Download File

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Download File Experimental Democracy – Collective Intelligence for a Diverse and Complex World Felix Gerlsbeck Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2013 © 2013 Felix Gerlsbeck All rights reserved Abstract Experimental Democracy – Collective Intelligence for a Diverse and Complex World Felix Gerlsbeck My dissertation is motivated by the following observation: while we care very much about the outcomes of the democratic process, there is widespread uncertainty about ex ante how to produce them—and quite often there is also disagreement and uncertainty about what they are in the first place. Consequently, unless we have a definite idea what “better decision-making” might be, it is not obvious which institutional reforms or changes in democratic structures would actually promote it. Democracy is a wide concept, and not all institutional constellations and rules and regulations that can be called democratic function equally well. In this dissertation therefore I offer a specific model of democracy— “Experimental Democracy”—that unites the view that the quality of decisions matter, with taking into account the circumstances of uncertainty and disagreement that define political problems. On this account, a desirable political mechanism is one that realizes an experimental method of policy-making directed at solving problems, such that we can expect it to make progress over time, even though we cannot rule out that it will get things wrong—possibly even frequently. I also show how democracy may best realize such an experimental method, and which particular institutional features of democracy could serve this purpose. The argument in the dissertation proceeds as follows. In the first part I develop a theory of the justifiability of political authority in the sense outlined above: a theory that is sensitive to the outcome concerns that many people share, but recognizes the fundamental disagreement surrounding this question. I establish that instrumental considerations should be of crucial importance when we evaluate political authority. Here I argue against pure proceduralist theories that see the outcome dimension as secondary. However, the facts of disagreement and uncertainty about the ends of politics, as well as concrete policy, do seem to pose a problem for any instrumental justification. In response I outline a pragmatic or experimental theory of political authority, which focuses precisely on the capacity of a political procedure to solve political problems under uncertainty. Just as in many other fields of inquiry experimentation and adaptation are seen as the adequate responses to uncertainty, I argue, an experimental and adaptive mode of policy-making is the best response to political uncertainty. In the second part I answer the question which form of democracy would best realize the ideal of experimental policy-making. Subsequently, we should evaluate democratic institutions mainly by their capacity to enable successful experimentation and adaptation. Here, contrary to popular “wisdom of crowds” arguments, I argue that since no single decision procedure can be expected to be reliable across the board, a justified political system may have to employ a plurality of first-order decision-making mechanisms. However, as I show for this to work, these mechanisms must be subject to effective democratic control. The key function of democratic institutions here is that of feedback, in order to enable successful adaptation. Finally, I offer some concrete examples how the functional requirements of a successful experimental strategy of policy-making can be institutionally realized within democratic systems. Table of Contents Table of Contents i List of Figures and Tables iii Acknowledgements iv Dedication vi 1. Introduction: What Should a Theory of Democracy Do? 1 1.1 An Icelandic Introduction 1 1.2 Differentiating Democracy 9 1.3 The Argument and the Level of Analysis 17 1.4 The Normative Basis 20 1.5 The Argument Coming Up 22 Part I: A Theory of Experimental Political Legitimacy 2. The Value of Democracy 32 2.1 Introduction 32 2.2 Justifying Rule; Democratic and Otherwise 37 2.3 What’s At Stake? 44 2.4 The Indeterminacy of Pure Proceduralism 47 2.5 Substantive Values Coming In 53 2.6 Practical Concerns 59 2.7 Intermediate Summary 64 2.8 Against Hybrid Principles 65 2.9 Political Equality as a Residual Value 73 2.10 Sources of Disagreement 83 2.11 Is Politics Really That Difficult? 91 2.12 Conclusion 95 3. Robust Universal Reliability of Democracy 97 3.1 Is “Universal Reliability” Possible? 97 3.2 The Possibility of Rational Choice Under Uncertainty 111 i 3.3 The Public Interest and the Common Good 127 3.4 Universal Reliability and How to Argue For It 133 3.5 Scientists, Not Jurors 150 3.6 A Pragmatic Model of Politics 156 3.7 Conclusion 159 4. Can Experimental Political Authority Be Justified? 162 4.1 Introduction 162 4.2 Complexity, Uncertainty, Difficulty 166 4.3 What is Experimental Politics? 