw Suzanne Clough M.A., University of Calgary, 1989 THESIS SUBMITTED JN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUiREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHZLOSOPHY Under Special Arrangements in the Faculty of Arts O Sharyn Suzanne Clough SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY June 1997 Al1 rights reserved. This work may not be reproduced in whole or in part, by photocopy or other means, without permission of the author. .----..-. ----- y of Canada ducanada Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographic Services services bibliographiques 395 Wellington Street 395. nie Wellington Ottawa ON KIA ON4 Ottawa ON KIA ON4 canada Canada The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence allowing the exclusive permettant à la National Library of Canada to Bibliothèque nationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distribute or seli reproduire, prêter, distribuer ou copies of this thesis in microform, vendre des copies de cette thèse sous paper or electronic formats. Ia forme de microfiche/film, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L' auteur conserve la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thèse. thesis nor substantial extracts fkom it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be printed or otheMtise de celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation. ABSTRACT Ferninist claims that scientific activity is intimately involved with the oppression of women, often identiw aspects of the epistemology of science, or scientific method, as the prirnary culprit. In my dissertation 1try to persuade my ferninist colleagues that despite the important gains we have made through the criticism of science, Our fairly ment investment in an epistemological critique is yielding dirninishing returns. 1begin by examining the episternological reflections of a number of feminist critics of evolutionary biology, including Ruth Hubbard and Ruth Bleier. 1 then discuss the more general epistemological approaches of Evelyn Fox Keller, Sandra Harding and Helen Longino. There are a number of features of feminist episternology which make it ineffective as a method for adequately addressing the oppression of women by science. For example, feminist epistemological examinations of science have often involved essentialist claims about "women's" experience, and over-general conceptions of science as an institution. These problems are discussed throughout the dissertation. However, the principal focus involves the philosophical details of the feminist epistemologies themselves. Specifically, 1 focus on their reliance on a questionable model of human psychology, that 1 refer to as "representationaiism." My anti-representationalist approach is inspired by the work of two neo- pragamatist philosophers, Richard Rorty and Donald Davidson. For the purposes of this dissertation, representationalism is the view that beliefs are the subjective, representational end-product of a sensory process, in which the objects of our world are sensed and then screened through our subjective perceptual frarneworks (the filters of our values, worldview, and language). My concern is that the representational conception of beliefs as filtered representations of the world makes coherent a global scepticism about the tmth of our beliefs. Since, on this model. beliefs do not arise iii from direct access to the wodd, then they can be radicalIy wrong. Al1 of our representations might be completely inaccurate because they are fiitered through our perceptual apparatus, language, culmral worldview andor theory allegiance. Foiiowing Rorty and Davidson, 1 argue that episternologicai debates are premised on the coherence of global scepticism, and that, dut to the nature of the representationalist mode1 on which the debates are based, the battle with global scepticism is futile. Surveying feminist contributions to epistemoiogicai debates in science, 1 show bow these contributions invite the coherence of scepticism. In the end, each contribution either accepts scepticism, with retativist resignation, or attempts to defeat it with various claims to ubjectivity. While the latter response has proven futile, for both feminist and traditionai epistemotogists alike, the former response is equally problematic. Either way, issues of relativism and scepticism can be used against our well-justified claims that women are king hmedby science. In the latter haif of my dissertation 1offer a pragmatic alternative based on Davidson's philosophy of language. Davidson argues that, on a non-representationalist mode1 of language use, global scepticism is not a coherent option. His views undermine the motivation for participating in the epistemological debates that attempt to address scepticism as a coherent and ever-present concern. By undermining the motivation for these philosophical pursuits 1 hope to encourage my feminist colleagues to return to their important work in science and science criticism with the assurance that out concepts of "error" and "truth" are not always enemies that need feminist epistemological reconfiguration. Acknowledgements My thanks go first to my mother Darline Gough, and my mentor and friend Bj@m Ramberg. Their material, emotional, and intellectual support throughout this entire project has been a great source of strength for me. 1 have been lucky to be surrounded by many other generous and supportive colleagues and friends. 