First Order Syntax

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

First Order Syntax first-order logic: ingredients There is a domain of interpretation, and I variables: x; y; z;::: ranging over the domain I constant symbols (names): 0 1 π e Albert Einstein I function symbols: + ∗ − = sin(−) exp(−) I predicates: = > 6 male(−) parent(−; −) I propositional connectives: ^ _ q −! ! O "# I quantifiers: 8 9. Tibor Beke first order syntax False. sentences Let the domain of interpretation be the set of real numbers. 8a 8b 8c 9x(ax2 + bx + c = 0) This formula is an example of a sentence from first-order logic. It has no free variables: every one of the variables a, b, c, x is in the scope of a quantifier. A sentence has a well-defined truth value that can be discovered (at least, in principle). The sentence above (interpreted over the real numbers) is Tibor Beke first order syntax sentences Let the domain of interpretation be the set of real numbers. 8a 8b 8c 9x(ax2 + bx + c = 0) This formula is an example of a sentence from first-order logic. It has no free variables: every one of the variables a, b, c, x is in the scope of a quantifier. A sentence has a well-defined truth value that can be discovered (at least, in principle). The sentence above (interpreted over the real numbers) is False. Tibor Beke first order syntax \Every woman has two children " but is, in fact, logically equivalent to every woman having at least one child. That child could play the role of both y and z. sentences Let the domain of discourse be a set of people, let F (x) mean \x is female" and let P(x; y) mean \x is a parent of y". 8x F (x) −! 9y9zP(x; y) ^ P(x; z) This sentence seems to be saying Tibor Beke first order syntax sentences Let the domain of discourse be a set of people, let F (x) mean \x is female" and let P(x; y) mean \x is a parent of y". 8x F (x) −! 9y9zP(x; y) ^ P(x; z) This sentence seems to be saying \Every woman has two children " but is, in fact, logically equivalent to every woman having at least one child. That child could play the role of both y and z. Tibor Beke first order syntax Suppose the domain of discourse is the natural numbers 0; 1; 2; 3;::: . What is the meaning of the following formula? 8p8q pq = n −! (p = 1 O q = 1) \n is a prime number" open formulas A first-order formula that contains free variables is said to be open. You cannot associate a truth value to it unless the free variables are specialized to some element of the domain: 8x f (x) 6 f (x0) An open formula can be thought of as defining a property (\predicate") of its free variable(s). Tibor Beke first order syntax \n is a prime number" open formulas A first-order formula that contains free variables is said to be open. You cannot associate a truth value to it unless the free variables are specialized to some element of the domain: 8x f (x) 6 f (x0) An open formula can be thought of as defining a property (\predicate") of its free variable(s). Suppose the domain of discourse is the natural numbers 0; 1; 2; 3;::: . What is the meaning of the following formula? 8p8q pq = n −! (p = 1 O q = 1) Tibor Beke first order syntax open formulas A first-order formula that contains free variables is said to be open. You cannot associate a truth value to it unless the free variables are specialized to some element of the domain: 8x f (x) 6 f (x0) An open formula can be thought of as defining a property (\predicate") of its free variable(s). Suppose the domain of discourse is the natural numbers 0; 1; 2; 3;::: . What is the meaning of the following formula? 