Quick viewing(Text Mode)

DOES HISTORY HAVE a FUTURE? an Inquiry Into History As Research

DOES HISTORY HAVE a FUTURE? an Inquiry Into History As Research

DOES HAVE A FUTURE? An Inquiry into History as Research

Ronald Alan Sulman

Submitted in total fulfilment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2008

School of Historical Studies THE UNIVERSITY OF

Produced on acid-free paper

ABSTRACT

This thesis explores the question of history’s future as a research discipline in the academy and the question of the discipline’s function in ‘pure’ inquiry. Central to the notion of research is the notion of discovery of new knowledge, but what constitutes new historical knowledge rather than simply more historical information is not clear. As the idea of research

(which is understood to mean the discovery and creation of new knowledge) is central to the idea of the modern university, the future of history as a research discipline in the research university would seem to depend on the discipline being clear on its research function.

Further complicating resolution of this question is the fact that the funding of research is informed by science and technology paradigms where research is defined as ‘pure basic research’, ‘strategic basic research’, ‘applied research’, and ‘experimental development’.

Curiously, what these classifications mean for the humanities generally and history in particular, remains unexamined—despite the fact that professional survival depends on the academic convincing sceptical funders of the relevance of humanist research. Do do basic research? If basic research is inquiry at the edge of understanding, how, and by whom, is the edge defined? In the first decades of the University of Berlin—the institution that formed the model for the modern research-university—the edge was defined through philosophy and history. Hegelian systematic philosophy, Fichtean philosophy of the subject, and the philosophical historicism of such thinkers as Ranke, Niebuhr, Ast and Boeckh was concerned with the subject’s knowledge of knowledge: there lay the edge. By the end of the nineteenth century no discipline was foundational. Epistemological ‘advance’ had resulted in not only the split of knowledge into that derived from humanities or ‘spirit’ studies

(Geisteswissenschaften) and that from science studies (Naturwissenschaften), but also the proliferation of disciplinary specialization that further entrenched the dichotomy.

In the twenty-first century, inquiry’s edge has moved on. Climate change, environmental degradation and biological and genetic engineering have posed wholly new existential questions. The Archimedean point from where the edge is viewed is no longer

iii

anthropocentric. Society and nature are inextricably connected. The physical and the spiritual can no longer be considered separately. When ‘we’ can either be manufactured or artificially enhanced the notion of autonomy and self-fashioning takes on a different hue in postmodernity than in modernity. There is now an increasing but unsatisfied need for more interdisciplinary and holistic knowledge. Unfortunately, no effective models or processes exist to enable this need to be met. This thesis explores ways in which the deficiencies might be overcome and explores academic history’s possible location within a future integrated- knowledge schema.

iv

DECLARATION

This is to certify that

i. the thesis comprises only my original work towards the PhD,

ii. due acknowledgement has been made in the text to all other material used,

iii. the thesis is less than 100,000 words in length, exclusive of tables, maps,

bibliographies and appendices.

v

vi

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

I wish to acknowledge the encouragement, support and guidance given to me in the production of this thesis by my supervisors, Laureate Professor and Dr

David Goodman, and also by Professor Peter McPhee, who regardless of other duties has always found time to discuss and advise. Without Peter’s encouragement and enthusiasm the project might have remained thoughts only. Without Stuart’s wise counsel and instinctive sense of proportion during the candidature, the line where angels fear to tread would have been crossed often; the nudging away from peril was always timely. Without David’s diplomatic but firm insistence that arguments needed to be both central and convincing, there might have been a very grand drive to a rather modest house.

I am grateful also to Dr Louis Sass and Dr Robyn Ferrell for the discussions we had and their generosity in giving me copies of unpublished papers presented by them at separate research seminars. Dr Sass’s seminar discussing ‘madness’, Oscar Weininger, and the intersection of clinical psychology and the creative imagination coincided with my interest in the relationship between intelligence and survival. Dr Ferrell’s seminar on the technology of

‘genre’ coincided with my interest in questions raised by Hans Jonas, Jürgen Habermas and others regarding post-human futures and the boundaries between the ‘natural’ and the manufactured.

I hope the house stands up to more than a gentle breeze. If it does not, it will be the fault of the architect alone.

vii

viii

TABLE OF CONTENTS

Abstract...... iii

Declaration...... v

Acknowledgements...... vii

Introduction...... 1

PART I: PAST

1. History and the Knowledge Business...... 17 1.1 The Barbarian’s Gaze 17 1.2 University Business 28 1.3 The Business of the University 38

2. Research and Scholarship...... 61 2.1 The Pursuit of Knowledge 61 2.2 History and Discovery 75 2.3 Discovery under Different Skies 97

3. Knowledge and Understanding ...... 113 3.1 History and Function 113 3.2 Knowledge and Reason 128 3.3 Research and Purpose 147

PART II: FUTURE

4. Integrated Pure Inquiry...... 163 4.1 Inquiry’s Moving Edge 163 4.2 Subjectivity, Embodiment, and Systems 177 4.3 Unified Inquiry and the Unity of Knowledge 195

ix

5. History and Research Management...... 211 5.1 A Constellation of Disciplines 211 5.2 Integrating Specialist Knowledge 234 5.3 Universities, Research, and History 252

Conclusion ...... 267

Bibliography...... 279

Tables 1. Knowledge Map 205

Figures 1. Knowledge Model 206 2. Inquiry Constellation 207

x

DOES HISTORY HAVE A FUTURE?

An Inquiry into History as Research

PART I: PAST

Introduction

INTRODUCTION

If poets are the unacknowledged legislators of the world, science fiction writers are its court jesters. We are the wise fools who can leap, caper, utter prophecies, and scratch ourselves in public. We can play with Big Ideas because the garish motley of our pulp origins makes us seem harmless … yet our ideas permeate the culture, bubbling along invisibly, like background radiation. —Bruce Sterling: Burning Chrome1

Historians have lately been poor synthesizers and may soon find that others are doing their synthesizing and paradigm-establishing for them. Whether they like evolution or not, an informed reaction would probably be timely. —David Gary Shaw: History and Theory2

In his book, The Practice of History, declared that when he read discussions

by others of how historians think, ‘how they claim to describe that which no longer exists, or

whether historical fact has an existence independent of the thinker about facts, I marvel at the

ingenuity of the writers, for usually they are men who have never apparently themselves tried

to do the work’.3 Elton, with his usual pugnacity, was entering into the debate on the

question ‘What is history?’, and Hugh Trevor-Roper observed at the time (1967) that

‘[Elton’s] challengers seldom emerge ungored … even an innocent bystander may be nicked

by the flashing horn’.4 Indeed they may—particularly the bystander embarking on a research

degree in history; and particularly if that embarkation was stimulated by interest in the

question of history’s future in the academy. Increasing the risk further is the requirement, for

successful completion of that degree, that the apprentice demonstrate ‘the ability to analyse

critically within and across a changing disciplinary environment’.5

The issue, however, is not so much the danger of the accidental nick as the fact that

1 Bruce Sterling, preface, in William Gibson, Burning Chrome (New York: Arbor House, 1986), 1. 2 David Gary Shaw, “The Return of Science”, History and Theory, 38, no. 4 (Dec., 1999): 8. 3 G. R. Elton, The Practice of History (: Fontana Press, 1987), vii. 4 Cover, Elton, The Practice of History. 5 Dean of the School of Graduate Studies, The : The PhD Handbook (Parkville: School of Graduate Studies, 2004), 1.

1 Introduction

there is an obvious truth in Elton’s remark. In practical life—that life which, as Ortega y

Gassett says, is fired at us point-blank6—experience counts for more than opinions. Until one

has done something, do not presume to preach to those that have. The Practice of History,

Elton explained, was not a treatise, but an explanation of one working ’s faith and

practice. His was a particular cast of mind and he had a particular, though orthodox, notion

of what history was; but given that he was an eminent, highly professional, historian, he had

earned the right to speak.

Elton’s injunction, however, to ‘watch and learn!’, while perhaps sound advice to the

apprentice for learning the craft of writing history, was certainly not sound advice if academic

history is more than a craft. Issues of scepticism (in its formal philosophical sense) may be

ignored, perhaps, but issues of objectivity, values, and critical stance may not. Faith is not

enough, and Elton was deliberately conflating form with content and declaring, emphatically,

that the past and the historian’s presentation of it were the same thing. Thus, common sense,

not theory, was what was needed for history’s practice. But academic history is, of course,

more than a craft for the presentation of information about the past. As academic history—as

distinct from antiquarianism or cultural narrative—it is a mode of inquiry whose purpose is to

find answers to particular conceptual questions. Consequently, the history craftsman can no

more ignore questions regarding history’s theoretical foundations than the buggy-whip

craftsman could ignore questions of transportation modes. The buggy-whip manufacturer

who assumed that the motor-car was not here to stay, would live to regret that assumption.

There are always larger forces operating. Transport modes change and associated trades

either adapt or die; society changes and institutions either adapt or die; and styles of reasoning

change and academic disciplines either adapt or die. ‘Adapt or suffer extinction!’ seems to be

one unavoidable, if primitive, lesson from experience.

As we now know, the philosophical drip that had irritated Elton in the , soon

became a post-structuralist trickle, which by the had turned into a postmodernist flood

6 José Ortega y Gassett, Mission of the University, ed. Howard Lee Nostrand (New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1992), 63.

2 Introduction

that threatened to sweep away the profession’s entire foundations. The severe effects of the

torrent were evident in the forum held by The American Historical Review in 1990 to discuss

the implications for the profession of Peter Novick’s That Noble Dream: The ‘Objectivity

Question’ and the American Historical Profession. Novick had discussed what he saw as ‘the

collapse of comity’ in the profession, and had concluded, gloomily, that by the last decades of

the twentieth-century: ‘every group its own historian’; that ‘there was no king in Israel’.7

According to the Review’s editor, the attendees to the forum were so numerous that ‘they

filled the aisles, the floor space in back (sic) of the room, and spilled into the corridor

outside’.8 In the first decade of the twenty-first century, the question of what the future holds

for the discipline is still ‘open’—as it is for the academy itself. What is it that academic

historians do that requires their location (either real or virtual) within the academy?

Conversely, what is it that the academy does that requires historians?

Dorothy Ross, in her attempt to summarize the American Historical Review’s forum

discussion, wondered whether ‘this radical disjunction between epistemology and practice …

could be a postmodern stance’. By ‘postmodern stance’ she meant a self-reflexive, ironic,

stance by the historian towards the objectivity of the historian’s own account. Her own view

was that the experience of historical research—in the words of another participant: the ‘quiet

listening to voices from the past’—was just ‘one stage within the hermeneutic process [italics

in original]’.9 In other words, the past was simply the field used by the researcher in the quest

for a deeper understanding of something else. Therefore, history was more than simply a

science-like reconstitution of past society; that ‘something else’, as Dilthey emphasized,

concerned meaning in the ‘human’ world—in all that world’s most mysterious and elusive

aspects. There were many ways of seeing, thus many ways of knowing. And the relationship

between language and how experience was understood, was complex. The human world’s

essence required more than science to capture, and its meaning required more than science to

7 Chapter headings, Peter Novick, That Noble Dream: The ‘Objectivity Question’ and the American Historical Profession (: Cambridge University Press, 1988). 8 Editorial Note, “AHR Forum: Peter Novick’s That Noble Dream: The ‘Objectivity Question’ and the American Historical Profession”, American Historical Review, 96, no. 3. (Jun., 1991): 675. 9 Dorothy Ross, “AHR Forum Afterword”, American Historical Review, 96, no. 3. (June, 1991): 705.

3 Introduction

communicate. Was, therefore, history also an art?

The question has proven intractable. In one-hundred years, the discipline has made

little progress on the history-as-art-or-science question since the debate was ignited by J. B.

Bury in his much criticized, but much misunderstood, 1903 inaugural lecture.10 And yet it

needs clarification if history’s function, and its different role inside and outside the academy,

is to be understood. Notwithstanding our current ironic stance, and our improved theoretical

equipment, the ‘What is History?’ debate is still active. Bury’s argument, and Trevelyan’s

rejoinder,11 are still pertinent.

In Australia, in 1993, the debate flared again, with great heat and great bitterness, over

the merit as history of ’s six volume, A . Whether the

combatants were from inside the academy or outside, it mattered little to the position taken.

To some the work epitomized ‘great’ history; to others it was just literary fiction, just the

highly coloured phrases of an author painting a preconceived vision; to still others, with

Clark, ‘the whole game had escaped him’. When a truce was called, neither side had been

moved from their original positions. It seemed that everyone had their own view of what the

history ‘game’ was about, and what truth was at its centre. 12 But there was no interest in the

question of where it was produced—whether from inside the academy or outside it. ‘History’

seemed not to be considered the exclusive province of the academy; there were no barriers-to-

entry perceived for . The relevant consideration seemed only to be how ‘good’

was the history that was written.

But, clearly, there must be a difference between an academic whose field of inquiry is

the past and an amateur whose field of interest is the past, if the one is to be paid as an

academic specialist. Or rather, there should be a difference if the academic historian is to

10 J. B. Bury, “The Science of History”, Selected Essays of J. B. Bury, ed. Harold Temperley (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1930). 11 G. M. Trevelyan, “Clio, A Muse”, George Macaulay Trevelyan, Clio, A Muse and Other Essays Literary and Pedestrian (London: Longmans, Green and Co., 1913). 12 The debate was sparked by Clark’s publisher, , in an article “Manning Clark”, Quadrant, 37, no. 9 (1993). The range of views can be found in, Manning Clark: Essays on His Place in History, ed. Carl Bridge (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1994).

4 Introduction

argue for remuneration as a specialist in the academy, not as an author in the marketplace. As

cultural beings, history is the air we breathe—we need origin stories; and as cognitive beings,

history is our intuitive conceptual frame—experience is our guide. Consequently, ‘history’s’

existence is assured. But academic history is not that history. That history is extrinsic to the

function the academic historian performs in the academy. If the discipline is to adapt

successfully to institutional and social change, then it must be clear on that difference; it must

be clear what ‘business’ it is in. The function of the academic historian cannot be that of (just

another) writer of if the word ‘academic’ is to have any meaning.

Dorothy Ross had noted, also, that

One thing that redefinition of historical objectivity based on intellectual communities cannot do … is render historiography immune from the deeper forces of historical contingency at work in the profession … questions, methods, and standards of competence inescapably flow with the tides of history.13

But Ross was assuming that the profession was capable of absorbing those forces and

refashioning itself. There is, of course, another possible outcome. The discipline could

simply sink beneath the tides, to be replaced by more vigorous forms of inquiry. There is no

law which says that the discipline (or the university) should survive the larger forces of

historical contingency—just as there is no law which says trades, or companies, should

survive. History and the ‘humanities’ are no more assured of a permanent place, as entities,

in the academy, than were the trivium and quadrivium which were once the very definition of

what was meant by ‘liberal education’, which, in turn, was the very definition of a university

education.

One could, however, speculate and conclude that a more likely outcome is that there

will be an increasing separation of practice from those inside the academy to those outside it.

Inside the academy ‘history’ will become a term like ‘molecular structure’ and be used by

many specialists in the prosecution of their particular inquiry. The historian might then

13 Ross, “AHR Forum Afterword”, 705–706.

5 Introduction

metamorphose to a more complex form of history specialist, and ‘history’ might then be the

term used to denote the particular product produced outside the academy—whether by history

professionals, or by the amateur craftsman—as with ‘painting’, ‘pottery’, and other ‘writing’.

At the beginning of the twenty-first century we are very aware of what, now, are some

of the deeper forces Ross was connoting. Population growth, globalization, the revolution in

information technology, and the revolution in biological science, have changed the world in

ways unimagined even in the last decades of the twentieth century. For the society, the

implications for future life of biotechnology, the ‘wired world’, and climate change are

immense. For the university, the implications of the ‘wired world’ on the university’s

traditional role as ‘knowledge gatekeeper’, is profound. And the implications of new notions

of intellectual property arising from such historically contingent actions as, for example, the

implementation of the Bayh-Dole Act,14 have already changed the way universities (and

governments) organize and value knowledge. For the disciplines, the effect of neuroscience,

nanotechnology, biological science, and genetic engineering on the boundaries of disciplinary

inquiry, is revolutionary. Notions of human nature, of human culture, and of

anthropocentricity itself, are changing. Thus, both the form and content of the ‘humanities’

and social sciences cannot fail to be affected. It does not mean that they are less relevant,

merely that they must be clear on what their distinctive domain and function is in the

academy as it evolves in the twenty-first century.

If the assumption is accepted that the academy as an idea will continue to denote an

intimate connection to knowledge and its creation, then each and every discipline must be

clear on how it, as specialist inquiry, contributes to the discovery of new knowledge within

these new knowledge-contexts. But since knowledge contexts evolve, so too do

understandings of what comprises useful knowledge. Therefore, neither the sciences, nor the

humanities and social sciences, alone, are sufficient for the discovery of useful new

knowledge. This does mean, however, that the academy, if it is to continue to claim a

distinctive institutional research role in the wider community, has an obligation to develop

14 In the US, in 1980.

6 Introduction

structures and processes that enable the effective integration of these very different specialist

researches conducted inside its boundaries. Currently no such structures and processes exist.

Mixing disciplines is not integrating knowledge.

II

The motivation for this thesis was curiosity regarding history’s future in the academy, and

what ‘evolve’ might mean for the practice. However, the stimulus for that curiosity was the

argument in Australia regarding the role of universities, the way in which research should be

funded, and the place of the arts and humanities in the new, global, ‘knowledge economy’.

The debate in Australia had its origins in the neo-liberal philosophy adopted by the Australian

government in the late 1980s and the affect this philosophy had on the funding and

organization of Australia’s tertiary education sector. In the public debate there appeared to be

an irreconcilable tension between the rationale of the arts and humanities and the commercial

logic of the ‘knowledge economy’. On the one hand, it seemed that no-one denied the

essential role that the arts and humanities had in fostering innovative thought and enhancing

‘quality of life’. On the other, the difficult question was: how is their value to be measured

(thus, what funding, and what mechanism for funding, is appropriate)?

The arguments forwarded by the arts and humanities lobbies as answers to these

questions seemed to be either self-defeating or autotelic. With economic rationalism clearly

identified as the enemy (because of its narrow conception of utility), the arts and humanities

could either argue for relevance through appeal to narrow instrumentalist logic—media

content, for example—or an opposite, abstract, appeal to the idea of the university, and the

idea of liberal education. The first argument was a capitulation; the second argument seemed

circular and based on faith, not logic. Unless the purpose of the pursuit of that belief could be

explained in terms of today’s needs, then its relevance would still be not obvious to those that

needed convincing. And yet, the conviction behind that belief—the intrinsic value of

knowledge for its own sake and the pursuit of ‘truth’—was central to the notion of ‘pure’

7 Introduction

research15 which, in turn, was central to the notion of the ‘knowledge economy’. The

economic rationalists’ central creed was that national ‘wealth’ depended on competitiveness

in the global knowledge economy, and that it was research which was the key to that

international competitiveness.

The problem was, neither the arts and humanities lobbyists, nor the economic

rationalists, had any clear idea of where or how arts and humanities research could be fitted

into the predominantly science- and technology-driven research and development (R&D)

paradigm. That paradigm defined the process by which knowledge was ‘advanced’ in the

international ‘knowledge economy’. How could two fundamentally different types of

knowledge—empirical knowledge and hermeneutic knowledge16—be fitted into the one

paradigm? One resulted in tangible products which, regardless of whether the product was a

mobile phone, a communication system, or a lunar module, delivered obvious utility to

individuals, society, and governments. The delivery of that utility, however, was only

possible through a phased development process which separated researchers at one end from

users at the other. The researchers could not produce the product, and the users could not

accomplish the research. Each phase of the conversion process required different skills and

different knowledge. In contrast, the ‘product’ of hermeneutic knowledge was

understanding. The user’s understanding of the research was the product utility. There was,

15 By ‘pure research’ is meant ‘basic research’. ‘Basic research’ is an OECD and Australian Bureau of Statistics R&D-category term; the categories are, in order: pure basic research, strategic basic research, applied research, experimental development; ‘innovation’ is a separate category, outside ‘R&D’. See footnote Chapter 3, p. 114. 16 The one type of knowledge derived from natural science or Naturwissenschaften, the other from the ‘moral sciences’ or Geisteswissenschaften (‘spirit ‘sciences or studies), to use the original nineteenth-century German term. Wissenschaft means pure learning as opposed to utilitarian skills. The tem Geisteswissenschaften was made popular by Jacob Schiel, the German translator of John Stuart Mill’s System of Logic, but through Dilthey the romantic, idealist heritage of the word, rather than its science root, was emphasized. See Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method (London: Continuum, 2004), 3–8. In the 1980s the term came to be associated with the neo-historicism that emerged from the ongoing national debate (Historikerstreit—‘historian’s quarrel’) on how to interpret Germany’s Nazi past. Jürgen Habermas described this neo-historicism as a reaction which ‘sees itself as a return to the important nineteenth-century German tradition of Geisteswissenschaften’. However, in this modern form, he explained, it was a “rehabilitation of narrative’ … the narrative presentation of events as opposed to the claims of theoretical understanding’. See Jürgen Habermas, Autonomy and Solidarity: Interviews with Jürgen Habermas, ed. Peter Dews (London: Verso, 1992), 237. Throughout this thesis the term Geisteswissenschaften will be used in its original sense of theoretical inquiry.

8 Introduction

therefore, the assumption that the pure research product and the user product were

coincident—that no additional process, other than articulation, separated them. Further,

judgements of the utility of the delivered knowledge would depend on not just whether it was

understood, but also on whether its content was agreed. Its utility would be demonstrated

through its general intellectual affectiveness. The non-specialist user was, in effect, judging

the relevance of esoteric basic research.

In that there can be no other judge of utility than the user, both product types were

similar. There are as many physical products judged to be ‘useless’ as there are ‘useless’

theories and ideas. But for one, there was a process by which basic research was shielded

from non-specialist scrutiny. For the other, there was no process. This was unfortunate as the

arts and humanities needed a process that insulated their basic research outputs from the

requirement to demonstrate value to government (and public) users, and yet which allowed

governments and the public to have confidence that they would benefit, eventually, from the

advances being made at the edge of human understanding. Although organizational

structures exist, in the form of expert panels in research funding bodies, which, in principle,

should ensure that research is funded on its basic-research merits not utility, in practice the

pervasiveness of and instrumental logic—through the governing boards and other

administrative bodies—often results in compromised selection.

A particular irony is that the styles of reasoning developed in the 1920s and 30s by the

philosophers and social scientists in the Frankfurt Institute for Social Research in order,

specifically, to make theoretical research socially relevant,17 and which have been seminal for

current social critique, are now seen by economic rationalists to epitomize ‘useless’

academic, postmodernist, indulgence, and peripheral to the ‘real world’ knowledge

economy.18 There is some recognition that no one disciplinary knowledge is foundational—

17 Max Horkheimer, towards the end of his life, commented that ‘The enterprise succeeded only because … a group of men, interested in social theory and from different scholarly backgrounds, came together with the belief that formulating the negative in the epoch of transition was more meaningful than academic careers.’ Max Horkheimer, “Foreword”, in Martin Jay, The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research 1923–1950 (Boston and Toronto: Little, Brown and Company, 1973), xi. 18 See, for example, Gideon Haigh, “The Nelson Touch: The New Censorship”, The Monthly,

9 Introduction

that specialist knowledge, whether scientific or non-scientific, is entwined. But what is still

lacking are conceptual models that enable the effective integration of the different researches.