178 4.4 Can We Experiment With Values? 183 4.5 Should We Experiment With Values? 195 4.6 Conclusion: What Does This Spell for Democracy? 212 Part II: A Theory of Experimental Democracy 5. Models of Democracy 218 5.1 Introduction 218 5.2 Aggregative/Majoritarian Models of Democracy 227 5.3 Deliberative Models of Democracy 243 5.4 Experimental Democratic Legitimacy 262 5.5 The Control Model of Democracy 280 6. The Institutions of Experimental Democracy 285 6.1 Introduction 285 6.2 The Identification of Problems 290 6.3 Creating Diversity in Problem-Solving 297 6.4 Making Feedback Effective 330 6.5 Putting it All Together 345 Bibliography 349 ii List of Figures and Tables Figure 1: Democratic Differentiation 15 Table 1: Case 3 125 Table 2: Case 3a 126 Figure 2: A Complex Estimation Problem 251 iii Acknowledgements This dissertation would not have been possible without the help and support I got from a great number of people. First I would like to thank my advisors at Columbia University, Jon Elster, Melissa Schwartzberg, and Philip Kitcher, who have been unfailing in their support throughout this project. Jon Elster stoked my interest both in the problem of uncertainty in politics, and in the questions of the design of collective decision- making institutions. His guidance and inexhaustible knowledge have been very important for me. To Melissa Schwartzberg I owe great debts of gratitude for her close mentorship. She followed my project at every stage, and without her practical advice as well as constructive criticism this would not have been successful. Philip Kitcher introduced me to am exciting great body of research at a crucial stage of my project, and I have learned (and hope to learn more) from his kind and perceptive comments. I also thank David Johnston and Jonathan Bendor for agreeing to be on my dissertation committee and for their comments and criticisms, which have helped me enormously (and will do so in the future) to clarify my thoughts on this project. I am very grateful to the rest of the faculty and especially also the staff at the Department of Political Science at Columbia, for their uncomplicated but crucial support. I would also like to thank Jeffrey Lax and Yotam Margalit for agreeing to be on my proposal committee and for their comments, which set me on the right track in the early stages of the project. I also owe thanks to the Mellon Interdisciplinary Graduate Fellows program at Columbia’s ISERP (now INCITE) for their support, material and— especially—otherwise. iv At Columbia and Oxford, throughout the years there, I benefited from the help, support, and criticism of teachers, friends and colleagues. Among many more, they are: Hiroaki Abe, Ashraf Ahmed, Andreas Avgousti, Adam Bronson, James Chappel, the late Jerry Cohen, Simon Collard-Wexler, Axel Domeyer, Kevin Elliott, Aimée Genell, Rob Goodman, David Hine, Kate Jackson, Jennifer Hudson, Yao Lin, Luke MacInnis, William McAllister, Alex Rigas, Pierce O Reilly, Neelanjan Sircar, Peter van der Windt, Jonathan Wright, Liya Yu and Jim Zetzel, as well as those I have likely forgotten to list here. Special thanks also to Michelle Chun for reading and commenting on almost the entire manuscript. Parts of this dissertation were presented at the following conferences and workshops (in chronological order): Brave New World 2011 in Manchester, the Association for Political Theory Annual Conference 2011, the Oxford Political Theory Graduate Conference 2012, the Midwestern Political Theory Annual Meetings 2012 and 2013, and the American Political Science Association Annual Meeting 2013. I owe thanks to all discussants, panelists, and audience members who were so gracious as to give me comments and encouragement. My family, both in Germany and in the United States, has been a constant source of support in so many ways, and I owe them more than I could express here. Most of all, I thank Solongo Wandan. None of this would have been remotely possible without you being part of my life. Thank you. v For Solongo vi 1 Introduction: What Should a Theory of Democracy Do? 1. An Icelandic Introduction Let me begin with a political story that, while it concerns a small and—to many people— probably peripheral place, illustrates a number of key themes of this dissertation.1 In the wake of the great banking crisis of 2008 the government of Iceland faced a particularly difficult decision. Icelandic banks had actively sought investments from foreign individuals, especially other Europeans in order to finance their investment in the immensely risky derivatives business whose collapse would eventually cause the crisis. The “Icesave” interest-bearing savings accounts from the Icelandic Landsbanki became a symbol of this business model. They were advertised heavily abroad and promised high returns on savings. Subsequently, as we all know, the Icelandic banks did fail, and the people who had invested in these accounts lost their savings.