8p8q pq = n −! (p = 1 O q = 1) \n is a prime number" Tibor Beke first order syntax \ x is a grandparent of y " 9w9z9uP(w; z) ^ P(z; x) ^ P(w; u) ^ P(u; y) \ x and y are cousins (or siblings, or the same people!) " open formulas F (x): x is female M(x): x is male P(x; y): x is a parent of y 9zP(x; z) ^ P(z; y) Tibor Beke first order syntax 9w9z9uP(w; z) ^ P(z; x) ^ P(w; u) ^ P(u; y) \ x and y are cousins (or siblings, or the same people!) " open formulas F (x): x is female M(x): x is male P(x; y): x is a parent of y 9zP(x; z) ^ P(z; y) \ x is a grandparent of y " Tibor Beke first order syntax \ x and y are cousins (or siblings, or the same people!) " open formulas F (x): x is female M(x): x is male P(x; y): x is a parent of y 9zP(x; z) ^ P(z; y) \ x is a grandparent of y " 9w9z9uP(w; z) ^ P(z; x) ^ P(w; u) ^ P(u; y) Tibor Beke first order syntax open formulas F (x): x is female M(x): x is male P(x; y): x is a parent of y 9zP(x; z) ^ P(z; y) \ x is a grandparent of y " 9w9z9uP(w; z) ^ P(z; x) ^ P(w; u) ^ P(u; y) \ x and y are cousins (or siblings, or the same people!) " Tibor Beke first order syntax first-order logic: syntax We will define the notion of well-formed formula. The definition will be \step-by-step" (inductive). • A term is a composite of function symbols, variables and constants. Terms denote elements of the domain | specific or unspecified elements. Examples of terms x π Pope Francis 23 · 24 sin2(kx) + 23 a · x2 + b · x + c Tibor Beke first order syntax first-order logic: atomic formulas • Suppose t1; t2;:::; tn are terms, and R(−; −;:::; −) is an n-ary relation symbol. The expression R(t1; t2;:::; tn) is called an atomic formula. Atomic formulas contain neither propositional connectives nor quantifiers. They are the simplest types of expressions that can be evaluated to True or False | if their free variables are specialized to some element of the domain, that is. They are the same, essentially, as the \atomic propositions" of propositional logic. Tibor Beke first order syntax examples of atomic formulas π > e x = y friends(Big Bird; Cookie Monster) spouse(Pope Francis; x) collinear(p; q; r) x2 + 1 > sin(z) + 23 Tibor Beke first order syntax first-order logic: well-formed formulas We will define well-formed formulas the following way: I Any atomic formula is well-formed. I If α and β are well-formed and ? is any binary propositional connective, then (α ? β) is well-formed. (`?' could be any of ^ _ −! O ! " # .) I If α is well-formed, so is qα. I If α is well-formed and x is any variable then the expressions 8xα 9xα are both well-formed. Tibor Beke first order syntax not well-formed (if we're sticklers!) wff not wff not wff wff wff wff (strange but true!) which of the following is a well-formed formula? P(x) ^ Q(y) ^ R(z) 9x P(x; y) ^ Q(x) _ R(y) 9x ^ 9y P(x)OQ(y) q q8x9yR(x) q 8xQ(x; y) −!q9yqqQ(z; z) q 8yq 9x P(z) ! 9xQ(x) q 8zq 8z9zQ(x; y) Tibor Beke first order syntax wff not wff not wff wff wff wff (strange but true!) which of the following is a well-formed formula? P(x) ^ Q(y) ^ R(z) not well-formed (if we're sticklers!) 9x P(x; y) ^ Q(x) _ R(y) 9x ^ 9y P(x)OQ(y) q q8x9yR(x) q 8xQ(x; y) −!q9yqqQ(z; z) q 8yq 9x P(z) ! 9xQ(x) q 8zq 8z9zQ(x; y) Tibor Beke first order syntax not wff not wff wff wff wff (strange but true!) which of the following is a well-formed formula? P(x) ^ Q(y) ^ R(z) not well-formed (if we're sticklers!) 9x P(x; y) ^ Q(x) _ R(y) wff 9x ^ 9y P(x)OQ(y) q q8x9yR(x) q 8xQ(x; y) −!q9yqqQ(z; z) q 8yq 9x P(z) ! 9xQ(x) q 8zq 8z9zQ(x; y) Tibor Beke first order syntax not wff wff wff wff (strange but true!) which of the following is a well-formed formula? P(x) ^ Q(y) ^ R(z) not well-formed (if we're sticklers!) 9x P(x; y) ^ Q(x) _ R(y) wff 9x ^ 9y P(x)OQ(y) not wff q q8x9yR(x) q 8xQ(x; y) −!q9yqqQ(z; z) q 8yq 9x P(z) ! 9xQ(x) q 8zq 8z9zQ(x; y) Tibor Beke first order syntax wff wff wff (strange but true!) which of the following is a well-formed formula? P(x) ^ Q(y) ^ R(z) not well-formed (if we're sticklers!) 9x P(x; y) ^ Q(x) _ R(y) wff 9x ^ 9y P(x)OQ(y) not wff q q8x9yR(x) not wff q 8xQ(x; y) −!q9yqqQ(z; z) q 8yq 9x P(z) ! 9xQ(x) q 8zq 8z9zQ(x; y) Tibor Beke first order syntax wff wff (strange but true!) which of the following is a well-formed formula? P(x) ^ Q(y) ^ R(z) not well-formed (if we're sticklers!) 9x P(x; y) ^ Q(x) _ R(y) wff 9x ^ 9y P(x)OQ(y) not wff q q8x9yR(x) not wff q 8xQ(x; y) −!q9yqqQ(z; z) wff q 8yq 9x P(z) ! 9xQ(x) q 8zq 8z9zQ(x; y) Tibor Beke first order syntax wff (strange but true!) which of the following is a well-formed formula? P(x) ^ Q(y) ^ R(z) not well-formed (if we're sticklers!) 9x P(x; y) ^ Q(x) _ R(y) wff 9x ^ 9y P(x)OQ(y) not wff q q8x9yR(x) not wff q 8xQ(x; y) −!q9yqqQ(z; z) wff q 8yq 9x P(z) ! 