Pure Geisteswissenschaften19 research is as fundamental to the knowledge economy as pure

scientific and technological research.

For this thesis, therefore, it seemed that if the future of the arts and humanities (history

in particular) was the object of interest, then the question to pursue was the nature of arts and

humanities research, and the relationship between scientific and non-scientific knowledge.

But inseparable from those questions were the associated questions of what is meant by

knowledge, thus what is meant by new knowledge as distinct from simply more information?

Hence, what is meant by ‘discovery’ in relation to knowledge? Could forgotten knowledge

rediscovered be considered new knowledge? To what extent is wisdom, knowledge? How do

we know? What do we know? Why know?20

It seemed, on reflection, that the utility of Geisteswissenschaften knowledge—its

affectiveness or value in ‘real’ life—is derived in two ways: through guidance in the ethical

and practical life: how to act, and in enrichment of ‘spiritual’ life or existential being—thus,

how to be. History, as a form of wisdom, Carlyle’s history, for example, or Clark’s, could

provide utility in both those ways (if their ‘history’ was agreed). In comparison, the aesthetic

arts would provide solely existential utility. It seemed, therefore, that any inquiry concerning

academic history’s future research role could not avoid epistemology or ontology; and neither

could it avoid teleology since origins and change were the matter of the historian’s traditional

research function.

As the pursuit of these questions was undertaken as part of a research degree in history,

not philosophy, and as the arguments and discussion were intended for historians, not

philosophers, so the approach taken was historical, not philosophical (in its disciplinary

sense). Genealogy and the tracing of custom and practice, not technical arguments in

May, 2006. 19 See note 16 above for the meaning of this term in this thesis. 20 ‘But why not allow oneself to be deceived?’ Nietzsche asked (The Gay Science, Book V, Passage 344).

10 Introduction

philosophy, were the main methods used. Specifically, the idea of research and the research

university was investigated, and the historical research paradigm, as it was enunciated and

then institutionalized, was traced. In particular, the different understandings and practices in

Germany, Britain, and Australia were studied. The different understandings and practices

arose from different intellectual traditions and institutional settings, and those differences

produced different histories. The study indicated that those different histories reflected the

search for different knowledge, different ‘truths’, and different understanding. Consequently,

the issues this raised regarding truth, knowledge, and understanding, were explored and their

implications for academic research considered.

The study recapitulated the (perhaps obvious) fact that all disciplinary intellectual

inquiry is a search for true knowledge through the penetration of appearances to an

underlying reality (disciplinary boundaries, in principle, define domains of interest, not

separate knowledge) but that there are epistemological and ontological problems because of

the ambiguity and elasticity of the terms ‘true’ and ‘underlying reality’. True to what?

Which reality is pre-eminent: social reality or physical reality? Can there be knowledge with

no point of view? 21 The study showed also that these perplexities had stimulated a related

and persistent concern, particularly since the mid-nineteenth century and becoming more

insistent throughout the twentieth century, that increasing specialization in research was

exacerbating an increasing but unsatisfied need for more interdisciplinary and holistic

knowledge. Thus, the question was not ‘What is the primary reality?’, nor even ‘Which

reality should be considered primary?’ Rather, it was: ‘If research is to ‘progress’, how can

the two types of research knowledge be unified so that ‘progress’ can be made?’ 22 And

specifically, where would history fit in any unified research schema? Consequently, the

thesis explored possible new conceptual frames, new knowledge models, and new

21 Or, as Thomas Nagel described it: a ‘view from nowhere’. Maurice Merleau-Ponty commented: ‘Since we are all hemmed in by history, it is up to us to understand that whatever truth we may have is to be gotten not in spite but through our historical inherence … As long as I cling to the ideal of an absolute spectator, of knowledge with no point of view, I can see my situation as nothing but a source of error.’ Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Signs, trans. Richard C. McCleary (Evanston, Ill: Northwestern University Press, 1964), 109. 22 The question of what ‘progress’ means is, of course, itself a perennial research question.

11 Introduction

institutional processes. The result is a thesis which moves from past practice to future

possibilities.

III

This thesis, consequently, is a project in intellectual history but one whose ‘stance’ is towards

the philosophy of history and the sociology of knowledge. The first phase investigated how

the search for knowledge became institutionalized in the modern university, and the ways in

which the fundamental philosophical problems inherent in the intuitive human desire to know

were articulated and reflected in disciplinary research—in particular, how they were reflected

in academic history in Germany, England and Australia in the nineteenth and twentieth

centuries. The roots of German Idealism and British Positivism were traced, as well as the

distinctive attitudes towards research, pedagogy and ‘Kultur’ that existed in each country.

The first phase concluded with a deeper investigation of the nature of knowledge and

understanding and what research at the edge of understanding might mean.

The final research phase looked more closely at the issues of reason, subjectivity and

the synthesis of empirical and hermeneutic knowledge. The rise and rise of the biological

sciences and genetic engineering in the late twentieth century has meant that the notion of

embodied cognition is now as fundamental to notions of subjectivity, judgement, and

intelligent action as disembodied logic, reason, and common sense had been earlier. There is

now an increasing understanding of the interconnectedness of the body/mind/culture network

that is our society and our life-world, and of the blurring in the present life-world—as a result

of biological and genetic engineering—of the distinction between the manufactured and the

‘naturally grown’. Increasingly, academic inquiry is investigating post-human futures.

The longitudinal and synthetic nature of the research questions in the research phases

meant that a wide range of literature had to be studied. Initially the focus was on literature

concerning the history of the university, education, and research, then literature concerning

German, British and Australian universities and historiography.23 However, quite quickly the

23 A wide range of literature old and new was reviewed, from standard works such as those of

12 Introduction

intellectual focus of the literature review became the investigation of what, in those

institutional and intellectual settings, the research ‘edge’ was perceived to be, and what was

the (moving) Archimedean point from which those researchers looked ‘down’ upon their

(changing) research objects. Regardless of whether the period was pre- or post-

Enlightenment, or pre- or post-modernity, and regardless of whether the argument concerned

the legitimacy of romanticism or modernity or postmodernity, at the core of those concerns

were always the apparently irreconcilable mind/body, agency/structure,

empiricism/rationalism dualisms.24 Finally, the focus became literature which explored

current notions of cognition, embodiment and genetic and biological engineering and their

inextricable connections to bioethics, neuroethics and posthuman futures.25

The review confirmed the intractability of the problem of the increasing need for the

integration of specialist research effort, but the lack of a conceptual framework by which this

might be managed. There were practical difficulties: only academic researchers appreciated

the intellectual value of the more ‘extreme’ pure basic research in the humanities, arts and

social sciences, and only managers appreciated the necessity of structure and control

(however disguised) for the successful execution of any group process. And there were

theoretical difficulties: there was general acceptance that no discipline was foundational, but

also that, paradoxically, research advance implied increasing specialization.26 But the

Laurence Veysey, George Iggers, Fritz Ringer, A. H. Halsey, Sheldon Rothblatt, to more recent work such as that of, for example, Michael Gibbons, Helga Nowotny, Ronald Barnett, Tony Becher, Simon Marginson and articles in current education journals such as American Journal of Education, British Journal of Educational Studies, European Journal of Education, etc. 24 As articulated in the last twenty years, for example, by contemporary thinkers such as Jürgen Habermas, Niklas Luhmann, Richard Rorty, Jean-Francois Lyotard, Paul Ricoeur, Hans Blumenberg, Hans-Georg Gadamer, Hans Jonas, Michel Serres, Reinhart Kosselleck, Frank Ankersmit, and other writers such as Hubert Dreyfus, Seyla Benhabib, Richard Bernstein, and Martin Jay, for example ( and journals such as History and Theory, New German Critique, Journal of the History of Ideas, and the Journal of Modern History, for example). 25 Literature exemplified by such writers as Daniel Dennett, Antonio Damasio, Howard Gardner, William Connolly, N. Katherine Hayles, Sharon Krause, Martha Nussbaum and (again) Jürgen Habermas, Richard Rorty, Hans Jonas, Michel Serres and their ilk. 26 Arguments such as those between Habermas and Rorty, or Habermas and Luhmann, or Rorty and Lyotard address these issues, but only as philosophical discussion. Where there is argument across the science/humanities divide—such as, for example the discussion between Jean-Pierre Changeux and Paul Ricoeur (What Makes Us Think?: A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain), the result is, inevitably, simply agreement to differ.

13 Introduction

literature reflected also that there was, and is, an underlying ontological problem. If the

intellectual journey from Enlightenment to modernity to postmodernity reflected what has

been called the crisis of reason, then the journey from postmodern to post-human is reflecting

what could be called the crisis of intelligence. Can research answer the question: ‘What is

knowledge, thus research, for?’ If pure basic research is inquiry at the edge of understanding,

how, and by whom, is the edge defined?

Chapter 1 of the thesis begins with the exploration of the conflict between the

economic-rationalist (‘managerialist’) funders and the arts and humanities fundees, and

explores notions of value and distinctive competence. It argues that universities and

disciplines must identify their unique research roles in the competitive knowledge economy.

Chapter 2 investigates the issue of research and scholarship and how the desire to know

became translated into separate domains of knowledge. It looks also at the way in which

academic history became institutionalized in Germany, England and Australia. The chapter

explores the different epistemological and social traditions in those countries, and the

relationship between research, scholarship, history, and the notion of epistemological

‘discovery’. Chapter 3 explores the relationship between data, information, and knowledge

and the question of the purpose of understanding. In looking at these questions, the role of

research and the issue of what academic history saw traditionally to be its function in the

search for knowledge and understanding, is investigated. In Chapter 4 the question of

inquiry’s ‘moving edge’ and its consequences is explored. The twenty-first century presents

new problems, thus new responses are required. The question of what constitutes ‘intelligent’

response becomes problematic if notions of intelligence are expanded beyond traditional,

narrow definitions. Possible new conceptual frames and knowledge models are discussed,

and academic history’s place in these new frames and models is explored. The final chapter

looks at past and current experience with the fragmentation of knowledge resulting from

increasing research specialization, and the ineffectiveness so far of institutional arrangements

to mitigate, or solve, the problem. The relevance of defence and aerospace models to the

management of whole-of-knowledge programs is investigated, and the institutional and

14 Introduction

disciplinary implications discussed. The discussion in this section of the thesis draws on the

candidate’s professional experience in the management of large and small multidisciplinary,

advanced-technology development projects in the defence, aerospace, telecommunications

and information-technology industries.

IV

This thesis has sought to investigate the future of academic history in rapidly changing

intellectual, institutional, and social contexts. Such a project is inherently risky—perhaps

naive. To attempt such broad questions, many of which lie outside the traditional boundaries

of the discipline, is to risk superficiality and lack of focus. The questions, however, arose

from real and current problems and the conviction that if a useful contribution, however

small, could made to the conversation surrounding these issues, then that contribution would

be of some value. What was not anticipated, but was fortunate, was the growing awareness

that the issue of synthesis of disciplinary knowledge—how to integrate disciplinary

knowledge into a more unified whole—was an important and widely recognized issue, but

one that was not being addressed by researchers because its broad interdisciplinary nature

was antithetical to research by the single researcher. Thus, although this thesis cannot claim

the discovery of new information within the many fields it covers, it has attempted to advance

conceptual understanding of those fields and of how multidisciplinary knowledge could be

synthesized. In that respect, it is hoped that it has avoided the risks of superficiality and lack

of focus, and enables enhanced professional knowledge in a specialist area.

15

16

CHAPTER 1

HISTORY AND THE KNOWLEDGE BUSINESS

Thus it was with Flexner’s Universities. Flexner thought he was describing the ideal modern university—an institution whose outlines he had glimpsed at Johns Hopkins and Berlin and whose realization throughout America, England, and Germany awaited only certain reforms which he enumerated. Instead, as the passage of history has revealed, he was writing a valedictory to a university form which was already passing—already evolving to a new stage. In so doing, he preserved for us, in perhaps its purest and most completely reasoned form, the “idea of a modern university” at a crucial stage of its development, just as Cardinal Newman, seventy-five years before, had so eloquently preserved the “idea of a University” at an earlier, equally important, and equally passing stage. —Clark Kerr: Introduction to Universities: American, English, German1

Scholars working in the humanities would be well advised to … see how their work contributed to a larger project, how its distinctive emphasis fit together with others both humanistic and nonhumanistic. They would then be in a better position to understand their actual and potential contributions to knowledge as a whole and even to the culture at large. They would, in other words, be better able to address one of the most stubborn dilemmas in higher education, the perennial crisis in the humanities. —Geoffrey Galt Harpham: ‘Beneath and Beyond the “Crisis in the Humanities”’2

It is not the strongest of the species that survive, not the most intelligent, but the one most responsive to change. —Charles Darwin3

The Barbarian’s Gaze

In their satirical introduction to the book Innovation & Tradition, Elizabeth Bullen and Simon

Robb, acting as ‘founding members’ of the ‘Committee for the Extermination of Arts and

Humanities Funding’, cleverly parody what they imply is the unimaginative and myopic

1 Abraham Flexner, Universities: American, English, German (New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1994), xviii. 2 Geoffrey Galt Harpham: “Beneath and Beyond the “Crisis in the Humanities””, New Literary History, 36, no. 1. (Winter, 2005): 21. 3 Quoted in The World Bank, Constructing Knowledge Societies: New Challenges for Tertiary Education (Washington D.C.: The World Bank, 2002), 1.

17 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

rationale of the ‘knowledge economy’, as publicly defined.4 That rationale, they find, as

other critics have found, is always being promoted through the ‘aggressive dominant

discourses of economic accountability and social practicality’.5 Neither Bullen nor Robb, nor

the other critics, would claim to be offering an impartial view, nevertheless, there is much

about the narrow instrumental reason they identify that can be parodied. The issue, though, is

not a new one. Both the rationale and its parody have a long history. In 1918, Thorstein

Veblen in particular had railed against ‘the conduct of universities by business men’, and had

described their behaviour in terms usually reserved for moral delinquents.6 Veblen was

grappling in his idiosyncratic way with the consequences of the new industrialism that was

remaking the American economic and commercial landscape, and was despairing of what he

perceived.7 For Veblen, businessmen were barbarians and their ‘barbarian culture’ was

pragmatic, utilitarian, worldly wise, and its learning partakes of the same complexion. The barbarian, late or early, is typically an unmitigated pragmatist; that is the spiritual trait that most profoundly marks him off from the savage on the one hand and from the civilized man on the other hand. “He turns a keen, untroubled face home to the instant need of things.”8

With Veblen, as with Bullen and Robb, the implication is that there is a logical

antithesis between practical, utilitarian, concerns, and aesthetic, civilized, concerns. Money,

along with its acquisition and distribution, is of the former type (except for salary of course—

that is more complex). In 1988, when in Australia, Bernd Hüppauf, then Professor of German

at New York University, commented bitterly on the ‘vulgar economism’ used by the

4 Simon Robb and Elizabeth Bullen, “A Provocation”, in Innovation & Tradition: The Arts, Humanities and the Knowledge Economy, eds. Jane Kenway, Elizabeth Bullen and Simon Robb (New York: Peter Lang Publishing, 2004), 1–9. 5 Simon Cooper, “Introduction” in Simon Cooper, John Hinkson, Geoff Sharp, Scholars and Entrepreneurs: The Universities in Crisis (Fitzroy: Arena Publications, 2002), 3. 6 The ‘moral delinquents’ phrase is A. H. Halsey’s. See A. H. Halsey, Decline of Donnish Dominion: The British Academic Profession in the Twentieth Century (: Clarendon Press, 1992), 40. 7 Louis M. Hacker, “Introduction”, in Thorsten Veblen, The Higher Learning in America: A Memorandum on the Conduct of Universities by Business Men (New York: Sagamore Press, 1957), viii. 8 Thorsten Veblen, The Higher Learning in America: A Memorandum on the Conduct of Universities by Business Men, 25.

18 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

Australian Government to justify the restructuring of the Australian universities. Hüppauf

complained that simply because of the ‘disturbing structural deficiencies’ the Australian

economy was suffering, the Government proposed to make the universities ‘instrumental in

the process of economic therapy’. ‘Vice-chancellors’, he declared, ‘not only appear to accept

such a crude approach to their institutions but are prepared to act as the Minister’s [John

Dawkins] auxiliary calculators’.9 In 2005, James Simpson, the expatriate Australian

medievalist on a visit to Australia from Harvard University, observed that Harvard was a

refuge from the ‘bullying, insistent governmental interference’ that confronts the humanities

in Britain and Australia. ‘The reality is’, he said,

that people go into university life for a vocation. They don’t need to be pressed and harried and calibrated and audited and pried into at every turn because they’re driven through vocational commitment to transmit a certain culture. Government has instead applied a managerial, commercial model to universities, which is a fundamental error.10

A fortunate life spoiled, unfortunately, by others.

The clear message in this civilized discourse is the inappropriateness and intellectual

crudity of mixing market philosophy with the higher intellectual aspirations and ideals of

university practice; and with the Australian situation, that the changes are the result of choice

enforced by an insensitive Government and supine administration. But behind that message

is the assumption that the arts and humanities are not getting the funding they deserve

because Governments and others are unable to recognize their true worth. Unfortunately,

missing from the discourse is identification of the mechanisms—the exchange process—by

which the barbarians, who pay, agree on the value of the ‘certain culture’ that is ‘transmitted’

to them. In the actual dynamics of the real, perhaps barbarian, but not theoretical society in

which we all live, sellers need buyers, and both need to accept the exchange conditions no

matter how unenlightened the buyer, and enlightened the seller. The academic culture is a

9 Bernd Hüppauf, “Universities and Postmodernism” in Simon Cooper, Scholars and Entrepreneurs, 11. 10 Bernard Lane, “The past fights back”, The Australian, 18 May 2005, 32.

19 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

particularly significant segment of the wider socio-cultural system, and the arts and

humanities are a fundamental part of that segment. There is no doubt that they have an

important role in the exploration and transmission of forms of cultural perception and

understanding. However, they are just a sub-set of the larger socio-cultural system—one sub-

set amongst others. They may seek to understand and influence the larger system, but they

cannot stand outside it. And they are affected no more and no less than any other segment by

macroeconomic change. They must adapt, as others must, if they are to survive. And clearly,

the implication of choice is wrong. No-one would argue that Government funds are

unlimited, or even sufficient to provide everyone with the money they claim as their just

allocation.

Further, the massive structural change that Australia in particular has been undergoing

over the last twenty-five years has been a consequence of global economic change. The very

large, adverse, changes to Australia’s terms of trade alone would have been enough to force

significant social and fiscal change. But of course, they have been just one of the many

interrelated economic, technological, and cultural factors that have caused change. In the

early 1950s Australia had just 30,000 university students in a population of just under 9

million. In 2003 that number was 930,000 in a population of 20 million.11 To imply that one

could choose to allow time-honoured assumptions and practices in universities to be

unaffected, is either mistaken or disingenuous.

None of this is to deny the essential social role of critical and creative thought. The

disastrous environmental and psychological effects of uncontrolled industrialization and

mindless consumerism are obvious; and the potentially insidious moral and social effects of

unbounded applications of technology to genetics, for example, are beginning to be sensed.

Nevertheless, it would be a mistake to assume that the logic of economic management and

business competitiveness is somehow irrelevant or destructive to the more intellectually

elevated logic which the parodists imply is the proper business of the university. The

11 University of Melbourne, Growing Esteem: Choices for the University of Melbourne. A Discussion Paper, July 2005, 6.

20 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

inescapable, if unpalatable, reality is that the university as an entity is as much a part of a

particular business sector as is, say, a telecommunications company part of another business

sector. ‘Business’ is the context which frames the university. Money is required to enable it

to function: thus budgets which relate expenditure to income must be determined, negotiated,

approved, and met. The market exchange process is at the core of the relationship between

income and expenditure, and thus the market exchange process is central to the university’s

ability to survive—as it has been since the first formation of the university in Bologna in the

late twelfth century. The university then was satisfying social, political, and commercial

needs, just as it is today. Two parties: the university as one, and either the Church, State, or

private or public patrons as the other, must reach agreement on ‘value’, however defined, and

each must agree on price, however defined. For the university, the point is to define what it is

that it is selling, what value its products provide, and what conditions of trade are acceptable.

None of these questions are easily answered. Any product is merely the vehicle for the

perceived ‘good’ that it delivers. The perceived ‘good’ is the real product. Thus it is the

perceived ‘good’ that must be identified, its value agreed, and its price determined.

Fortunately for the arts and humanities and social sciences, intelligent answers to these

questions are impossible without their critical input. Not even barbarians would claim that a

meaningful life is irrelevant, or that it can be acquired through science and commerce solely.

Nor would they be likely to deny that wisdom and understanding require deeper soil than

science and commerce alone can provide. And although they might argue that the university

cannot claim wisdom and understanding as its exclusive province, they are likely to affirm a

strong, intuitive, belief in the idea of the pursuit of ‘truth’ and the indispensability of rational

inquiry and intellectual freedom to that idea. They are likely to affirm also that the modern

university is the site most closely associated with intellectual independence and disinterested

inquiry. That is the characteristic that distinguishes the university from others in the market-

place. Intellectual independence and disinterested inquiry are the concepts that define its

business identity. The market place perceives cogitation to be the university’s specialist skill,

and a distinctive intellectual acuity to be the necessary attribute of its academic employees.

21 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

Of course the life-cycle durations of universities and companies are quite different;

years for companies, centuries or half-centuries for universities; however, both entities arise,

grow and evolve—or decline and die. Their product definitions, ‘value-propositions’, target

markets, and measures of customer satisfaction and business success are different, but certain

foundational principles apply to both. They must identify products (distasteful as that word

may be) for which only they have the distinctive capabilities to produce; they must establish

effective, acceptable exchange conditions for the products—in other words, establish an

effective business model—and they must maintain the desirability of the products as

circumstances change. The university cannot assume an intrinsic social or cultural superiority

because of the intellectual nature of its product. Nor can it claim that an academic product

such as, say, social critique, is intrinsically more valuable than an industrial product such as,

say, the mobile phone, unless certain existential assumptions regarding the nature of society,

the individual, and value, are accepted as truths. In judging value who other than the ‘citizen’

can act as the impartial third party? There is no ‘higher’ court.12

Even in terms of knowledge, the ‘intellectual’ product cannot assume superiority.