Recommended publications
  • Are Condorcet and Minimax Voting Systems the Best?1
    1 Are Condorcet and Minimax Voting Systems the Best?1 Richard B. Darlington Cornell University Abstract For decades, the minimax voting system was well known to experts on voting systems, but was not widely considered to be one of the best systems. But in recent years, two important experts, Nicolaus Tideman and Andrew Myers, have both recognized minimax as one of the best systems. I agree with that. This paper presents my own reasons for preferring minimax. The paper explicitly discusses about 20 systems. Comments invited. [email protected] Copyright Richard B. Darlington May be distributed free for non-commercial purposes Keywords Voting system Condorcet Minimax 1. Many thanks to Nicolaus Tideman, Andrew Myers, Sharon Weinberg, Eduardo Marchena, my wife Betsy Darlington, and my daughter Lois Darlington, all of whom contributed many valuable suggestions. 2 Table of Contents 1. Introduction and summary 3 2. The variety of voting systems 4 3. Some electoral criteria violated by minimax’s competitors 6 Monotonicity 7 Strategic voting 7 Completeness 7 Simplicity 8 Ease of voting 8 Resistance to vote-splitting and spoiling 8 Straddling 8 Condorcet consistency (CC) 8 4. Dismissing eight criteria violated by minimax 9 4.1 The absolute loser, Condorcet loser, and preference inversion criteria 9 4.2 Three anti-manipulation criteria 10 4.3 SCC/IIA 11 4.4 Multiple districts 12 5. Simulation studies on voting systems 13 5.1. Why our computer simulations use spatial models of voter behavior 13 5.2 Four computer simulations 15 5.2.1 Features and purposes of the studies 15 5.2.2 Further description of the studies 16 5.2.3 Results and discussion 18 6.
    [Show full text]
  • Majority Judgment: a New Voting Method
    Paradoxes Impossbilities Majority Judgment Theory Applications of MJ Logiciels JM Experimental Evidences Conclusion Majority Judgment: A New Voting Method Rida Laraki CNRS (Lamsade, Dauphine) and University of Liverpool Colloquium J. Morgenstern, INRIA, Sophia-Antipolis December 11, 2018 (Joint work with Michel Balinski) R. Laraki Majority Judgment: A New Voting Method Paradoxes Impossbilities Majority Judgment Theory ApplicationsMethods of MJ Logiciels of Voting JM Paradoxes Experimental in Theory Evidences Paradoxes Conclusion in Practice 1 Paradoxes Methods of Voting Paradoxes in Theory Paradoxes in Practice 2 Impossbilities May’s Axioms for Two Candidates Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem 3 Majority Judgment From Practice Small Jury Large Electorate 4 Theory Domination Paradox Possibility Manipulation 5 Applications of MJ Trump 2016 Gillets Jaunes Délé´gué CM1 6 Logiciels JM 7 Experimental Evidences 8 Conclusion R. Laraki Majority Judgment: A New Voting Method First-past-the-post: also called plurality voting, used in UK, US and Canada to elect members of house of representatives. A voter designate one candidate. The most designated wins. Two-past-the-post: used in France and several countries (Finland, Austria, Russia, Portugal, Ukraine, etc) to elect the president. A voter designates one candidate. If a candidate is designated by a majority, he is elected. Otherwise, there is a run-off between the two first candidates. Paradoxes Impossbilities Majority Judgment Theory ApplicationsMethods of MJ Logiciels of Voting JM Paradoxes Experimental in Theory Evidences Paradoxes Conclusion in Practice Voting methods most used in elections R. Laraki Majority Judgment: A New Voting Method A voter designate one candidate. The most designated wins. Two-past-the-post: used in France and several countries (Finland, Austria, Russia, Portugal, Ukraine, etc) to elect the president.