9xQ(x) wff q 8zq 8z9zQ(x; y) Tibor Beke first order syntax which of the following is a well-formed formula? P(x) ^ Q(y) ^ R(z) not well-formed (if we're sticklers!) 9x P(x; y) ^ Q(x) _ R(y) wff 9x ^ 9y P(x)OQ(y) not wff q q8x9yR(x) not wff q 8xQ(x; y) −!q9yqqQ(z; z) wff q 8yq 9x P(z) ! 9xQ(x) wff q 8zq 8z9zQ(x; y) wff (strange but true!) Tibor Beke first order syntax unique parsing If α is a wff but not atomic then it must arise from smaller wff (\subformulas") using one of the three rules of formation: (1) If α and β are well-formed and ? is any propositional connective, then (α ? β) is well-formed.
Recommended publications
  • Verifying the Unification Algorithm In
    Verifying the Uni¯cation Algorithm in LCF Lawrence C. Paulson Computer Laboratory Corn Exchange Street Cambridge CB2 3QG England August 1984 Abstract. Manna and Waldinger's theory of substitutions and uni¯ca- tion has been veri¯ed using the Cambridge LCF theorem prover. A proof of the monotonicity of substitution is presented in detail, as an exam- ple of interaction with LCF. Translating the theory into LCF's domain- theoretic logic is largely straightforward. Well-founded induction on a complex ordering is translated into nested structural inductions. Cor- rectness of uni¯cation is expressed using predicates for such properties as idempotence and most-generality. The veri¯cation is presented as a series of lemmas. The LCF proofs are compared with the original ones, and with other approaches. It appears di±cult to ¯nd a logic that is both simple and exible, especially for proving termination. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Overview of uni¯cation 2 3 Overview of LCF 4 3.1 The logic PPLAMBDA :::::::::::::::::::::::::: 4 3.2 The meta-language ML :::::::::::::::::::::::::: 5 3.3 Goal-directed proof :::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 6 3.4 Recursive data structures ::::::::::::::::::::::::: 7 4 Di®erences between the formal and informal theories 7 4.1 Logical framework :::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 8 4.2 Data structure for expressions :::::::::::::::::::::: 8 4.3 Sets and substitutions :::::::::::::::::::::::::: 9 4.4 The induction principle :::::::::::::::::::::::::: 10 5 Constructing theories in LCF 10 5.1 Expressions ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::
    [Show full text]
  • Logic- Sentence and Propositions
    Sentence and Proposition Sentence Sentence= वा啍य, Proposition= त셍कवा啍य/ प्रततऻप्‍तत=Statement Sentence is the unit or part of some language. Sentences can be expressed in all tense (present, past or future) Sentence is not able to explain quantity and quality. A sentence may be interrogative (प्रश्नवाच셍), simple or declarative (घोषड़ा配म셍), command or imperative (आदेशा配म셍), exclamatory (ववमयतबोध셍), indicative (तनदेशा配म셍), affirmative (भावा配म셍), negative (तनषेधा配म셍), skeptical (संदेहा配म셍) etc. Note : Only indicative sentences (सं셍ेता配म셍तवा啍य) are proposition. Philosophy Dept, E- contents-01( Logic-B.A Sem.III & IV) by Dr Rajendra Kr.Verma 1 All kind of sentences are not proposition, only those sentences are called proposition while they will determine or evaluate in terms of truthfulness or falsity. Sentences are governed by its own grammar. (for exp- sentence of hindi language govern by hindi grammar) Sentences are correct or incorrect / pure or impure. Sentences are may be either true or false. Philosophy Dept, E- contents-01( Logic-B.A Sem.III & IV) by Dr Rajendra Kr.Verma 2 Proposition Proposition are regarded as the material of our reasoning and we also say that proposition and statements are regarded as same. Proposition is the unit of logic. Proposition always comes in present tense. (sentences - all tenses) Proposition can explain quantity and quality. (sentences- cannot) Meaning of sentence is called proposition. Sometime more then one sentences can expressed only one proposition. Example : 1. ऩानीतबरसतरहातहैत.(Hindi) 2. ऩावुष तऩड़तोत (Sanskrit) 3. It is raining (English) All above sentences have only one meaning or one proposition.