There is no absolute definition of knowledge. Discursive, logocentric, knowledge is only one

form of knowledge. The global mobile computing software network, the computing core, the

exotic materials of the mobile devices, and the skills required for their fabrication and

construction, represent very high levels of intellectual abstraction, and very advanced levels

of ‘new’ knowledge.13 In comparison, it might be argued that much social critique is simply

recycled old knowledge—recycled ‘immanent critique’—the application to contemporary

settings of early twentieth-century critical theory, and as such, not new knowledge. But such

12 Paul Ricoeur in a discussion of the ‘historian and the judge’ (in the context of the ‘great crimes’ of our era) says that in order to arbitrate the differences between the two, we need an ‘impartial but not infallible third party.’ This third party is ‘the citizen’. Hayden White comments that this is not to imply that the informed judgements of the historian or the judge are to be overridden by the ‘ordinary man in the street’, but that ‘the actions taken on the basis of such judgments always have to be assessed on the basis of their adequacy to the ideals informing the goals and aims of the community’. Hayden White, “Guilty of History? The Longue Durée of Paul Ricoeur”, History and Theory, 46, no. 2. (May, 2007): 248. 13 Barry Hill argued recently that such ‘artifactual knowledge’ is a better definition of knowledge than the orthodox one using discursive, logocentric, criteria. Barry Hill, ‘Turning Back the Linguistic Turn in the Theory of Knowledge’, Thesis Eleven, no. 89. (May, 2007), 6–22.

22 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

a comparison is pointless. All that can be argued is that the products are very different and

serve different purposes.

Nevertheless, although very different, the artifactual and the cultural are never separate.

Culture determines use and value as much as ‘plain’ instrumentalism. In this age of the

‘wired world’ and the convergence of the social with the technological, the products from

each sector, though very different, are inextricably connected. Today, any social critique

concerning social relationships and cultural values can no more ignore personal

communication technologies, such as mobile phones and the internet, than can technology

companies ignore the effect of social relationships and cultural values on usage patterns and

markets. Each is embedded in the other. The university cannot stand a pace apart from the

commodified knowledge economy.

Parody as one may the values of managerialism and the business world, one thing that

that world can’t be accused of is misunderstanding the ruthless and unforgiving nature of that

environment. Successful companies understand that self-pity is wasted energy: energy that is

needed for maintaining their competitive edge in order to survive. No-one in, for example,

the Finnish multi-national company Nokia, the world leading company in its sector and with

net sales in 2007 of AUD $84 billion,14 could reasonably assume that the company will still

exist in ten years, or five years, unless somehow they maintain their competitive edge. They

understand that unless they can convince customers that Nokia has products that are capable

of satisfying the customer’s needs or ‘wants’ better than competitors’ products, and that a

price can be agreed that represents a fair exchange, then the company will fail, quickly.

Satirizing the customer’s taste and intellectual discrimination is not a viable competitive

strategy. Nokia clearly has formidable, very powerful, competitors, and Nokia must

understand not only technology but the way cultural and social patterns of acceptance and

usage of technology operate throughout the world. That knowledge and those understandings

are key determinants of market success. And the company cannot stand still. To maintain the

14 Nokia, Form 20-F 2007, 7.

23 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

same competitive position it must continually evolve. The task is daunting. No-one but

shareholders, employees and creditors weep for failed companies.

Regardless of whether an enterprise is for profit or not for profit, it is a business; money

or its equivalent is required for its continued existence. Some-where, some-how, some-one in

either the demand chain or the supply chain pays for the expended effort. And some-where,

some-how, those that are paying need both to be satisfied that the exchange is ‘fair’ value,

however that may be judged, and to have sufficient reserves or income to make payment

possible. Coarse as it may be, the question ‘Who pays?’ remains central to any material

transaction. Regardless of theories on the ideological genesis of use-value and exchange-

value and of ideology’s constitutive role in the relationship between objects and desires (our

current understanding, in Jean Baudrillard’s view, is founded on the ‘naïve anthropology of

homo economicus, or at best homo psychoeconomicus’),15need, utility and price remain

central to real material exchange. The market axiom that something is only worth what

someone will pay, has yet to be disproven. Money does ‘talk’ in most people’s lives even if it

has a rather ambiguous place in critical theory. And to say that the barbarian knows the price

of everything and the value of nothing is to self-authorize one’s own values as normative.

There are no transcendental truths regarding how value should be perceived. As Richard

Rorty has observed, ‘diagnoses of illusion or confusion are just polemical ways of describing

your opponent’s distinctions, or their failure to make your distinctions. But distinctions are as

much up for grabs as anything else. There are no quick fixes.’16 James Simpson’s freedom

at Harvard is due as much to the fact of that university’s AUD $35 billion endowment fund,

its annual fundraising of AUD $725 million, and its operating income of AUD $3.7 billion, as

to an enlightened administration.17 Both are needed. The colour of barbarian money is not

15 Jean Baudrillard, in Jean Baudrillard: Selected Writings, ed. Mark Poster (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998), 47. 16 Richard Rorty, “Holism, Intrinsicality, Transcendence”, in Dennett and His Critics: Demystifying Mind, ed. Bo Dahlbom (Cambridge M.A.: Blackwell Publishers, 1993, 192. 17 Endowment fund as at December 2006; https://post.harvard.edu/mhr/vp/index.html, [3 May 2007]. Fundraising for 2006; http://www.cae.org/content/pdf/VSE.2006.Press.Release.pdf, [3 May 2007]. Operating income year ending November 2006; https://post.harvard.edu/mhr/balancesheets/net_assets.html, [7 May 2007].

24 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

without a certain charm.

II

The very language and metaphor of competition and survival used in argument such as this

may seem to prove the point of the satirists: that there is something primary and primitive

about the focus and pre-occupations of the business world, and it has missed the larger

intellectual point. In their final thrust, Bullen and Robb use exactly this narrow, primitive,

language to emphasize the vacuousness of that world-view. ‘Aesthetic knowledge and the

aesthetic personality need to bend to the “whole-person” imperatives of the globalized

knowledge economy. If they do not, they will be wiped away’, they taunt.18 Perhaps only

those with non-aesthetic knowledge and non-aesthetic personalities are dispensable.

Unfortunately, since aesthetic personalities produce neither food, clothing, shelter nor any

other kind of physical sustenance or protection, then, unless they wish to die, they need the

non-aesthetic personalities to carry on with their non-aesthetic activity. Even the money the

aesthetes need to enable them to transmit a certain culture can only come, ultimately, from the

non-aesthetic drudges. Those in the academy cannot exist in a closed aesthetic loop.

Perhaps—with apologies to E. P Thompson—those whom Bullen and Robb speak for should

see that it may be time to rescue the poor businessman, the marketer, the manager, and even

the deluded followers of the economic rationalists, from the enormous condescension of

intellectual contemporaneity. They have strategies for survival—can the parodists say the

same?

But it would be a profound error also to assume that there is a simple opposition, and

choice to be made, between the values of the marketplace and the values of the arts and

humanities community. Both are needed. Corporate survival skills are valuable, and

business thinking precludes neither subtlety nor abstraction. Conversely, no-one lives simply

to work. Business is only ever a means to some other more meaningful end and the arts and

humanities seem, from past experience, to be fundamental in some way to that end.

18 Simon Robb and Elizabeth Bullen, “A Provocation”, 7.

25 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

Similarly, it is as fatuous to say that the arts and humanities academic does not understand the

heat of competition as it is to say that the businessman does not understand the ‘life of mind’.

Clearly, just as there is complexity and subtlety in business theory and practice, so there is

relentless, unforgiving, competition in academic practice and placement. The standard

oppositions between culture and utility, intrinsic value and instrumentalism, ‘real world’ and

‘ivory tower’, are at best unhelpful and at worst destructive. The dyads are complementary,

not oppositional. Their relationships are complex, but are symbiotic, not antithetic. To see

them otherwise is a mistake, as Ian Hunter and Geoff Stokes have concluded. They note that

in the ‘ordinary practical and theoretical reflections of the humanities’, there is a ‘remarkable

blindspot’. ‘At the edge of its field of vision, precisely at the point where it is attached to the

social body, the insight of the humanities academy fails.’ The relationship is not a battle

between warring parties, they argue, but ‘a history of contingent and unpredictable

interactions.’19 But even that is to perpetuate a view that the academy exists at a point

outside society, that the academy interacts with society as other, whereas the reality is that the

academy is just a collection of members of society who have specialized in a particular type

of work and organized themselves in a particular way to improve effectiveness. If these

contingent and unpredictable interactions are to be successfully negotiated, then the academy

must assess, as business does, the strengths, weaknesses, threats and opportunities affecting

them, and then develop the strategies required for them to survive and prosper. In particular

they must accept that change is inevitable, and must cultivate an intellectual flexibility that

enables them to respond appropriately. ‘It is not the strongest of the species that survive,’

Charles Darwin concluded, ‘not the most intelligent, but the one most responsive to

change.’20

At times of general prosperity and rising public spending on education, the blindness

Hunter and Stokes note may appear to cause few problems. When Clark Kerr (then President

19 Ian Hunter and Geoff Stokes, ‘Introduction’, in Ian Hunter, Denise Meredyth, Bruce Smith, and Geoff Stokes, Accounting for the Humanities: The Language of Culture and the Logic of Government (: Institute for Cultural policy Studies, 1991), 1, 3. 20 World Bank, Constructing Knowledge Societies, 1.

26 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

of the University of California at Berkeley) delivered his influential Godkin lectures at

Harvard University in 1963, he noted that ‘it was … a good time for the American research

university, already taking its place in world leadership.’ That period, he felt, was the

American universities’ ‘Golden Age.’21 But even in America in the 1960s there were

complaints from within the university system itself of a reflexive blindness; that graduate

academic departments had become ‘autotelic’. The critics observed that ‘to suggest that the

advancement of a particular academic discipline [was] not synonymous with the advancement

of the human condition [was] to be regarded as myopic’.22

This reflexive blindness may be incidental during a golden age, but in times of

adversity it can be ruinous. And assumptions which induce a culture of complaint can be

equally ruinous. They reduce the humanities’ energy, creativity and effectiveness just when

those qualities are most needed. The ability to negotiate change successfully is an essential

survival skill for any organism or organization. Energy wasted on complaint is better spent

on creative response to the divergent forces affecting, and threatening, the organization. An

outstanding feature of the most successful American universities has been their sensitivity

and speed of response to market forces; their disposition to respond, as Clark Kerr has noted,

to ‘the current reality and not a glamorized perception of an earlier reality’.23 Recently, the

Vice-Chancellors of eight of Australia’s leading universities, in their policy discussion paper

delivered to Government, noted:

The contemporary research university must be an adaptive institution evolving in the changing society—it cannot live outside the forces of its transformation. Its legitimacy depends not on what it has achieved in the past but on what it is becoming and how it can contribute in the future.24

21 Clark Kerr, The Uses of the University (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press, 1995), 166. 22 Christopher Jencks and David Riesman, The Academic Revolution (Chicago: The Chicago University Press, 1968), 250, quoted in Roger Geiger, “Research, Graduate Education, and the Ecology of American Universities: An Interpretive History”, in The European and American University since 1800: Historical and Sociological Essays, eds Sheldon Rothblatt and Bjõrn Wittrock (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 255. 23 Abraham Flexner, Universities: American, English, German, xii. 24 Group of Eight, Seizing the Opportunities: A Group of Eight Policy Discussion Paper, 6 June 2007 (: The Group of Eight, 2007), 14.

27 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

The arts and humanities disciplines must be clear on what business it is that they are part of

and why their specialist skills are indispensable to that larger enterprise.

University Business

Despite idealistic, philosophical, or theological, notions of the ‘idea of a university’, and even

if the concept of ‘customer value proposition’ is not used, the question of money has long

been central to the university’s operation. The idea of ‘knowledge for its own sake’ has never

existed in isolation from some notion of utility, no matter how abstract. The idea became

institutionalized in the nineteenth century German university environment, but was never

separate from realpolitik. In the University of Berlin, the idea’s value had been identified as

enabling the Prussian people (and hence the State) to achieve their ‘highest possibilities’.25

But scholarship and realpolitik at the local level were not always so elevated. When, as a

young scholar, Friedrich Wolf at the University of Göttingen told the Rector, Heyne, that he

wished to study philology, Heyne’s reaction was to ask Wolf who had been so stupid as to

give that advice. In Heyne’s view that choice was ‘the straight road to starvation’ since ‘there

were hardly six good chairs of philology in all of Germany.’26 Lord Robbins in his 1963

report on higher education in Britain (quoting from the Analects of Confucius) observed that

‘it was not easy to find a man who has studied for three years without aiming at pay’.27 The

Privatdozenten at the University of Berlin and the tutors at the Universities of Cambridge and

Oxford in the nineteenth century were very aware of the relationship between ‘customers’ and

income. Professors also. R. Steven Turner has commented that German professors,

‘especially those in the arts or philosophical faculties’, in the early nineteenth century

‘depended heavily on student fees to supplement their small government salaries’.28

25 This will be discussed in Chapter 2. 26 This was in 1777. See John Edwin Sandys, A History of Classical Scholarship: vol. 3 (New York: Hafner Publishing Company, 1967), 51–52. 27 Robbins Report, Higher Education: Report of the Committee Appointed by the Prime Minnister under the Chairmanship of Lord Robbins 1961–63 (Cmnd. 2154), 1963, 6, quoted in A. H. Halsey, Decline of Donnish Dominion, 7. 28 R. Steven Turner, “University Reformers and Professorial Scholarship in Germany 1760–

28 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

According to F. M. Powicke, in his later years liked to describe the ritual

observed at the professorial lectures in the Taylorian Institute ‘when those who attended were

still required to deposit their fee in a box on the professor’s desk’.29 Sir in his

memoir of Oxford described the appointment of fellows and the heat that generated because

of the fellows’ entitlement to stipends and portions of college income. It was ‘preposterous’,

he wrote, that ‘the celibate lay life-fellows of 1857–77 who had not taken up academic work

… should draw several hundreds a year from a college’. Professor-fellows, he complained,

were often ‘intruded by an external force’ and the excuse of ‘college finance’ was the ‘usual

hindering plea’ for postponing the creation of a chair.30 Mark Pattison lamented that ‘the

leading men of our university’ had put ‘out of sight’ all ‘the objects of science and learning

for which a university exists’ in favour of ‘consideration of the means of endowing them’.31

Recently, Sander Gilman described how ‘graduate students and younger faculty’ were asking

with some anxiety ‘(quietly and in private) about their own future, not in the world of high

theory, but in the academy in general’.32

Financial considerations were central also, of course, to potential students. In America

prior to the land-grant era, university education was an expensive undertaking. Some of the

appeal of the German universities to the American students who attended them throughout the

nineteenth century was the fact that they were cheaper. In 1889, a year of study in Germany,

including the cost of travel, was approximately one-third cheaper than a year at Johns

Hopkins, Harvard, or Cornell.33 As a consequence, German universities received a large

number of American students. In England also, a university education was expensive. Four

years residence at an Oxford college in the 1850s was very expensive. When the ‘sober

1806”, in The University in Society, vol. 2, ed. Lawrence Stone (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974), 498. 29 F. M. Powicke, “Obituary Notice Thomas Frederick Tout, 1855–1929”, Proceedings of the British Academy, vol. 15 (London: Oxford University Press, 1929), 492. 30 Sir Charles Oman, Memories of Victorian Oxford: and of some early years (London: Methuen, 1941), 193, 195. 31 Mark Pattison, Memoirs (London: Macmillan, 1885), 90. 32 Sander L. Gilman, ‘Collaboration, the Economy, and the Future of the Humanities’, Critical Inquiry, 30, no. 2. (Winter, 2004): 384. 33 Laurence Veysey, Emergence of the American University (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1965), 130.

29 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

young man of thrifty habit and sound schooling would run up bills of over £150 a year,’ the

cost was one few could afford.34 Lawrence Stone claims the cost to be ‘between £200 and

£250 a year in the early and mid-19th century’.35 By comparison, in 1850 the salary of the

Oxford Regius Professor of Modern History was £400 a year.36 Nevertheless, without

students, there would be neither discipline, nor college, nor university. When the University

of Manchester established the research doctorate after the First World War, a primary reason

was the desire to attract the American students who had gone to Germany.37

In Australia the question of utility and value and their relationship to income and

survival has always been very close to the surface. Although the modern consumer-market

jargon is not quite that which he used, William Hearn, the inaugural professor of modern

history and literature, political economy and logic, at the University of Melbourne, certainly

accepted the market framework for an understanding of the value of the academic enterprise.

In an argument that he and William Wilson, the inaugural professor of mathematics and

natural philosophy, advanced to Redmond Barry (the University Chancellor) against the

compulsory teaching of classics, they expressed the view that many parents thought that ‘a

classical education was a bad preparation for industrial life’ and that these parents ‘would not

send their sons to the university if the classics were compulsory’. Consequently, examination

of such a ‘suicidal’ decision was of great importance.38 It was a consistent view. Six years

earlier, in Galway, Hearn had argued in very modern marketing terms for the newly

established [Queen’s] College of Galway to understand what was its product, what was its

34 James Heywood, The Recommendations of the Oxford University Commissioners (London, 1853), 204, quoted in Peter R. H. Slee, Learning and a Liberal Education: the study of modern history in the universities of Oxford, Cambridge and Manchester 1800–1914 (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1986), 1. 35 Lawrence Stone, “The Size and Composition of the Oxford Student Body 1580–1909”, in The University in Society, vol. 1, ed. Lawrence Stone (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974), 43. 36 Sir Llewellyn Woodward, “The Rise of the Professorial Historian in England”, in Studies in International History: Essays Presented to W. Norton Medlicott, Stevenson Professor of International History in the , eds K. Bourne, and D. C. Watt (London: Longmans, 1967), 24. 37 H. B. Charlton, Portrait of a University 1851–1951: To Commemorate the Centenary of Manchester University (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1951), 93. 38 Hearn and Wilson, “On the Proposed Course for the Degree of Bachelor of Arts in the University of Melbourne”, Argus (Melbourne), 1855, 2, quoted in R. J. W., Selleck, The Shop: The University of Melbourne 1850–1939 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 2003), 46.

30 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

competitive position, and what was its customer value proposition. As Richard Selleck has

described, Hearn argued that a new university had to prove that it produced ‘the article which

it brings into the great market of the nation, either better than its rival [Trinity College,

Dublin], or at a cheaper rate, or both better and cheaper … [this principle was] as applicable

to education as to any other question in which the interests of the public are concerned’.

Further, he argued that Galway was freer than its competitor, Dublin, in its choice of offered

subjects. Galway, therefore, could introduce students to a wider range of knowledge through

subjects such as foreign languages, history, chemistry, natural history and English language

and literature. ‘A great truth’, Hearn said, ‘was becoming universally recognized:’

unless any business be beneficial to the public at large, and not to the projectors merely, to the consumers, if I may so speak, and not to the producers alone, it must be undeserving of support and ought to be allowed to fall.39

They are words that would make an economic rationalist beam, but not all colleagues of

Hearn’s shared his opinion. Charles Pearson was one who did not.

Pearson, the newly appointed lecturer in history, complained in a letter to Charles W.

Eliot40 that his fellow professors were ‘essentially of the practical type’ and regarded

knowledge as a ‘saleable commodity’.41 Pearson’s views on the purpose and function of the

university differed from Hearn’s; particularly, it would seem, on what was meant by the terms

‘commodity’, and ‘saleable’. However, at issue was not the principle of exchange, but

disagreement on, first, what knowledge has value, second, who decides that value, and, third,

what needs the knowledge satisfies. If one accepts the modern marketing definition of a

product as something which is capable of satisfying a human need or want,42 that this

capability is exercised through an exchange process between two parties where each party has

something that could be of value to the other, and that the terms of exchange can be agreed,

39 “Professor Hearn’s lecture”, Galway Vindicator and Connaught Advertiser, 5 December 1849, 2, quoted in Selleck, The Shop, 47. 40 In 1868, a year prior to Eliot being appointed president of Harvard University in 1869. 41 Selleck, The Shop, 143. 42 For example, Philip Kotler, Peter Fitzroy, Robin Shaw, Australian Marketing Management (: Prentice-Hall, 1980), 14.

31 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

then the question becomes one of what persons, groups, or organizations represent the

‘parties’ and how value is agreed. The term ‘saleable commodity’ is not pejorative in itself: it

depends on the nature of what is offered and what price is agreed. The issue Pearson raised is

not so much about the nature of the product, in this case a ‘knowledge’ product, but the nature

of the transaction. The process Pearson referred to was not one transaction, but two. Both

Hearn and Pearson were being paid to deliver. Their negotiation as individuals was with their

employer. When lecturing they became simply the public face of their employer. It was their

employer who had judged knowledge to be saleable and who, in turn, had come to an

agreement on price with whomever it was that gave the university money—perhaps students,

perhaps the Government, or both. Hearn and Pearson, long before their appointments in

Melbourne, had clearly decided on the saleability of knowledge when they chose an academic

vocation and accepted employment with an academic institution.

Historians would be cautious about assuming that they understood the full context in

which those words of Hearn’s, or Pearson’s, were spoken. The similarities with current

discourse are obvious, the silences are not. Nevertheless, it seems reasonable to propose that

Hearn thought of academic activity as a business and Pearson did not. Although as he,

Pearson, had demonstrated a keen sense of his own worth during the salary bargaining

process on selection, he may have been a little narrow in his definition of ‘saleable

commodity’.43 With regard to Hearn, has noted that at Galway

there was no great future for an ambitious and able man with a young family—and Melbourne offered the enormous salary of £1,000 a year, a free house, and other emoluments—in real terms an income far higher than that of any university professor today. It is no wonder that three of the first four Melbourne professors came from these Queen’s Colleges.44

Money, though coarse, has little accent or odour, and it can have a higher purpose. In the

report of the Cambridge University Commission of 1852, the salary for the Professor of Law

43 Selleck, The Shop, 142–3. 44 J. A. La Nauze, “The Frontier and Scholarship”, The W. E. Hearn Historical Lecture for 1965, University of Melbourne, 21 June, Melbourne Historical Journal, 5, 1965.

32 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

was £312, for the Regius Professor of Modern History was £421, but that of the Regius

Professor of Divinity was £1,209, and that of the endowed divinity chair: Lady Margaret’s

Chair of Divinity, was £1,854.45 Praise be given!

But there are many other considerations than money, of course. Certainly, the

assumptions on which the Hearn-Wilson argument was based were not ones which at first

glance appealed to Redmond Barry. Barry, forty-one years old, an Irishman and third son of

a Major-General, educated at Trinity College, Dublin and the senior puisne judge of the

Supreme Court of Victoria, had, at the foundation of the University, declared that the

University was ‘instituted in honour of God, for establishing young men in philosophy,

literature and piety, cultivating the talent of youth, fostering the arts, and extending the

bounds of science'.46 The value proposition proposed by Barry was, clearly, derived from

quite different criteria than those Hearn used. In Barry’s view the university’s mission was to

form the character ‘not of individuals, but of the nation’.47 The implied need was that of the

community’s, not the individual’s as such. His offer was to the community of Victoria.

Barry had firm views on the role cultural institutions should play in that mid-nineteenth

century community. The implied exchange was between an institution, with its unique

knowledge product, and the State, with its unique knowledge needs. The parties to the

negotiation would be the State and the authorised representative of the University.

Nevertheless, the indisputable fact is that Barry’s ‘value proposition’ was only an offer until

buyers could be found, and an agreement struck on what the buyers were willing to pay.

