<<

124.1 ]

Hegel contra Schlegel; Kierkegaard contra de Man ayon roy

Irony as the negative is the way; it is not the truth but the way. —Søren Kierkegaard, The Concept of Irony1

rony is a permanent parabasis.” This cryptic declaration “ was made in 1797 by Friedrich Schlegel, the German Romantic Iwriter who inaugurated modern on .2 In an- cient Greek drama, parabasis is the moment when the continuity of the dramatic narrative is disrupted by the sudden intrusion of the playwright. By bringing the dramatic device of parabasis into vio- lent confrontation with the rhetorical of irony, Schlegel forces both concepts to exceed their respective parameters. In Schlegel’s hands, irony explodes its rhetorical confines, widening into a philo- sophical and existential category.3 Irony as a permanent parabasis, then, seems to be nothing less than the abyssal operation by which any claim to stability or continuity—be it artistic, philosophical, or existential—is incessantly undermined. Indeed, as Schlegel empha- sized in “On Incomprehensibility,” his 1800 metaessay on irony, one of irony’s basic features is its permanently disruptive force: its refusal to be neatly defined or circumscribed, its uncanny tendency to pro- ayon roy is a PhD candidate in English at liferate endlessly into further . At the essay’s climax, he gave the University of California, Berkeley. This voice to a question that has lost none of its urgency more than two essay derives from his dissertation, “The centuries after it was first posed: “What gods will be able to rescue After of Art: Kant, Hegel, and the Dialec- us from all these ironies?”4 tics of Aesthetic Irony.” His articles on po- Recent critics have devoted inordinate attention to Schlegel’s etry and have appeared or are forthcoming in the Journal of the of theory of irony not least because of its startling resonances with some Ideas, the Wallace Stevens Journal, Arizona of the central concerns of postmodernity. In his influential 1977 es- Quarterly, Gingko Tree Review, and Epoché: say “The Concept of Irony,” Paul de Man makes a persuasive case A Journal for the History of Philosophy. for conceiving Schlegel’s theory of irony as a bold anticipation of

[ © 2009 by the modern language association of america ] 107 108 Hegel contra Schlegel; Kierkegaard contra de Man [ PMLA

­poststructuralism. For de Man, irony as the Romantic irony in the twentieth century (and radically diachronic operation of permanent up to the present) has been willing to approach parabasis is a proto-­form of ’s the Hegel-­Schlegel debate from a broadly Kier­ principle of différance, which always already ke­gaard­ian perspective that would seek to interrupts—or differs and defers—any pur- honor the competing claims of both parties.5 portedly synchronic claim to sheer immediacy While Schlegel’s theory of irony has generated or self-­presence. The virtuosity of “The Con- seemingly endless commentary in recent criti- cept of Irony” consists in de Man’s sustained cal discourse, Hegel’s critique of Schlegel has effort to anchor his poststructuralist interpre- tended to be ignored or, at best, summarily tation of Schlegel’s theory of irony in a provoc- dismissed as little more than a historical curi- ative and subtle revaluation of some of the key osity. Indeed, Oskar Walzel’s 1938 pronounce- figures in modern philosophy: Johann Gottlieb ment can be said to have set the tone for nearly Fichte, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, and all subsequent treatments of Hegel’s agon with Søren Kierkegaard. As de Man recognized, Schlegel: “A quite great man, Hegel, speaks how we interpret Schlegel’s theory of irony has falsely out of blind hate about F. Schle­gel’s ro- far-­reaching implications for philosophical mantic irony.”6 In “The Concept of Irony,” de and critical discourse more generally. Man clearly participates in this general trend A brief survey of the reception of Schle- when, instead of engaging the details of He- gel’s theory of irony from Hegel up to the gel’s critique of Schlegel, he dismisses Hegel’s present will help us situate and assess de critique wholesale as a spurious attempt to Man’s poststructuralist approach to Schlegel. “defuse” irony by reducing it to a moment in Shortly after Schlegel presented his theory of “a dialectics of history” (170). irony in the journals Lyceum and Athenaeum The widespread neglect of Hegel’s cri- between 1797 and 1800, his contemporary tique of Schlegel in recent criticism can be Hegel launched a bitterly polemical campaign attributed in part to a burgeoning interest against Schlegel by trying to demonstrate that in Schlegel’s complex stance toward Fichte’s beneath Schlegel’s reveling in the abyssal, ver- post-­Kantian idealist philosophy. By making tiginous dimension of irony lurked a hyper­ subtle use of Schlegel’s copious philosophical inflated ego modeled on the absolute Ich at writings, recent critics have drawn our atten- the basis of Fichte’s philosophy. In his 1841 tion to the various ways Schlegel breaks with, doctoral dissertation, The Concept of Irony, and makes significant advances over, Fichte.7 the young Kierkegaard attempted single- Ernst Behler, the most important contem- ­handedly to raise this apparently harmless porary Schlegel critic, is typical in dating feud into a matter of world-­historical signifi- Schle­gel’s break with Fichte as early as 1796, cance. On the one hand, Kierkegaard con- a year before Schlegel even begins to develop ceded the force of Schlegel’s theory of irony his theory of irony (Ironie 143).8 This trend and made a powerful case for conceiving it as in recent scholarship has made it very easy the fundamental principle of a disenchanted to dismiss Hegel’s apparently straightfor- modernity. On the hand, he tried to re- ward attribution of Fichtean subjectivism to cover a substantive critique of irony from He- Schlegel’s theory of irony—a dismissal that, gel’s against Schlegel and ultimately in turn, seems to render irrelevant Hegel’s po- sided with Hegel in arguing for the need to lemical critique of irony itself. overcome the ironic stance. The guiding conviction of this essay, how- Curiously, however—with the important ever, is that critics have been too quick to dis- exceptions of the early and miss Hegel’s so-­called dismissal of Schlegel. Georg Lukács—virtually no commentator on To make my case, I will focus on an aspect of 124.1 ] Ayon Roy 109

Schlegel’s engagement with Fichte largely ig- long way toward illuminating the basic logic nored by recent criticism: Schlegel’s complex of his concept of irony, although it can hardly stance toward the philosophical category of be taken as definitive. In fact, between 1797 intuition (Anschauung).9 In the first two sec- and 1800 Schlegel felt compelled to define and tions of this essay, I hope to establish that the redefine irony in ever stranger and more cryp- Fich­tean category of intuition plays a signifi- tic formulations scattered throughout issues of cant role in Schlegel’s theory of irony and in the journals Lyceum and Athenaeum. It can be his philosophical thinking more generally. said that much of the complexity of Schlegel’s Schlegel’s philosophical lectures delivered be- theory of irony derives from his constant vac- tween 1800 and 1805 betray an aporetic stance illation between characterizations of the inner toward intuition: despite conscious efforts to logic of irony as such and descriptions of the repudiate the category, Schlegel ultimately ironist’s mood or state of mind.11 Schlegel en- remains committed to Fichte’s intuitional counters a unique problem in describing the epistemology.10 This will lay the groundwork ironist: how is it possible to offer an account for the third section, where I seek to resusci- of irony that does not illegitimately exempt tate the subtlety and force of Hegel’s critique the ironist from the operation of parabasis? of Schlegel’s theory of irony. I argue that the In other words, any description of the ironist primary target of Hegel’s critique is precisely seems haunted by the self-­contradiction that the unexamined epistemology of intuition at such an account requires smuggling in a stable the basis of Schlegel’s theory. position that goes unironized. In the In the course of this essay, I hope cumu- famous fragment 42 in his 1797 Lyceum Frag­ latively to demonstrate that de Man is guilty ments, Schlegel registers an acute awareness of what might be called a poststructuralist de- of this dilemma. Irony is presented there as fusing of irony. De Man’s dismissal of Hegel’s “the mood that surveys everything and rises critique of Schlegel proves to be sponsored by infinitely above all that is conditioned, even a series of interpretive moves that depend on above its own art, virtue, or genius.”12 If the the strategic suppression of manifold com- ironist truly rises above all that is conditioned, plexities in Schlegel’s theory of irony, Fichte’s Schlegel realizes, then it will not do to assume account of the absolute Ich, and Schlegel’s am- that the ironist’s subject position is somehow bivalent stance toward Fichte. In the essay’s unconditioned. Hence, the final clause of this final section, I suggest that de Man’s insights formulation insists that the ironic mood rises in “The Concept of Irony” can be traced to above even its own art, virtue, or genius. Yet a curiously willed moment of blindness: his this approach to handling the dilemma seems persistent refusal to honor Kierkegaard’s dis- plagued by an infinite regress, for the subject tinctive contribution to modern discourse on position of the ironist can in turn be ironized irony. Kierkegaard’s subtle recasting of He- only from a still-higher subjective standpoint gel’s critique of Schlegel, I argue, can be mobi- that remains unironized. lized as a powerful challenge both to standard Schlegel’s ingenious strategy for handling poststructuralist-­inflected critiques of Hegelian this problem is to build infinite regress into dialectics and to the of suspicion his conception of irony: irony becomes, para- dominating contemporary literary studies. doxically, the radicalization of regress itself, a regress made reflexively aware of its status as regress. In “On Incomprehensibility,” Schle- Schlegel’s Epistemology of Irony gel revels in what he calls “the irony of irony” In 1797 Schlegel characterized irony as “a per- (“die Ironie der Ironie”), irony’s relentless manent parabasis”—a formulation that goes a tendency to regress into higher-­order ironies 110 Hegel contra Schlegel; Kierkegaard contra de Man [ PMLA