    [Show full text]
  • Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch
    Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch. August 16, 2020 Contents Page 1 Axioms and Formal Systems 1 1.1 Introduction 1 1.2 Preliminaries: axioms and formal systems. 3 1.2.1 The formal language of ZF set theory; terms 4 1.2.2 The Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms 7 1.3 Transfinite Recursion 9 1.4 Relativisation of terms and formulae 11 2 Initial segments of the Universe 17 2.1 Singular ordinals: cofinality 17 2.1.1 Cofinality 17 2.1.2 Normal Functions and closed and unbounded classes 19 2.1.3 Stationary Sets 22 2.2 Some further cardinal arithmetic 24 2.3 Transitive Models 25 2.4 The H sets 27 2.4.1 H - the hereditarily finite sets 28 2.4.2 H - the hereditarily countable sets 29 2.5 The Montague-Levy Reflection theorem 30 2.5.1 Absoluteness 30 2.5.2 Reflection Theorems 32 2.6 Inaccessible Cardinals 34 2.6.1 Inaccessible cardinals 35 2.6.2 A menagerie of other large cardinals 36 3 Formalising semantics within ZF 39 3.1 Definite terms and formulae 39 3.1.1 The non-finite axiomatisability of ZF 44 3.2 Formalising syntax 45 3.3 Formalising the satisfaction relation 46 3.4 Formalising definability: the function Def. 47 3.5 More on correctness and consistency 48 ii iii 3.5.1 Incompleteness and Consistency Arguments 50 4 The Constructible Hierarchy 53 4.1 The L -hierarchy 53 4.2 The Axiom of Choice in L 56 4.3 The Axiom of Constructibility 57 4.4 The Generalised Continuum Hypothesis in L.
    [Show full text]
  • Propositional Logic
    Propositional Logic - Review Predicate Logic - Review Propositional Logic: formalisation of reasoning involving propositions Predicate (First-order) Logic: formalisation of reasoning involving predicates. • Proposition: a statement that can be either true or false. • Propositional variable: variable intended to represent the most • Predicate (sometimes called parameterized proposition): primitive propositions relevant to our purposes a Boolean-valued function. • Given a set S of propositional variables, the set F of propositional formulas is defined recursively as: • Domain: the set of possible values for a predicate’s Basis: any propositional variable in S is in F arguments. Induction step: if p and q are in F, then so are ⌐p, (p /\ q), (p \/ q), (p → q) and (p ↔ q) 1 2 Predicate Logic – Review cont’ Predicate Logic - Review cont’ Given a first-order language L, the set F of predicate (first-order) •A first-order language consists of: formulas is constructed inductively as follows: - an infinite set of variables Basis: any atomic formula in L is in F - a set of predicate symbols Inductive step: if e and f are in F and x is a variable in L, - a set of constant symbols then so are the following: ⌐e, (e /\ f), (e \/ f), (e → f), (e ↔ f), ∀ x e, ∃ s e. •A term is a variable or a constant symbol • An occurrence of a variable x is free in a formula f if and only •An atomic formula is an expression of the form p(t1,…,tn), if it does not occur within a subformula e of f of the form ∀ x e where p is a n-ary predicate symbol and each ti is a term.