1 am forever thankful to Ian Hollingshead for getting me to Vancouver to start this project in the first place; to Hannah Gay for taking on an interdisciplinary task of immense scope and helping me to whittle it down to a manageable size; to the Philosophy of Psychology reading group at SFU, and especially Jeff Sugarman and David Harnmond, for introducing me to the work of Richard Rorty, and for providing a space where intellectual vigour and ski11 were encouraged and expected; to Dave Carter for suggesting that Bj@m Ramberg was someone 1 REALLY SHOULD MEET; to Lou Bruno for long philosophical conversations over very good food; to Sam (Vanda) Black and Paul Reniers for the links they helped me forge between feminist theory and the real world of labour politics; to Bernie Corneau whose love and support helped me cary this project to completion; and last, but not least, to Edne Sobstyl who has no idea how much her humour, grace and intellectual guidance have made this project much better than it would have been otherwise. Table of Contents Abstract iii Acknowledgements v I. Introduction 1.1 Epis temology defined 1.2 An important distinction remains 1.3 The feminist move from epistemology to Epistemology 1.4 Lessons from pragmn t is rn 1.5 Chapter highlights 1.6 Concluding remarks 2. Ferninist Episternology: Problems in Practise & Theory 2 6 2.1 Symptom: Scepticism; Diagnosis: Representationalism 3 2 2.2 The Epistemological failzrre to defeaf scepticism 3 8 2.3 Another look af correspondence 48 2.4 Surnmary 5 I 3. Feminist Epistemology and Evolritionary Theory 5 4 3.1 The Darwinian theo y of sexual selection 55 3.2 Blackwell: The Sexes Throughout Nature 63 3.3 Second-wave Epistemologists 68 3.4 Science, objectivity and masculini~ 79 4. Keller's Episternological Reflections on Gender & Science 4.1 Keller and psychoanalyfic object relations fheory 4.2 Object relations, objectivity and science 4.3 A mid-point review 4.4 Accepting biological deterrninism at whaf cost? 4.5 Complicating sex/gender 4.6 Object relations and feminist standpoint theoy 4.7 Representationalism continued in "The gender/science system" 5. From Objectivism to Relativism in Feminist Epistemology 113 5.1 Harding on objectivity II5 5.2 From objectivism to relativism 123 5.3 Longino and feminist science 127 5.4 Longino, underdetermination theory and relativism 1 3 O 5.5 Symptom: Relativism; Diagnosis: Representationalism 1 3 2 6. A Pragmatist, Davidsonian Alternative 137 6.1 "A reason for belief that isn 't evidence for belieft 139 6.2 Telling the sceptic to "go away" 147 6.3 Evaluating Davidson's escape from Epistemology 151 7. Feminist Science und Science-Criticism from a Pragmatist Perspective 159 7.1 Davidson on underdetermination theory 160 7.2 Feminist science without Epistemology 164 7.3 A pragmatist view of sex/gender categories 169 7.4 Summary 175 8. A Pragmatist Case Study: Back to the Theory of Evolution 8.1 A pragmatist view of biological function 8.2 The function of "(European) male superiority" 8.3 The function of menstruation 8.4 "The physiology of menstruation shows adaptive design" 8.5 The etiological account: Some concerns 8.6 A pragmatist prescription 8.7 Conclusion Works Cited 211 vii Chapter 1: Introduction Ferninist claims that the oppression of women is systemic in science, often identify the epistemology of science as the primary culprit. Three of the leading theorists who make this case are Keller (1982, 1983 [1978], 1985, 1987, 1992a, 1992b, 1992c), Harding (1986a, 1986b, 1990, 1991, 1993b) and Longino (1987, 1990, 1993a, 1993b). 1 agree with their claim that scientific inquiry, across disciplines and laboratories, often serves to hm rather than help h~rnankind.~Further, they are surely correct that not everyone has an equally likely chance of falling victim to this sort of hm, and that sexism is one of the best explanations of this inequality. The important work by this "second-wave"2 of Western feminists, has equipped yet a new generation of ferninists with a range of critical diagnostic tools for the investigation of oppression in science. However, the more 1 investigate, the less certain 1 have become that an examination of the epistemology of science will help us further the goal of eliminating the ham science causes. 1 will argue this point throughout the balance of rny dissertation, directly confronting the works of Harding, Keller, and Harding enumerates examples in The Science Question in Feminism (1986a, 20 - 22). See also Tavris, The Mismeasure of Woman (1992).