(C h a ­r a k ­t e ­r i ­s t i ­k e n 369). To begin to appreci- infinitely teeming chaos.”16 One could , ate the centrality of the problem of regress in however, that this formulation proves insuffi- Schlegel’s theory of irony, we should consider ciently aware of the regress problem in that it Lyceum fragment 48, where Schlegel defines sets up too sharp a contrast between the sta- irony as “the form of ” (“der Form ble, unironized subject position of the ironist’s des Paradoxen”; 153). In Lyceum fragment clear consciousness and the infinitely teeming 108, irony’s paradoxical form is more specifi- chaos of which the ironist is conscious. A year cally articulated as containing and arousing or two earlier, in an underdiscussed fragment “a feeling of indissoluble antagonism between in his Philosophische Lehr­jahre, Schlegel offers the unconditioned and the conditioned.”13 a subtly different formulation of irony that In other words, far from rising above the handles the regress problem by collapsing the realm of the conditioned by straightfor- distance between the ironist and that which is wardly inhabiting a higher, purportedly un- ironized: “Irony is clear χα [chaos] in agility, conditioned standpoint, the ironist faces the intellectual intuition of an eternal χα. . . .”17 If more daunting challenge of inhabiting both in the Ideen formulation irony is defined as realms at once—or, at least, shuttling con- the clear consciousness of chaos, in this ear- stantly between them. Not surprisingly, in lier, violently paradoxical formulation, the the Athe­nae­um Fragments Schlegel repeat- genitive disintegrates: irony is clear χα, that edly describes irony as a kind of shuttling or explosive point at which clarity and chaos hovering between antithetical extremes. In impossibly meet. In the next clause, Schlegel Athenaeum fragment 51, for instance, irony invokes the Fichtean category of intellectual is characterized as the “constant alternation intuition as a means of conveying this radi- of self-­creation and self-­destruction.”14 Behler cal ironizing of the very distance between the convincingly argues that this “rhythm of self- ironist and the ironist’s medium. ­creation and self-­destruction, of enthusiasm In his 1800 Dialogues on Poetry, pub- and skepticism” is the “fundamental charac- lished in the same Athenaeum issue as Ideen, teristic of Schlegel’s conception of irony.”15 Schlegel once again characterizes irony in Hence, there seem to be three basic coor- terms of intuition: “We therefore adhere only dinates in Schlegel’s theory of irony: the two to the meaning of the Whole; what stimulates, first-­order ironies of enthusiasm and skepti- moves, occupies, and amuses individually the cism and the second-­order irony of irony, sense, the heart, the understanding, and the which oscillates continually between the first- imagination appears to us only as a figure, a ­order ironies. This master frame helps fore- means to the intuition of the Whole, to which ground an aspect of Schlegel’s theory of irony we raise ourselves in an instant.”18 Notice that largely neglected in the critical literature: his this formulation is structurally identical to occasional linkage of irony with intuition, Schlegel’s 1797 definition of irony as a “mood” one of the key categories in post-­Kantian ide- that rises above everything conditioned. alist epistemology. In this case, the realm of the conditioned We can begin to explore irony’s curious becomes a realm of mere figures, and the affiliation with intuition by comparing two mechanism by which the ironist rises above of Schlegel’s formulations of irony that are this realm is an instantaneous intuition of a almost, but not quite, identical. In his 1800 rather mysterious Whole. (Not surprisingly, Ideen fragment 69, contained in the penul- it is precisely this synchronic dimension of timate issue of the Athenaeum, Schlegel viv- Schlegel’s theory of irony that gets suppressed idly describes second-­order irony: “Irony is in de Man’s account.) At this point, it should clear consciousness of eternal agility, of the remain an open question whether Schlegel’s 124.1 ] Ayon Roy 111 invocation of intuition really avoids the re- into infinity, and in this way consciousness gress problem or simply masks it: by what cannot be explained. The main reason for this right, after all, does Schlegel exempt this in- impossibility is that consciousness is always tuition of the Whole from ironic parabasis? taken as a state of mind, as an object, which As far as I am aware, these are the only always requires another subject.22 two formulations in Schlegel’s entire corpus in which irony is explicitly linked to the fac- So long as self-­consciousness is understood as ulty of intuition. However, this affiliation of being aware of oneself as object, there seems irony with intuition gains significance once no way to avoid an infinite regress: since ev- we note the frequency of Schlegel’s invocation ery object requires a subject that is aware of the of intuition throughout the Athenaeum. Intu- object, self-­consciousness itself becomes the ition (Anschauung) and intellectual intuition object of a higher-­order self-­consciousness, ad (i n ­t e l ­l e k ­t u ­ale Anschauung ) are frequently ex- infinitum. The only way to avoid this problem alted in the Athenaeum as faculties capable of infinite regress, Fichte goes on to argue, is of overcoming the limitations of rational or to conceive self-­consciousness as the “immedi- discursive modes of thought.19 The exemplary ate” (“unmittelbar”)—that is, nondiscursive— passage in this regard has to be Schlegel’s 1800 consciousness of the unity of subject and object Ideen fragment 150: “One can neither explain (W i s ­s e n ­s c h a ft s ­l e h r e 30). nor comprehend the universe—one can only In his 1797 Introductions to the Wis­ intuit and reveal it.”20 Passages such as these sen­schafts­lehre, Fichte characterizes this offer preliminary evidence—against many re- immediate consciousness as the “fact-­act” cent critics—that even in 1800 Schlegel had (“Tat­hand­lung”) by which “the primordial not entirely repudiated Fichte’s philosophy. self” (“das ursprüngliche Ich”) comes into existence (Introductions 48; Zur theoretischen P h i ­l o ­s o ­p h i e 465). In a decisive move, Fichte Intuition as a Philosophical Problem: identifies this immediate consciousness with Fichte, Hegel, Schlegel none other than intellectual intuition: “This To begin to appreciate Schlegel’s complex intuiting of himself that is ascribed to the stance toward intuition and intellectual intu- philosopher, in performing the act whereby ition we will need a basic understanding of the self arises for him, I call intellectual intu­ the philosophical heritage of these categories. ition.”23 For Fichte, we might say, the primor- One of the primary motivations of Fichte’s dial Ich itself emerges in—and as—an act of philosophy—in particular, in the texts collec- intellectual intuition through which the im- tively known as his later Jena W i s ­s e n ­s c h a ft s ­ mediate unity of subject and object is directly lehre—is to establish the precise nature and registered. Fichte soon goes on to affirm that status of self-­consciousness.21 As a starting “intellectual intuition is the only firm stand- point, Fichte indulges in a thought experi- point for all philosophy.”24 ment that he believes can reveal the unique But what, more concretely, does Fichte status of self-­consciousness: mean by intellectual intuition? At various points in his work, Fichte seems to vacillate I am conscious of an object B, but I cannot be between what might be called logical and conscious of B without being conscious of my- self. . . . I am, however, only conscious of myself phenomenological accounts of intellectual in- in that I am conscious of consciousness. I must tuition.25 On the one hand, Fichte insists that therefore be conscious of . . . the consciousness since intellectual intuition is the condition of of consciousness. How will I become conscious possibility of all empirical consciousness, in- of this consciousness? This process proceeds tellectual intuition itself is never present in 112 Hegel contra Schlegel; Kierkegaard contra de Man [ PMLA

consciousness (Introductions 9; Z u r t h e ­o ­r e ­t i ­ Fich­te’s philosophy begins with the immediacy schen Philosophie 425). As he puts it, “[T]here of intuition, Hegel’s “phenomenology of spirit” is no immediate, isolated consciousness of begins with mediation and ends with an im- intellectual intuition.”26 On the other hand, mediacy earned through mediation. Fichte sometimes suggests that intellectual This background should help us avoid re- intuition is “demonstrable in consciousness” ductive accounts of Schlegel’s complex stance (“im Bewuβtseyn nachzuweisen”) and hence toward the Fichtean category of intellectual phenomenologically verifiable Introductions( intuition and should set into relief Schlegel’s 14; Zur theoretischen Philosophie 428). In this distinctive engagement with post-­Kantian vein, he claims that the “faculty of intellec- idealism more generally. In “The Concept of tual intuition” is something that “everyone Irony,” de Man offers a problematic account must find immediately in himself; otherwise, of Schlegel’s agon with Fichte in large part he will never make its acquaintance.”27 because he fails to honor the complexity of In his 1807 Phenomenology of Spirit, Hegel Fich­te’s and Schlegel’s philosophical posi- subjects to radical critique the foundationalist tions. According to de Man, Fichte’s radical intuitionism espoused by Fichte, among oth- insight is that the self is a “linguistic” con- ers. First, he attacks intuition’s nonconceptual struct rather than an “experiential” or “phe- immediacy: the content of intuition is doomed nomenological” category (172–73). De Man to be vacuous, Hegel argues, so long as it ex- then argues that Fichte’s entire dialectic of the cludes conceptual mediation. The “rapturous self turns out to be an “ of tropes”—a haziness” (“Begeisterung und Trübheit”) of systematic narrative of the circulation of rhe- intuition is a mere “empty depth” (“eine leere torical tropes as they compose and decom- Tiefe”), “an intensity without content” (“eine pose the linguistic self (176–77). However, de ge­halt­lose Intensität”; Phenomenology 4; Phä­ Man is only able to sustain this allegorical n o ­m e ­n o ­l o ­g i e 17). Second, Hegel claims that interpretation by ignoring both Fichte’s key the radically subjective category of intuition category of intellectual intuition and Fichte’s can never serve as the objective basis for phi- repeated insistence that the absolute Ich is losophy. Intuition, as Hegel puts it, “merely more than a linguistic construct since—as we gives free rein both to the contingency of the have seen—it serves as the ontological condi- content within it, and to its own caprice.”28 tion of possibility of all consciousness. Third, in the introduction to Phenomenology, Schlegel accepts the strictly linguistic Hegel interrogates foundationalism itself—the status of the self, de Man goes on to argue, very urge to “ground” philosophy on some but rejects Fich­te’s move of inscribing this lin- purportedly absolute principle or assertion. guistic self within a grand narrative. Schle­gel­ Philosophy must not be grounded on a “bare ian irony, as de Man puts it, is the “necessary assurance” since “one bare assurance is worth undoing” of Fichte’s allegory of tropes (179). just as much as another.”29 All foundationalist Tellingly, however, de Man ignores Schlegel’s philosophizing remains haunted by the pos- philosophical lectures, which suggest a more sibility that its supposedly presuppositionless vexed stance toward Fichte than de Man al- starting point in fact smuggles in a host of lows. Two of Schlegel’s lecture courses (neither presuppositions that escape interrogation. On of which has been translated into En­glish) are He­gel’s account, instead of starting with some particularly relevant for our purposes: his absolute ground, philosophy must be “an expo- course Transcendental Philosophy offered at sition of how knowledge makes its appearance” the University of Jena between 1800 and 1801 (“die Dar­stel­lung des erscheinenden Wissens”; (at least part of which Hegel attended)30 and Phenomenology 49; Phänomenologie 72). So if his course The Development of Philosophy 124.1 ] Ayon Roy 113 in Twelve Books delivered to a private audi- tures, they generally lack any talk of intel- ence in Köln between 1804 and 1805.31 These lectual intuition. Schlegel here singles out for lecture courses place Schlegel somewhere criticism the mystical epistemological basis of between Fichte and Hegel. Schlegel advances intuition: its source of cognition is “a super- trenchant criticisms of intuition years before natural, higher revelation” (“eine übernaturli- Hegel’s Phenomenology appears, yet he never che, höhere Offenbarung”; Philosophische seems willing—or able—to take the Hegelian V o r ­l e ­s u n ­g e n 258). Yet at this early point in the step of repudiating the category altogether. Köln lectures he still seems convinced that Early in the Jena lectures, Schlegel regis- the category of intuition can be retained so ters skepticism about the faculty of intuition: long as its epistemological basis is revamped. “The longing for the infinite must always be He first proposes what he callsSelbst ­an­schau­ a longing. It cannot occur in the form of in- ung: “the investigation of all sources of phi- tuition. The ideal can never be intuited. The losophy leads us to self-­intuition as the most ideal is produced through speculation.”32 certain starting point of philosophy.”34 What seems a straightforward dismissal of the However, Schlegel’s confidence in the category of Anschauung, however, soon proves category of Selbstanschauung wanes as he more complicated. Before long, he advances begins to generate powerful general objec- intellectual intuition as nothing less than the tions to the notion of Anschauung. Recall that absolute basis of his philosophical system: Fichte appeals to the category of intellectual “The consolidation of the entire primordial intuition as a means of avoiding the infinite consciousness, when it comes into conscious- regress involved in any attempt to conceive ness—that is, the primordial consciousness self-­consciousness as an object. Here Schlegel intuited and understood—is intellectual in­ cleverly turns this argument implicitly against tuition. The absolute thesis of all philosophy Fichte by arguing that intuition turns out to cannot be proved; it has absolutely nothing fall prey to the very infinite regress that it is to do with proof; it contains its proof within meant to overcome: “This capacity to be the itself.”33 Schlegel clearly subscribes here to ‘I’ of ‘I’ is, however, infinite; for just as there is Fichte’s foundationalist intuitionism in estab- an intuition of intuition, there can just as well lishing intellectual intuition as the absolute be an intuition of intuition of intuition and thesis of all philosophy. However, this passage so on into infinity; this has absolutely no lim- also reveals some of the subtle ways in which its.”35 Shortly thereafter, Schlegel argues that Schlegel implicitly reworks Fichte’s doctrine any model of Anschauung faces the insuper- of intellectual intuition. While Fichte himself able problem that fixing an object intuitively vacillates between conceiving intellectual in- is tantamount to destroying it. “As for intu- tuition as a state of empirical consciousness ition,” he writes, “it has already adequately and as the logical condition of possibility of been shown that it can afford no cognition in empirical consciousness, Schlegel claims that the actual sense precisely because it crushes intellectual intuition is the coming to con- the inner of the object—the living, the sciousness of primordial consciousness. And free and moving.”36 For Schlegel, any theory whereas Fichte rarely appeals to direct self- of intuition faces a Heisenbergian dilemma: ­evidence in his justification of intellectual in the very process of delimiting an object as intuition, Schlegel insists that intellectual in- an object, intuition necessarily falsifies it. An- tuition contains its proof within itself. ticipating Hegel’s critique of An­schau­ung as The Köln lectures delivered a few years an “intensity without content,” Schlegel con- later reveal an even more conflicted stance cludes that intuition “can afford no cognition toward intuition. In contrast to the Jena lec- in the actual sense.” 114 Hegel contra Schlegel; Kierkegaard contra de Man [ PMLA