Barry was an effective salesman and negotiator and found the Government to be a very

receptive and satisfactory customer. They did much business and the community gained, in

addition to the university, an excellent public library and art gallery.

45 Cambridge University Commission Report of Her Majesty’s Commissioners into the State, Discipline, Studies and Revenues of the University and Colleges of Cambridge (London: HMSO, 1852), 71. 46 Words composed on the inscription, in Stuart Macintyre and R. J. W. Selleck, A Short History of the University of Melbourne (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 2003) 2. 47 Proceedings on the Occasion of the Inauguration of the University of Melbourne (Melbourne: Government Printer, 1855), 22, quoted in Selleck, The Shop, 44.

33 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

Less business was done with prospective students or parents of students. Sixteen

students were enrolled when the university was inaugurated. Their needs were individual, the

utility to be delivered more practical. In an editorial referring to the university’s curriculum,

The Age newspaper stated unequivocally its view of what the colony needed: ‘However

excellent and valuable classical education may be in itself, it is precisely the kind of

education which they [the colonists] do not want; since it is utterly unsuited to the place, the

time, and the character of the population’. What was needed it said was ‘emphatically and

pre-eminently, practical culture,—culture that will enable us to develop the resources, and lay

strongly and firmly the social and political foundations of the noble country which

Providence has given us’.48 Agreement on what ‘certain culture’ needed to be transmitted

still had to be reached.

II

The Age’s view was representative of one that existed not just in Australia, but America and

England as well. In England it was from a number of sources. One was the pressure exerted

on universities by the rise in importance of natural science; a pressure manifested in agitation

to broaden the curricula to include ‘modern subjects’ so that the universities were ‘more

productive and useful’. In this it was encouraged also by scientists whose desire was to

improve their professional status.49 Another source was Utilitarianism with its ethic of social

usefulness. T. W. Heyck has argued that, particularly in the 1820s and 1830s, the utilitarian

ethic had generated the desire ‘to make all institutions conform to middle-class values of

work, productivity and efficiency [and] to make the universities more useful to the main

activities of the nation—mainly to business and industry’.50

But ‘usefulness’ to business did not always mean just the sciences and ‘practical

culture’. Fifty years earlier, in Manchester, the ‘Reverend Thomas Barnes D.D.’ read a paper

48 Age (Melbourne), 3 March 1855, 4, quoted in Selleck, The Shop, 46. 49 Linked to this also was an ambition to convert universities into research establishments. 50 T. W. Heyck, The Transformation of Intellectual Life in Victorian England (London: Croon Helm, 1982), 155–6.

34 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

before the Manchester Literary and Philosophical Society on ‘A Plan for the Improvement

and Extension of Liberal Education in Manchester’ in which he was hopeful that ‘the happy

art’ might be learned ‘connecting together liberal science and commercial industry’. Dr.

Barnes explained, in sentiments more aligned with Barry’s, that

The object to be aimed at is, to give a boy in those intermediate years, to which alone our plan extends, that degree of knowledge and of taste, which makes him more than the mere man of business [italics in source] in future life.51

There had been a ‘liberal and comprehensive’ institution established in 1755 at Warrington

near Manchester (the Warrington Academy) by the English Presbyterian Protestant Dissenters

of Manchester to provide instruction in theology, moral philosophy, logic, metaphysics,

natural philosophy, languages, and ‘polite literature’.52 But it wasn’t until 1851 that a

university, Owens College, was established—and then it was a businessman that made it

possible.

Owens College was named after its benefactor, the businessman John Owens. For,

although a barbarian, Owens believed deeply that social progress was to be secured through

education.53 Owens had held ‘very strong views about the injustice of the university tests

which shut out Nonconformists from the colleges of Oxford and Cambridge’, and determined

that his college should be ‘absolutely unsectarian … without any test of creed, or

subscription’. The inscription on his gravestone records ‘his zeal for the advancement of

learning and science’. 54 The Reverend Barnes would have been pleased to observe that

Owens was not just ‘the mere man of business’; but then, few businessmen are.

In America, similarly, there had long been a utilitarian dimension to the question of

value and university education. Forty years before Dr. Barnes made his proposal, Benjamin

51 Memoirs of the Literary and Philosophical Society, ii, Second ed., 1789, 16, quoted in Joseph Thompson, The Owens College: Its Foundation and Growth and its Connection with the Victoria University, Manchester (Manchester: J. E. Cornish, 1886), 4. 52 Thompson, The Owens College, 2–3. 53 Charlton, Portrait of a University 1851–1951, ix. 54 Thompson, The Owens College, 44, 45.

35 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

Franklin expressed his desire for the College of Philadelphia, now the University of

Pennsylvania, to produce ‘a more useful culture of young minds’. He was interested in

training people for agriculture, commerce, exploring science, and wanted education to ‘serve

mankind’.55 In the decades after the Civil War, the links between higher education and

wealth strengthened, moving higher education ‘much closer to the ways of thinking shared by

the practical and the wealthy’.56 The view of prominent academic donor Ezra Cornell was

that the university was ‘a place where everything useful in high and broad sense may be

taught’.57 Charles W. Eliot, the Harvard President, ‘wished that the sharp line between an

educated and a practical man might somehow simply disappear’.58 David Starr Jordan, the

Stanford President, declared that the whole university movement ‘is toward reality and

practicality’.59 Under the Morrill Act of 1862, the federal government offered aid to states

which would support colleges that would provide instruction in ‘agriculture and the

mechanical arts ... in order to promote the liberal and practical education of the industrial

classes’.60 Although progress was gradual and uneven, this marked the starting point for state

support for higher education.61

Not only was usefulness incorporated into the ethic of higher education, but by 1918,

when Veblen was excoriating the ‘business principles’ that reduced education to a

‘commodity, to be produced on a piece-rate plan’, liberal education had become part of,

rather than an alternative to, the industrialization he so abhorred. The department store

magnate Edward Filene in 1919 concluded that liberal education was needed to enable a more

55 Benjamin Franklin, Proposals Relating to the Education of Youth in Pensilvania (sic) (Philadelphia, 1749), quoted in Clark Kerr, The Uses of the University, 9. 56 Veysey, The Emergence of the American University, 3. 57 C. M. Woodward, ‘The Change of Front in Education’, Science, XIV (1901), 476, quoted in Laurence Veysey, The Emergence of the American University, 71. 58 C. W. Eliot, Educational Reform (New York, 1898), 224, quoted in Veysey, The Emergence of the American University, 71. 59 D. S. Jordan, The Voice of the Scholar (San Francisco, 1903), 46, quoted in Veysey, The Emergence of the American University, 61. 60 Marty Wechselblatt, “The End(s) of the University in the Information Society”, Antipodes, December 2002, 16, no. 2: 186. 61 Veysey, The Emergence of the American University, 15. Nevertheless, there were earlier educational foundations that had a religious purpose but were supported by the state, for example, Harvard.

36 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

efficient industrialized society. ‘Mass production’ he said, ‘requires the education of the

masses; the masses must learn to behave like human beings in a mass production world ...

They must achieve, not mere literacy, but culture’.62 Filene may have spoken in the language

and with the intent of the early twentieth-century arch-capitalist, but the end-result he desired

was identical to that of the late eighteenth-century theologian and humanist, Dr. Barnes.

Thus the idea of the commodification of knowledge, of culture as a ‘product’, and the

primacy of the criterion of utility, disdained by Bullen, Robb, and others, have a long

pedigree. As has the idea of a ‘knowledge industry’. In 1892 Thomas Huxley expressed the

view that ‘The medieval university looked backwards; it professed to be a storehouse of old

knowledge … The modern university looks forward, and is a factory of new knowledge’.63

Consequently, the issue is not so much about the commodification of knowledge—which,

like , is with us through social evolution not barbarian fiat—but rather the role of

the university in the production of ‘useful’ knowledge, and role of the arts and humanities in

enabling the university to perform that role. Unarguably, the arts and humanities have an

indispensable role in helping to find agreement on what ‘useful’ means. And even the most

keenly instrumental businessman would acknowledge the connection between the arts and

creativity, and thus design and innovation. But the fact that the arts and humanities feel

marginalized in those discussions indicates a conceptual disjunction between market and

academy.

For some in the humanities academic community, the current market framework in

which knowledge is now produced and circulated may seem distasteful or inimical to the

perception of an earlier, more desirable, reality. But this is the current reality. If—to use the

language of this cruder reality—the humanities as an entity is to survive, then the real issue is

how to adapt and refine the mechanisms by which their research-derived abstract products

engage with the market processes of the ever-changing post-modern society.

62 Wechselblatt, “The End(s) of the University in the Information Society”, 185. 63 Letter from T. H. Huxley to E. Ray Lankester, 11 April 1892, quoted in Kerr, The Uses of the University, 158.

37 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

In order to maintain relevance and agency in a continually changing world, the products

must continually change. This is a business task, and business has developed modes of

analysis and principles and techniques to help them to adapt successfully. The barbarians

may lack a certain culture, but they don’t lack a certain alertness and an ability to learn

quickly from experience. Indisputably, the lessons learned and management knowledge

accumulated by them over more than one hundred years of professional management activity

have more than a certain value.

The Business of the University

In 1960, the Harvard Business Review published an article titled ‘Marketing Myopia’ by

Theodore Levitt. The article—which Levitt later defended as ‘a manifesto, not a

prescription’—became one of those seminal business articles published by that journal which

was the catalyst for industry-wide conceptual change. Most business graduates and

executives would have known its theme even if they had not read it. In it, Levitt argued that

failures of various industry sectors and individual businesses were the result of management

not identifying or understanding “what business they were in”. His argument was that market

definitions of a business or industry are superior to product or technological definitions

because products and technologies are transient while basic market needs—underlying social

needs—are, relatively, unchanging. For example, Levitt argued that the ‘railroad’ companies

should define themselves as being in the transportation business, and oil refiners as being in

the energy business—they had to ‘think of [themselves] as taking care of customer’s needs …

management must think of itself not as producing products but as providing customer-creating

value satisfactions’.64 He made the point that there is no guarantee against product

obsolescence, that if a company’s own research did not make a product obsolete, then

another’s would. One example that he used—the ‘buggy whip manufacturers’—became

64 Theodore Levitt, “Marketing Myopia”, Harvard Business Review, 38, no. 4 (July–August 1960): 36, 38.

38 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

famous. Throughout business schools and working groups, managers tried to identify the

business that would have enabled a buggy whip manufacturer to be independent of the fate of

its, then, major customer group. Perhaps ‘flagellation’ suggested one writer irritated by the

increasingly unrealistic suggestions being offered in the business literature. ‘Buggy whip

manufacturer’ became a key signifier in management discourse, acting as both warning and

catalyst. It is a function it still performs.

The article had an immediate impact on business thinking. Companies rushed to

redefine themselves and the ‘business’ they were really in. It stimulated, for example,

according to marketing folklore, a new managing director of Parker Pens to identify that the

company’s greatest competitor was not the Shaeffer pen company as had been assumed, nor

was it any other product whose purpose was writing or communication, such as the

telephone—it was the Ronson cigarette lighter. The reason was that analysis of sales data

showed that the majority of purchases were made by individuals buying the pens as gifts for

other people. When considering what to buy, often an alternative was a quality cigarette

lighter. Thus the company assessed itself to be in the ‘quality gift market’ which,

consequently, had widespread implications for product development, packaging, advertising,

distribution and pricing.65

As Levitt’s premise was the inadequacy of management vision, the purpose of his

article was to broaden the vision of managers. In that objective he undoubtedly succeeded,

however, in some ways he was too successful. His article encouraged managers to believe

that a simple redefinition of themselves would ensure success, whereas the reality was that

redefinition alone was disastrous. The questions: ‘What is our business?’ and ‘What should it

be?’ are among the most difficult questions a company, or any organization, will ever have to

answer. There is no single correct answer to the question of whether a company should build

on existing capabilities or develop new ones; stay in existing markets or find new ones.

65 Attributed to Graham Kenwright, Birmingham Chamber of Commerce, in Graham Hooley, John Saunders, Nigel Piercy, Marketing Strategy and Competitive Positioning (Harlow: Pearson Education Limited, 2004), 36.

39 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

Many companies never achieve agreement on those questions, for the simple reason that

organizations and their environments are never stable, their interactions and reactions

unpredictable, the variables almost unlimited. There are always a number of potentially

successful strategies, and many potentially disastrous ones, however, the underlying theme of

successful ones seems to be that of building on strengths while mitigating weaknesses.

Most market-based definitions—‘business’ definitions in Levitt’s terminology—are too

broad to provide real direction. Very little in the world is not related to energy, health,

entertainment, transportation, or knowledge, for example; and very few companies have

strategic capabilities that are as varied and adaptable as required to allow them to move much

distance from their assigned market location. The market, intrinsically, is no more important

than a product or a competence.66 Distinctive competencies are critical to success. Had

Parker Pens determined that it was their core competency in ink technology which best

assured their future, they might have become the dominant supplier of ink cartridges to the

office equipment industry. Today, a strategy which identifies the cigarette lighter as a key

competitor might seem a poor one. Similarly, a few words on paper and unanimous

agreement by an executive board do not mean that a railways company can operate an airline

effectively, or that an oil refiner can make fuel cells competitively. For every company that

profited from this heightened sensitivity to customers and consumers, there were others for

whom it was a disaster—a consequence which Levitt acknowledged in his retrospective

commentary published fifteen years later.67

The underlying problem with the manifesto was that when taken as a prescription, as it

was by many companies, it was too simplistic and reductive. It encouraged rupture with the

past and the introduction of new business paradigms. However, experience showed that

effective management of change required adaptation rather than rupture. There is always

present continuity with change, even during the most violent re-adjustments—in institutions

66 But, nevertheless, no less important, they are all important and interdependent—three legs of a three-legged stool. 67 Theodore Levitt, “Marketing Myopia—Retrospective Commentary”, Harvard Business Review, 53, no. 5 (September–October 1975): 177–81.

40 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

as old as universities, most markedly so. Form may change, but function, linked as it is to

competence, is more constant. What companies need to do most is to be environmentally

sensitive, organizationally adaptive, but critically aware of their intrinsic distinctive

competence. They need to identify what the ‘real’ competence is that sustains the business,

and focus their research effort in that direction, at the same time recognizing that an effective

business model is essential if competence is ultimately to translate to profit.

Although Levitt’s article had flaws, which Levitt acknowledged in his retrospective

commentary, there were important generalizations that could be made.68 To survive—let

alone be successful—an organization needed to balance an internal focus with an external

focus. Thus it had to balance an internal focus on ‘materials and methods’ with an ‘external

orientation towards uses, users, and markets-balancing’. Strategically this meant that

companies needed to ask themselves ‘whether they wished to be masters of certain

technologies, for which they would seek markets, or be masters of markets for which they

would seek customer-satisfying products and services’. For complex products (as are the

university’s) the former strategy tended to be the most appropriate, for simpler products, the

latter, generally, would be more appropriate. However, whatever option chosen, one thing

was central: continual development of products and capability was necessary. That was the

one underlying theme in Levitt’s original argument which remained unchanged in his review,

and he reiterated its critical importance. Industries and products are dynamic—yesterday’s

growth industry is today’s obsolescent one. The product which yesterday appeared as the

‘runaway substitute’ for an earlier product, is today itself replaced.

It was one observation that was never challenged. To survive, a company must ensure

that its products maintained their competitive advantage by continually evolving. Thus, the

company’s intellectual property—the specialist knowledge which drives product

innovation—was dynamic, it must continually ‘advance’. Yesterday’s specialist knowledge

becomes today’s general knowledge. Today’s specialist knowledge, as specialist knowledge,

68 Levitt, “Retrospective Commentary”, 177–81.

41 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

is always knowledge at the ‘leading edge’. By always ‘advancing’ it continues to be new

knowledge—thus always specialist knowledge which, by definition, no-one else has. But it is

only through research that specialist knowledge can ‘advance’. Only through research can

specialist knowledge remain new knowledge (or new practice) derived from, but extending,

previous knowledge. Consequently, knowledge concerned with human understanding—arts

and humanities knowledge—to be specialist knowledge must always be knowledge at the

limits of current understanding. The research from which it derives, explores meaning. It is

knowledge of knowledge. Scientific understanding, on the other hand, is concerned with

explanation, not meaning, as Dilthey first emphasized and others elaborated. Science’s

research is at the edge of human understanding of causality, not meaning.69

For organizations whose technologies were complex (the university’s ‘technologies’—

critical and experimental techniques—are complex), Levitt’s observation was simply

reiterating a fact well known to them. The market ‘food chain’ is dynamic, not static. The

maintenance of one’s position in that food chain requires continual advance. In effect, one

has to keep climbing the food chain in order, even, to stand still. The company that yesterday

made system components, today either integrates systems or makes more advanced

components. The components which once only it possessed the knowledge to manufacture,

are today being manufactured by less advanced companies. Without substantial, well

directed research a company cannot hope even to survive, let alone prosper. For companies

hoping to lead, leading research is required.

In 2005 Nokia employed 20,882 people in research and development activity—36% of

their total workforce—and their research and development expenditure was around AUD

$6.27 billion.70 In 2007, 30,415 employees were engaged in research and development

activity (representing 27% of the workforce); expenditure was around AUD $9.26 billion and

included increased collaboration with third parties such as the .71

69 The split between Naturwissenschaften and Geisteswissenschaften is a theme which will be discussed in later chapters. 70 Nokia, Review by the Board of Directors and Nokia Annual Accounts 2005, 3. 71 Using exchange rate EUR:AUD of 0.61. Nokia, Form 20-F 2007 (Annual Report), 87, 39.

42 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

The company’s business focus is now not only ‘mobile devices’, but multimedia and

enterprise solutions. Nokia understands the link between research, development and survival.

It understands that unless it keeps ‘climbing the food chain’, it will be eaten. In 2008 a new

business group, Entertainment and Communities, was formed to move the company ‘up’ into

the social networking field to which the video, game, and photo sharing capabilities of the

new mobile phone technology could be applied. Entertainment and communities were the

new strategic focus. The newly appointed head of the group commented: ‘Change is painful

but you have to figure this out in order to be successful … the question is, are you willing to

play by the new rules?’72

II

The question that arises is how usable, really, are views such as these for a university or an

academic discipline? Can any business philosophy—a style of reasoning that is so

historically, culturally, and ideologically formed—be useful in the management of intellectual

inquiry, in all its many forms, and with all its many epistemological and ontological

implications? Does not that require a more intellectually complex and more conceptually

open framework? After all, intellectual inquiry actually influences or changes the way value

judgements are made, and how social reality is perceived.73 Epistemologically it is prior to

historically and culturally located business paradigms. Perhaps. But while those may be

valid observations, they are wrong if they mix the act of intellectual inquiry with its

organization. The organization of higher education, and the role of the universities in that

sector, is currently a concern of governments globally; widespread change and increased

competition for funding is a common current feature of the higher education sector. These are

predominantly business considerations, even if their rationale is unsubstantiated

epistemologically and ontologically. Change remains an actuality. There is little doubt that

72 Laura Holson, “A future that’s music to mobile ears”, New York Times, reprinted Age (Melbourne) 24 June 2008. 73 Which includes not just what ‘business’ and ‘exchange’ means, but what they mean within the notion of a particular society; in other words the history, anthropology, and sociology of and exchange.

43 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

in the last half of the twentieth century there has been a trend for universities (certainly, those

in Britain and Australia) to change from institutions which (in the nineteenth and the first half

of the twentieth century) were elitist, collegial, and cloistered, to ones which are, increasingly,

open, managed, and ‘virtual’. For the university, change needs to be conceptualized no less in

business terms than critical terms if the university wishes to continue to function as an

organization.

There is, however, an important distinction to be made between outer form and inner

essence. While the form of the university may change, and access to the institution and its

products may change, its essence remains unchanged, namely, the advancement, creation, and

dissemination of knowledge. Research, scholarship, teaching, and learning are purely the

functions that manifest that essence. But it is research that enables knowledge to advance.

Scholarship cannot achieve that. Scholarship’s function is to elaborate and fashion the

research outputs. If learning is not to be simply indoctrination, then it must be through

teaching which relies on scholarship based on awareness of the latest research and on open

thinking within a subject; otherwise it is just scholarship based on antiquarianism , custom, or

‘revealed’ truth. The latest research on which scholarship is based should have derived from

an open, multifaceted intellectual environment. The distinctive competence of the academy is

its ability to facilitate ‘pure’ inquiry conducted within a broad, truly multidisciplinary, open-

ended, intellectual environment. Research institutions and research centres are always

intellectual subsets—their fields of operation are purposely limited.

It is no coincidence that leading universities produce leading research. The research

institutions produce leading research also. They, however, are not, nor are they designed to

be, universities (in the nineteenth and early twentieth-century sense). Paradoxically, because

of current economic-rationalist logic which demands of institutions a focus on ‘ends’, the

university—as its idea—is the only site where the pursuit of ‘whole’ knowledge is possible.

The paradox for the university is that its most valuable competitive tool in the instrumentalist

world is its ability and freedom to pursue knowledge for its own sake. Other sites, by the fact

44 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

of deliberately differentiating themselves as non-universities, pursue more directed, applied

ends.

If the pursuit of new knowledge is at the core of ‘knowledge economy’, then the fact

that specialist knowledge can, logically, only be partial knowledge, means that a multi-

disciplinary, integrative environment is necessary for the effective pursuit of more complete

knowledge. The research university is the institution which is best able to satisfy that

requirement. And, certainly, if it is accepted that the quest is the pursuit of more complete

knowledge, then Geisteswissenschaften knowledge must be central to that quest; thus, the arts

and humanities must be central to that quest. Further, since knowledge that does not contain

Geisteswissenschaften knowledge is fundamentally limited, it could be argued that research

that excludes Geisteswissenschaften knowledge is not true basic research, despite the fact

that, under current international classification, the term ‘basic research’ refers to any

disciplinary ‘pure’, non-strategic, non-applied, research. Perhaps such sectoral research

should be considered more as strategic basic research than basic research since it is limited,

channeled, inquiry. Basic research, in its purest sense, is at the leading edge of

epistemological and ontological understanding, not simply at the leading edge of bounded

disciplinary understanding. Basic research is what universities should be able to do better

than anyone else.

In the cruder world of business competition, the best strategy for survival is to be one

of the best in one’s field. For the true university, knowledge as knowledge is its natural field,

thus true basic research is the means by which it advances in that field. The business

philosophy discussed, however, is not seeking to manage the matter of intellectual inquiry. It

is merely seeking to ensure that an organization: first, identifies the domain in which its

distinctive competence lies; second, establishes proper structures and processes to allow that

competence to be developed continually in ways that continually result in products that are

desired by external agents; and third, that it has a business model that enables total product

income to exceed total product cost. How a university and the disciplines within it satisfy

45 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

those requirements is the university’s and the discipline’s prerogative. It is also their

responsibility.