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy in Biology and Medicine: Biological Individuality and Fetal Parthood, Part I
    Oslo, Norway July 7–12, 2019 ISHP SS B BOOK OF ABSTRACTS 2 Index 11 Keynote lectures 17 Diverse format sessions 47 Traditional sessions 367 Individual papers 637 Mixed media and poster presentations A Aaby, Bendik Hellem, 369 Barbosa, Thiago Pinto, 82 Abbott, Jessica, 298 Barker, Matthew, 149 Abir-Am, Pnina Geraldine, 370 Barragán, Carlos Andrés, 391 D’Abramo, Flavio, 371 Battran, Martin, 158 Abrams, Marshall, 372 Bausman, William, 129, 135 Acerbi, Alberto, 156 Baxter, Janella, 56, 57 Ackert, Lloyd, 185 Bayir, Saliha, 536 Agiriano, Arantza Etxeberria, 374 Beasley, Charles, 392 Ahn, Soohyun, 148 Bechtel, William, 259 El Aichouchi, Adil, 375 Bedau, Mark, 393 Airoldi, Giorgio, 376 Ben-Shachar, Erela Teharlev, 395 Allchin, Douglas, 377 Beneduce, Chiara, 396 Allen, Gar, 328 Berry, Dominic, 56, 58 Almeida, Maria Strecht, 377 Bertoldi, Nicola, 397 Amann, Bernd, 40 Betzler, Riana, 398 Andersen, Holly, 19, 20 Bich, Leonardo, 41 Anderson, Gemma, 28 LeBihan, Soazig, 358 Angleraux, Caroline, 378 Birch, Jonathan, 22 Ankeny, Rachel A., 225 Bix, Amy Sue, 399 Anker, Peder, 230 Blais, Cédric, 401 Ardura, Adrian Cerda, 380 Blancke, Stefaan, 609 Armstrong-Ingram, Tiernan, 381 Blell, Mwenza, 488 Arnet, Evan, 383 Blute, Marion, 59, 62 Artiga, Marc, 383 Bognon-Küss, Cécilia, 23 Atanasova, Nina, 20, 21 Bokulich, Alisa, 616 Au, Yin Chung, 384 Bollhagen, Andrew, 402 DesAutels, Lane, 386 Bondarenko, Olesya, 403 Aylward, Alex, 109 Bonilla, Jorge Armando Romo, 404 B Baccelliere, Gabriel Vallejos, 387 Bonnin, Thomas, 405 Baedke, Jan, 49, 50 Boon, Mieke, 235 Baetu,
    [Show full text]
  • Robert Klee and the Latest Face of Scientific Realism P. Kyle Stanford
    Pergamon Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci., Vol. 30, No. 2, pp. 367–375, 1999 1999 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved Printed in Great Britain 0039-3681/99 $ - see front matter Essay Review Preaching to the Choir? Robert Klee and the Latest Face of Scientific Realism P. Kyle Stanford* Robert Klee, Introduction to the Philosophy of Science: Cutting Nature at its Seams (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), xi ϩ 258 pp., ISBN 0- 19-5106113, paperback. Perhaps the most important point to make about Robert Klee’s recent Introduc- tion to the Philosophy of Science: Cutting Nature at its Seams is that we need many more books like it: it is an engaging, accessible and comprehensive introduc- tory text in the philosophy of science which manages to avoid sailing over the head of the beginner philosophy student without talking down to the working pro- fessional. I suspect that many teachers of the philosophy of science will, along with their students, find something in this book to stimulate their own thinking about the subject. Despite its many strengths, however, the book’s central strategy of argument is, as we shall see, compromised by a fundamental weakness. One particularly impressive feature of the text is its effective use of immunology as a case study. Klee’s first chapter presents the basics of immunological science, and it serves him well as a constant source of illustration throughout the text. As Klee notes, this pedagogical strategy avoids the traditional exclusive focus on the (sometimes idiosyncratic) features of physics. Far more importantly, however, it avoids the classic philosopher’s mistake of testing accounts of science against a high-school textbook reconstruction of scientific activity, rather than the sophisticated, complex, richly detailed and messy business in which real science consists.