The force of these objections compels tivism to the theory of irony fails to honor the him to renounce his earlier espousal of the actual complexities of Schlegel’s engagement category of self-­intuition as the basis for phi- with Fichte. Second, they argue that Hegel’s losophy. He turns instead to the category of exclusive emphasis on a single aspect of irony “feeling” (“Gefühl”), yet he soon admits that at the expense of other equally fundamental feeling could just as well be called “spiritual aspects betrays an impoverished understand- intuition” (“geistige Anschauung”) or “aes- ing of Schlegel’s theory. Indeed, there seems no thetic intuition” (“ästhetische Anschauung”; dearth of evidence to support either of these P h i ­l o ­s o ­p h i ­sche Vorlesungen 355). Evidently, claims. Critics frequently point to Hegel’s despite his uneasiness about intuition, Schle- treatment of Schlegelian irony in a passage in gel nonetheless feels compelled to invoke the his Lectures on the History of Philosophy: category because he insists on grounding his philosophical system in a nonconceptual form This [Schlegel’s] irony is an application of of cognition. Hence, Benjamin aptly char- Fichte’s philosophy, it emerges from Fichte’s acterizes Schlegel’s seemingly paradoxical philosophy. . . . It is when subjective con- enterprise as the search for “an unintuitable sciousness is finished with all things: “It is I who through my cultured thoughts can intuition” (“eine unanschauliche Intuition”; negate all determinations of right, moral- Der Be­griff 42).37 ity, good, etc.; and I know that if anything Schlegel’s self-­defeating efforts to theorize seems good to me I can just as well subvert a nonintuitional model of immediate cogni- it. I know myself absolutely as the master of tion culminates in this astonishing claim: “The all these determinations—I can make them infinite fullness as such cannot be intuited; one valid or also not; all things are only true to must then assume an intuition that can never me insofar as they please me now.”39 be completed. This concept comes only . . . through the foreboding, prophesying feeling in Beginning with the vague assertion that human consciousness.”38 If the infinite fullness Schlegel’s theory of irony emerges from Fich- cannot be intuited, why must we then assume te’s philosophy, Hegel proceeds to lampoon such an incomplete intuition, such a mysteri- the ironic consciousness as an absolute sub- ous faculty of prophecy? Why not rather re- jectivity confident in its mastery over all its pudiate the category of intuition altogether, determinations. as Hegel does? Over the course of his Jena and Scattered passages throughout Hegel’s Köln lectures, as we have seen, the category of work echo these sentiments, inviting critics to intuition reemerges in various terminological dismiss his understanding of Romantic irony guises. Ultimately, Schlegel remains commit- as hopelessly one-­sided. Behler’s response to ted to an aporetic epistemology doomed to Hegel’s critique of irony is typical: collapse repeatedly into the very intuitionism it seeks so desperately to overcome. One can say that it is precisely at this point that Hegel’s understanding of irony errs com- pletely and his conception of the absolute Recuperating Hegel’s Metacritique of power of the ironic self proves definitely false. Schlegel For the critique that expresses itself in irony is no outwardly directed irony that merely We can turn now to Hegel’s critique of Schle- wants to deceive and bewilder but a self- gel’s theory of irony. The standard dismissal ­critique of the artist directed toward himself of Hegel’s critique is based on two premises. (“­self-­destruction”), which should protect First, critics claim that Hegel’s seemingly him from investing too much trust, hubris, straightforward attribution of Fichtean subjec- and self-­importance in “­self-­creation.”40 124.1 ] Ayon Roy 115

Recall from the first section of this essay that In fact, in the short section of his Lec­ Schlegel’s theory of irony involves three ba- tures on the History of Philosophy devoted to sic coordinates: the two first-­order ironies Schlegel, Hegel specifically isolates Schlegel’s of self-­creation and self-­destruction and the problematic attempt to develop forms of sen- second-­order irony of irony, which alternates sation that could avoid Fichtean subjectivism: between self-­creation and self-­destruction. “The Fichtean standpoint of subjectivity has Working from this schema, Behler swiftly retained its character of being unphilosophi- dispenses with Hegel’s critique of irony. On cally worked out, and arrived at its comple- Behler’s account, Hegel mistakes the irony of tion in forms belonging to sensation which self-­creation for Schlegelian irony tout court, were in part the effort—futile though it was— thereby neglecting—or perhaps willfully to get beyond subjectivity.”43 Hegel then gets ignoring—the equally important moment of quite canny. He implicitly links the Fichtean self-­destruction within irony.41 subjectivism at the core of Schlegel’s theory of I hope to demonstrate, however, that He- irony to the specifically intuitional subjectiv- gel’s understanding of Schlegel’s theory of ism of Friedrich Schleiermacher.44 In his 1799 irony and its allegedly Fichtean underpinnings work On Religion, Schleiermacher—himself is significantly more nuanced and penetrating an occasional contributor to the Athenaeum— than critics have been willing to acknowledge. repeatedly privileges the faculty of intuition The first step in making my case is to establish (An­schauung­ ) as the primary means for the that Hegel was in fact fully aware of the com- direct apprehension of God.45 That Schlegel plexities of Schlegel’s engagement with Fichte. and fellow early Romantics frequently praised It has already been noted that Hegel attended On Religion in the Athenaeum was not lost on at least some of Schlegel’s Jena lectures, Hegel. So Hegel proceeds to launch a joint which reveal Schlegel’s vexed stance toward attack on what he perceives to be the shared Fichte. That Hegel did not take Schlegel to be intuitional basis of Schlegel’s theory of irony a straightforward Fichtean is also clear from and Schleiermacher’s epistemology: a remark in his Aesthetics: “Friedrich von Schlegel, like Schelling, started out from the In accordance with this principle, the spiri- Fich­tean standpoint, Schelling to go beyond tual living essence has then transformed into it entirely, Friedrich von Schlegel to develop self-­consciousness, and it intends to know the it in his own way and to tear himself away unity of spirit immediately from itself, and in from it.”42 Recent critics have been so eager to this immediacy to know it in a poetic or at show the various ways Schlegel moves beyond least a prophetic manner. As regards the po- Fichte that they tend to neglect those aspects etic manner, it knows the life and person of the Absolute immediately in an intuition, not of Schlegel’s thinking that remain persistently in the Concept, and it thinks it would lose the Fich­tean: most notably, as I have tried to show, Whole as Whole, as a self-­penetrating unity, his stance toward intuition. Hegel proves here were it not to express the same in poetic to be a subtler critic of Schlegel in his careful form; and what it thus expressed poetically distinction between a complete overcoming of is the intuition of the personal life of self- Fich­te’s philosophy and a more immanent— ­consciousness.—But the truth is absolute and tortured—negotiation with it. Indeed, as movement. . . .46 a characterization of Schlegel’s engagement with Fich­tean intuition, Hegel’s remark can Indeed, the details of this passage suggest hardly be bettered: Schlegel tries precisely to Schlegel as the primary target. In his al- develop the category of intuition “in his own lusions to knowing the unity of spirit “in a way and to tear himself away from it.” poetic or at least a prophetic manner,” Hegel 116 Hegel contra Schlegel; Kierkegaard contra de Man [ PMLA