The original question, however, (the usefulness of business theory) is spurious. Neither

the university nor its disciplines are claiming to stand outside their own historical, cultural,

and ideological moment. Their disquiet arose through the question of their funding and

relevance in our current market-based, post-industrial, capitalist society. Even in the

the autumn of the ‘Golden Age’ of which Clark Kerr spoke—there was recognition of the

reality that universities cannot stand apart. Lawrence Stone, writing from Princeton,

commented that

The university like the family and the church, is one of the most poorly integrated of institutions … And yet, in the long run, no institution can survive in glorious isolation, and the interaction between the university’s own built-in and the pressures on it to adapt to new external conditions is one of the most potentially illuminating, but most practically obscure, aspects of historical change.74

Charles Rosenberg also, writing around that time, commented that ‘the marketplace’ is never

removed entirely from the reality of even the most esoteric disciplines’.75 Whether as the

object of disciplinary critique, or as the context which frames the disciplines’ relevance, the

marketplace is ubiquitous.

At the beginning of the twenty-first century, it is widely recognized that the view from

the window of the twenty-first century university, particularly in Australia and Britain, is

much less serene than that from Princeton in the 1970s. The eight Australian vice-chancellors

quoted earlier were very aware that each institution had to look forward, not back; that the

legitimacy of each depended on ‘what it is becoming and how it can contribute in the future’.

Baroness Warwick, the chief executive officer of Universities UK, in a recent address

74 Lawrence Stone, ed., The University in Society, vol. 1 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974), v. 75 Charles Rosenberg, “An Ecology of Knowledge”, in The Organization of Knowledge in Modern America, 1860–1920, eds Alexandra Oleson and John Voss (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1979), 452n.

46 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

observed:

We have seen universities evolve from a focus on the classical, highly structured curriculum to fluid institutions where many kinds of knowledge—liberal and professional, general and specialised, religious and secular, theoretical and practical—vie for space. Universities may have very different missions: local versus national, teaching versus research, open access versus elite, vocational and professional versus liberal arts, distance learning versus campus organised; and there are surely more … There are many dimensions to diversity in a modern university. Yet increasing diversity of funding may represent the future for most universities … It would be surprising if universities did not evolve into many different forms.76

The British Government also, in its White Paper on the future of higher education, was clear

that it expected diversity of mission. ‘Individual institutions [must] focus on what they do

best’, it stated. Diversity (within the sector), the Government reasoned, would reduce

competition within the sector and encourage collaboration among those with ‘complementary

missions’. ‘In research’, it said, ‘this will help us preserve the best pockets of isolated

research while concentrating funding on the very best’.77 Similarly, in 2005 the Australian

Government, in an investigation of the approval and accreditation processes for Australian

higher education, spoke of the ‘need for a diverse range of higher education institutions

servicing different communities and varied requirements.’ It commented that this ‘will not be

achieved through the “one size fits all” model … it is worth debating the requirement for all

universities to undertake research as well as teaching’. And it asked: ‘Should universities be

determined more by function and quality and less by form and structure?’78

In other words, for the British and Australian Governments, universities must work

76 Baroness Warwick, “Introductory Paper”, delivered at ‘The Future of Higher Education: dilemmas and opportunities’ conference, Cumberland Lodge, Windsor 28 July–3 August 2003, http://www.21stcenturytrust.org/warwick.html, [3/6/08]. 77 Department for Education and Skills, The Future of Higher Education (London: The Stationery Office Limited, 2003), 20–21. 78 Department of Education, Science and Training, Building University Diversity: Future Approval and Accreditation Processes for Australian Higher Education (Canberra: Australian Government, 2005), i. The current government intends negotiating research ‘missions’ with each university.

47 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

within a business paradigm; they must identify what they do best, and how they will do it, if

they wish to survive. Clearly, then, business philosophy and technique can help substantially

to illuminate the ‘practical obscurities’ Professor Stone identified concerning that adaptation

to the marketplace identified as necessary by the British and Australian Governments.

There are, of course, several critical differences between the business organization

whose purpose is the financial remuneration of a relatively small number of shareholders, and

the university whose purpose is altruistic and idealistic service to society. Both are concerned

with the creation and transfer of certain types of knowledge to the wider community, but for

one the ultimate purpose of that knowledge transfer is a better financial return on invested

capital than can be obtained elsewhere, for the other the ultimate purpose is social enrichment

and transformation through the expansion of understanding. One is concerned with saleable

products whose creation requires advancing knowledge, the other is concerned with new

information whose understanding requires advancing knowledge—new knowledge of

previously new knowledge. One, the for-profit company, works at the edge of applied

knowledge and innovation, the other, the university, works at the edge of knowledge itself –

the edge of epistemic and ontological understanding. The question for the university is how

best to organize that inquiry, how best to transfer that understanding, and how best to secure

sufficient funding to enable leading research at the leading edge of understanding.

The differences in core product of the two types of organization (both have many other

products)—one core product being at one end of the research–development–production–sales

chain, the other at the other end—mean that there are also critical differences in competitive

strategy. For the for-profit company, research is irrelevant unless it finally results in a

developed, manufactured, packaged, product that the market wants. For any university, the

end products are irrelevant, no matter how popular, unless they reflect, however far removed,

original basic research. However, as with for-profit companies, and as urged by the British

Government, universities should pick a niche or range where they believe they can excel. In

the British and Australian Governments’ view, a university may decide to concentrate on

48 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

teaching and leave basic research to other institutions. However, from the perspective of

competitive strategy, that is a strategy which is second-best. The best strategy for those with

complex products with relatively low volume and high costs, is to move to the market

position that affords the highest barriers to entry for competitors (thus allowing higher

product prices to be charged); then, through continual product development, to maintain that

position.

Regardless of the urging of Governments, though, and despite the particular niche that

best fits the competence of an individual university, one market ‘reality’ remains

incontrovertible: the higher the skill requirement, the higher the barriers to entry, the better

the competitive position, the better the chance of survival. Notwithstanding the symbiosis

that exists between research, development, and application, the quality and breadth of pure-

basic-research capability is the distinctive competence which best defines a university’s

competitive strength and best reflects its market position. ‘Top tier’ means top basic

research. For a university to be classified ‘top tier’ in any global ranking, the university must

possess broad, high quality, ‘top tier’ basic research competence. For the research university,

basic research is the strategic product—it is its ‘killer’ product.

The widely discussed argument, therefore, advanced by a team of distinguished

scholars, that the site of knowledge production is changing from academic institutions to

other sites outside the academy, is wrong in its implication that the site of new knowledge—

in the true basic research sense—is changing.79 It is not. The site for the refashioning and

transforming of knowledge may be changing, but not that of the discovery or creation of

epistemologically and ontologically new knowledge. In their book The New Production of

Knowledge, the scholars argue that there has been, and is continuing, a dramatic and

irreversible shift in the mode of knowledge production from ‘Mode 1’ knowledge—academic

knowledge—to ‘Mode 2’ knowledge, which they define as transdisciplinary knowledge

79 Michael Gibbons, Camille Limoges, Helga Nowotny, Simon Schwartzman, Peter Scott, Martin Trow, The New Production of Knowledge: The Dynamics of Science and Research in Contemporary Societies (London: Sage Publications, 1994).

49 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

generated outside academic institutions and carried out in a context of practical application.

Among the reasons they give is that ‘the creation of many new sites is an unintended result of

the process of massification of education and research’.80 Thus, they argue, the dramatic

expansion of the number of research-qualified graduates unable to secure employment within

the academy has meant that industry and other institutions and organizations have acquired

those graduates and their research skills. There is no doubt also that a consequence of the rise

of the ‘knowledge society’ is that the broader society is able to access and manipulate

knowledge, not just the educated élites. But while there is little doubt that the ‘massification’

of education and the consequent rising intellectualization of the community, has enabled the

transformation and application of knowledge to be performed outside the university, any

knowledge produced outside the idea of the university can only be contracted research or

scholarship defined within the specific social and economic contexts identified by Gibbons,

Limoges, Nowotny, Schwartzman, Scott, and Trow. Thus, it cannot be true basic research;

consequently, it cannot be true new knowledge. That knowledge can only be produced within

the milieu of the university idea. The process of multi-disciplinary, disinterested, undirected,

peer reviewed and refereed, research cannot exist effectively within a contracted, for-profit

paradigm. New knowledge can only be Mode 1 knowledge.

The organization which is the site of production of Mode 1 knowledge need not,

however, have the name ‘university’; it can be any organization whose functional rationale is

the idea of the university. In practice, there are many organizations that call themselves

‘university’ but operate outside that idea. Conversely, it is difficult, if not impossible, to

identify an organization that operates (to the implied breadth and quality) within that idea,

that is not identified either formally or in the public mind as a ‘university.’ In that regard,

even the term ‘university’ in the sense of the idea has a distinct cultural meaning which no

fiddling with names can erase. Joseph Hermanowicz found, in his study of American higher

education institutions, that by using structural characteristics only—staff size, degree level,

scores, and so on—to differentiate universities, the very significant cultural differences (and

80 Ibid., 10.

50 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

similarities) which existed between universities, were elided. The differences ‘shaped’

academic performance and careers. Hermanowicz remarked that ‘conceptions of career

success or failure are socially generated and made meaningful only as a result of collective

understandings’; and that this collective understanding was based on a particular university’s

position on a spectrum represented by ‘elite’ (“to be among the best”, research intensive),

‘pluralist’ (mixed motivation and aspiration) and ‘communitarian’ (“good [university]

citizenship”) groupings.81 The level and quality of research had a clear cultural influence on

the institution, and affected its ability to attract the best researchers. Membership of an elite

group conferred prestige to the individual but imposed high intellectual performance

obligations. In terms of business strategy, ‘elite’ signifies the highest barriers to entry in the

whole-knowledge field.

The requirement for basic research to have breadth as well as depth if genuine

epistemological and ontological advances in knowledge are to be made, is incontrovertible.

Scientific research alone is insufficient; a wider frame is needed. In 2001, three of the

authors of The New Production of Knowledge produced a new work which had a definite shift

in tone from the first book. The narrow, Naturwissenschaften, notion of knowledge which

they used earlier had been shown, when interrogated, to be the limited knowledge it clearly is.

The authors had seen only the ‘scientization’ of society and had been blind to the

socialization of science. But the context had refused to be silent. Consequently, in their new

book, Re-Thinking Science: Knowledge and the Public in an Age of Uncertainty, the authors

addressed the larger context: the contextualization of science. They observed that the

tendency in the ‘knowledge society’ to ‘maintain a “line”’ between science and society

missed the most important aspects of society and culture, which were that society needed

‘socially robust knowledge’.82 The authors were acknowledging what most needed to be

acknowledged (though not using these terms): that knowledge that lacks

81 Joseph C. Hermanowicz, “Classifying Universities and Their Departments: A Social World Perspective”, Journal of Higher Education, 76, no. 1, 2005, 42–43, 53. 82 Helga Nowotny, Peter Scott, Michael Gibbons, Re-Thinking Science: Knowledge and the Public in an Age of Uncertainty (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2001), vii, 94–95, 166–178.

51 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

Geisteswissenschaften input is partial knowledge at best.

But if the focus on modes of knowledge and sites of production failed to distinguish

between types of research, it also occluded the fundamentally different aspect of true basic

research when compared with other types of research and development. Just as scholarship

transforms and refashions research, so applied research transforms and refashions basic

research. Basic research being research whose field is unbounded, whole knowledge, and

which works at the edge of human understanding, can only be undertaken within the

university idea. Other research can be conducted elsewhere, drawing on basic research as

required, but the ‘newest’ new knowledge can only be produced within the university as

institutionalized idea—in either real or ‘virtual’ form. In ‘virtual’ form, the university as

intellectual site may have no geographic centre to its intellectual heart (though there will be

one for its administrative arm), which reinforces the point that the university is an idea.

‘Outside’ the university can only mean outside the idea.

Steve Fuller went some way towards stimulating awareness of this reality in the

introduction to Merle Jacob and Tomas Hellström’s book: The Future of Knowledge

Production in the Academy, but only indirectly. Fuller started by drawing attention to ‘the

most pernicious feature of the ‘Myth of the Modes’’ which was that ‘the two modes are seen

not just as mutually exclusive, but also jointly exhaustive—that is, not admitting of other

possibilities’. In particular, ‘the idea of the university as an autonomous site for knowledge

production that constitutes a whole that is greater than the sum of its disciplinary parts’. Thus

he was reaching towards the notion of the advance of more complete, integrated knowledge,

but for Fuller, the value of this was its critical and pedagogic utility, not its epistemic and

ontological validity. The ‘common curriculum’, the ‘foundation of liberal education’, he

said, provides ‘a basis for the university to present a unified image of itself as a critical force

in society’s self-reproductive processes’.83 Indeed it does, and indeed that is of profound

social value, but true basic research is driven by a fundamental, intuitive, non-rational,

83 Steve Fuller, ‘Foreword’, in The Future of Knowledge Production in the Academy, eds Merle Jacob, Tomas Hellström (Buckingham: SRHE and Open University Press, 2000), xiii.

52 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

impulse to know more deeply without consideration of value or utility. That, paradoxically, is

its research value, and hence, ultimately, its instrumental value to the university. The

fundamental value of basic research is that all other research and development derives from it,

but in its own conception it is knowledge for its own sake.84 Fuller’s focus, however, was the

broad benefit (which is undeniable) to society of a richer and more useful way of thinking,

not the unique research aspect that only the university idea can sustain. Thus he concluded:

The fact that several firms in Western countries have begun to invest in the funding of doctoral programmes for their middle management personnel suggests that they have begun to see that certain intellectual traits can be gained only through an immersion in traditional university values.85

But here it is the uniqueness of the style of thinking which is being valued, not the uniqueness

of the field of inquiry—human understanding and ‘being’—and the unlimited possibilities

that, potentially, arise from research in that field. It may be that one role the university

performs is that of cognitive trainer to industry, but if so that derives from, and is subordinate

to, its (unique) primary role which is exploration at the limits of understanding and

transmission of the discoveries made there.

III

The task for the research university and the disciplines within it, then, is to acknowledge that

it operates as a research specialist and business enterprise. Thus if the university is to survive

and prosper it must, like its business peers, develop and manage a product portfolio that

reflects both the university’s distinctive competence and competitive strength, and which

meet the university’s need for present and future income streams. The business model the

university defines will determine the role each product has in the process of ‘profitable’

84 This is not to suggest that the R&D process is one-way from basic research to experimental development. Often it is practical problems that drive back along the process to manifest themselves in some element of basic research. Nor is the basic researcher an impulsive blank slate. The drive to inquire may be non-rational and intuitive, but it emerges from the actuality of the body–mind–culture network; it does not emerge wholly unformed from without. This will be discussed further in following chapters. 85 Merle Jacob, Tomas Hellström, eds, The Future of Knowledge Production in the Academy (Buckingham: SRHE and Open University Press, 2000), xv.

53 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

customer engagement, and, hence, the investment profile for each.86

The university must manage a number of product ‘layers’ that arise from those two

roles. The first is the product layer related to the basic research dimension, the second is

related to the other research and development dimensions (strategic basic research, applied

research, experimental development), and the third is related to the scholarship and teaching

dimension. At the disciplinary level, there is yet another product layer: that of the

commercial product—either contracted research, consultancy, or (for arts and humanities

specialists) literary and artistic commission (or submission). These, though, for the arts and

humanities academic, are ancillary to the primary role of academic research specialist, in

particular, basic research specialist.87 Value is delivered to the wider basic research

enterprise through the specialist mode of inquiry and category of knowledge, not the single-

discipline end product.88 Popularity in the market of particular disciplinary general education

or vocational products is a business consideration, not a research issue. The disciplines’

primary intellectual responsibility is to identify where the leading knowledge edge is in their

field and ensure that their research is continually at that edge. Only in this way can they

continue to ‘move up the food chain’ and stay ahead of their Mode 2 competitors. The

university’s primary intellectual responsibility is to identify how it can ensure that its

intellectual whole is always greater than its disciplinary parts.

For the individual discipline, a business appreciation of a product’s relation to the

marketplace is needed if the discipline is not to be distracted from its primary research role.

Apart from the issue of product types, the function of a product is a quite separate issue from

86 For example, which products are price setters, which are ‘cash cows’, and which are the strategic, ‘experimental’, products which eventually will become the future price-setters and cash cows. The first are prestige driven, not income driven, but require significant basic research investment, the second are the main income providers and require operating and maintenance investment, the last are development products requiring development investment. 87 Thus, professional bodies are simply the autonomous unions or guilds to which the specialist belongs. The professional bodies’ function is the same as any other professional association and has no research or business role in the university. The members of the profession are employed by competitors—other universities, institutions, companies—and partners alike. 88 Questions asked, and materials used. There are many possible ways of defining these two classes. Chapter 4, Section 3, discusses some of them.

54 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

how, by whom, and in what form it is developed and delivered to users—and how it will be

used by them. Users don’t care who produces, or how or where a product is produced as long

as its functionality, price, availability and quality meet their expectations. Consider ‘history’.

The original source of ‘histories’ may have been the university, but if histories of the same

content and quality were available more conveniently and more cheaply from some other

source, then that is where they would be sourced from. Historical narratives can now be

produced by museums, art galleries, companies, and ‘free-lancers’. Many professional

journalists and other workers are capable of writing articles of a quality acceptable to the

market. Dipesh Chakrabaty noted recently that

to the degree that the media and other institutions of popular culture today (such as films, television, internet, museums, and so on) challenge the hegemony of the university as the producer and disseminator of research and knowledge by setting up parallel institutions that, socially speaking, serve the same function with respect to the past, narratives about the past will have many different sources authorizing them.89

The academic historian’s product, therefore, must be more ‘advanced’ than that of the

honours graduate or higher degree journalist or curator who works outside the academy—if,

that is, the academic specialist is to claim a distinctive intellectual position. Or rather, it

should be more intellectually advanced if the academic historian is to argue for remuneration

as a specialist in the academy, not as an author in the marketplace. The academic historian

must be clear where the basic research frontier lies and what other basic research in the

academy shares a common border. In that region will be found the spring that will sustain the

academic historian’s work as academic.

History is perhaps an obvious target in such argument. To the marketplace, history (as

remembered past) is accessible and communal, each member of the community would claim

some voice in the exposition and legitimation of that ‘history’. But even the (apparently)

more abstract created product is victim of the process of absorption, adaption, and re-creation.

89 Dipesh Chakrabaty, “A Global and Multicultural “Discipline” of History”, History and Theory, 45, no. 1. (Feb., 2006): 109.

55 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

Critical theory, for example, has become a form of vocational liberal education. To be an

active, informed participant in the intellectualised community of the twenty-first century is to

have absorbed and ‘normalized’ the previously esoteric language and highly developed

philosophical concepts used by specialists working at the once leading edge of social theory.

The ‘intellectual’ product has become, in Martin Jay’s words, ‘a highly profitable commodity

in the cultural market-place’, to be used as adornment and common discursive currency.90 As

Jay has remarked: ‘For even the most discerning of observers, reality and pose have become

difficult to distinguish.’ But, again, this is not the result of academic social engineering, but

of the culture’s inexhaustible capacity to absorb complex products and adapt them to new

uses. It is the result of, in Jay’s words again, ‘our culture’s uncanny ability to absorb and

defuse even its most uncompromising opponents.’

The conclusion that can be drawn here is that determination of the use-value of an

intellectual product, and of way in which it will be used (and, consequently, its user-form)

will be made outside the academy. The utility leading edge will always be outside the

academy, thus a significant portion of the formal research and development chain can, or will,

lie outside the academy. Thus, again, the only part of that chain which does not, nor cannot,

lie outside the academy, is the basic research link. It is not the nature of the product, but the

function within a dynamic process of intellectualization that determines where and by whom

those functions are performed. In this sense ‘academic’ defines the location at the front end

of an intellectualization process, not the location within an institution or the producer of

particular consumer products. The academic always works at the leading edge of a dynamic

intellectual process. If this is not understood, then the danger is that the academic will feel

overwhelmed by the forces of change which seem to be demolishing that special place at a

distance from the rest of society, previously reserved for academics and the academy. The

academic will confuse natural habitat with location in the food chain.

90 All quotes in this paragraph are from Martin Jay, The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research 1923–1950 (Boston and Toronto: Little, Brown and Company, 1973), xiv.

56 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

Simon Cooper makes this mistake, and more, when he identifies what he argues is the

contradiction (and problem for academics) at the heart of any knowledge society. He

remarks:

[a] fully reconstructed knowledge society provides no place to stand outside, and as such leaves little room for sustainable interpretation or critique … we are moving to a state of ‘post-intellectuality’ [where] intellectuals increasingly will come to resemble forms of artificial intelligence—running through paradigm–defined operations—lacking insight into their own conditions of possibility.91

But this is to confuse the more knowledgeable worker with the knowledge–worker. The taxi

driver may have a post-graduate qualification, but he or she is driving a taxi, not producing

social critique or conducting basic research. The economic food chain in the knowledge

society remains unchanged, it is just that everyone in it has become more knowledgeable.

Similarly, the intellectual food chain remains the same, it is just that the academic has to

move ‘up’ intellectually in order to maintain his or her place. Cooper seems to be implying

that immanent critique is the terminus of intellectual inquiry, rather than an intellectual

moment with its own history, to be studied. He is worrying that there is nowhere left for the

academic to stand once the Mode 2 barbarians have vaulted the wall.

Clearly, the implication that the academic must always stand ‘outside’, that he or she

cannot function within dynamic epistemological and ontological processes, is wrong. Inquiry

will always be ‘inside’. The very stuff of intellectual inquiry is the search for the next

Archimedean point from which to observe—whether it is Kantian transcendentalism, or

Cartesian–inspired vitalism, or Derridean différence, or (as intellectual renunciation of

metaphysical thought) immanent critique itself. There will always be a conceptual boundary

between inside and outside. The boundary is where the academy conducts its basic research.

The essential and unique contribution of Geisteswissenschaften specialists is their ability to

comprehend that moving boundary and place it within a context that enables inquiry and

91 Simon Cooper, “Post-Intellectuality” in Simon Cooper, John Hinkson, Geoff Sharp, Scholars and Entrepreneurs, 230, 231.

57 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

knowledge to proceed and evolve. But, similarly, it is the responsibility of the university to

manage that other boundary: the university/society boundary, so that the often semi-

independent ‘inside’/‘outside’ elements of research, teaching, and knowledge transfer can be

integrated in a way that allows their vigorous intellectual interaction. Each informs and is

informed by the other, none can function independently.92 Research grows from that

interaction.

The university must manage, also, a profitable business engagement by the university

with the marketplace. Like its commercial peers, it must identify its customer range and the

product variations required to match that range. And like its commercial peers it must

understand why its ‘whole’ is larger than its specialist parts. As they do, it must have that

understanding if it is to be able to justify retention of the parts. But whereas companies, as

they grow, continually cull the weakest parts, for the research university pursuing whole–

knowledge basic research there are, intellectually, no ‘weakest’ parts. There is no ‘core

research’ that is irrelevant, thus no discipline that undertakes basic research can be

superfluous. The increased attention given by funding authorities to ‘whole of knowledge’

projects (as the result of the increasing awareness that there is no privileged, single, mode of

explanation) means, fortuitously, that on this point intellectual and business logic

correspond.93 Intellectually and commercially, the area of highest ‘value-add’ is research.