    [Show full text]
  • Objectivity in the Feminist Philosophy of Science
    OBJECTIVITY IN THE FEMINIST PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requisites for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Karen Cordrick Haely, M.A. ***** The Ohio State University 2003 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Louise M. Antony, Adviser Professor Donald C. Hubin _______________________ Professor George Pappas Adviser Philosophy Graduate Program ABSTRACT According to a familiar though naïve conception, science is a rigorously neutral enterprise, free from social and cultural influence, but more sophisticated philosophical views about science have revealed that cultural and personal interests and values are ubiquitous in scientific practice, and thus ought not be ignored when attempting to understand, describe and prescribe proper behavior for the practice of science. Indeed, many theorists have argued that cultural and personal interests and values must be present in science (and knowledge gathering in general) in order to make sense of the world. The concept of objectivity has been utilized in the philosophy of science (as well as in epistemology) as a way to discuss and explore the various types of social and cultural influence that operate in science. The concept has also served as the focus of debates about just how much neutrality we can or should expect in science. This thesis examines feminist ideas regarding how to revise and enrich the concept of objectivity, and how these suggestions help achieve both feminist and scientific goals. Feminists offer us warnings about “idealized” concepts of objectivity, and suggest that power can play a crucial role in determining which research programs get labeled “objective”.
    [Show full text]
  • Fehr, “What Is in It for Me? the Benefits of Diversity in Scientific
    Chapter 7 What Is in It for Me? The Benefits of Diversity in Scientific Communities Carla Fehr Abstract I investigate the reciprocal relationship between social accounts of knowledge production and efforts to increase the representation of women and some minorities in the academy. In particular, I consider the extent to which femi- nist social epistemologies such as Helen Longino’s critical contextual empiricism can be employed to argue that it is in researchers’ epistemic interest to take active steps to increase gender diversity. As it stands, critical contextual empiricism does not provide enough resources to succeed at this task. However, considering this view through an employment equity lens highlights areas where such theories need to be further developed. I argue that views such as Longino’s ought to attend to nuances of community structure and cultural features that inhibit critical social interactions, if we are to maximize the epistemic as well as the ethical improvements associated with a social approach to knowing. These developments advance these epistemic theories for their own sake. They also help develop these theories into a tool that can be used by those calling for increased diversity in the academy. Keywords Feminist philosophy of science • Social epistemology • Implicit bias • Employment equity • Workplace environment issues 7.1 What Is in It for Me? A while ago I gave a lecture to science faculty members and university administrators regarding the underrepresentation of women and minorities in science, technology, engineering and mathematics (STEM) fields.1 After my talk, an administrator, with 1 In this paper I am primarily focusing on gender diversity.
    [Show full text]
  • Agency and First-Person Authority by Matthew Thomas Parrott A
    Agency and First-Person Authority By Matthew Thomas Parrott A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the Requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Barry Stroud, Co-Chair Professor Daniel Warren, Co-Chair Professor Alison Gopnik Spring 2011 © 2011 Copyright Matthew Thomas Parrott All rights reserved Abstract Agency and First-Person Authority By Matthew Thomas Parrott Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professor Barry Stroud, Co-Chair Professor Daniel Warren, Co-Chair Ordinarily when someone tells us about her psychological states, we presume that she is right. By deferring to her in this way, we treat her as a kind of authority on her own psychological life. Although a person usually has this authority, she lacks it whenever she takes a more detached, indirect, or third-personal point of view toward her psychological states. We see this, for example, when she learns about a belief or desire from a friend or therapist. For this reason an adequate account of the phenomenon of "first-person authority" must explain why we have it only for some but not all of our psychological states. Most philosophers believe first-person authority is an epistemic phenomenon, consisting in each of us being better situated to know about our own psychological states than anyone else. Against all such epistemic views, I argue that, because they base their accounts on epistemic privileges that are in principle available to anyone, they cannot capture the exclusively first-personal character of our authority.