    [Show full text]
  • Majority Judgment Vs. Majority Rule ∗
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Liverpool Repository Majority Judgment vs. Majority Rule ∗ Michel Balinski CNRS, CREST, Ecole´ Polytechnique, France, [email protected] and Rida Laraki* CNRS, University of Paris Dauphine-PSL, France, [email protected] and University of Liverpool, United Kingdom June 6, 2019 Abstract The validity of majority rule in an election with but two candidates|and so also of Condorcet consistency| is challenged. Axioms based on evaluating candidates|paralleling those of K. O. May characterizing ma- jority rule for two candidates based on comparing candidates|lead to another method, majority judgment, that is unique in agreeing with the majority rule on pairs of \polarized" candidates. It is a practical method that accommodates any number of candidates, avoids both the Condorcet and Arrow paradoxes, and best resists strategic manipulation. Key words: majority, measuring, ranking, electing, Condorcet consistency, domination paradox, tyranny of majority, intensity problem, majority-gauge, strategy-proofness, polarization. 1 Introduction Elections measure. Voters express themselves, a rule amalgamates them, the candidates' scores|measures of support|determine their order of finish, and the winner. Traditional methods ask voters to express themselves by comparing them: • ticking one candidate at most (majority rule, first-past-the-post) or several candidates (approval voting), candidates' total ticks ranking them; • rank-ordering the candidates (Borda rule, alternative vote or preferential voting, Llull's rule, Dasgupta- Maskin method, . ), differently derived numerical scores ranking them. However, no traditional method measures the support of one candidate.1 Instead, the theory of voting (or of social choice) elevates to a basic distinguishing axiom the faith that in an election between two candidates majority rule is the only proper rule.
    [Show full text]
  • Democracy Without Elections Mainz
    Democracy without Elections: Is electoral accountability essential for democracy? Felix Gerlsbeck [email protected] Paper prepared for the workshop “Democratic Anxiety. Democratic Resilience.” Mainz, 15-17 June 2017 DRAFT VERSION, PLEASE DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHOR’S PERMISSION 1. Introduction The idea of choosing political decision-makers by sortition, that is, choosing them randomly from a pool of the entire population or from some qualified subset, through some form of lottery or other randomizing procedure, is familiar to democrats at least since ancient Athens. Apart from the selection of trial juries, however, sortition has all but disappeared from official decision-making procedures within contemporary democratic systems, and free, equal, and regular election through voting by the entire qualified population of candidates who put themselves forward for political office, has taken its place. Nevertheless, there has been renewed interest in the idea of reviving sortition-based elements within modern democratic systems over the last years: a number of democratic theorists see great promise in complementing elected decision-making institutions with those selected randomly. These proposals variously go under the names mini-publics, citizen juries, citizen assemblies, lottocracy, enfranchisement lottery, and even Machiavellian Democracy.1 The roots of this practice go back to ancient Athens. During the 5th century Athenian democracy, the equivalent of the parliamentary body tasked with deliberating 1 See for instance, Guerrero 2014; Fishkin 2009; Warren & Gastil 2015; Ryan & Smith 2014; Saunders 2012; López-Guerra 2014; López-Guerra 2011; McCormick 2011. 1 and drafting policy proposals, the boule, was chosen by lot from the citizens of Athens through a complex system of randomization.
    [Show full text]
  • Election by Majority Judgment: Experimental Evidence
    Chapter 2 Election by Majority Judgment: Experimental Evidence Michel Balinski and Rida Laraki Introduction Throughout the world, the choice of one from among a set of candidates is accomplished by elections. Elections are mechanisms for amalgamating the wishes of individuals into a decision of society. Many have been proposed and used. Most rely on the idea that voters compare candidates – one is better than another – so have lists of “preferences” in their minds. These include first-past-the-post (in at least two avatars), Condorcet’s method (1785), Borda’s method (1784) (and similar methods that assign scores to places in the lists of preferences and then add them), convolutions of Condorcet’s and/or Borda’s, the single transferable vote (also in at least two versions), and approval voting (in one interpretation). Electoral mechanisms are also used in a host of other circumstances where win- ners and orders-of-finish must be determined by a jury of judges, including figure skaters, divers, gymnasts, pianists, and wines. Invariably, as the great mathemati- cian Laplace (1820) was the first to propose two centuries ago they asked voters (or judges) not to compare but to evaluate the competitors by assigning points from some range, points expressing an absolute measure of the competitors’ mer- its. Laplace suggested the range Œ0; R for some arbitrary positive real number R, whereas practical systems usually fix R at some positive integer. These mechanisms rank the candidates according to the sums or the averages of their points1 (some- times after dropping highest and lowest scores). They have been emulated in various schemes proposed for voting with ranges taken to be integers in Œ0; 100, Œ0; 5, Œ0; 2, or Œ0; 1 (the last approval voting).