Even if the research market is not the largest revenue source—and it is not, for that is not its

92 The nature of the connection between teaching and research has long been contentious, but that the connection is symbiotic seems undeniable. In 1965, in Australia, in a paper commissioned by the Australian Humanities Research Council, the distinguished academic John McManners observed that: ‘One’s research may directly assist only a fraction of one’s teaching; but reflective preparation for teaching should enliven one’s research, however indirectly’. J. McManners, R. M. Crawford, The Future of the Humanities in the Australian Universities (Melbourne: Melbourne University Publishing on behalf of the Australian Humanities Research Council, 1965), 20. The research, teaching, knowledge transfer chain is two way, as is the research, development, application, operation chain. This will be addressed in Chapter 5. 93 For example, see PMSEIC (Prime Minister’s Science, Engineering and Innovation Council) Working Group, Imagine Australia: The Role of Creativity in the Innovative Economy (Canberra: PMSEIC, 2005); also Jenni Metcalfe, et. al., CHASS Occasional Papers; Collaborating Across the Sectors: The Relationships between the Humanities, Arts and Social Sciences (HASS) and Science, Technology, Engineering and Medicine (STEM) Sectors, November 2006 (Canberra: Council for Humanities, Arts and Social Sciences (CHASS), 2006). Chapter 5 will discuss this trend in more detail.

58 Ch. 1: History and the Knowledge Business

function—it is a key differentiator and price-maker. Through its price-making function

revenue is maximised in the main revenue sources which are general education and

professional and vocational training. Research quality determines perceptions of university

‘rank’, and university rankings determine the attractiveness of both the research and

educational environment for researchers and students alike.

Research is the ‘premium’ category in the knowledge economy, and basic research is

the highest rung of that category.

59

60

CHAPTER 2

RESEARCH AND SCHOLARSHIP

Had such a statement [‘He learned much that other men had discovered, and conveyed much of this to others’] been always the best that could be said of any man, our science today would be that of the primitive cave-dweller. It is the minds that have advanced beyond what they have received from others that have brought us to the point where we are. It is to the discoverers, in far greater measure than to the transmitters, that the world is under obligation. —William Gardner Hale1

The moment the historian conceives the ambition to understand, and conducts his historical studies accordingly, he brings upon himself the curse of homo sapiens. After all, Adam’s curse was to labour not with the grease of his elbow but with the sweat of his brow. —Munia Postan2

Once a fellow has been elected, he finds no suitable direction in Oxford. He must go for instruction to Berlin or even to Catholic and arriéré Vienna. Oxford cannot give it to him. —Mark Pattison3

The Pursuit of Knowledge

‘Research’ is considered a self-evident ‘good’ in contemporary society. To be an academic in modern society means to be a person accomplished in the conduct of specialist disciplinary research. Regardless of the activity that person may be undertaking in the academy, whether it is administrative, pedagogic, research, or a mix of all these, the person’s identity, status, and legitimacy is determined by their level of research accomplishment. However, the notions that research is central to the idea of the university and central to academic competence, are recent perceptions. Their emergence and hegemony have their origins in the rise and rise of

1 William Gardner Hale (1848–1928), Latinist, University of Chicago, quoted in Hugh Hawkins, ‘University Identity: the Teaching and Research Functions’, in The Organization of Knowledge in Modern America, 1860–1920, eds Alexandra Oleson and John Voss (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1979), 289. 2 M. M. Postan, “Fact and Relevance in Historical Study”, Historical Studies, 13, no. 51 (Oct., 1968): 425. 3 Quoted in Sir Llewellyn Woodward, “The Rise of the Professorial Historian in England”, in Studies in International History, eds K. Bourne, and D. C. Watt, 30, footnote 42, no reference given.

61 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

science in European societies particularly since the seventeenth century, and the idea and

establishment of the ‘research’ university developed and implemented in Germany during the

late eighteenth century and early nineteenth century—in particular, the establishment of the

University of Berlin in 1809 to the intellectual design of Friedrich Schleiermacher, Johann

Fichte, and Wilhelm von Humboldt.

In England and America, science in the academy had always been associated with

research: however, for the humanities, research as a notion was only embraced in the last half

of the nineteenth-century—and research training only in the last twenty years of the

nineteenth-century. For the history discipline in England, consensus only emerged on the

need for research in the second half of the nineteenth century, and it was to Germany that it

looked when seeking to establish research processes. But although the discipline may have

emulated German research method, the English conception of research purpose was quite

different to the German conception.4 For the English it was applied knowledge, for the

Germans it was ‘pure’ knowledge. Consequently, the ‘truths’ sought and the understandings

derived from that research, were quite different. For the Germans the discipline was,

primarily, a means to a basic research end: to expand ‘knowledge of knowledge’ (in effect, a

probing of epistemological and ontological boundaries)—it was to understand more deeply

the nature of being.5 For the English, research was primarily a means to a pragmatic end: to

derive history’s political and moral lessons—thus, to understand more deeply how to act. For

the Germans, the knowledge sought had its roots in theology, philosophy, and mystical

intuition; for the English, the roots were in statecraft, government, and the tradition of civil

‘freedom’ and obligation.

I

The two styles of thought had not always differed. When the institution of the

university was first established, in the medieval period, it represented a ‘commonwealth of

thought’ that was little affected by national differences since that thought was grounded in the

4 ‘English’ denotes geography, not ethnicity; Bury, for example, was Irish. 5 The phrase ‘knowledge of knowledge’ is discussed below in a later section.

62 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

common system of inviolable, Christian, theological truth. Scholars, possessing as they did

both common understanding and common language (Latin), moved freely between the major

universities. Until the beginning of the fifteenth century, masters in the faculties of

philosophy, or law, or theology in Paris, or Oxford, or Cologne might be from any part of

Europe. But with the extensive social transformations of the fifteenth century, particularly

the rise of literacy stimulated by the availability of printed material, the rise of humanist

thought and Protestant revolt, and the early use of vernacular language in academic

scholarship and discourse, national differences between the universities began to emerge.6

Masters now were more likely to be from the country in which the university was located,

and to reflect national cultural differences

In England, Bacon’s rejection of Scholasticism, and his redefinition of the purpose of

‘learning’ and how it should be advanced, has been said to mark the point at which a

distinctive British intellectual style began to emerge.7 From the latter decades of the

seventeenth century in England, with the great success of experimental scientists such as

Newton, Boyle, and other members of the Royal Society, and with philosophers such as

Hobbes and Locke, a distinctive British empiricist mind-set emerged; and which was to

evolve further into the utilitarian empiricism of Bentham, Mill and others. Utilitarianism was

to typify a distinctively ‘British’ form of positivism.

In Germany, quite different influences had, by the last decades of the eighteenth

century, produced a very different intellectual orientation. In 1789, Germany was not a single

nation but, rather, as the remains of the Holy Roman Empire, an empire with no central

government nor financial system, nor dominant religious denomination. The Reformation

and Counter-Reformation, the Thirty-Years War, and the contingencies of geography and

politics had produced a ‘Germany’ constituted by a collection of 1,789 (sic) independent

6 Bacon, for example, was responding to influences that were becoming widespread not just in Cambridge, but Paris and other centres of learning. But after his death his books became particularly influential in British ‘natural philosophy’ circles. Robert Boyle, a founding member of the Royal Society (1660), was an admirer and did much to publicize the content of the works. Meyrick H. Carré, Phases of Thought in England (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949), x, 234, 238–240. 7 J. Seth, English Philosophers and Schools of Philosophy (London: Dent, 1912), 10, quoted in Meyrick H. Carré, Phases of Thought in England, ix.

63 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

kingdoms, electorates, principalities, duchies, margravates, free cities, and ecclesiastical

territories. Some, such as Prussia and Austria, were independent states and European powers,

but most consisted only of a few castles and villages.8 It was, though, an empire with a large

number of long established and intellectually substantial universities.9 The oldest,

Heidelberg, had been founded in 1385. Marburg, founded 1527 was the first Protestant

university, and Halle, founded 1694, became the academic centre of Pietism. Because of

Germany’s tumultuous political, religious, and intellectual history, the need arose for civil,

theological, and philosophical expertise.10 Consequently, most universities were strong in

one or more of the traditional disciplines, particularly law, theology, classical scholarship,

and philosophy.

In religion also, differences emerged between the two countries. The threads of

mysticism and logic which had always informed intellectual inquiry (and manifested as the

interweaving of reason and faith in medieval academic thought) began to assume different

emphases. In Germany, the growth of religious mysticism, particularly in the Rhenish

territories, combined with the personalized faith promoted by Lutheranism and Calvinism,

produced a German theological and philosophical style of thought which had at its centre

spirituality and subjectivity, not liturgy and public worship.11 German pietism, although

influenced by English and Dutch pious religious thought, had developed its own distinctive

character from earlier German religious mystics such as Meister Eckehart (c. 1260–1327/28),

Johannes Tauler (c. 1300–61), Heinrich Suso (c. 1295–1366), Thomas à Kempis (c. 1380–

1471), and then (c. 1483–1546) and other contemporary reformist thinkers

8 Golo Mann, The History of Germany Since 1789 (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1974), 21. Most of these disappeared in the administrative rationalization and political bargaining during the period of French hegemony under Napoleon, after which there remained 38 substantial states. 9 In 1789, of the 143 universities still functioning in Europe 35 were in Germany. The four largest German universities at that time were Halle, Göttingen, Jena, and Leipzig with a total of around 3,200 students (40% of all students). See Christophe Charle, ‘Patterns’, in, A History of the University in Europe, vol 3: Universities in the Nineteenth and early Twentieth Centuries (1800–1945), ed. Walter Rüegg (Cambridge: Cambridge Iniversity Press, 2004),33. 10 What is meant here by ‘intellectual’ is the divergent intellectual orientations and patronage of the many independent courts—some Catholic, some Lutheran, some Calvinist, some Francophile, others Francophobe, etc. 11 Institutionally mediated faith and experience was replaced with personal belief through personal spiritual ‘experience’ (spiritual intuition).

64 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

such as John Oecolampadius (c. 1482–1531) and Sebastian Franck (c. 1499–1542). In

England, mysticism, in the form of personal spiritual experience, grounded English

Puritanism and Deism, and later, through contact with the German Moravian church, the

Methodism of Wesley. But in Germany, pietist thought was institutionalized, along with

Lutheranism, Calvinism, and Roman Catholicism, in the university system and civil service.

In England it was excluded from both the university and civil service. In Germany, theology

was infused with a tradition of subjectivity and intuitive cognition. In England, theology was

infused with Church of England orthodoxy which privileged authority and doctrine.

II

For the institution of the university, the pursuit of knowledge had always been central to its

function. However, for most of the institution’s life that pursuit was through scholarship and

learning to which reason was applied within prescribed ontological and epistemological

limits. The purpose of intellectual endeavour was clarification, rather than research in the

sense of the expansion of ontological and epistemological boundaries through discovery and

creative thought. It was designed to preserve and transmit. As a Church-inspired and

Church-sponsored institution, the medieval university’s theoretical vision was filtered through

a Christian ontology which presumed as self-evident a natural and (sacred) supernatural world

whose boundaries were transcendent and absolute. This presumption framed the conception

of knowledge’s forms and the manner of its acquisition. Knowledge was of two distinct

types: natural knowledge, for which reason and ‘philosophy’ were the means for its

acquisition, and supernatural knowledge, for which faith and theology were the appropriate

means. It was assumed as self-evident that supernatural knowledge was derived from divine

revelation: thus it was through faith and theology not rational inquiry that ultimate access to

that revealed truth would be provided. But reason, as logical argument, was the means to

validate and articulate, thus authorize, a mystical end.

From the Greek philosophers had come the conclusion that belief in a super-sensible

intelligible world, and in eternal and exact truth, could be proven. Through mathematics it

65 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

appeared to be possible to discover things about the actual world by first noticing what was

self-evident, and then using deduction to extend that knowledge. By deductive reasoning one

could start with the self-evident and arrive at theorems and ‘laws’ that were far from self-

evident, but which accorded with experience—as science had continually demonstrated.

Theology, particularly in its Scholastic form, was the rigorous application of deductive

thought to the supernatural world, just as science was the application of deductive thought to

the natural world. The eternal world was revealed to the intellect, the natural world to the

senses.12 Through reason, a belief in self-evident, eternal, exact, Christian truths could be

validated.

Religious faith derived from mysticism, but religious authority derived from reason.

Given the intricate and turbulent relationship between religious and secular authority that

existed for much of the university’s early life, the university’s special theological and legal

ability, and its special theological and legal knowledge, assured it of a distinctive and

indispensable political and religious role. On theoretical matters concerning law and religion,

the university was the ultimate intellectual authority. On practical matters concerning the

government of law and religious doctrine, the academic was the most expert advisor to

authority. There was no expectation for either the university or the academic to create

knowledge in the modern research sense, but the university and the academic represented the

highest, thus most distinctive and pre-eminent, intellectual competence available.

Despite the restriction its religious assumptions imposed, intellectual inquiry in the

medieval academy represented the most advanced attempts to advance understanding on the

perennial philosophical questions regarding the nature of reality and the nature of ‘man’. For

the Church, these general questions manifested themselves as particular questions on

substance and non-substance, will and action, realism and nominalism (the problem of

universals and particulars),13 and the provability of God’s existence. God existed, that was

12 Bertrand Russell, History of Western Philosophy (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1969), 55–56. 13 And, broadly, using either Platonic or Aristotelian premises in the investigation of the problem.

66 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

given, but there were ontological puzzles and doctrinal problems. The academic was the one

most able to unravel these complex and subtle intellectual and doctrinal issues. The

philosophical solutions developed by St. Thomas Aquinas were particularly influential as

their dexterous synthesis of the thought of Plato, Aristotle, Augustine, and other early Church

Fathers overcame many of the ontological and doctrinal problems that previous syntheses had

left unresolved: for example, problems regarding the relationship of matter to eternity, and

the nature of the human soul and human ‘being’. Through the principles and methods he

devised, Aquinas had provided a means by which reason could be harmonized with belief.

But, significantly, he had concluded, as others had concluded before him, that reason and

belief were a dyad: neither one could replace the other, they could only be brought into

harmony.

Aquinas had concluded, finally, that theology was of three forms: ‘natural’,14

‘philosophical’,15 and ‘revealed’, and that, ultimately, the first two required the divinely

revealed propositions of the third, if they were to avoid mistakes about the truth of God. ‘All

human well being … depends on cognition of that truth’, he wrote.16 Doctrinal mysteries

were not impervious to investigation, but unaided reason could never discover divine truths.

Regarding the central mystery of the Trinity he declared: ‘It is impossible to arrive at a

cognition of the Trinity of the divine persons by means of natural reason’.17 Discovery

required spiritual intuition, thus faith, since spiritual intuition was wholly constitutive of faith.

John Duns Scotus, too, had concluded rationally that philosophy was insufficient to satisfy

the deep need for profound knowledge. For Duns Scotus, to truly understand the concept of

human being was to understand that the immanent and the transcendent world had a single

meaning. In this conclusion, Duns Scotus had anticipated the German Idealism of Fichte,

Schelling, and Hegel, and the later phenomenological ontology of Heidegger. And in their

general conclusion that ‘spirit’ and reason were dyadic, the Scholastic thinkers had

14 A combination of Aristotelianism and Greek and Arab scientific thought. 15 The application of reason to revelation. 16 Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologia Ia.1.1c, quoted in Norman Kretzman, Eleonore Stump, ‘Thomas Aquinas’, The Shorter Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Craig (Abingdon: Routledge, 2005), 46–47. 17 Ibid., Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologia Ia.32.1c, 47

67 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

anticipated the English and German Romanticist thought of the eighteenth and nineteenth

century. Whether the dyad was thought of as reason and faith, or subject and object, or

imagination and rationality, or phenomena and noumena, its identity represented the limit of

ontological and epistemological understanding.

Scholasticism, Romanticism and Idealism treat mysticism and rationality as two

fundamental human impulses. The Scholastics, working at the edge of human understanding

and with an exemplary intellectual rigour, had reached the same conclusion as thinkers five

hundred years later: that of the unavoidable interdependence of reason and belief. They had

shown, as later thinkers were also to do, that, ultimately, reason rests on belief and

assumption—reason by itself cannot explain why there is reason rather than no reason—but

belief needs rational grounding if it is to have any religious, political, moral or social

authority. The corollary of this was that, in order to go beyond current understanding a

combination of intuition and reason was required. Originality required both reason and

intuition; new knowledge in its many forms required both perception and conception for its

acquisition.

Bertrand Russell observed:

the attempt to conceive the world as a whole by means of thought, has been developed, from the first, by the union and conflict of two very different human impulses, the one urging men towards mysticism, the other urging them towards science … in Hume, for example, the scientific impulse reigns quite unchecked, while in Blake a strong hostility to science coexists with profound mystic insight … the greatest men … have felt the need both of science and of mysticism: the attempt to harmonize the two was what made their life … 18

Hume personified empiricism, Blake romanticism. But for earlier thinkers such as Descartes,

Spinoza, Pascal, Leibniz, and Wolff, and for contemporary ones such as Kant, Herder,

Coleridge, Faraday and Hegel the power and originality of their speculations were due in no

small part to them being an intimate blending of spiritual intuition with reason. For those

18 Bertrand Russell, Mysticism and Logic: And Other Essays (London: Unwin Books, 1969), 9.

68 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

thinkers there were no disciplinary boundaries.

For them, disciplinary boundaries were irrelevant. Disciplinary labels simply described

particular modes of inquiry. Then, as now, the boundaries were porous. Descartes, Leibniz,

Pascal moved with equal ease and legitimacy between philosophy, mathematics, natural

philosophy, theology, and history. They simply sought to know and understand more than

was already known and understood. Leibniz was philosopher, mathematician, historian,

philologist, jurist. Kant’s early works were more concerned with science than with

philosophy. For the nineteenth-century scientist Michael Faraday, scientific research was just

the means by which his deep search, like Leibniz, for that single ‘monistic’ universal force by

which the natural and supernatural became unified, could be progressed. George Airey, the

Astronomer Royal at the Cambridge observatory, commented to fellow astronomer John

Herschel: ‘I have always known Faraday as a mystic: I suppose however that a good share of

that character is indispensable for an advancing philosopher.’19 For Faraday, in his desire to

explore the ‘detailed complexity of the actual,’20 and to understand reality, there were no

logical or disciplinary boundaries. The melding of reason and intuition, science and

philosophy was accepted without anxiety.

For John Henry Newman, it was only knowledge of that whole reality which

constituted ‘universal knowledge’. Newman regarded the established categories of

knowledge as parts of that unified whole; the disciplines were just modes of inquiry into that

larger whole. The fact, though, of that reality was a revealed truth and beyond reason. All

inquiry, however free, operated within that truth. In his discourses on the idea of the

university, he insisted that natural philosophy, theology, philosophy, mathematics and history

were one as means to the acquisition of universal knowledge; as he said, since truths resided

in ‘the natural order, as well as in the supernatural’, none could be excluded.21 For Newman,

19 It is assumed that this remark is meant as it appears. Airey to Herschel, 20 March 1857 (John Herschel Papers, Royal Society), quoted in Susan Faye Cannon, Science in Culture: The Early Victorian Period, 58. 20 This is a phrase used by Susan Cannon in another context, in Susan Faye Cannon, Science in Culture: The Early Victorian Period (New York: Dawson & Science History Publications, 1978), 59. 21 John Henry Newman, The Idea of a University, ed. I. T. Ker (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1976), Discourse II, 37–8.

69 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

the idea of the university implied the notion of ‘universal knowledge’.

But for Newman, the university’s role was not the creation of knowledge; rather, it was

‘the perfection of the Intellect’ through the contemplation of the integrity and unity of

knowledge.22 It was the unity of all knowledge, like the ‘Idea’ or the ‘Absolute’ of the

German Idealists, which was the essential truth to be apprehended and ‘felt’. Contemplation,

not discovery, was the key. He deplored what he saw in the new London University:

a sort of bazaar, or pantechnicon, in which wares of all kinds are heaped together for sale in stalls independent of each other … The majestic vision of the Middle Age, which grew steadily to perfection in the course of centuries, the University of Paris, or Bologna, or Oxford, has almost gone out in night. A philosophical comprehensiveness, an orderly expansiveness, an elastic constructiveness, men have lost them, and cannot make out why. This is why: because they have lost the idea of unity.23

Newman had never set himself against either reason or research.24 He acknowledged

quite freely that ‘if we invite reason to take its place in our schools, we must let reason have

full and fair play … we cannot use it by halves’. But he considered the two dogmas of faith:

natural and revealed knowledge to be inviolate; thus science (which exemplified inquiry and

open-ended research) could only ever coexist with religion, it could not integrate with it or

displace it. The university’s role lay beyond research.25 ‘The philosophy of an imperial

intellect’, he said, ‘for such I am considering a University to be’, has as its ‘true

representative’ one who ‘aims at no complete catalogue, or interpretation of the subjects of

knowledge, but a following out, as far as man can, what in its fullness is mysterious and

unfathomable’.26

Newman had never been able to reconcile a genuine intellectual liberalism with a

22 Newman, The Idea of a University, Discourse I, ix, Discourse VI, 124–125. A. Dwight Culler, The Imperial Intellect: A Study of Newman’s Educational Ideal (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1958), 174. 23 Newman, The Idea of a University, 1852 Discourse V, 421, 422–423. 24 The medical school in the Catholic University of Ireland had first-rate laboratories and libraries and was the most flourishing in the University. See Culler, The Imperial Intellect, 160. 25 Newman, The Idea of a University, University Subjects VIII, 379–380. 26 Ibid., University Subjects VIII, 382, 371–2.

70 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

religious submissiveness; it was a stressful tension, as his discourses and occasional lectures

and essays reveal. His prostration before Church dogma prevented him from ever achieving a

harmonization of reason and faith. All that was possible was a theological mysticism that

could never progress intellectual inquiry. Education, not discovery, was his intellectual

concern, as it was for the English academy. As Mark Pattison had commented: under a

Newman system, ‘a college must become a mere priestly seminary and not an agent of a

university’.27

III

The Romanticism and Idealism which emerged in Germany, and the Romanticism which

emerged in England, during the second half of the eighteenth century were a new

manifestation of the instinctive search, like Herder’s and Faraday’s, for a deeper more

complete understanding of a ‘whole’ reality. Although natural forces, mechanical causation,

and rational critique had replaced divine purpose and the supernatural as the keys to

explanation of the phenomenal and rational world, they still left unfulfilled the hunger for a

‘deeper’, more subjective, knowledge. With the Enlightenment had come the notion of

human agency and historical possibility: that social and natural science could be combined

into a science of man whereby revolutionary change could be achieved through rational,

‘intelligent’, action. But neither mechanical causation, nor physiological research could

explain ‘free will’, the soul, moral sense, or ‘sensibility’, and reason alone could not engage

the complexity and raw, visceral, immediacy of life.