registers an acute awareness of Schlegel’s vari- the debasement of the same to appearance in ous efforts to theorize a nonintuitional mode the subject and to appearing for others.49 of cognition—including Schlegel’s last-­ditch attempt to develop the category of prophecy What should not be missed is Hegel’s careful in the Köln lectures. In his reference to intuit- distinction between Fichte’s genuinely specu- ing the Whole as Whole, Hegel may even have lative philosophy and Schlegel’s decidedly in mind Schlegel’s Athenaeum definition of nonspeculative appropriation of Fichte. As we irony as the “intuition of the Whole.” Hegel’s have seen, whereas Fichte never straightfor- point is that all of Schlegel’s efforts to over- wardly aligns intuition with immediate cer- come intuitionism are doomed to fail so long tainty, Schlegel makes precisely this dogmatic as Schlegel remains committed to the dogma identification in his philosophical lectures of immediacy (Unmittelbarkeit). when he claims that intellectual intuition In a dense passage in his essay “Solger’s “contains its proof within itself.” For Hegel, Posthumous Writings and Correspondence,” Schlegel’s assumption of the radical presup- Hegel most decisively links his critique of positionlessness of his intuitional epistemol- Fich­tean intuition to his critique of Schlegel’s ogy itself turns out to be an unexamined theory of irony. He begins by rehearsing, in presupposition. Hegel then goes on to argue condensed form, his critique of Fichte’s in- that Schlegel’s merely subjective affirmation tuitional epistemology. He credits Fichte for of Fichtean idealism directly sponsors his bringing to consciousness “the highest start- theory of irony. ing point for the problem of philosophy”47— In addressing Hegel’s critique of Schle- namely, the task of developing “the particular gel, critics have failed to acknowledge what from the presuppositionless, the universal.”48 emerges here as the strict inseparability of However, the principle Fichte invokes to carry Hegel’s critique of irony from his critique of out this task is “itself a presupposition” (“selbst intuition. As a result, they can easily dismiss eine Voraussetzung”; Berliner Schrif­ten 254). It Hegel’s attribution of Fichtean subjectivism to is at this point that he specifically targets Fich- Schle­gel­ian irony. On my account, however, te’s intuitional epistemology, one that is shown Hegel’s general alignment of the ironic sub- to underwrite Schlegel’s theory of irony: ject with the Fichtean subject should be taken as the corollary to his more pointed—and A principle must also be proved, not require more fundamental—metacritique of Schle- that it be accepted from intuition, immediate gel’s theory of irony: that is, his critique of certainty, inner revelation, or as one may call irony’s underlying epistemology of intuition. it in a word, in good faith; the requirement The success of Hegel’s metacritique of irony of proof, however, has become something would then depend on the plausibility of his obsolete for the many monochromatic phi- claim about irony’s intuitional basis. losophies of the time. . . . In this cited form My examination of Schlegel’s philosophi- such negativity has remained only in the cal lectures in the previous section has, I hope, one-­sided, finite affirmation that it has as I. already made plausible Hegel’s identification In this merely subjective affirmation, it has of an intuitionism at the heart of Schle­gel’s been taken up from Fichtean philosophy by Friedrich von Schlegel with a lack of under- epistemology, so it remains to be shown how standing of the speculative and a setting aside this intuitional epistemology infects Schlegel’s of the same; and it has been so torn from the theory of irony. Let us turn first to a revealing field of thought that, applied directly to real- sentence from Hegel’s discussion of Roman- ity, it has flourished intoirony , into the nega- tic irony in his Lectures on the History of Phi­ tion of the liveliness of reason and truth and losophy: “The divine is said to be the purely 124.1 ] Ayon Roy 117 negative attitude, the intuition, the conscious- In the fascinating oral supplement to ness of the vanity of everything. . . .”50 Hegel section 140 of Elements of the Philosophy of provocatively claims here that intuition is the Right—not available in either of the extant mode of consciousness by which the ironist En­glish translations of the text—Hegel traces registers the vanity of everything. Hegel’s fre- the ironist’s absolute subjectivity to an un- quent attacks on the of elevation per- derlying Fichtean epistemology of conviction vading Schlegel’s descriptions of irony then (Ü b e r ­z e u ­g u n g ): suddenly become understandable: the epis- temological means by which ironists elevate [I]n Friedrich v. Schlegel’s particular concep- themselves above everything is none other tion of the “I,” this “I” is itself portrayed as than the faculty of intuition.51 We need only God with respect to the good and beautiful, recall Schlegel’s 1800 definition of irony as so that objective good is only a figment of my conviction and only gains support through the “intuition of the Whole, to which we raise me, and I emerge as lord and master over it ourselves in an instant.” Although Schlegel and can make it disappear. Insofar as I en- rarely links irony with intuition, Hegel’s point counter something objective, it is at the same is that those occasional instances when Schle- time nugatory for me, and I therefore hover gel does establish this link betray irony’s fun- over a monstrous space, from which I call damental structure: ironists raise themselves forth and destroy shapes.53 to the Whole by means of the immediate per- ception of intuition. For Fichte, conviction is a prerational form In section 140 of his Elements of the Phi­ of certainty, and he often claims that con- losophy of Right, Hegel interrogates the ironist’s viction is apodictically true: as he puts it, declaration of the vanity of everything: the “conviction of error is utterly impossible.”54 form of irony “is not only the vanity of all ethi- Hegel’s implicit suggestion is that Schlegel’s cal content in the way of rights, duties, and laws theory of irony depends on a tacit identifica- . . . but it is also the form of subjective vanity: it tion of the Fichtean categories of intuition knows itself as the vanity of all content and in and conviction as a spurious means of secur- this knowledge knows itself as the Absolute.”52 ing intuition’s apodictic validity. The ironist’s This passage offers us a very precise way of han- self-­proclaimed mastery over “the good and dling Behler’s critique of Hegel. On Beh­ler’s ac- the beautiful” masks an absolute subjectivity count, Hegel treats the self-­creation aspect of for which the external world is a mere sub- irony as irony tout court, thereby neglecting the jective projection: “objective good is only a equally fundamental aspect of self-­destruction. figment” of the ironist’s conviction. The bril- However, this passage suggests that the primary liantly polemical final sentence targets the target of Hegel’s critique is in fact the second- boundless hubris of an absolute subjectivity ­order irony hovering between the first-­order hovering between shapes that it alternately ironies of self-­creation and self-­destruction. creates and destroys. It is no coincidence that The passage’s final clause is crucial: at precisely Hegel employs here the language of hovering the moment that the ironist declares itself (schweben)—the very language Schlegel typi- to be vain—the moment, we can say, of self- cally invokes to describe the ironist’s move- ­destruction—it elevates itself to the status of the ment between enthusiasm and skepticism.55 Absolute. What Hegel attacks, in other words, So if Schlegel presents his notion of irony is the underlying absolute subjectivity that ar- of irony as a hovering between what seem the rogates to itself the capacity to alternate at will equally fundamental extremes of enthusiasm between self-­creation and self-­destruction, be- and skepticism, Hegel points out that such tween enthusiasm and skepticism. second-­order hovering itself depends on a 118 Hegel contra Schlegel; Kierkegaard contra de Man [ PMLA

ground-­level acceptance of enthusiasm. Let tal inadequacy—one might even say incoher- us revisit Schlegel’s 1800 definition of irony as ence—of irony as a self-­sustaining paradigm. “clear consciousness of eternal agility, of the A truly thorough­going irony would radicalize infinitely teeming chaos.” Notice that Schle- its own instability and thereby ironize the ab- gel defines irony not simply as eternal agility solute subject (the “primordial consciousness” but as the clear consciousness of eternal agil- from the Jena lectures) that gets smuggled into ity. In a Philosophische Lehrjahre fragment, as Schlegel’s theory of irony. As soon as this ab- we have seen, Schlegel redefines the ironist’s solute subject is itself subjected to irony, irony “clear consciousness” as the “intellectual emerges in its truth as a dialectical moment intuition of an eternal χα [chaos].” It is as if that ultimately supersedes itself—that is, as Schlegel comes clean here in establishing the Hegel puts it in his Aesthetics, the necessary faculty of intellectual intuition as the enabling moment of “infinite absolute negativity” (“un- precondition for the ironist’s agile hovering endliche absolute Negativität”; 160; Vorlesun­ between enthusiasm and skepticism. From a gen über die Äs­the­tik 211). Ironically enough, Hegelian vantage, however, the Schlegelian it is Schlegel who expresses this Hegelian view ironist seems not quite agile enough, since of irony as a self-­sublating moment years be- the ironist’s own intuitive faculty remains fore Hegel comes on the scene. In a private unironized. In effect, Hegel applies Schlegel’s notebook dated around the time of his Ath­ argument in the Köln lectures about the in- enaeum contributions, Schlegel observes with finite regress of intuition to the intuitional startling honesty, “Perfect, absolute irony epistemology at the basis of Schlegel’s theory ceases to be irony and becomes serious.”56 of irony. Hegel’s basic point is that Schlegel’s invocation of intellectual intuition does not Toward a Dialectical Hermeneutics so much resolve the problem of infinite re- gress as mask it. If irony is the intellectual De Man acknowledges at the outset of “The intuition of an eternal chaos, then this intu- Concept of Irony” that the title of his essay ition will in turn have to become the object of “is taken from Kierkegaard, who wrote the a higher-­order intuition, ad infinitum. best book on irony that’s available” (163). Cu- Hegel’s metacritique of Schlegelian irony riously, however, instead of specifying what thus proves to be strictly immanent: it seeks to makes Kierkegaard’s The Concept of Irony the demonstrate that a problem internal to Schle- best contribution to discourse on irony, de gel’s theory of irony—namely, the problem of Man goes on to lump Kierkegaard with Hegel infinite regress—is ultimately insuperable, and to argue that both of them are guilty of and Schlegel’s last-­ditch recourse to intellec- reducing irony to a moment in “a dialectics tual intuition simply reinstates the problem of history” (170). Why this ambiguous ges- in another form. For Hegel, then, Schlegelian ture of avowing his debt to Kierkegaard only irony turns out to be insufficiently radical in to suppress the subtlety and force of Kier­ke­ that it fails to follow through on its own inner gaard’s argument? It is as if de Man opens his logic. In the Jena and Köln lectures, Schlegel essay with a vague paean to Kierkegaard to is unable to repudiate the category of intu- excuse himself from confronting the philo- ition even in the face of his own strong doubts sophical and hermeneutic implications of about the category. From Hegel’s metaper- Kier­ke­gaard’s distinctive recasting of the spective, this point of equivocation in Schle- Hegel-­Schlegel debate. Indeed, I hope to dem- gel’s epistemology results in a permanently onstrate that Kierkegaard’s unique interven- unstable theory of irony; and irony’s inherent tion threatens the foundations of de Man’s instability, in turn, attests to the fundamen- poststructuralist hermeneutics. 124.1 ] Ayon Roy 119