    [Show full text]
  • And the Loser Is... Plurality Voting Jean-François Laslier
    And the loser is... Plurality Voting Jean-François Laslier To cite this version: Jean-François Laslier. And the loser is... Plurality Voting. 2011. hal-00609810 HAL Id: hal-00609810 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00609810 Preprint submitted on 20 Jul 2011 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. ECOLE POLYTECHNIQUE CENTRE NATIONAL DE LA RECHERCHE SCIENTIFIQUE AND THE LOSER IS... PLURALITY VOTING Jean-François LASLIER Cahier n° 2011-13 DEPARTEMENT D'ECONOMIE Route de Saclay 91128 PALAISEAU CEDEX (33) 1 69333033 http://www.economie.polytechnique.edu/ mailto:[email protected] And the loser is... Plurality Voting Jean-Franc¸ois Laslier Abstract This paper reports on a vote for choosing the best voting rules that was organized among the participants of the Voting Procedures workshop in July, 2010. Among 18 voting rules, Approval Voting won the contest, and Plurality Voting re- ceived no support at all. 1 Introduction Experts have different opinions as to which is the best voting procedure. The Lever- hulme Trust sponsored 2010 Voting Power in Practice workshop, held at the Chateau du Baffy, Normandy, from 30 July to 2 August 2010, was organized for the purpose of discussing this matter.
    [Show full text]
  • What's the Matter with Tie-Breaking? Improving Efficiency in School Choice
    American Economic Review 2008, 98:3, 669–689 http://www.aeaweb.org/articles.php?doi=10.1257/aer.98.3.669 What’s the Matter with Tie-Breaking? Improving Efficiency in School Choice By Aytek Erdil and Haluk Ergin* In several school choice districts in the United States, the student proposing deferred acceptance algorithm is applied after indifferences in priority orders are broken in some exogenous way. Although such a tie-breaking procedure preserves stability, it adversely affects the welfare of the students since it intro- duces artificial stability constraints. Our main finding is a polynomial-time algorithm for the computation of a student-optimal stable matching when pri- orities are weak. The idea behind our construction relies on a new notion which we call a stable improvement cycle. We also investigate the strategic properties of the student-optimal stable mechanism. (JEL C78, D82, I2) Until about a decade ago, children in the United States were assigned to public schools by the district they live in, without taking into account the preferences of their families. Such systems overlooked reallocations of seats which could Pareto improve welfare. Motivated by such con- cerns, several US cities, including New York City, Boston, Cambridge, Charlotte, Columbus, Denver, Minneapolis, Seattle, and St. Petersburg-Tampa, started centralized school choice pro- grams. Typically in these programs, each family submits a preference list of schools, including those outside their district, and then a centralized mechanism assigns students to schools based on the preferences. The mechanisms initially adopted by school choice programs were ad hoc, and did not perform well in terms of efficiency, incentives, and/or stability.
    [Show full text]
  • Voting with Rank Dependent Scoring Rules
    Voting with Rank Dependent Scoring Rules Judy Goldsmith, Jer´ omeˆ Lang, Nicholas Mattei, and Patrice Perny Abstract Positional scoring rules in voting compute the score of an alternative by summing the scores for the alternative induced by every vote. This summation principle ensures that all votes con- tribute equally to the score of an alternative. We relax this assumption and, instead, aggregate scores by taking into account the rank of a score in the ordered list of scores obtained from the votes. This defines a new family of voting rules, rank-dependent scoring rules (RDSRs), based on ordered weighted average (OWA) operators, which include all scoring rules, and many oth- ers, most of which of new. We study some properties of these rules, and show, empirically, that certain RDSRs are less manipulable than Borda voting, across a variety of statistical cultures and on real world data from skating competitions. 1 Introduction Voting rules aim at aggregating the ordinal preferences of a set of individuals in order to produce a commonly chosen alternative. Many voting rules are defined in the following way: given a vot- ing profile P, a collection of votes, where a vote is a linear ranking over alternatives, each vote contributes to the score of an alternative. The global score of the alternative is then computed by summing up all these contributed (“local”) scores, and finally, the alternative(s) with the highest score win(s). The most common subclass of these scoring rules is that of positional scoring rules: the local score of x with respect to vote v depends only on the rank of x in v, and the global score of x is the sum, over all votes, of its local scores.