In the eighteenth century, through medical science, the model of man had changed

incrementally from ‘homme machine’ to ‘homme sensible’. Enlightenment scientism had

evolved into an Enlightenment vitalism in order to mediate between early eighteenth-century

mechanism and animism.28 Cartesian mechanism, like Bacon’s new science of observation

27 Mark Pattison, Memoirs (London: Macmillan, 1885), 87. The paragraph above is a rather facile generalization of a complex subject. Martin Svaglic’s review of Culler’s The Imperial Intellect captures that complexity; Martin J. Svaglic, Modern Philology, 55, no. 1 (Aug., 1957): 66–70. 28 The term ‘Enlightenment vitalism’ is Peter Hanns Reill’s; see Peter Hanns Reill, “Science and the Construction of the Cultural Sciences in Late Enlightenment Germany: the Case of Wilhelm von Humboldt”, History and Theory, 33, no. 3 (Oct., 1994): 345–366.

71 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

and experiment, had opposed the teleological, animistic view of Aristotelian science as

represented, in its assimilated Thomistic form, in Roman Catholic and Protestant theology,

but it merely placed the human soul or mind—Kant’s transcendental self—outside

deterministic nature. Descartes, after having long cherished the hope that ‘the science of

man’ could be deduced from physics, concluded that it could not be done.29 And Kant had

simply explored, as he declared, the limits of reason in order to allow room for faith.30 His

principal goal was to refute Hume’s argument denying knowledge of causality. But ‘vital

force’ or essence still remained, and its location and relationship to nature still obscure. The

relationship between, on the one hand: soul, mind, consciousness, free will, and moral sense,

and on the other: body and brain, required reconsideration. The functions of the ‘physique’

now appeared to be ‘intrinsically and jointly interwoven with the functions of the moral.’31

Since soul or ‘spirit’ (Kant’s moral agent), and ‘will’ were linked to mind, then as mind was

linked to brain, the physical and the moral must be linked through some ‘vital’ agency. The

problem was the issue of control: how at a social and individual level the ‘will’ is exercised,

or fails to be exercised. Social order, civility, and morality depended on inhibition and ethical

sense. ‘Will’ must transcend, but control, physiological functions; but how this was so

remained mysterious.. The metaphysical solutions to problems of immanence–transcendence,

subject–object, propounded by thinkers such as Spinoza and Leibnitz did not address the

mind–body problem which ‘will’ and physiology presented.32

In Germany, Hamann’s powerful, intellectual, religiously inspired, primitivism was

emphasizing a ‘whole man’ conception of human nature and understanding. For Hamann,

neither Deism, which was directed to the intellect, nor Pietism, which was directed to

intuition, were adequate—‘whole man’ was a dynamic unity of belief and sexuality

29 Sergio Moravia, “From Homme Machine to Homme Sensible: Changing Eighteenth-Century Models of Man’s Image”, Journal of the History of Ideas, 39, no. 1 (Jan. – Mar., 1978): 46. 30 In the Preface to the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason (1787) he explained: ‘I had to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith.’ For Kant, the concept of God and the practical (i.e. moral) use of reason were intimately connected. 31 Sergio Moravia, “From Homme Machine to Homme Sensible”, 59. 32 It was not until Wundt established his psychology laboratory in the University of Leipzig in 1879, that physiology and philosophy were joined.

72 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

(Geschlecht)33; ‘whole man’ was energetic.34 When combined with the New Humanism35

that was emerging in the German academy (the studies of such scholars as Winckelmann,

Lessing, Herder, Heyne, and F. A. Wolf were raising awareness of the importance of poetry

and art to understanding past cultures and, consequently, one’s own) the resulting ideas of

organic unity produced ways of understanding and experiencing lived reality that were

orthogonal to Enlightenment’s positivist, reductive, thought. Now, for these scholars, myth

and poetry were the oldest history. Imagination was a portal to an historical truth not

accessible to pure reason.36 Dilthey too, many years later, concluded that historical

‘objectivity’ was made possible by the fact that historical understanding draws on the same

imaginative capacities that enable poets to transcend the limits of their own historical

context.37 Empiricism and reason alone were insufficient.

Herder’s insistence that cultural explanation required ‘whole’ cultural understanding,

when joined with the literary innovation of Goethe, Schiller and other writers, produced a

distinctive German form of historical and cultural explanation. It produced a German

Enlightenment unlike that of other countries. To Herder, man was more than dry reason, and

progress was a chimera, the past was as valid in its own terms as the present was.

Civilization was not the salon; civilization was authenticity and wholeness—that organic

33 James C. O’Flaherty, Johann Georg Hamann (Boston: Twayne Publishers, 1979), 36–37. 34 Goethe characterized the thought of Hamann in the words: ‘All that a man undertakes to perform, whether by deed, by word, or otherwise, must proceed from all his powers united; everything isolated is worthless.’ The Autobiography of Goethe, trans. John Oxenford, vol. 2, 136, quoted in James C. O’Flaherty, Johann Georg Hamann, 34. 35 The Old Humanism sought to imitate the latin classics, the New Humanism sought to assimilate the substance and to form the mind and taste. See John Edwin Sandys, A History of Classical Scholarship, vol. 3 (New York: Hafner, 1967), 7. 36 Donald R. Kelley, “Mythistory in the Age of Ranke”, in George G. Iggers, James M. Powell (eds.), and the Shaping of the Historical Discipline (Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 1990), 5. In Italy (though earlier), Vico, in New Science, described his discovery of what he calls ‘the master key’ to the principles of humanity: ‘that the first gentile peoples, by a demonstrated necessity of nature, were poets who spoke in poetic characters.’ Giambattista Vico, The New Science of Giambattista Vico (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988), paras. 120–27, 34, quoted in Sandra Rudnick Luft, Vico’s Uncanny Humanism: Reading the New Science between Modern and Postmodern (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2003), 1. Goethe was given a copy of Scienza Nuova from a student (of Vico) whom he visited in Naples in 1787. 37 See Michael Ermarth, Wilhelm Dilthey: The Critique of Historical Reason (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1978), 126ff, 271ff. See also Jacob Owensby, Dilthey and the Narrative of History (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994), 137ff.

73 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

totality of intellectual, spiritual and artistic life that was Kultur.38 Literature and art were the

living expression of that wholeness. That, for Hugh Trevor-Roper, was the ‘essential doctrine

of the great Germans of the late 18th century’. Significantly it was, as Trevor-Roper observes,

a doctrine particularly acceptable in a country whose only unity was provided not by politics—politics only divided and weakened it—but by culture: which was saved from being a mere geographical expression by its newly discovered greatness as a Kulturvolk.39

Germany could not be defined by geography, as Britain could be. The German desire to

understand, in Herder’s sense, was a desire to understand ‘Who are we?’ It was an existential

question which connected to the exploration of subjectivity and ‘universal’ identity pursued

by Schelling, Fichte, Hegel, and others. It connected, too, assisted by the hermeneutic

theories of Schleiermacher and Boeckh, to the centrality of historical consciousness in the

work of Schiller, Niebuhr, Ranke, Humboldt, Droysen, and others.40

In contrast to German Romanticism and Idealism which were grounded in philosophy,

Geist, Kultur, and historical consciousness, the roots of English Romanticism were grounded

in late eighteenth-century literary notions of the natural sublime and intense feeling. The

intensity of feeling generated through awe, or terror, transported the subject beyond reason to

an absolute sensibility. Coleridge, influenced by Kantian and German Idealist thought,41

provided some philosophical substance, but it remained a literary, aesthetic, movement. By

reversing Kant’s logic, and making imagination the primary agent of subjectivity, not reason,

Coleridge was able to explore the notion of the union of emotion and thought manifested

through imagination. Imagination was primary, intelligence secondary; intelligence was

38 Hugh Trevor-Roper, “Jacob Burckhardt”, Proceedings of the British Academy, vol. 70, 1984 (London: Oxford University Press, 1985): 360. 39 Ibid., 360. 40 See, for example, Rudolf Makkreel’s review of Wilhelm Dilthey. The Critique of Historical Reason by Michael Ermarth, History and Theory, 19, no. 3. (Oct., 1980), 355. 41 In 1798–99 Coleridge visited Germany and had attended lectures in Göttingen and become familiar with the work of Kant, Schelling, Fichte, Lessing and Schiller well before those scholars were known on England; as well he became aware of German biblical scholarship, ‘Higher Criticism’, and philology. There is substantial literature from the earliest twentieth century onwards debating the connection between English Romanticism and German Romanticism and Idealism.

74 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

subordinate to imagination.42 Literature and poetry's special capacity was their ability to

provide this integration of reason, intuition, and feeling. English Romanticism was almost

wholly connected to individual poetic and literary expression: it had no connection with

‘Englishness’ as identity—unlike German Romanticism which was infused with the spirit of

Germanic linguistic and cultural community.43 And unlike German Romanticism, for

English Romanticism the university was peripheral, not central, to its formation.

History and Discovery

The eighteenth-century ‘idea’ of the university held research not to be central to university

practice. The idea was to retain much of its force in England throughout the first half of the

nineteenth century, and to some degree until the twentieth century. Important scientific

research was being conducted, but that almost wholly outside the academy. In contrast, in

Germany by the end of the eighteenth-century acceptance of the idea of research as intrinsic

to academic function, had become widespread.

Earlier in the eighteenth-century in Germany, research had not been considered a duty

intrinsic to the academic office itself—though many scholars who held university chairs did

pursue extensive scholarly research.44 However, with the renewal of the German university

system at the beginning of the nineteenth century, and with the example set by the University

of Berlin, research became intrinsic to the idea of the university. By the end of the first

quarter of the nineteenth-century German research and scholarship had come to epitomize

original, innovative, and professional academic endeavour.

42 ‘The imagination then I consider either as primary, or secondary. The primary imagination I hold to be the living power and prime agent of all human perception, and as a representation in the finite mind of the eternal act of creation’. Samuel Taylor Coleridge, Biographia Literaria: Or Biographical Sketch of My Literary Life and Opinions, ed. George Watson (Dutton: Dent, 1971), 162. 43 Nor did it have any significant connection, I would argue, to the sentimental humanitarianism which emerged in the eighteenth century from the Christian Deist idea of self-sufficient virtue and moral sensitivity—such as promoted by Anthony Ashley Cooper (Third Earl of Shaftesbury). 44 See R. Steven Turner, “University Reformers and Professorial Scholarship in Germany 1760– 1806”, in The University in Society, vol. 2, ed. Lawrence Stone (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974), 495–531.

75 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

Central to the university reform had been the alteration of the way appointments and

promotions were determined. Only scholarship which enhanced the individual’s reputation

among his disciplinary peers was now rewarded, thus the scholar’s most important work was

directed to the specialist group. It was only the specialist group who were capable of properly

judging the work’s scholarly merit. The inevitable consequence was increasing

specialization. By 1840 in Germany specialization was firmly established. Professorial

output now meant original research addressed to specialists in that field. Work addressed to a

broader audience—textbooks and popular works, for example—was considered to be

secondary professorial activity.45 In England, the view that research was peripheral to

education, thus of questionable relevance to the university, remained influential throughout

the nineteenth century. Initially, the purpose of research was more the replacement of

foreign-authored student textbooks, and the editing and ordering of public records, than

discovery in any epistemological sense.46 It required scholarship rather than basic research

of the kind Wolf, Winckelmann, Niebuhr, and Ranke undertook.

Without the impulse of conceptual discovery behind it, scholarship can lack vitality and

purpose and risk being little more than antiquarianism or pedantry. The uncovering of

another document is in itself no more useful than uncovering another pebble in the quarry,

unless there is an original conceptual query behind the recovery. There was much German

scholarship that was simply pedantry—a criticism often made of it in England. Acton, using

Ritschl as an example, had remarked that ‘The extreme subdivision of labour narrowed his

view, and gave an unusual scope and value to diligent mediocrity. Dull men built themselves

an everlasting name’.47 But for the German scholars whose search was conceptual, as

Herder, Winckelmann, Niebuhr and Boeckh’s, for example, was, the narrowed focus was the

means to a more general truth. By accessing a particular authentic past, a general truth could

be ‘sensed’. The power of Niebuhr’s History of Rome derived from the drive to understand

45 R. Steven Turner, ‘University Reformers and Professorial Scholarship in Germany 1760– 1806’, 522. 46 See later section below. 47 Lord Acton, “German Schools of History”, English Historical Review, 1, no. 1 (Jan., 1886): 26.

76 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

conceptually. In a letter to a young friend Niebuhr had explained that ‘true’ philology

brought health to the soul. The purpose of classical study was to assimilate the spirit of those

times, not to make them themes for aesthetic criticism. Learned investigations in themselves,

he said, belonged to a lower level.48 An English scholar wrote of the ‘freshness’ of Niebuhr’s

History of Rome, of ‘its elation of real or supposed discovery, the impression it conveys of

actual contact with a great body of new and unsuspected truths’.49 Thomas Arnold’s

biographer remarked that when Arnold read Niebuhr’s History of Rome ‘a new intellectual

world dawned upon him, not only in the subject to which it related, but in the disclosure to

him of the depth and research of German literature’.50 Mark Pattison commented that ‘One

was expected at that time [1830s] to know something of Niebuhr’s views.’51

For Ranke, too, the spirit of German Idealism—that fusion of philosophy, subjectivity,

and spiritual intuition—shaped his research. His exemplary methodological rigour served an

entirely intuitive, mystical impulse. Ranke had declared Fichte—the supreme metaphysician

of subjectivity and consciousness—to be the one to whom, after Niebuhr, he was most in

debt.52 Ranke looked in his sources for vitality; for that essence which only the historian

could distill from the deeds of the past. The historical truth he sought transcended factuality.

His search was epistemological and ontological:

Over against the world of truth there is a world of appearance which goes to the roots and develops an ever more profound appearance until it ends in phantasy … Talent is an intimation, an immediate empathy with essence. I scent the track of the spirit … The spirit from which things come, and the

48 Brief an einen jungen Philologen (1822), quoted in John Edwin Sandys, A History of Classical Scholarship, vol. 3 (New York: Hafner Publishing Company, 1967), 80. Niebuhr had been appointed professor in the University of Berlin in 1810. 49 Garnett (sic) in Encyclopaedia Britannica, quoted in John Edwin Sandys, A History of Classical Scholarship, vol. 3, 81. Presumably Richard Garnett. 50 A. Stanley, Life and Correspondence of Thomas Arnold (London, 1844), vol. 1, 43 quoted in Sir Llewellyn Woodward, ‘The Rise of the Professorial Historian in England’, 17. 51 Mark Pattison, Memoirs (London: Macmillan and Co., 1885), 151. Seventy years later, G. Gooch acknowledged Niebuhr’s greatness but maintained that the ‘faculty of intuition’ which Niebuhr used ‘to determine the value of unsupported evidence’, was ‘radically unsound’. The historical research ‘edifice … had to be erected on surer foundations.’ G. Gooch, ‘The Rise of Historical Science’, in The Cambridge Modern History, eds A. W. Ward, G. W. Prothero and Stanley Leathes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1910), 821, 822. 52 Acton, “German Schools of History”: 15.

77 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

knower, will be one. In this theory of knowledge the most subjective is at the same time the most general truth.53

It could have been Schelling describing his ‘absolute Idea’, or Fichte his ‘absolute Subject’.

Ast also explained that ‘Being cannot transform itself into knowledge, or the corporeal into

spirit, without being akin to it or fundamentally one with it. All life is spirit and without the

spirit there is no life’.54 The significance of Ranke’s statement ‘wie es eigentlich gewesen’—

‘to show how it essentially was’55—was that the track of the spirit could only be followed by

capturing, as Herder, Winckelman, Wolf and others had insisted, the authentic past of each

culture studied. Nothing existed outside Geist and Kultur. ‘When we remove the shells from

things and turn out what is essential in them’ Ranke wrote, ‘it happens that in our own selves

essence, spiritual life, soul, and the breath of God take wing, or at least have existence’.56

‘To show how it essentially was’, was an ontological statement—only its practical

consequence was methodological. Scholarly rigour was the necessary handmaiden only, and

scholarship only the incidental result, of research into authenticity and Geist. The search for

knowledge involved metaphysical discovery, and, for those searchers, historical research was

fundamental to that discovery.

In the seventeenth-century German academy, history was an adjunct to jurisprudence

and theology; it had no independent interpretive existence.57 In the eighteenth century, the

intellectual centre had been defined by philosophy, classical studies, and philology; with

history their companion only. But by the early nineteenth century, in Acton’s words, ‘the

53 Ranke, Aus Werk und Nachlass, eds Walther Peter Fuchs and Theodor Schieder, 3 Vols. (Munich, 1964–73), 1: 120, quoted in Leonard Krieger, Ranke: The Meaning of History (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1977), 11. 54 Friedrich Ast, Grundlinien der Grammatik, Hermeneutik und Kritik (Landshut, 1808), 165. Pages 165–212 reprinted in Gayle L. Ormiston and Alan D. Schrift, eds, The Hermeneutic Tradition: From Ast to Ricoeur (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1990), 39. 55 Georg Iggers argues that ‘essentially’ not ‘really’ is the more accurate word; see Peter Novick, That Noble Dream (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 28. 56 Ranke to Anton Richter, 13 April 1823, in Briefwork, 38, quoted in Leonard Krieger, Ranke: The Meaning of History (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1977), 10. 57 Peter Hanns Reill, The German Enlightenment and the Rise of Historicism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1975), 14. The Thirty Years War (1618–48), in particular, had produced an intellectual ‘civil war’ involving ‘natural law’, theological, and metaphysical philosophical combatants. See, for example, Ian Hunter, Rival Enlightenments: Civil and Metaphysical Philosophy in Early Modern Germany (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).

78 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

servant of many masters rose to be a master over them, and having become a law to itself

imposed it on others’.58 Not only were Geist and Kultur historical, but as Hegel had argued,

reason—the world’s transcendental reality—was itself historical, reason defined history.

History was the dialectical working-through of reason to the moment of reason’s final

realization as the totality of all truth—the ‘Absolute’ of all being.59 Wilhelm von Humboldt

explained how ‘There is actually no historical truth, neither in an account of a single fact nor

of a sequence of events if one does not descend to the invisible idea that is revealed in every

event’.60 In his seminal paper to the Prussian Academy in 1821, Humboldt told his audience

that ‘In its final, yet simplest solution the historian’s task is the presentation of the struggle of

an idea to realize itself in actuality’.61

II

The idea of active vital forces, and the importance of Geist and Kultur to the character of a

people were central to the intellectual and political spirit which saw the establishment of the

University of Berlin in 1809. By the end of the eighteenth century, the distinctively German

idea of culture that had emerged began to be seen, particularly in Prussia, as a central

component of political resistance to the French domination that had occurred in the

Napoleonic aftermath to the French Revolution. Humanity, in this cultural view, was not

everywhere the same; each culture marked the realization of its own distinct potential. As

Herder, Ranke and others had proclaimed, each culture was both related to all others and yet

unique and uniquely valuable (‘immediate to God’ was Ranke’s expression).62 This new

cultural-humanism emphasized that culture and the free development of the individual

58 Acton, “German Schools of History”: 7. 59 There was, however, a marked difference between the philosophy of history of the historians and Hegel’s philosophy of history. Each were critical of the other. See Herbert Schnädelbach, Philosophy in Germany 1831–1933, trans. Eric Matthews (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 40–47. 60 Wilhelm von Humboldt, Werke in fünf Bänden, ed. Andreas Flitner and Klaus Giel (Darmstadt: Cotta, 1981), 5, quoted in Rudolph Vierhaus, “Historiography between Science and Art”, in Leopold von Ranke and the Shaping of the Historical Discipline, eds Georg G. Iggers and James, M. Powell (New York: Syracuse University Press, 1990), 63 61 Wilhelm von Humboldt, “On the Historian’s Task”, History and Theory, 6, no. 1 (1967), 70. 62 Lionel Gossman, Basel in the Age of Burckhardt: A Study in Unseasonable Ideas (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2000), 252.

79 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

personality—Bildung—not economic and political power, were the way a people and nation

achieved greatness. In a letter written in 1791 to his friend, the political journalist Friedrich

Gentz, Wilhelm von Humboldt, echoing Hamann, expressed his conviction that a culture

which suppressed sensuality and failed to bring it into creative tension with reason could

never realize its highest possibilities. For while reason ‘gives direction’ to energy, Humboldt

wrote, ‘sensuality is the source of all vital energy’.63 The supreme social purpose should be

to make possible individual self-fulfillment through ‘inner development of [ones] capacities

and inclinations’.64

After Prussia’s devastating military defeat by Napoleon at Jena and Auerstädt, political

attention became focused on the development of the state as the political expression of

Prussian culture, and by that means to provide a defence against French hegemony. That

defence was provided through the development of the citizenry, and education was the

obvious means by which this strategy could be implemented. Consequently, Humboldt, as

Director of the Section for Ecclesiastical Affairs and Education in the Prussian Ministry of

the Interior from February 1809 to June 1810,65 was charged with the implementation of state

policy and, in David Sorkin’s words, ‘revamped the Prussian educational system in accord

with the neo-humanist conception of Bildung’.66

In the new Friedrich-Wilhelm University (University of Berlin)—established by

Humboldt and formally instituted by Prussian royal decree in 1809—Bildung was activated

through ‘freedom’, realised as Lehrfreiheit, the right to pursue and teach67 one’s competence,

63 Humboldt to Gentz, 1791, Historische Zeitschrift, 152 (1935), 52; Cited in Paul R Sweet, Wilhelm von Humboldt: A Biography (Columbus, Ohio, 1978–1981), I, 109–110, quoted in Lionel Gossman, Between History and Literature (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), 39. Also in Paul R. Sweet, “Young Wilhelm von Humboldt’s Writings (1789–93) Reconsidered”, Journal of the History of Ideas, 34, no. 3 (Jul.–Sep., 1973): 478 64 Wilhelm von Humboldt, Gesammelte Schriften (Berlin, 1903–36), I, 70, quoted in Paul R Sweet, Wilhelm von Humboldt: A Biography (Columbus, Ohio, 1978–1981), 471. 65 Humboldt’s title, translated, varies between sources. This one is from Walter Rüegg, “Themes”, in A History of the University in Europe, vol. 3, ed. Walter Rüegg (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 22. 66 David Sorkin, “Wilhelm von Humboldt: The Theory and Practice of Self-Formation (Bildung), 1791–1810”, Journal of the History of Ideas, 44, no. 1 (Jan.–Mar., 1983): 55. 67 Here ‘teach’ meant interchange in seminars of the professor’s experiences in the search for knowledge, not the transmission of a static body of knowledge. See Schnädelbach, Philosophy in

80 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

and Lernfreiheit, the right to choose what one studied, to choose one’s path to self-cultivation.

The mode of instruction was the seminar and interchange between student and specialist

based on a free spirit of inquiry, not the lecture and the transmission of approved information.

Thus, the fundamental principles on which the university was organized were academic

freedom, the unity of research and teaching, and the unity of knowledge.68 The roots of the

pedagogic philosophy were broad, but the philosophy was a synthesis of, in particular, the

writings of Schelling, Fichte (the first Rector), and Schleiermacher. Schleiermacher, who had

been forced out of the University of Halle after Napoleon’s invasion of Prussia, had joined

Humboldt and Fichte in Berlin for the planning of the new university. His liberal ideas

regarding the conduct of research and teaching were particularly influential.