De Man is no doubt correct to claim that familiar reproach that Hegel proves over­eager Kierkegaard adopts an essentially Hegelian to sublate the moment of negativity into his stance toward irony. Kierkegaard clearly fol- positive system, thereby failing to honor nega- lows Hegel in arguing that Schlegel’s theory of tivity as such—or what Derrida variously calls irony is grounded in an inflation of Fichte’sIch in Writing and “negativity without into what he calls “an exaggerated subjectiv- reserve” (259), the “experience of absolute dif- ity, a subjectivity raised to the second power” ference” (263), or “the play outside meaning” (275). However, Kierkegaard’s basic move is (274). Hegelian Aufhebung, as Derrida puts it, to recover and amplify an aspect of Hegel’s “conserves the stakes, remains master of the critique of Schlegel that remains almost en- play, limiting it and putting it to work by giv- tirely submerged under Hegel’s polemics (and ing it form and meaning” (255).59 to which I briefly alluded at the end of the Although this is not the occasion for an previous section): namely, Hegel’s favorable assessment of Derrida’s alternative model of construal of irony as a dialectical moment of negativity, I can at least begin to interrogate “infinite absolute negativity” (328). Kier­ke­ Der­ri­da’s critique of Hegelian negativity. Tar- gaard expresses the central thesis of his disser- rying with the intricacies of Hegel’s critique of tation in a dense aphorism that serves as this irony can help us appreciate that Hegel’s notion essay’s epigraph: “Irony as the negative is the of negativity is more radical and nuanced than way; it is not the truth but the way” (327). The Derrida allows.60 In Phenomenology of Spirit, polemical cast of Hegel’s critique of Schlegel Hegel vividly characterizes his dialectical enter- occludes the fact that Hegel accords an impor- prise as “the way of despair” (“Weg der Ver­zwei­ tant place to irony in his philosophical system flung”; 49; Phänomenologie 7 2 ) . K i e r ­k e ­g a a r d , by conceiving it as the fundamental moment in effect, builds irony into the core of Hegelian of infinite absolute negativity. And lest we as- dialectics by conceiving the way of despair as sume that this is a term of censure, we should none other than the way of irony itself—that recall that Hegel was the foremost champion is, the way of infinite absolute negativity. From of the need to “tarry with the negative.”57 By a Kierkegaardian perspective, what Derrida’s insisting on irony as the way, Kierkegaard critique misses is precisely the absoluteness of foregrounds the central role of irony in Hegel’s Hegel’s moment of infinite absolute negativity. own phenomenology of spirit and provides the As Hegel’s critique of irony demonstrates, the resources to defend Hegelian dialectics against absolutization of negativity means nothing less recent poststructuralist-­inflected critiques than pursuing the immanent logic of a given originating in the work of Derrida. stance to the point where that stance is forced The basis of Hegelian dialectics is the op- to declare its internal impossibility and thereby eration of Aufhebung (“sublation”) as the ne- to call for its own self-­sublation.61 Accordingly, gation of the negation. Accordingly, in such Hegelian Aufhebung is the negation of the ne- works as (1967), Writing gation not in the sense of negating the negative and Difference (1967), and Glas (1973), Der- into a positive but in the sense of absolutizing— rida grounds his critique of Hegelian dialec- or radicalizing—the negative itself. Dialectics, tics in a searching interrogation of Hegel’s as Hegel puts it, is a “­self-­completing skepti- notion of Aufhebung. For Derrida, Hegelian cism” (“sich vollbringende Skeptizismus”), a Aufhebung consists in the double gesture of skepticism so radical that it dissolves the skepti- invoking the moment of negativity only to cal paradigm from within (Phenomenology 50; reinscribe this moment into a positive meta- P h ä ­n o ­m e ­n o ­l o ­g i e 72). physics of the Absolute.58 At the core of Der- De Man’s dismissal of Hegel’s and Kier­ke­ rida’s critique, in other words, is the now gaard’s dialectical approach to irony and his 120 Hegel contra Schlegel; Kierkegaard contra de Man [ PMLA

selective reading of Schlegel’s theory of irony does not want them to say, but what go un- thus prove to be inseparable from a Der­ri­ questioned are the reader’s narrowly semantic dean orientation that forces him to overlook expectations in the first place.63 or suppress many of the complexities involved What would happen, we might ask, if de in Hegelian dialectics. The stakes of de Man’s Man granted the text the power to call into interpretation of Schlegel become apparent question even these ground-­level readerly in “The Concept of Irony” when de Man goes expectations? In the brilliant final section of on to derive a poststructuralist hermeneutics The Concept of Irony (tellingly entitled “Irony based on the endless “free play of the signi- as a Controlled Element, the Truth of Irony”), fier” (181). For de Man, textuality is a form Kier­ke­gaard explores this possibility by of permanent parabasis: the semantic inde- sketching a hermeneutics—derived from his terminacy of the literary text permanently recasting of Hegel’s critique of Schlegel—that frustrates the reader’s will to interpretive can be read as a powerful proleptic challenge mastery. De Man’s key move is to shift the lo- to de Manian poststructuralism. Kier­ke­ cus of agency from the reader to the text. As gaard’s decisive move is to follow through on he puts it, “Words have a way of saying things de Man’s abortive attempt to shift the locus which are not at all what you want them to of agency from the reader to the text: hence, say” (181). Starting from this premise, de Man for Kierkegaard, “the poem has the center of draws the now familiar implications of a post- gravity in itself” (324). Adapting the Hegelian structuralist hermeneutics: in confronting a view of irony to the hermeneutic sphere, Kier­ text, the reader is faced with an uncontrol- ke­gaard conceives the literary text as a dialec- lable “polysemy of meanings” and the text be- tical arena in which the pressures of irony are comes endless and playful testimony to “the continually negotiated. As Kierkegaard puts impossibility of understanding” (167). it, “[I]rony is not present at some particular From a Hegelian vantage, however, we point of the poem but is omnipresent in it, so can ask, What if de Man’s very reveling in the that the irony visible in the poem is in turn text’s refusal of understanding masks a more ironically controlled” (324). In startling an- fundamental will to interpretive mastery that ticipation of twentieth-­century modernism, goes unironized? Notice that although de Man Kier­ke­gaard suggests that irony can be a con- grants the text enough agency to frustrate the trolled element in a text precisely in the text’s reader’s desire for semantic stability, he none- reflexive capacity to adopt an ironic stance theless retains just enough readerly agency to toward its own ironic energies. Hence, from a detect—and to savor—the text’s ironic poly- Kier­ke­gaard­ian perspective, the text might be semy. De Man’s poststructuralist hermeneutics, able to ironize the very de Manian impulse to in other words, betrays an abortive radicality read texts in terms of the endlessly ironic free in its constitutive incapacity to ironize the sta- play of the signifier. ble readerly standpoint from which to revel in Kierkegaard would have been the first to the endless free play of the signifier.62 Indeed, insist on the limitations of abstract thinking one could probe even further and show that about art, so I propose that we turn to a brief beneath the de Manian reader’s reveling in the example from modernist poetry to enliven text’s ironic free play lurks an absolute com- these abstractions.64 In the opening lines mitment to a discursive orientation to texts, of Wallace Stevens’s poem “Man Carrying one grounded in the assumption that reading Thing” (1947), the speaker stages the poem as a text is primarily an effort to establish what the dynamic site of an active textual agency the text says or means. For de Man, as we have capable at once of reflecting on and dictating seen, words may say things that the reader the terms in which it is read: 124.1 ] Ayon Roy 121