    [Show full text]
  • Balinski's Majority Judgment
    BALINSKI’S MAJORITY JUDGMENT: A GOOD ALTERNATIVE FOR THE NETHERLANDS? Madeleine Michèlle Versteeg Faculty of Philosophy Erasmus University Rotterdam MA Filosofie van een Wetenschapsgebied Maatschappij- en Geesteswetenschappen Prof. Dr. H. de Swart Dr. P. Schuurman 18 ECTS Word count: 22.026 May 2017 1 A long habit of not thinking a thing wrong gives it a superficial appearance of being right, and raises at first a formidable outcry in defence of custom. But the tumult soon subsides. - Thomas Paine i ABSTRACT Social Choice Theory teaches us that the Majority Rule currently used in most democracies is not the most democratic method at all. In most democracies voters are supposed to vote for one alternative, either a candidate or a party, and the alternative with the most votes or with a majority of the votes is the winner. This method is prone to certain paradoxes and causes a major loss of information: voters may put only one cross before the name of one candidate, but usually have much more elaborate thought about the alternatives that they cannot express. As we shall see, majority voting may not elect the option that is the highest in esteem among the voters. This holds in particular for political elections, and is demonstrated by the very recent US presidential election where Hilary Clinton won the popular vote but was not elected. Alternative voting methods have been developed to solve this problem. Although none of them perfect, Balinski and Laraki’s method of Majority Judgment, based on evaluations instead of individual preferences, seems closest to aggregating individual opinions into a social or common ranking of the alternatives in a satisfactory way.
    [Show full text]
  • Ecole Polytechnique Departement D'economie
    ECOLE POLYTECHNIQUE CENTRE NATIONAL DE LA RECHERCHE SCIENTIFIQUE Judge : Don't Vote! Michel BALINSKI Rida LARAKI Novembre 2010 Cahier n° 2010-27 DEPARTEMENT D'ECONOMIE Route de Saclay 91128 PALAISEAU CEDEX (33) 1 69333033 http://www.economie.polytechnique.edu/ / mailto:[email protected] Judge : Don't Vote! 1 Michel Balinski 2 Rida Laraki Novembre 2010 Cahier n° 2010-27 Résumé: Cet article explique pourquoi (1) le modèle traditionnel de choix social n’est pas réaliste, (2) il ne peut en aucun cas proposer une méthode acceptable pour classer et élire, et (3) qu’un modèle plus réaliste implique inévitablement une seule méthode pour classer et élire ---le jugement majoritaire--- qui satisfait le mieux qu’il se peut les critères traditionnels de ce qui constitue une bonne méthode. Abstract: This article explains why (1) the traditional model of the theory of social choice misrepresents reality, (2) it cannot lead to acceptable methods of ranking and electing in any case, and (3) a more realistic model leads inevitably to one method of ranking and electing---majority judgment---that best meets the traditional criteria of what constitutes a good method. Mots clés : Paradoxe d’Arrow, paradoxe de Condorcet, patinage artistique, choix social, jugement majoritaire, manipulation stratégique, vote Key Words : Arrow’s paradox, Condorcet’s paradox, majority judgment, skating, social choice, strategic manipulation, voting Classification JEL: D71, C72 Classification AMS: 91A, 91C, 90B 1 Economics Department of the Ecole Polytechnique and CNRS, France. 2 Economics Department of the Ecole Polytechnique and CNRS, France. Judge : Don’t Vote! Michel Balinski and Rida Laraki The final test of a theory is its capacity to solve the problems which originated it.