    [Show full text]
  • First Order Logic and Nonstandard Analysis
    First Order Logic and Nonstandard Analysis Julian Hartman September 4, 2010 Abstract This paper is intended as an exploration of nonstandard analysis, and the rigorous use of infinitesimals and infinite elements to explore properties of the real numbers. I first define and explore first order logic, and model theory. Then, I prove the compact- ness theorem, and use this to form a nonstandard structure of the real numbers. Using this nonstandard structure, it it easy to to various proofs without the use of limits that would otherwise require their use. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 An Introduction to First Order Logic 2 2.1 Propositional Logic . 2 2.2 Logical Symbols . 2 2.3 Predicates, Constants and Functions . 2 2.4 Well-Formed Formulas . 3 3 Models 3 3.1 Structure . 3 3.2 Truth . 4 3.2.1 Satisfaction . 5 4 The Compactness Theorem 6 4.1 Soundness and Completeness . 6 5 Nonstandard Analysis 7 5.1 Making a Nonstandard Structure . 7 5.2 Applications of a Nonstandard Structure . 9 6 Sources 10 1 1 Introduction The founders of modern calculus had a less than perfect understanding of the nuts and bolts of what made it work. Both Newton and Leibniz used the notion of infinitesimal, without a rigorous understanding of what they were. Infinitely small real numbers that were still not zero was a hard thing for mathematicians to accept, and with the rigorous development of limits by the likes of Cauchy and Weierstrass, the discussion of infinitesimals subsided. Now, using first order logic for nonstandard analysis, it is possible to create a model of the real numbers that has the same properties as the traditional conception of the real numbers, but also has rigorously defined infinite and infinitesimal elements.
    [Show full text]
  • Unification: a Multidisciplinary Survey
    Unification: A Multidisciplinary Survey KEVIN KNIGHT Computer Science Department, Carnegie-Mellon University, Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania 15213-3890 The unification problem and several variants are presented. Various algorithms and data structures are discussed. Research on unification arising in several areas of computer science is surveyed, these areas include theorem proving, logic programming, and natural language processing. Sections of the paper include examples that highlight particular uses of unification and the special problems encountered. Other topics covered are resolution, higher order logic, the occur check, infinite terms, feature structures, equational theories, inheritance, parallel algorithms, generalization, lattices, and other applications of unification. The paper is intended for readers with a general computer science background-no specific knowledge of any of the above topics is assumed. Categories and Subject Descriptors: E.l [Data Structures]: Graphs; F.2.2 [Analysis of Algorithms and Problem Complexity]: Nonnumerical Algorithms and Problems- Computations on discrete structures, Pattern matching; Ll.3 [Algebraic Manipulation]: Languages and Systems; 1.2.3 [Artificial Intelligence]: Deduction and Theorem Proving; 1.2.7 [Artificial Intelligence]: Natural Language Processing General Terms: Algorithms Additional Key Words and Phrases: Artificial intelligence, computational complexity, equational theories, feature structures, generalization, higher order logic, inheritance, lattices, logic programming, natural language
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Similarity in the Foundations
    Self-similarity in the Foundations Paul K. Gorbow Thesis submitted for the degree of Ph.D. in Logic, defended on June 14, 2018. Supervisors: Ali Enayat (primary) Peter LeFanu Lumsdaine (secondary) Zachiri McKenzie (secondary) University of Gothenburg Department of Philosophy, Linguistics, and Theory of Science Box 200, 405 30 GOTEBORG,¨ Sweden arXiv:1806.11310v1 [math.LO] 29 Jun 2018 2 Contents 1 Introduction 5 1.1 Introductiontoageneralaudience . ..... 5 1.2 Introduction for logicians . .. 7 2 Tour of the theories considered 11 2.1 PowerKripke-Plateksettheory . .... 11 2.2 Stratifiedsettheory ................................ .. 13 2.3 Categorical semantics and algebraic set theory . ....... 17 3 Motivation 19 3.1 Motivation behind research on embeddings between models of set theory. 19 3.2 Motivation behind stratified algebraic set theory . ...... 20 4 Logic, set theory and non-standard models 23 4.1 Basiclogicandmodeltheory ............................ 23 4.2 Ordertheoryandcategorytheory. ...... 26 4.3 PowerKripke-Plateksettheory . .... 28 4.4 First-order logic and partial satisfaction relations internal to KPP ........ 32 4.5 Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory and G¨odel-Bernays class theory............ 36 4.6 Non-standardmodelsofsettheory . ..... 38 5 Embeddings between models of set theory 47 5.1 Iterated ultrapowers with special self-embeddings . ......... 47 5.2 Embeddingsbetweenmodelsofsettheory . ..... 57 5.3 Characterizations.................................. .. 66 6 Stratified set theory and categorical semantics 73 6.1 Stratifiedsettheoryandclasstheory . ...... 73 6.2 Categoricalsemantics ............................... .. 77 7 Stratified algebraic set theory 85 7.1 Stratifiedcategoriesofclasses . ..... 85 7.2 Interpretation of the Set-theories in the Cat-theories ................ 90 7.3 ThesubtoposofstronglyCantorianobjects . ....... 99 8 Where to go from here? 103 8.1 Category theoretic approach to embeddings between models of settheory .