The poem must resist the intelligence semantic: their shared adoption of an a priori Almost successfully. (350) negative stance toward the work of art reflects an underlying hermeneutics of suspicion that Notice first the speaker’s acute reflexive aware- remains constitutively blind to what Theodor ness of the de Manian temptation to read po- Adorno, in a decidedly Hegelian vein, calls the etry as a permanent parabasis of the reader’s “force of negativity in the artwork” itself.65 intelligence—that is, as a permanent frustra- Importing Hegel’s dialectical model of tion of the reader’s impulse to understand the irony as infinite absolute negativity into the text at the semantic level. In fact, taken by it- hermeneutic sphere would mean drastically self, the first line would give succinct expres- widening the scope of textual negativity. A sion to an essentially ironic imperative: “The dialectical alternative to the hermeneutics poem must resist the intelligence.” But how of suspicion dominating contemporary lit- would de Man handle the second line? How, erary studies would be a hermeneutics that in other words, would de Man account for genuinely risks shifting the center of gravity a poetic intelligence so supple and so canny from the reader to the text—in other words, in the deployment of its reflexive energies a hermeneutics that strives to honor the text’s that it can adopt an ironic stance toward the immanent forces of negativity. Instead of con- ironic imperative itself? Everything depends touring passively to the reader’s given herme- on the delicate—and, indeed, richly ironic— neutic orientation, the text would be able to precision of the “almost.” It is in the dialec- shape the very terms of the reader’s ground- tical space of this “almost” that the speaker ­level engagement with it. By rendering fluid at once registers and resists the temptation to the reader’s normally fixed semantic expecta- reduce the intricate art of reading a poem to tions, the text’s negative energies could expand the question of whether the poem caters to or and enrich the reader’s hermeneutic grammar resists the reader’s “intelligence.” And it is in for determining what counts as semantically the space of this “almost” that one could be- salient in the first place. Capable of turning its gin to challenge any hermeneutic orientation suspicion against the suspicious readerly stance that conceives the stakes of reading a text in itself, the text would constitute a dialectical lo- primarily discursive terms. cus where we could inhabit and explore modes The absolute Ich at the basis of Schle- of being that simply cannot be accounted for gel’s theory of irony, we might say, finds its in the terms of sociocultural critique. contemporary hermeneutic analogue in the Perhaps only a dialectical hermeneutics permanently suspicious reader grown leery can leave us open to the radical possibility of traditional claims to aesthetic value and that such claims about the potentialities of for whom the literary text is a cultural docu- art cannot be straightforwardly dismissed ment that reflects—or, at best, reflectson —the as hopeless piety or ideological fantasy. In an complex sociocultural field in which it is em- all too ironic age, one could do worse than bedded. If the poststructuralist critic tends to to seek to activate those traces of spirit that reduce the semantic dimension of literary texts threaten to be ironized away. to an endless proliferation of discursive signi- fiers, the cultural-­studies-oriented critic tends to epiphenomenalize the semantic features of texts into so many elements in an elaborate sociological symptomatology. Both interpre- No t e s tive approaches, in other words, rely on a se- 1. “Ironie er som det Negative Veien; ikke Sandheden, verely impoverished model of what counts as men Veien” (327; Om Begrebet Ironi 329). 122 Hegel contra Schlegel; Kierkegaard contra de Man [ PMLA

2. “Die Ironie ist eine permanente Parekbase” (Phi­lo­ ment in the Biographia undermines itself as a result of his so­phi­sche Lehrjahre 85). All unattributed translations of vexed stance toward intuition. German passages are my own, and I often silently emend 11. For a classic survey of the various “subjective” and attributed translations. “objective” interpretations of Schlegel’s theory of irony in 3. In “The of Permanent Parabasis,” Michel the critical literature, see Immerwahr. Chaouli offers a helpful discussion of Schlegel’s under- 12. “[D]ie Stimmung, welche alles übersieht, und sich standing of parabasis. über alles Bedingte unendlich erhebt, auch über eigne 4. “Welche Götter werden uns von allen diesen Iro­ Kunst, Tugend, oder Genialität” (Charakteristiken 152). nien erretten können?” (Charakteristiken 369). A trans- See Schlegel’s Philosophical Fragments for translations of lation of Schlegel’s “Über die Unverständlichkeit,” titled the Lyceum and Athenaeum fragments. “On Incomprehensibility,” can be found in his Lucinde 13. “[E]in Gefühl von dem unauflöslischen Wider- and the Fragments. streit des Unbedingten und des Bedingten” (C h a ­r a k ­t e ­r i ­ 5. In their early work, Benjamin and Lukács follow s t i ­k e n 160). Kier­ke­gaard in acknowledging the power not only of 14. “[S]tete Wechsel von Selbstschöpfung und Selbst­ Schle­gel’s theory of irony but also (if only implicitly) of ver­nich­tung” (Charakteristiken 172). He­gel’s critique of it. See Lukács’s Die Theorie 73 and 15. “Obgleich dieser Rhythmus von Selbstschöpfung Benjamin’s Der Begriff 75–81. und Selbstvernichtung, von Enthusiasmus und Skepsis 6. “Ein ganz Groβer, Hegel, sagt aus blindem Haβ das grundlegende Merkmal der von Schlegel bestimmten Fal­sches über F. Schlegels romantische Ironie” (50). Iro­nie umreiβt . . .” (Ironie 97). For similar verdicts, see Allemann 97; Strohschneider- 16. “Ironie ist klares Bewuβtsein der ewigen Agilität, ­Kohrs 216; Behler, Studien 19; Bubner, “Zur dia­lek­ti­ des unendlich vollen Chaos” (Charakteristiken 263). schen Be­deu­tung” 93–94; Bohrer 146; and Egginton 17. “Ironie ist klares χα in Agilität, intell.[ektuale] 1040. One of the few critics to offer a more sympathetic Ansch.[auung] eines ewigen χα . . .” (228). view of He­gel’s critique is Otto Pöggeler in his study 18. “Wir halten uns also nur an die Bedeutung des He­gels Kritik der Ro­man­tik (45–54), but he remains at the general level of establishing irony as “substanceless Gan­zen; was den Sinn, das Herz, den Verstand, die Ein­ subjectivity” (“sub­stanz­lose Subjektivität”). The most bil­dung einzeln reizt, rührt, beschäftigt und ergötzt, comprehensive treatment of Hegel’s critique of Schle­ scheint uns nur Zeichen, Mittel zur Anschauung des gel­ian irony is Beh­ler’s long chapter “Hegels Polemiken Gan­zen, in dem Augenblick, wo wir uns zu diesem erhe- ge­gen Ironie” (I r o ­n i e 115–49), but Behler also dismisses ben” (Charakteristiken 323). He­gel’s critique (126). 19. For references to Anschauung and intellektuale 7. Frank might be the most vocal and influential An­schau­ung, see Ideen fragments 78 (263), 102 (266), and critic arguing for Schlegel’s more or less total break with 150 (271) and Athenaeum fragments 76 (176), 102 (180), Fichte. See lecture 17 of Einführung (287–306); “Philoso- 336 (223–25), 342 (226), and 448 (254). phische Grund­lagen” 106–30, and lectures 10 and 11 of 20. “Das Universum kann man weder erklären noch Philosophical Foundations (177–200). Also see Bubner, be­grei­fen, nur anschauen und offenbaren” Charakteristi­( “Von Fichte zu Schlegel”; Behler, German Romantic Lit­ ken 271). erary Theory 184–94; Rush 187; ch. 7 of Beiser (106–30); 21. Any fully adequate account of the category of in- Millán-­Zaibert; Götze; and Frischmann. tellectual intuition would have to begin with a discussion 8. Similarly, Beiser claims, “If Schlegel were ever a of Kant, but for reasons of space, I skip Kant and proceed disciple of Fichte, it was only for a short time, probably at directly to Fichte. most for a year, from the summer of 1795 to the summer 22. “Ich bin mir irgend eines Objects B bewust, deβen of 1796” (121). aber kann ich mir nicht bewust sein, ohne mir meiner selbst 9. Since Benjamin’s sustained treatment of the prob- be­wust zu sein. . . . Ich bin mir aber nur dadurch mei­ner lematic of intuition in Fichte and Schlegel, few critics selbst bewust[,] daβ ich mir des Bewustseins bewust bin. have addressed the complexities of Schlegel’s stance to- Ich muβ mir also bewust sein . . . des Bewustseins vom Be­ ward intuition. An important exception is Frischmann’s wust­sein. Wie werde ich mir deβen bewust? Dieβ geht ins helpful discussion of Schlegel’s engagement with Fichtean un­end­li­che fort und auf diese Weise läβt sich das Bewust- intuition in her recent book (176–83). sein nicht erklären. Der Hauptgrund die­ser Unmöglichkeit 10. I think one can make a more general case for the ist, daβ das Bewustsein als Zustand des Gemüths, immer central role of the category of intuition in both German als Object genommen wurde, wozu es denn immer eines and British . Some of the relevant source an­de­ren Subjectes bedurfte” W( i s ­s e n ­s c h a ft s ­l e h r e 30). texts for such a study would be Novalis’s Fichte-­Studien 23. “Dieses dem Philosophen angemutete Anschauen and Samuel Taylor Coleridge’s Biographia Literaria. In sei­ner selbst im Vollziehen des Aktes, wodurch ihm das my article “The Specter of Hegel in Coleridge’sBiographia Ich entsteht, nenne ich intellektuelle Anschauung” (Intro­ L i ­t e ­r a ­r i a ,” I argue that Coleridge’s philosophical argu- ductions 46; Zur theoretischen Philosophie 43). 124.1 ] Ayon Roy 123