    [Show full text]
  • The Prospects & Limits of Deliberative Democracy
    on the horizon: Dædalus Civil Wars & Global Disorder: Threats & Opportunities edited by Karl Eikenberry & Stephen Krasner with James D. Fearon, Bruce Jones & Stephen John Stedman, Stewart Patrick, Martha Crenshaw, Paul H. Wise & Michele Barry, Sarah Kenyon Lischer, Vanda Felbab-Brown, Hendrik Spruyt, Stephen Biddle, Will Reno, Aila M. Matanock & Miguel García-Sánchez, and Barry Posen Ending Civil Wars: Constraints & Possibilities Democracy Summer 2017 The Prospects & Limits of Deliberative Dædalus edited by Karl Eikenberry & Stephen Krasner Francis Fukuyama, Tanisha M. Fazal, Stathis N. Kalyvas, Journal of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences Steven Heydemann, Chuck Call & Susanna Campbell, Sumit Ganguly, Clare Lockhart, Thomas Risse & Summer 2017 Eric Stollenwerk, Tanja A. Börzel & Sonja Grimm, Seyoum Mesfi n & Abdeta Beyene, Nancy Lindborg & Joseph Hewitt, Richard Gowan & Stephen John Stedman, The Prospects & Limits of Lyse Doucet, and Jean-Marie Guéhenno Deliberative Democracy Native Americans & Academia edited by Ned Blackhawk, K. Tsianina Lomawaima, James S. Fishkin & Jane Mansbridge, guest editors Bryan McKinley Jones Brayboy, Philip J. Deloria, Loren Ghiglione, Douglas Medin, and Mark Trahant with Claus Offe · Nicole Curato John S. Dryzek · Selen A. Ercan Carolyn M. Hendriks · Simon Niemeyer Bernard Manin · Hélène Landemore Representing the intellectual community in its breadth Arthur Lupia · Anne Norton · Ian Shapiro and diversity, Dædalus explores the frontiers of Cristina Lafont · André Bächtiger · Simon Beste knowledge and issues of public importance. Alice Siu · Cass R. Sunstein · Roy William Mayega Lynn Atuyambe · Nathan Tumuhamye Julius Ssentongo · William Bazeyo Baogang He · Mark E. Warren U.S. $15; www.amacad.org; @americanacad Dædalus Journal of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences “The Prospects & Limits of Deliberative Democracy” Volume 146, Number 3; Summer 2017 James S.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Paradoxes Afflicting Various Voting Procedures Where One out of M Candidates (M ≥ 2) Must Be Elected*
    Review of Paradoxes Afflicting Various Voting Procedures Where One Out of m Candidates (m ≥ 2) Must Be Elected* Dan S. Felsenthal University of Haifa and Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science London School of Economics and Political Science Revised 26 May 2010 This paper will be presented at the Leverhulme Trust sponsored 2010 Voting Power in Practice workshop held at Chateau du Baffy, Normandy, France, 30 July – 2 August, 2010 Please send by email all communications regarding this paper to the author at: [email protected] or at [email protected] * I wish to thank Vincent Chua, Rudolf Fara, and Moshé Machover for helpful comments, as well as Hannu Nurmi for sending me several examples contained in this paper. No member of the Voting Power & Procedures (VPP) project at LSE, except myself, bears any responsibility whatsoever for the opinions and recommendations expressed here. Abstract The paper surveys 17 deterministic electoral procedures for selecting one out of two or more candidates, as well as the susceptibility of each of these procedures to various paradoxes. A detailed appendix exemplifies the paradoxes to which each electoral procedure is susceptible. It is concluded that from the perspective of vulnerability to serious paradoxes, as well as in light of additional technical-administrative criteria, Copeland’s or Kemeny’s proposed procedures are the most desirable. 1. Introduction Three factors motivated me to write this paper: • The recent passage (25 February 2010) by the British House of Commons of the Constitutional Reform and Governance Bill, clause #29 of which states that a referendum will be held by 31 October 2011 on changing the current single member plurality (aka first-past- the-post, briefly FPTP) electoral procedure for electing the British House of Commons to the (highly paradoxical) alternative vote (AV) procedure (aka Instant Runoff).
    [Show full text]