    [Show full text]
  • Monadic Decomposition
    Monadic Decomposition Margus Veanes1, Nikolaj Bjørner1, Lev Nachmanson1, and Sergey Bereg2 1 Microsoft Research {margus,nbjorner,levnach}@microsoft.com 2 The University of Texas at Dallas [email protected] Abstract. Monadic predicates play a prominent role in many decid- able cases, including decision procedures for symbolic automata. We are here interested in discovering whether a formula can be rewritten into a Boolean combination of monadic predicates. Our setting is quantifier- free formulas over a decidable background theory, such as arithmetic and we here develop a semi-decision procedure for extracting a monadic decomposition of a formula when it exists. 1 Introduction Classical decidability results of fragments of logic [7] are based on careful sys- tematic study of restricted cases either by limiting allowed symbols of the lan- guage, limiting the syntax of the formulas, fixing the background theory, or by using combinations of such restrictions. Many decidable classes of problems, such as monadic first-order logic or the L¨owenheim class [29], the L¨ob-Gurevich class [28], monadic second-order logic with one successor (S1S) [8], and monadic second-order logic with two successors (S2S) [35] impose at some level restric- tions to monadic or unary predicates to achieve decidability. Here we propose and study an orthogonal problem of whether and how we can transform a formula that uses multiple free variables into a simpler equivalent formula, but where the formula is not a priori syntactically or semantically restricted to any fixed fragment of logic. Simpler in this context means that we have eliminated all theory specific dependencies between the variables and have transformed the formula into an equivalent Boolean combination of predicates that are “essentially” unary.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Logic
    Copyright c 1998–2005 by Stephen G. Simpson Mathematical Logic Stephen G. Simpson December 15, 2005 Department of Mathematics The Pennsylvania State University University Park, State College PA 16802 http://www.math.psu.edu/simpson/ This is a set of lecture notes for introductory courses in mathematical logic offered at the Pennsylvania State University. Contents Contents 1 1 Propositional Calculus 3 1.1 Formulas ............................... 3 1.2 Assignments and Satisfiability . 6 1.3 LogicalEquivalence. 10 1.4 TheTableauMethod......................... 12 1.5 TheCompletenessTheorem . 18 1.6 TreesandK¨onig’sLemma . 20 1.7 TheCompactnessTheorem . 21 1.8 CombinatorialApplications . 22 2 Predicate Calculus 24 2.1 FormulasandSentences . 24 2.2 StructuresandSatisfiability . 26 2.3 TheTableauMethod......................... 31 2.4 LogicalEquivalence. 37 2.5 TheCompletenessTheorem . 40 2.6 TheCompactnessTheorem . 46 2.7 SatisfiabilityinaDomain . 47 3 Proof Systems for Predicate Calculus 50 3.1 IntroductiontoProofSystems. 50 3.2 TheCompanionTheorem . 51 3.3 Hilbert-StyleProofSystems . 56 3.4 Gentzen-StyleProofSystems . 61 3.5 TheInterpolationTheorem . 66 4 Extensions of Predicate Calculus 71 4.1 PredicateCalculuswithIdentity . 71 4.2 TheSpectrumProblem . .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 75 4.3 PredicateCalculusWithOperations . 78 4.4 Predicate Calculus with Identity and Operations . ... 82 4.5 Many-SortedPredicateCalculus . 84 1 5 Theories, Models, Definability 87 5.1 TheoriesandModels ......................... 87 5.2 MathematicalTheories. 89 5.3 DefinabilityoveraModel . 97 5.4 DefinitionalExtensionsofTheories . 100 5.5 FoundationalTheories . 103 5.6 AxiomaticSetTheory . 106 5.7 Interpretability . 111 5.8 Beth’sDefinabilityTheorem. 112 6 Arithmetization of Predicate Calculus 114 6.1 Primitive Recursive Arithmetic . 114 6.2 Interpretability of PRA in Z1 ....................114 6.3 G¨odelNumbers ............................ 114 6.4 UndefinabilityofTruth. 117 6.5 TheProvabilityPredicate .