24. “Die intellektuelle Anschauung ist der einzige . . . durch das ahnende, weissagende Gefühl in das mensch­ feste Standpunkt für alle Philosophie” (Introductions li­che Bewußtsein” (Philosophische Vorlesungen 381). 46–50; Zur theoretischen Philosophie 466). 39. “Diese Ironie ist eine Wendung der Fichteschen 25. For helpful discussions of this aspect of Fichte’s Phi­lo­so­phie, aus ihr hervorgegangen. . . . Sie ist das Fertig- philosophy, see Neuhouser 86; Bowie 78. sein des subjektiven Bewuβtseins mit allen Dingen: »Ich 26. “[D]aβ es kein unmittelbares, isoliertes Be­wuβt­ bin es, der durch mein gebildetes Den­ken alle Bestimmun- sein der intellektuellen Anschauung gibt . . .” (Introduc­ gen zunichte machen kann, Be­stim­mun­gen von Recht, tions 47; Zur theoretischen Philosophie 464). Sitt­lich­keit, Gut usw.; und ich weiβ, dass, wenn mir etwas 27. “Jeder muβ es [ein solches Vermögen der in­tel­ als gut erscheint, gilt, ich mir dies ebenso auch verkeh- lektu­el­len Anschauung] unmittelbar in sich selbst finden, ren kann. Ich weiβ mich schlecht­hin als den Herrn über oder er wird es nie kennen lernen” (Introductions 46; Zur all diese Bestimmungen, kann sie gelten lassen und auch the­o­re­ti­schen Philosophie 463). nicht; alles gilt mir nur wahr, insofern es mir jetzt gefällt«” 28. “[N]ur bald in sich selbst die Zufälligkeit des In­ (Greek Philosophy 400–01; Vorlesungen . . . I 460). halts, bald in ihm die eigene Willkür gewähren läβt” 40. “Man kann sagen, daβ genau an dieser Stelle das (Phenomenology 6; Phänomenologie 18). Iro­nie­ver­ständ­nis Hegels völlig in die Irre geht und na­ tür­lich schon seine Sehweise der absoluten Vollmacht des 29. “[E]in trockenes Versichern gilt aber gerade soviel iro­ni­schen Ich falsch ist. Denn die Kritik, die sich in der als ein anderes” (Phenomenology 49; Phänomenologie 71) Iro­nie äuβert, ist keine nach auβen gerichtete Ironie, die 30. Behler cites as evidence a letter of Hegel’s indicating bloβ täuschen und verblüffen will, sondern eine auf sich attendance at some of Schlegel’s Jena lectures (Ironie 139). selbst gerichtete Selbstkritik des Künstlers (‘Selbst­ver­ 31. For a general discussion of the circumstances of nich­tung’), die ihn davor schützen soll, zu viel Vertrauen, Schlegel’s Jena lectures, see Behler’s essay, “Friedrich An­maβung und Selbsteinschätzung in die ‘Selbstschöp- Schlegels Vorlesungen über Transzendentalphilosophie: fung’ zu investieren” (Ironie 126). Jena 1800–1801.” 41. Benjamin was one of the first commentators to 32. “Die Sehnsucht nach dem Unendlichen muβ im- emphasize the moment of objectivity in Schlegel’s theory mer Sehnsucht seyn. Unter der Form der Anschauung of irony (“Concept” 160–65; Der Begriff 75–81). See also kann es nicht vorkommen. Das Ideal lässt sich nie an- Strohschneider-­Kohrs 216 and Bohrer 147. schauen. Das Ideal wird durch Spekulazion erzeugt” (Phi­ 42. “Friedrich von Schlegel wie Schelling gingen von l o ­s o ­p h i ­sche Vorlesungen 8). dem Fichteschen Standpunkt aus, Schelling, um ihn 33. “Die Zusammenfassung des ganzen ursprüngli- durch­aus zu überschreiten, Friedrich von Schlegel, um chen Bewuβtseyns, wenn es zum Bewuβtseyn kommt, ihn eigentümlich auszubilden und sich ihm zu entreiβen” d. h. das ursprüngliche Bewuβtseyn anschaut und ver­ (Aesthetics 64; Vorlesungen über die Ästhetik 93). steht, ist die intellektuelle Anschauung. Die absolute The- 43. “Der Fichtesche Standpunkt der Subjektivität hat sis aller Philosophie kann nicht bewiesen werden; es geht seine nicht philosophisch ausgeführte Wendung behal­ schlecht­hin nichts darüber; es enthält seinen Beweis in ten und so seine Vollendung erhalten in Formen, die der sich selbst” (Philosophische Vorlesungen 24). Emp­fin­dung angehören und zum Teil das Bestreben wa­ 34. “[D]ie Untersuchung aller Quellen der Philosophie ren, über die Subjektivität hinauszugehen, obgleich es führt uns auf die Selbstanschauung, als den si­cher­sten dazu unfähig war” (Medieval and Modern Philosophy An­fangs­punkt der Philosophie” (Philosophische Vor­le­ 507; Vorlesungen . . . III 415). s u n ­g e n 299). 44. For a helpful account of Schleiermacher’s theo- 35. “Diese Fähigkeit, das Ich des Ichs zu sein, ist aber logical doctrine and Hegel’s critique of it, see Reid. un­end­lich; denn so wie es eine Anschauung der An­schau­ 45. For instance, Schleiermacher calls the “intuition ung gibt, kann es ebensogut eine Anschauung der An­schau­ of the universe” (“Anschauen des Universums”) “the ung der Anschauung geben usw. bis ins unendliche; dies hat highest and most universal formula of religion” (“die all­ gar keine Grenzen” (Philosophische Vor­le­sun­gen 325). ge­mein­ste und höchste Formel der Religion”) (24; Über 36. “Was die Anschauung betrifft, so ist schon hin­ die Religion 52). läng­lich dargetan worden, daβ sie im eigentlichen Sinne 46. “Nach diesem Prinzip hat denn das geistige leben- keine Erkenntnis geben kann, weil sie eben das innere dige Wesen sich in das Selbstbewuβtsein versetzt, und die We­sen des Gegenstandes, das Leben, das Freie und Be­ Ein­heit des Geistes meint es unmittelbar aus sich selbst we­gli­che erdrückt” (Philosophische Vorlesungen 331). und in dieser Unmittelbarkeit auf eine poetische oder we­ 37. The En­glish translation of Benjamin’s text mis- nigs­tens prophetische Weise zu wissen. Was die poe­ti­sche leadingly renders “unanschauliche Intuition” as “non- Weise betrifft, so weiβ sie von Leben und Person des Ab­so­ ­eidetic intuition” (“Concept” 139–40). lu­ten unmittelbar in einer Anschauung, nicht im Be­griffe, 38. “Die unendliche Fülle als solche läßt sich nicht an- und meint das Ganze als Ganzes, als sich durch­drin­gende schauen, man müßte dann eine Anschauung annehmen, Ein­heit zu verlieren, wenn sie es nicht poetisch aus­sprä­ die nie vollendet werden könnte. Dieser Begriff kommt nur che; und was sie poetisch ausspricht, ist die An­schau­ung 124 Hegel contra Schlegel; Kierkegaard contra de Man [ PMLA

des eigenen Lebens seines Selbstbewuβtseins. – Aber die 57. Hegel refers to the “magical power” (“Zauber- Wahr­heit ist die absolute Bewegung . . .” (Medieval and kraft”) of “tarrying” (“verweilen”) with the negative in Modern Philosophy 508–09; Vorlesungen . . . III 416). the preface to Phenomenology (19; Phänomenologie 36). 47. “[D]er höchste Anfangspunkt für das Problem der 58. I focus here on Derrida’s critique of Hegel in Writ­ Phi­lo­so­phie” (Berliner Schriften 254). ing and Difference, but he offers a similar critique in Of 48. “[V]on dem Voraussetzungslosen, Allgemeinen aus Grammatology (106) and Glas (8–11, 25–26). das Besondere zu entwickeln” (Berliner Schriften 254). 59. Trans. slightly modified. The original reads, “Par 49. “Ein Prinzip muß auch bewiesen, nicht ge­for­dert ce recours à l’Aufhebung qui conserve la mise, reste maî- wer­den, daß es aus Anschauung, unmittelbarer Ge­wiß­ tresse du jeu, le limite, le travaille en lui donnant forme heit, innerer Offenbarung, oder wie man es nennen mag, et sense . . .” (L’ écriture 376). mit einem Wort auf Treu und Glauben angenommen 60. For an interesting Hegelian critique of Rich- werde; die Forderung des Beweisens ist aber für die so ard Rorty’s poststructuralist-­inflected theory of liberal vie­len und zugleich so eingeworden. . . . In der an­ge­ ironism, see Matarrese. führ­ten Form ist jene Negativität nur in der einseitigen, 61. Robert Pippin offers an illuminating account of endlichen Affirmation geblieben, welche sie alsIch hat. In Hegel’s notion of “absolute negativity” (163). die­ser nur subjektiven Affirmation ist sie aus der Fichte­ 62. For a similar argument against poststructuralist schen Philosophie mit Unverständnis des Spekulativen models of irony, see Berel Lang’s shrewd essay “The Limits und Beiseitesetzung desselben von Friedrich von Schlegel of Irony,” which convincingly argues that poststructural- auf­ge­nom­men und aus dem Gebiete des Denkens so he­ ist irony—like its Romantic predecessor—ultimately “dis- raus­ge­ris­sen worden, daß sie, direkt auf die Wirklichkeit closes a transcendent and foundationalist origin” (580). g e ­w e n ­d e t , z u r Ironie gediehen ist, zum Verneinen der 63. A longer essay would have to address in detail de Le­ben­dig­keit der Vernunft und Wahrheit und zur He­ Man’s brilliant earlier treatment of irony in his 1969 es- rab­set­zung derselben zum Schein im Subjekt und zum say “The Rhetoric of Temporality” (contained in Blind­ Schei­nen für andere” (Berliner Schriften 255). ness and Insight). In “The Rhetoric of Temporality,” de Man starts out with a diachronic account of irony as “un- 50. “Das Göttliche soll die negative Haltung sein, relieved vertige, dizziness to the point of madness” (215), das Anschauen, Bewuβtsein der Eitelkeit von allem . . .” but by the end of the essay he claims that irony betrays (Greek Philosophy 401; Vorlesungen . . . I 461). an ultimately “synchronic structure” in its reliance on 51. Irony, as Hegel tersely puts it, is always “away an epistemology of the “instant” (226). I would suggest above everything” (“über alles hinaus”) (Aesthetics 243; that the early de Man’s insight bears striking affinities Vor­le­sun­gen über die Ästhetik 315). with Hegel’s critique of Schlegel: Schlegel’s apparently 52. “Diese Gestalt ist nicht nur die Eitelkeit alles sitt­ diachronic conception of irony as “permanent paraba- l i ­c h e n Inhalts der Rechte, Pflichten, Gesetze . . . sondern sis” proves inseparable from his appeal to a synchronic sie tut auch die Form, die subjektive Eitelkeit, hinzu, sich epistemology of intuition. “The Rhetoric of Temporality” selbst als diese Eitelkeit alles Inhalts zu wissen und in could then be read as an uncanny proleptic critique of his die­sem Wissen sich als das Absolute zu wissen” (Elements later essay “The Concept of Irony.” 182; Grundlinien 279). 64. For a more sustained treatment of the problematic 53. “Von Fichte ist eigentlich nicht zu sagen, dass er of irony in twentieth-century American poetry, see my im Praktischen die Willkür des Subjekts zum Prinzip ge­ articles on Wallace Stevens and John Ashbery, where I ar- macht habe, aber späterhin ist im Sinne der besonderen gue that both writers seek to develop a poetics that resists Ich­heit von Friedrich v. Schlegel dieses Besondere selbst the seductions of the ironic stance (“From Deconstruc- in betreff des Guten und Schönen als Gott aufgestellt tion”; “Postmodern Convexity”). wor­den, so daβ das objektiv Gute nur ein Gebilde meiner 65. “[D]ie Kraft der Negativität im Kunstwerk” Aes( ­ Über­zeu­gung sei, nur durch mich einen Halt bekommt, thetic Theory 12; Ästhetische Theorie 26). und daβ ich es als Herr und Meister hervortreten und ver­schwin­den lassen kann. Indem ich mich zu etwas Ob­ jek­ti­vem verhalte, ist es zugleich für mich untergegangen, und so schwebe ich über einem ungeheuren Raume Ge­ Wo r k s Ci t e d stal­ten hervorrufend und zerstörend” (Grundlinien 286). Adorno, Theodor.Aesthetic Theory. Trans. Robert Hullot- 54. “Überzeugung vom Irrtum ist schlechterdings ­Kentor. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1997. Print. u n ­m ö g ­l i c h ” ( Introductions 98; Zur theoretischen Philoso­ ———. Ästhetische Theorie. 1970. Frankfurt am Main: phie 513). Suhr­kamp, 1992. Print. 55. See, for instance, Schlegel’s invocation of schweben Allemann, Beda. Ironie und Dichtung. Pfullingen: Neske, in Athenaeum fragment 116 (Charakteristiken 182–83). 1956. Print. 56. “Die vollendete absolute Ironie hört auf Ironie zu Behler, Ernst. “Friedrich Schlegels Vorlesungen über seyn und wird ernsthaft” Fragmente( 144). T r a n ­s z e n ­d e n ­t a l ­p h i ­l o ­s o ­phie: Jena 1800–1801.” Der 124.1 ] Ayon Roy 125