    [Show full text]
  • Toward an Engaged Account of Objectivity: Contributions from Early Phenomenology
    Toward an Engaged Account of Objectivity: Contributions from Early Phenomenology Author: Amanda Gibeault Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/730 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2009 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. ! ∀# ∃%∃&∋ ∃! ∃∀( )&∗ ( ) & + ( ∃ !) + , −../ 0 +( ∃ !) −../ ! ∀# ∃%∃&∋ ∃! ∃∀( )&∗ ( ) & + ∃ 1∃2 +321 45 6∃ 45 +1 ++ 72 1 18 +426∃ 8 6∀1∃ 54 2+326∃ 72+321 45 61∃ 1 +326 5 5 + 2+ 9215 5+ +326 1∃ 2 ∗) :815 +32 ,6∗ 1+, 2 6∃2 54 ;15 ∃∗ 6∀1∃+ +81 22251 +326 251 ,+325 2214 281+121 ,6∃ 1∃ + 5 +326 ! ∀ #∃ % ∀ &∋( ) ∗ ∀ %+ ∀ %, %∀ % ∃ %− +∀ + +% ,∀ . +, /∀ 0 +− ∀ 1 23 +4 %∀ . 5 . 6 +! +∀ ∃ 7 8 8 9 ,: ,∀ 3 3; , −∀ 3 6 < 3 ,% /∀ / ,+ ∀ & 3 ,+ %∀ 6∋ . ,∗ +∀ = ∃ >1 2 −% 3 ∀ ( ∃ −, ∀ −∗ ,∀ / −! /∀ 4% % 3 4, ∀ 6 & 4∗ ∀ ? 4∗ %∀ 6 4≅ +∀ 0 . ∗: ,∀ 6∃ 3 6 ∗ ∀ 1 ? 0 & ∗, ∀ ? !− /∀ 7 <∃ 8> 8& ≅, /∀ :+ + ; 3 :4 ∀ ; 3 0 :∗ ∀ Α . ∃ . :! ∋ %∀ 76;1 81 8 % 1 ∀ ; 3 − ∀ ∋ 8∃85 − %∀ 7 5 ∃ ∗ +∀ ; 3 %∗ ,∀ +: ∀ 1 6 +− ∀ 6 +4 %∀ 6 ,: +∀ =3 , ,∀ 6 ; 3 ,% /∀ ,4 ,∃?(6 −: ∀ 6 6 −% ∀ 4: ∀ ∗: ∀ ∗: %∀ ∗− /∀ = ∗≅ ∀ = ∗≅ %∀ = ! +∀ & = !− /∀ 3) 3 !! ∀ 6 ≅% /∀ 6 ≅, /∀ ≅∗ − 6 ≅! ∀ 0 %: ∀ .∃ %:− ∀ %:− %∀ % +∀ = 6∃ %+ ,∀ 66 %≅
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Adventures
    Philosophical Adventures Elisabeth A. Lloyd INDIANA UNIVERSITY John Dewey lecture delivered at the one hundred tenth annual Central Division meeting of the American Philosophical Association in New Orleans, Louisiana, on February 21, 2013. I had the lovely opportunity of being introduced by Alison Wylie, to whom I owe a large thank you, and thank you especially to Anne Jacobson, and the whole program committee, for this chance to share a bit of my life and career with you. This invitation charged that I was to give an “autobiographical sort” of talk. Specifically, it required the speaker to provide “an intellectual autobiography, with perhaps some account of the way in which [she] was shaped by or shaped the profession, how the profession seems to have changed over the years, etc. The lecturer might reflect on the people and issues that led [her] into philosophy and provide a personal perspective on the state of the field today.” I tried to stick pretty closely to this mandate. Over the course of my career, which is now—although I find this astounding—over thirty years long, I have had the great pleasure of seeing my primary field of research grow and establish itself as a serious field of thought and activity in philosophy. When I was in graduate school at Princeton in the early 1980s, I was told, and I quote, “there is no such thing as Philosophy of Biology. You can’t write a dissertation on that.” And John Beatty wrote that same year: “In the world of academic specialties and subspecialties, philosophy of biology certainly counts as a self-respecting, if not otherwise respected, field of study.”1 It is impossible to imagine anyone saying that now! Five years later, I was also told that feminist philosophy of science was hopeless, that there were no good cases of male bias in science worth discussing, and that since science was self- correcting, those sorts of bias couldn’t have any long-term significance.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Aspects of Scientific Knowledge