    [Show full text]
  • 3. Temporal Logics and Model Checking
    3. Temporal Logics and Model Checking Page Temporal Logics 3.2 Linear Temporal Logic (PLTL) 3.4 Branching Time Temporal Logic (BTTL) 3.8 Computation Tree Logic (CTL) 3.9 Linear vs. Branching Time TL 3.16 Structure of Model Checker 3.19 Notion of Fixpoint 3.20 Fixpoint Characterization of CTL 3.25 CTL Model Checking Algorithm 3.30 Symbolic Model Checking 3.34 Model Checking Tools 3.42 References 3.46 3.1 (of 47) Temporal Logics Temporal Logics • Temporal logic is a type of modal logic that was originally developed by philosophers to study different modes of “truth” • Temporal logic provides a formal system for qualitatively describing and reasoning about how the truth values of assertions change over time • It is appropriate for describing the time-varying behavior of systems (or programs) Classification of Temporal Logics • The underlying nature of time: Linear: at any time there is only one possible future moment, linear behavioral trace Branching: at any time, there are different possible futures, tree-like trace structure • Other considerations: Propositional vs. first-order Point vs. intervals Discrete vs. continuous time Past vs. future 3.2 (of 47) Linear Temporal Logic • Time lines Underlying structure of time is a totally ordered set (S,<), isomorphic to (N,<): Discrete, an initial moment without predecessors, infinite into the future. • Let AP be set of atomic propositions, a linear time structure M=(S, x, L) S: a set of states x: NS an infinite sequence of states, (x=s0,s1,...) L: S2AP labeling each state with the set of atomic propositions in AP true at the state.
    [Show full text]
  • First-Order Logic
    Lecture 14: First-Order Logic 1 Need For More Than Propositional Logic In normal speaking we could use logic to say something like: If all humans are mortal (α) and all Greeks are human (β) then all Greeks are mortal (γ). So if we have α = (H → M) and β = (G → H) and γ = (G → M) (where H, M, G are propositions) then we could say that ((α ∧ β) → γ) is valid. That is called a Syllogism. This is good because it allows us to focus on a true or false statement about one person. This kind of logic (propositional logic) was adopted by Boole (Boolean Logic) and was the focus of our lectures so far. But what about using “some” instead of “all” in β in the statements above? Would the statement still hold? (After all, Zeus had many children that were half gods and Greeks, so they may not necessarily be mortal.) We would then need to say that “Some Greeks are human” implies “Some Greeks are mortal”. Unfortunately, there is really no way to express this in propositional logic. This points out that we really have been abstracting out the concept of all in propositional logic. It has been assumed in the propositions. If we want to now talk about some, we must make this concept explicit. Also, we should be able to reason that if Socrates is Greek then Socrates is mortal. Also, we should be able to reason that Plato’s teacher, who is Greek, is mortal. First-Order Logic allows us to do this by writing formulas like the following.
    [Show full text]
  • First Order Logic (Part I)
    Logic: First Order Logic (Part I) Alessandro Artale Free University of Bozen-Bolzano Faculty of Computer Science http://www.inf.unibz.it/˜artale Descrete Mathematics and Logic — BSc course Thanks to Prof. Enrico Franconi for provoding the slides Alessandro Artale Logic: First Order Logic (Part I) Motivation We can already do a lot with propositional logic. But it is unpleasant that we cannot access the structure of atomic sentences. Atomic formulas of propositional logic are too atomic – they are just statement which may be true or false but which have no internal structure. In First Order Logic (FOL) the atomic formulas are interpreted as statements about relationships between objects. Alessandro Artale Logic: First Order Logic (Part I) Predicates and Constants Let’s consider the statements: Mary is female John is male Mary and John are siblings In propositional logic the above statements are atomic propositions: Mary-is-female John-is-male Mary-and-John-are-siblings In FOL atomic statements use predicates, with constants as argument: Female(mary) Male(john) Siblings(mary,john) Alessandro Artale Logic: First Order Logic (Part I) Variables and Quantifiers Let’s consider the statements: Everybody is male or female A male is not a female In FOL, predicates may have variables as arguments, whose value is bounded by quantifiers: ∀x. Male(x) ∨ Female(x) ∀x. Male(x) → ¬Female(x) Deduction (why?): Mary is not male ¬Male(mary) Alessandro Artale Logic: First Order Logic (Part I) Functions Let’s consider the statement: The father of a person is male In FOL objects of the domain may be denoted by functions applied to (other) objects: ∀x.
    [Show full text]