Streit um die Gestalt einer Ersten Philosophie. Ed. Wal­ ——— . Zur theoretischen Philosophie. Ed. I. H. Fichte. Ber- ter Jaeschke. Hamburg: Meiner, 1999. 52–71. Print. lin: Veit und Comp, 1845–46. Print. Vol. 1 of Sämmt­ ——— . German Romantic . Cambridge: liche Werke. Cambridge UP, 1993. Print. Frank, Manfred. Einführung in die frühromantische Äs­ ——— . Ironie und literarische Moderne. Paderborn: Schö­ thetik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1989. Print. ningh, 1997. Print. ——— . The Philosophical Foundations of Early German ——— . Studien zur Romantik und zur idealistischen Phi­lo­ Romanticism. Trans. Elizabeth Millán-­Zaibert. Al- s o ­p h i e . Paderborn: Schöningh, 1988. Print. bany: State U of New York P, 2004. Print. Behler, Ernst, and Jochen Hörisch, eds. Die Aktualität der ———. “Philosophische Grundlagen der Frühromantik.” Früh­romantik. Paderborn: Schöningh, 1987. Print. Athe­näum: Jahrbuch für Romantik 4 (1994): 37–130. Beiser, Frederick. The Romantic Imperative: The Concept Print. of Early . Cambridge: Harvard Frischmann, Bärbel. Vom transzendentalen zum früh­ UP, 2003. Print. romantischen Idealismus. Paderborn: Schöningh, 2005. Print. Benjamin, Walter. Der Begriff der Kunstkritik in der deutschen Romantik. 1916. Frankfurt am Main: Suhr­ Götze, Martin. Ironie und absolute Darstellung. Pader- kamp, 1973. Print. born: Schöningh, 2001. Print. ——— . “The Concept of Criticism in German Romanti- Hegel, G. W. F. Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art. Trans. cism.” Trans. David Lachterman, Howard Eiland, T. M. Knox. Vol. 1. Oxford: Clarendon, 1975. Print. and Ian Balfour. Selected Writings I: 1913–1926. Ed. ——— . Berliner Schriften 1818–1831. Frankfurt am Main: Marcus Bullock and Michael Jennings. Cambridge: Suhr­kamp, 1970. Print. Vol. 11 of Werke. Bel­knap, 1996. 116–200. Print. ——— . Elements of the Philosophy of Right. Trans. H. B. Bohrer, Karl Heinz. Die Kritik der Romantik. Frankfurt Nis­bet. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1991. Print. am Main: Suhrkamp, 1989. Print. ——— . Greek Philosophy to Plato. Trans. E. S. Haldane. Bowie, Andrew. Aesthetics and Subjectivity: From Kant to Lincoln: U of Nebraska P, 1995. Print. Vol. 1 of Lec­ tures on the History of Philosophy. N i e t z ­s c h e . 2nd ed. Manchester: Manchester UP, 2003. Print. ——— . Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts oder Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse. Bubner, Rüdiger. “Von Fichte zu Schlegel.” Fichtes Wis­ Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1970. Print. Vol. 7 sen­schafts­lehre 1794: Philosophische Resonanzen. Ed. of Werke. Wolf­ram Hogrebe. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, ——— . Medieval and Modern Philosophy. Trans. E. S. Hal- 1995. 35–49. Print. dane and Frances Simson. Lincoln: U of Nebraska P, ———. “Zur dialektischen Bedeutung romantischer Iro­ 1995. Print. Vol. 3 of Lectures on the History of Phi­ nie.” Behler and Hörisch 85–95. losophy. Chaouli, Michel. “The Politics of Permanent Parabasis.” ——— . Phänomenologie des Geistes. Frankfurt am Main: Studies in Romanticism 42.3 (2003): 323–40. Print. Suhr­kamp, 1970. Print. Vol. 3 of Werke. de Man, Paul. “The Concept of Irony.”Aesthetic . ——— . Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. A. V. Miller. Ox- Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1996. 163–84. Print. ford: Oxford UP, 1977. Print. ———. “The Rhetoric of Temporality.” Blindness and In­ ——— . Vorlesungen über die Ästhetik I. Frankfurt am sight. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1983. 187–228. Main: Suhr­kamp, 1970. Print. Vol. 13 of Werke. Print. ——— . Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie I. Derrida, Jacques. L’écriture et la différence. Paris: Seuil, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1971. Print. Vol. 18 1967. Print. of Werke. ——— . Glas. Trans. John P. Leavey, Jr., and Richard Rand. ——— . Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie Lincoln: U of Nebraska P, 1984. Print. III. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1971. Print. ——— . Of Grammatology. Trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Vol. 20 of Werke. Spi­vak. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1976. Print. Immerwahr, Raymond. “The Subjectivity or Objectivity ——— . Writing and Difference. Trans. Alan Bass. Chicago: of Friedrich Schlegel’s Poetic Irony.” Germanic Re­ U of Chicago P, 1978. Print. view 26.3 (1951): 173–91. Print. Egginton, William. “Cervantes, Romantic Irony and the Kierkegaard, Søren. The Concept of Irony. Trans. Howard Making of Reality.” MLN 117.5 (2002): 1040–68. Print. Hong and Edna Hong. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1989. Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. Introductions to the Wissen- Print. schaftslehre. Trans. Daniel Breazeale. Indianapolis: ——— . Om Begrebet Ironi. 1841. Köbenhavn: Gyldendal, Hackett, 1994. Print. 1962. Print. ——— . Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo. Hamburg: Mei­ Lang, Berel. “The Limits of Irony.” New Literary History ner, 1982. Print. 27.3 (1996): 571–88. Print. 126 Hegel contra Schlegel; Kierkegaard contra de Man [ PMLA

Lukács, Georg. Die Theorie des Romans. Berlin: Cassirer, Schlegel, Friedrich. Charakteristiken und Kritiken I. Ed. 1920. Print. Hans Eichner. München: Schöningh, 1967. Print. Matarrese, Craig B. “Satisfaction or Supersession? Ex- Vol. 2 of Kritische Ausgabe. pression, Rationality, and Irony in Hegel and Rorty.” ——— . Fragmente zur Poesie und Literatur. Ed. Hans Clio: A Journal of Literature, History, and the Philoso­ Eich­ner. Paderborn: Schöningh, 1981. Print. Vol. 16 phy of History 36.1 (2006): 41–58. Print. of Kritische Ausgabe. Millán-­Zaibert, Elizabeth. Friedrich Schlegel and the ———. “On Incomprehensibility.” Lucinde and the Frag­ Emergence of Romantic Philosophy. Albany: State U ments. Trans. Peter Firchow. Minneapolis: U of Min- of New York P, 2007. Print. nesota P, 1971. 257–71. Print. Neuhouser, Frederick. Fichte’s Theory of Subjectivity. ——— . Philosophical Fragments. Trans. Peter Firchow. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1990. Print. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1991. Print. Pippin, Robert. Modernism as a Philosophical Problem. ——— . Philosophische Lehrjahre 1796–1806. Ed. Ernst Oxford: Blackwell, 1991. Print. Behler. München: Schöningh, 1963. Print. Vol. 18 of Pöggeler, Otto. Hegels Kritik der Romantik. 1956. Mün­ Kri­ti­sche Ausgabe. chen: Fink, 1998. Print. ——— . Philosophische Vorlesungen 1800–1807. Ed. Jean- Reid, Jeffrey. “Hegel on Schleiermacher and Postmoder- ­Jacques Anstett. München: Schöningh, 1964. Print. nity.” Clio: A Journal of Literature, History, and the Vol. 12 of Kritische Ausgabe. Philosophy of History 32.4 (2003): 457–72. Print. Schleiermacher, Friedrich. On Religion: Speeches to Its Roy, Ayon. “From to Decreation: Wallace Cultured Despisers. Trans. Richard Crouter. Cam- Stevens’ Notes toward a Poetics of Nobility.” Wallace bridge: Cambridge UP, 1988. Print. Stevens Journal 29.2 (2005): 249–62. Print. ——— . Über die Religion: Reden an die Gebildeten unter ihren ———. “Postmodern Convexity and Hegelian Dialec- Verächtern. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck, 1967. Print. tics in Ashbery’s ‘Self-­Portrait in a Convex Mirror.’” Stevens, Wallace. “Man Carrying Thing.” The Collected Gingko Tree Review 4.1 (2007): 25–46. Print. Poems of Wallace Stevens. New York: Knopf, 1961. ———. “The Specter of Hegel in Coleridge’s Biographia 350–51. Print. L i ­t e ­r a ­r i a .” Journal of the History of Ideas 68.2 (2007): Strohschneider-­Kohrs, Ingrid. Die romantische Ironie in 279–304. Print. Theorie und Gestaltung. 1958. Tübingen: Niemeyer, Rush, Fred. “Irony and Romantic Subjectivity.” Philo­ 2002. Print. sophical Romanticism. Ed. Nikolas Kompridis. Lon- Walzel, Oskar. “Methode? Ironie bei Friedrich Schlegel don: Routledge, 2006. 173–95. Print. und bei Solger.” Helicon 1 (1938): 33–50. Print.