    1 Social Aspects of Scientific Knowledge Ilkka Niiniluoto ABSTRACT. From its inception in 1987 social epistemology has been divided into analytic (ASE) and critical (CSE) approaches, represented by Alvin I. Goldman and Steve Fuller, respectively. In this paper, the agendas and some basic ideas of ASE and CSE are compared and assessed by bringing into the discussion also other participants of the debates on the social aspects of scientific knowledge – among them Raimo Tuomela, Philip Kitcher and Helen Longino. The six topics to be analyzed include individual and collective epistemic agents; the notion of scientific community; realism and constructivism; truth-seeking communities; epistemic and social values; science, experts, and democracy. KEYWORDS. democracy, epistemic values, experts, scientific community, scientific realism, social epistemology, truth-seeking, Introduction: Analytic and Critical Social Epistemology Social epistemology studies knowledge from a social point of view. As a complement to empirical studies, such as the sociology of knowledge and the sociology of science, social epistemology aims to provide a normative philosophical account of knowledge as a collective achievement. Even though the term dates from the 1950s, the work in this field started in 1987 with a special issue of Synthese, edited by Frederick Schmitt, and the new journal Social Epistemology – A Journal of Knowledge, Culture, and Policy, founded by Steve Fuller. In the next year Fuller published a monograph with the title Social Epistemology. Alvin I. Goldman, who published in the 1987 Synthese issue an article on “Social Epistemics”, developed his reliabilist epistemology in the direction of social practices in his Knowledge in a Social World (1999).
    [Show full text]
  • Environments of Intelligence
    Environments of Intelligence “An absorbing volume that integrates an extraordinarily wide area of work, with interesting observations and new twists right to the end.” Ruth Millikan, University of Connecticut, USA What is the role of the environment, and of the information it provides, in cognition? More specifically, may there be a role for certain artefacts to play in this context? These are questions that motivate “4E” theories of cognition (as being embodied, embedded, extended, enactive). In his take on that family of views, Hajo Greif first defends and refines a concept of information as primarily natural, environmen- tally embedded in character, which had been eclipsed by information-processing views of cognition. He continues with an inquiry into the cognitive bearing of some artefacts that are sometimes referred to as “intelligent environments”. With- out necessarily having much to do with Artificial Intelligence, such artefacts may ultimately modify our informational environments. With respect to human cognition, the most notable effect of digital computers is not that they might be able, or become able, to think but that they alter the way we perceive, think and act. Hajo Greif teaches at the Munich Center for Technology in Society (MCTS), Technical University of Munich, Germany, and the Department of Philosophy, University of Klagenfurt, Austria. His research interests cover the philosophy – and some of the history and the social studies – of science and technology, as well as the philosophy of mind. History and Philosophy of Technoscience Series Editor: Alfred Nordmann For a full list of titles in this series, please visit www.routledge.com 1 Error and Uncertainty in Scientific Practice Marcel Boumans, Giora Hon and Arthur C.
    [Show full text]
  • Austin & Hempel Lectures 1991-1995
    Austin & Hempel Lectures 1991-1995 Dr. Hilary Putnam, Cogan University Professor, Harvard University October 20, 1995: “Wittgenstein & Philosophy of Mathematics” October 19, 1995: “The Importance of Nonscientific Knowledge” Dr. James Tully, McGill University March 23, 1995: "The Quebec Referendum and the Future of Canada" (In cooperation with the Political Science Department at Dalhousie University) March 24, 1995: "Problems of Cultural Recognition" (In cooperation with the Political Science Department at Dalhousie University) Dr. Sandra Harding, Delaware University and UCLA October 6, 1994: "Is Western Science and Ethno-Science? Feminist and Post-colonial Issues" (In cooperation with the Women's Studies Programme of Dalhousie University) October 7, 1994: "Strong Objectivity: After the Neutrality Ideal" (In cooperation with the Women's Studies Programme of Dalhousie University) Dr. Daniel Dennett, Tufts University September 29, 1994: "Some Confusions about Evolution" September 30, 1994: "Consciousness of Time - and Time of Consciousness" Dr. Naomi Scheman, University of Minnesota February 10, 1994: "On Waking Up One Morning and Discovering We Are Them" (In cooperation with the Women's Studies Programme at Dalhousie University) February 11, 1994: "Closets, margins, and Forms of Life" (In cooperation with the Women's Studies Programme at Dalhousie University" Dr. Barbra Partee, University of Massachusetts Amherst November 4, 1993: "Quantification in Natural Languages and Some Questions for Semantic Typology" November 5, 1993: "Generalized context-Dependence in Quantified Structures" Dr. Paul Horwich, MIT October 14, 1993: "Is Time Travel Possible" October 15, 1993: "What is it Like to be a Deflationary Theory of Meaning?" Dr. Ian Hacking, University of Toronto September 30, 1993: "Memoro-Politics: Trauma and the Soul" (In cooperation with the Political Science Department at Dalhousie University) October 1, 1993: "Reasoning and Realism" (In cooperation with the Political Science Department at Dalhousie University) Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemological Realism As an Intuitive Doctrine Ron Wilburn
    Dialogos, 78 (2001) pp. Ss-73 IS THE SKEPTIC'S REASONING OUR OWN? EPISTEMOLOGICAL REALISM AS AN INTUITIVE DOCTRINE RON WILBURN I. INTRODUCTION Is the skeptic's reasoning our own? That is, is the ske ptic's reasoning recognizably ordinary, or is it a product, so to speak, of pre mises and inferential standards peculiar to distitzctively philosophical preoccu­ patio ns? The question is an important one on two levels. At a general level, it is important to those who, like myself, regard skepticism as a paradigmatic philosophical issue. For, as such, it raises fundamental con­ cerns regarding the status of philosophical reasoning generally. But even at a mo re particu lar level, it raises interesting concerns about the status and do main of episte mology. For, if it could be shown that there is something significantly artificial about the skeptic's global concerns over the possibility of empirica l knowledge, then the more parochial and immanent agendas of naturalistic knowledge theory would seem to ac­ quire validation. This is because the challenge that has been posed by Stro ud and othe rs to naturalized episte mology's compre he nsiveness qua knowledge theory would have been met. Thus, my concern : Is the skeptic's reasoning about knowledge truly our own? Is his negative proclamation a discovery about w hat we can all reflectively recognize as our true epistemic relation to the world, or is it an artifact of some per­ verse obsessio n that the skeptic has with an idealized episte mo logical relation of concern only to him? In the space I have available here, I would like to address at least one aspect of this question.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Knowledge, Authenticity and Obedience 1. the Issue Self
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Repositori d'Objectes Digitals per a l'Ensenyament la Recerca i la... JOSEP E. CORBÍ Self-knowledge, Authenticity and Obedience 1. The Issue Self-ascriptions of mental states and dispositions are assumed to have a privileged epistemic authority compared to third-party ascriptions. An agent does not need to check her own behavior in order to know that she intends to read The Karamazov Brothers for a while. Anyone else would have to ask her instead, or infer what she intends from one or another piece of evidence. Within the analytic tradition, the debate on self-knowledge has mainly been concerned with this asymmetry between the first- person and the third-person perspectives. Traditional accounts seek to identify a specific epistemic ability that should account for the privileges of the first-person view. Following up on David Finkelstein, I will refer to this kind of view as “detectivist” 1 . There is “the old, Cartesian, detectivist view” according to which only the agent herself has a direct, infallible access to her own mental states. It has famously been objected, though, that the states and events of a fully private mind cannot coherently be identified, for there is no way in which appearance and reality could be distinguished within a Cartesian mind2. Alternatively, some philosophers have defended a naturalistic detectivist view (“new detectivism” in Finkelstein’s own terms) according to which the first-person privilege derives from the existence of an exclusive, inner perceptual mechanism that is significantly more reliable than any other perceptual 1 Finkelstein (2003), p.
    [Show full text]