For Schleiermacher, as for Humboldt and Fichte, it was the essence of things rather

than their external phenomena that was the point of investigation. Schleiermacher’s vision

was that university seminars would be where:

the scientific spirit, awakened by philosophical teaching, would penetrate more deeply into the particular, to research, combine, and create something of its own, and to confirm by the correctness of its judgement the insight it has gained into nature and the coherence of all knowledge.69

The professor as teacher, Schleiermacher wrote, ‘must not narrate what he knows, but rather

reproduce his own way to knowledge’. In this way students ‘should not only collect

knowledge. They should directly observe the activity of the intelligence producing

knowledge’, and in this way learn themselves how to do it.70

An essential element in the University of Berlin model was the importance, indeed

superiority, of the philosophical faculty in relation to the other faculties.71 However, the

Germany 1831–1933, 25–27. 68 See Jürgen Habermas, “The Idea of the University: Learning Processes”, New German Critique, 41 (1987): 3–22, 10–12; Thorsten Nyborn, “The Humboldt Legacy: Reflections on the Past, Present, and Future of the European University”, Higher Education Policy, 16 (2003): 144–146. 69 Rüegg, “Themes”, 14. 70 F. Schleiermacher, Gelegentliche Gedänken über Universitäten im deutschen Sinn. (Berlin, 1808), 63, quoted in Rüegg, “Themes”, 21. 71 Christophe Charle, “Patterns” in A History of the University in Europe, vol. 3, 48.

81 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

peculiar dynamism of the Berlin model was due, in Christophe Charle’s view, ‘probably’ to

the fact that it was ‘not shaped according to the idealistic rigour of a Fichte, but by the

liberalism of Schleiermacher and Humboldt’. For Schleiermacher, the university’s role was

practical. It was to:

awaken the idea of scholarship in noble-minded youths … to help them to a mastery of it in the particular field of knowledge to which they wish to devote themselves … and to see every individual thing not in isolation, but in its closest scholarly connections, relating it constantly to the unity and entirety of knowledge … thus they themselves acquire the ability to carry out research, to make discoveries, and to present these, gradually working things out in themselves. This is the business of a university.72

The idea of education developed in the University of Berlin was very different in its

conception from the English idea of ‘liberal education’ with its emphasis on behaviour rather

than learning, and on public leadership.73 But it was a view which was the epitome of the

modern concept of basic research. Through a fortunate coincidence of a distinctive

intellectual spirit and a distinctive political need, the ideal of knowledge for its own sake was

desired and valued by both researchers and funders. What was missing from this

arrangement, however, was the modern understanding of the conceptual differences between

types of research and types of development. German Idealism may have explored

epistemological limits and avoided intellectual superficiality, but without effective mediation

became irrelevant to practical life.

By 1841, when Schelling returned to the University of Berlin, orthodox (‘right-wing’)

Hegelianism had become increasingly remote from ‘real’ life. Schelling’s mission was to

revitalize the connection. ‘That is why I am here’, proclaimed Schelling, ‘for the salvation of

72 F. Schleiermacher, Gelegentliche Gedanken über die Universitäten Deutschen Sinn. Nebst einem Anhang über eine neu zu errichtende (Berlin, 1808), 22–3, quoted in Charle, ‘Patterns’, 48. But see also discussion by John Herkless where he argues that the relationship between academic freedom and national power, and their harmonization, were also central issues for Humboldt and Schleiermacher. John L. Herkless, “Economic Change and the Idealist Revival at the Turn of the Century”, History and Theory, 26, no. 2. (May, 1987): 178. 73 Sheldon Rothblatt and Björn Wittrock, “Introduction: universities and ‘higher education”, in The European and American University Since 1800: Historical and Sociological Essays, eds Sheldon Rothblatt and Björn Wittrock (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 11.

82 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

the Germans lies in systematic, philosophical knowledge’.74 But Schelling’s ‘positive

philosophy’ mix of mythology and revelation (of a personal God) missed the political mood,

expressed in Left Hegelianism, which saw philosophy’s role as social critique and social

action. Hegel’s unfolding of abstract reason now became the unfolding of a new, free,

German society. In that period of historical crisis, the new vehicle for systematic

philosophical knowledge was history. For German historians, politics and the ‘State’

represented the organic unity of Geist and Kultur. Kulturvolk had been replaced by

Kulturstaat. The new ‘realpolitisch’ ethos of the post-1848 Prussian Historical School

became orthodoxy and was to dominate German historical writing for almost a century. Even

Burkhardt, whom modern historians have seen as being the School’s only effective challenger

among German-speaking historians,75 shared Droysen’s conviction that history consisted of

the gradual unfolding of freedom, it was the form not the principle to which he objected; and

he denied that there was a ‘philosophy’ of history.76

Nevertheless, regardless of how deeply embedded German historiography became in

politics after 1848, its core remained intensely philosophical. Power existed in freedom;

power’s unfolding was the counterpart of freedom’s unfolding. Nation was the expression of

collective Geist and the empirical form of the unfolding of purpose/spirit. Nation as Geist

gave meaning to historical understanding. For Droysen, to understand history was to

combine the empirical and the spiritual. ‘In understanding’, Droysen wrote, ‘the entire

spiritual–sensuous nature of man is completely active, at the same time giving and taking,

producing and receiving’.77 Historical understanding was not about general laws, it was, he

said, ‘relating materials from the past as left in the present to the idea of some future spiritual

74 F. W. J. Schelling, Philosophie der Offenbarung, 1841–42, Manfred Frank, ed. (Frankfurt: 1977), 95, quoted in John Toews, Becoming Historical: Cultural Reformation and Public Memory in Early Nineteenth-Century Berlin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 4. 75 For example, Hugh Trevor-Roper and Lionel Gossman. See Hugh Trevor-Roper, “Jacob Burckhardt”, 361. See also Gossman, Basel in the Age of Burckhardt, 440–2, 444–51. Peter Ghosh argues that this view ‘framed in the 1940s and 1950s’, needs review. See Peter Ghosh, “Review” [of Gossman’s Basel in the Age of Burckhardt], History of European Ideas, 28, no. 4 (Dec., 2002): 299. 76 Georg G. Iggers, [Untitled Review], American Historical Review, 100, no. 3 (Jun., 1995): 915–916. 77 J. G. Droysen, Historik (Darmstadt, 1967), 26, quoted in Makkreel, [Review], op. cit., 356.

83 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

goal’.78 Research was the means to achieve this understanding.79 In his research, Droysen

sought to advance ontological understanding. And it was Droysen who first saw that it was

only Geisteswissenschaften (his term, but one made famous by Dilthey), not

Naturwissenschaften, which could provide meaning to understanding.

III

In the late eighteenth century and early nineteenth century, English-dominated Britain was a

very different society from Prussian-dominated Germany. The problems the two societies

were addressing were very different. The larger effects of industrialisation were yet to be felt

in Germany. In contrast, Britain dominated world trade and its government presided over the

largest empire in the history of mankind. In socially turbulent, industrially dynamic, Britain it

could no more be agreed what should constitute ‘universal knowledge’ than it could be agreed

what a ‘liberal education’ should mean. The working society, unlike Church and State, was

pluralist rather than elitist. The gifted mechanic, chemist, or instrument-maker was as highly

valued as the clever graduate. Science was as important as religion; and merit as important as

patronage—particularly with the introduction of written examination in the university. If, at

the beginning of the nineteenth century, research in Germany was mostly academic and

philosophical, in Britain research was outside the academy and mostly connected to science

and technology. The object of research was not transcendental knowledge from metaphysical

speculation, it was material advantage from scientific method.

Trade and commerce touched most people in Britain, unlike the university which

touched few. In 1820, the estimated first-year admissions to Oxford and Cambridge were

around 400 each when the total population of England and Wales was around thirteen million.

In contrast, by 1850, 47% of the total workforce worked in industry.80 Economic pragmatism

78 Makkreel, [Review], 356. 79 ‘Understanding through research’ he said; J. G. Droysen, Historik (Darmstadt, 1967), 22, quoted in Makreel, [Review], 355. 80 Lawrence Stone, “The Size and Composition of the Oxford Student Body 1580–1909”, in The University in Society, ed. Lawrence Stone, vol. 1, 6 (Graph 1); T. W. Heyck, The Transformation of Intellectual Life in Victorian England (London: Croom Helm, 1982), 28; Charles More, Understanding the Industrial Revolution (London: Routledge, 2000), 7.

84 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

was a way of life. To the Germans, the soul of British Kultur was ‘Manchesterpolitik’.

Treitschke remarked irritably how the English confused soap with civilization,81 and

complained of ‘the flood of Manchester theory, which washes away the moral values of

[British] life’.82 During the nineteenth century the public requirement of the academy was to

train intellectually and morally sound future leaders for an empire on which the sun never set.

The task for historians was not to advance epistemological and ontological understanding, but

to pursue explanation of how Britain came to be the leader of the civilized world. The

function of the academy was the liberal education of an elite, not research at the boundaries of

epistemological and ontological understanding.

For the first half of the nineteenth century, the universities of Oxford and Cambridge

were largely spectators to the transformation of intellectual life that was occurring in

England.83 In contrast to German historians, most English historians worked outside the

university and were not expected to hold academic chairs.84 The British understanding of

national identity was derived not from philosophy, as it was for the Germans, but from British

literature, from Britain’s libertarian political constitution, and from the society’s subtle

understanding of the multi-layered and interdependent nature of rights and duties—from

Government and society’s common, practical, understanding.

Oxford and Cambridge from the end of the eighteenth century until ‘the crisis of 1850–

60’ were under increasing criticism for the standard of their teaching and learning. The

examination system had been reformed progressively from the turn of the century, but

81 David Blackbourn and Geoff Eley, The Peculiarities of German History: Bourgeois Society and Politics in Nineteenth-Century Germany (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), 219. It was a point made also by Carlyle. 82 Heinrich von Treitschke, “Die Feuerprobe des Norddeutschen Bundes”, Preussische Jahrbücher, XXVI (1870), 249, quoted in Charles E. McClelland, The German Historians and England: A Study in Nineteenth-Century Views (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971), 180. 83 Most science was conducted outside the academy, and for every influential humanist inside the university, there were many more outside, for example: Carlyle, Ruskin, Macaulay, Dickens, Tennyson, Arnold, Eliot, Mill, Bentham, Huxley, et. al. 84 For example: Sharon Turner, Palgrave, Kemble, Milman, Thirlwall, Alison, Lingard, Hallam, Macaulay, Sir James Stephen, Stubbs (initially), Grote, Seebohm, as well as Acton, Montague Burrows, Green, who held chairs later in life. See Sir Llewellyn Woodward, ‘The Rise of the Professorial Historian in England’, 27–8.

85 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

increasingly the narrowness and relevance of their curricula and the purpose of that education

were being questioned. During the 1840s it became clear that if the universities did not

reform, then Parliament would compel them to. Benjamin Jowett in 1847 asked if it was

at all probable that we shall be allowed to remain as we are for twenty years longer, the one solitary, exclusive, unnational Corporation … a place, the studies of which belong to the past, and unfortunately seem to have no power of incorporating new branches of knowledge? 85

For history in the university, the problem was not so much one of reform but one of

legitimacy. There was widespread doubt that it was a subject worthy of university study. It

could not, it was felt, be considered dispassionately; it aroused prejudice. According to Tout,

Gladstone proposed to forbid its teaching in the planned new Irish university, ‘lest it should

excite theological or political controversy’.86 Also, it was thought to be too intellectually

undemanding. The point of the established literae humaniores subjects was not so much the

knowledge obtained through their study, though that had value, but the intellectual rigour and

mental agility their mastery required. They were difficult, and provided the type of mental

training and mental flexibility desirable for, and in, future members of the governing elite.

History, however, seemed to demand little more than memory; it would, some argued, ‘lure

the idle and the indolent from studies of greater severity and more lasting disciplinary

value’.87

Whatever the hesitation of the academic boards in the universities, the reading public

had always shown a strong interest in history. English historians, for whom Macaulay

represented the peak of readability, in their emphasis on prose style and accessibility, looked

more to the standards of the quality press—the reviews—than to the standards of the

specialist research community. Carlyle, Macaulay and Froude were particularly popular.

85 E. Abbot and L. Cambbell, eds, Life and Letters of Benjamin Jowett (London, 1897), vol. 1, letter to Roundell Palmer, 15 November 1847, 190, quoted in Peter H. Slee, Learning and a Liberal Education: The Study of Modern History in the Universities of Oxford, Cambridge and Manchester (Manchester: Manchester Unversity Press, 1986), 15–16. 86 Thomas Frederick Tout, The Collected Papers of Thomas Frederick Tout, vol. 1 (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1932), 94. Ireland was, though, a special case. 87 Thomas Arnold, Inaugural Lecture in the Study of Modern History, 2 December 1841 (Oxford, 1841), 4, quoted Slee, Learning and a Liberal Education, 20.

86 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

‘Historical mindedness’ grew alongside the strong and disturbing sense of the rapid,

comprehensive, change that was occurring; and of which one consequence was a loss of

belief in institutionalized religion.88 But it was very apparent that while Europe was

consumed by revolution, English institutions—the constitution, the system of representative

government—survived. In fact they flourished and were admired and envied by much of

Continental Europe. The process of British constitutional development was unique and

historical study appeared the obvious means to discover, thus to understand, its inherent

principles. History was political and moral. Its purpose, in Macaulay’s much-quoted phrase,

was to ‘supply statesmen with warnings and examples’.89 The story of how the constitution

had grown into its present state, the perils that had been faced, and the courage and wisdom

that had ensured its triumph, was a moral tale that ‘every young man should know’.90 The

purpose of English historical research was the transformation of British history from a

hearsay story of its kings to a source-based scholarly narrative of the institutions, processes,

and motivations that made Britain’s story the ‘success’ it so demonstrably seemed to be. And

that narrative was being produced from outside the academy more effectively than from

within.

Within the academy, as well as the problem of legitimacy, the profession was faced

with the question of professorial role. The transformation of intellectual life that was

occurring saw the emergence of claims, particularly from the 1830s and driven by the

scientific community, for professionalization and specialization. In the universities,

professors and tutors scrambled to define and secure careers. For English professors of

history, this meant securing recognition that professional, scientific, historical training was

needed, and that only they were qualified to provide it. For tutors, it meant the establishment

of a system of teaching that ensured students under their supervision achieved the finest

results in the university examinations—a preoccupation of students since the beginning of the

88 The latter typified by such widely discussed novels and poems as, for example, Tennyson’s In Memoriam A.H.H, Froude’s The Nemesis of Faith, Seeley’s Ecce Homo, Mrs Humphry Ward’s Robert Elsmere. 89 T. B. Macaulay, “On Mitford’s History of Greece” in The Miscellaneous Writings of Lord Macaulay, vol. 1 (London, 1860), 176. 90 Edinburgh Review, XV, 1809, 52, quoted Slee, Learning and a Liberal Education, 21.

87 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

century and which was to reach its peak in the latter half, to the chagrin of those who

abhorred the ‘machinery of cram’ that was its consequence.91 For the tutors, the teaching of

standards of thought and behaviour prevailed over the interests of single subjects.92 Only

later in the century, did colleges emphasise particular disciplinary strengths. Jowett had been

one of the first masters to send students of his college to the best tutors, regardless of college.

In the battle for hearts and minds waged between history professors and tutors, those

promising success in examinations were invincible when matched against an opponent who

could only offer the personal satisfaction of research using original documents and

specialized techniques.93 And that for a discipline that offered few career opportunities.

Even as late as 1910 Tout was complaining of the lack of ‘training in medieval technique’ in

the staff of the Public Record Office, that they were ‘appointed from the successful

candidates of the ordinary Civil Service examination, and are only historians by accident’.94

Professors were faced with a dilemma. Their mandate was to lecture and research.

However, if they wanted anyone to attend those lectures, the lectures needed to be

‘interesting’ rather than, necessarily, scholarly or erudite. As lectures, their pedagogical

mode was transmission of established knowledge, not exploration and interchange as

exemplified by the German research seminar. And if research was to have any instrumental

value, a requirement of Manchesterpolitik, then research meant preparing material that could

be used for the training of others in research techniques. The result for the institutionalized

profession was a prioritization of the accessible over the recondite, and the technical over the

theoretical. Professorial research was primarily a means to professional training, the teaching

of the research craft rather than epistemological and ontological discovery. Discovery was

for others.95

91 Pattison Memoirs, 89. 92 Reba Soffer, Discipline and Power: The University, History, and Making of an English Elite, 1870–1930 (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1994), 78–9. 93 This is not to imply that tutors didn’t recognize, value, or practice scholarship. 94 Tout, The Collected Papers, 84. 95 Firth in his inaugural lecture at Oxford in 1904 declared that: ‘if the study of history means an endeavour to add to this common inheritance of knowledge, surely the teaching of history means an endeavour to train men capable of adding to knowledge? This, at all events is the principle upon which I base my conception of my duty here.’ C. H. Firth, A Plea for the Historical Teaching of History: an

88 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

In drawing a distinction between tutors (‘lecturers’) and professors, the Cambridge

Royal Commission emphasised the catechetical method of the former, implying active

interchange, with the passive receptivity of the professorial ‘lecture’.96 It was not until the

beginning of the twentieth-century, when Bury, Tout and Firth tried to define anew the

relationship between research and the professorial function that the question of advancing

knowledge was addressed. Even then, because of the English empiricist ideology and

antipathy to the philosophical treatment of the problems of history, knowledge was conflated

with facts and causation in the phenomenal world. Advancing knowledge meant finding new

facts about that world and then explaining their teleological significance. Ontological and

epistemological understanding was unproblematic. Research was about new information

enabling improved explanation.

Consequently, in England, arguments in the university regarding research within the

history discipline were mainly practical in nature: how it was to be organised, who it should

be done by, how it should be examined. The exemplary and much lauded Manchester

university history research school lead by Tout achieved its prominence because it achieved

administratively and professionally what the professors had been arguing for. Tout, like

Firth, had the appetite, the stamina, and the resilience to fight the political, administrative

battles. But Tout in Manchester, unlike Firth in Oxford, did not have the ‘big guns’ of the

colleges, with their wealth and influence and numbers, firing at him; on the contrary, he had a

‘green-field’ site and the delegated authority to build on it.97 He, unlike Firth, was successful

in establishing an acclaimed research school.

Inaugural Lecture delivered on November 9th 1904 (Oxford, 1904), 11. Quoted Slee, Learning and a Liberal Education, 129–30. 96 Cambridge University Commission Report of Her Majesty’s Commissioners Appointed to Inquire into The State, Discipline, Studies, and Revenues of the University and Colleges of Cambridge Together with the Evidence and an Appendix Presented to both Houses of Parliament by Command of Her Majesty (London: HMSO, 1852), 81. 97 In his presidential address to the medieval section of the International Historical Congress at London in 1913, Tout explained why Stubbs had failed to establish a research ‘school’: ‘The traditions of English individualism, the forces of the ‘college system’, the cast iron of the great examination machine, repelled him from even entering the conflict’, Tout said. T. F. Tout, “The Present State of Mediaeval Studies in Great Britain”, in Proceedings of the British Academy 1913–1914 (London: Oxford University Press, 1915), 153–54

89 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

But in that school, the advancement of knowledge meant the provision of better

validated and ordered source material—as Tout said: the depositing of another ‘humble brick

in the mighty edifice of learning’ which research was constructing.98 In a presidential address

to the 1913 International Historical Congress in London, Tout argued passionately that the

point of the research was to enable the production of ‘a critical edition of our early laws’ and

to be able to ‘edit all our own chronicles and records’.99 But he never explained what basic

research purpose those research products served. In an earlier article he had argued that the

research ideal in history was the same as that of ‘physics and chemistry’, and that in the

‘historical ‘laboratory’ … our methods, then, must necessarily be the methods of the

observational sciences … the study of history should be largely a study of processes and

method’.100

Powicke in his obituary to Tout, tried to introduce a more philosophical theme to

Tout’s vision. The ‘spirit in which they were written’, Powicke wrote, was this:

He was concerned to understand the methods of mediaeval government, and to adjust the generalizations of the constitutional historian to the salutary experience of men, great men and little men, ministers of state and clerks living their lives of routine among associations now forgotten … [he] tried to work out in detail the interplay, from year to year, of administration and policy.101

Though not intended to be, it was faint praise. It was still unexplained how that wider

knowledge of the past was anything more than technically proficient antiquarianism. By

itself it was not basic research in the epistemological and ontological sense; in the way that

Germans such as Schleiermacher, Humboldt, Niebuhr, Ranke, Droysen and Burkhardt saw

research.

IV

98 Tout, The Collected Papers, 108. 99 Tout, “The Present State of Mediaeval Studies in Great Britain”, 163. 100 Tout, The Collected Papers, 79, 80. 101 F. M. Powicke, ‘Thomas Frederick Tout: 1855 – 1929’, in Proceedings of the British Academy, 1929 (London: Oxford University Press), 517.

90 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

The research benchmark for English academic history had been set by Stubbs at Oxford in the

second half of the nineteenth-century. Stubbs, Regius Professor at Oxford from 1866 to 1884

(and later to become Bishop of Chester, and of Oxford), was recognized internationally for his

scholarship, but for him, like his fellow High Churchman Pusey, theoretical reflection was

irrelevant to scholarship; religion and the archives provided all that was required.102 ‘I desire

to introduce myself to you’ he had remarked in his inaugural lecture of 1867, ‘not as a

philosopher nor as a politician, but as a worker at history.’ History, he said, was ‘the ebb and

flow of human progress … the leading on by the divine light … [we must] believe and trust

that the victory of light and truth is drawing nearer every day’.103 This was religion of a

different sort to the spiritual intuition of Ranke and Schleiermacher. It produced a history

which, in Reba Soffer’s rather merciless judgement, was ‘essentially a theodicy in which

moral forces triumphed over the immoral’, and which ‘was not only didactic, but mindlessly

complacent’.104 Maitland, with his characteristic poise and warmth, provided a more

forgiving, but no less critical, judgement:

He loved the concrete, and was not happy among abstractions of a high order, such as a contrast between ‘rights, forces, and ideas.’ We think how Seeley’s agile mind would have played round, and perhaps played with, such a theme.105

Seeley’s agile mind had, indeed, played round with ideas, though it was disciplinary

direction, not ontological understanding that he saw as the challenge. It was to understand

that the discipline’s purpose was not constitutional law, nor ‘great men’ biography, nor social

commentary, but to ‘exhibit the general tendency of English affairs in such a way as to set us

102 Mark Pattison noted the hostility towards German scholarship in Oxford in the mid- nineteenth-century; he referred to ‘Dr. Pusey’s’ extreme irritation with ‘the mental activity prevailing in the German universities’ and complaining of, in Pusey’s words, their ‘theories which pull to pieces what has been received for thousands of years[italics in original]. Mark Pattison, Memoirs, 79–80. 103 William Stubbs, “On the Purposes and Methods of Historical Study 9 May 15, 1877)”, in William Stubbs, Seventeen Lectures on the Study of Medieval and Modern History and Kindred Subjects: Delivered at Oxford, Under Statutory Obligation in the Years 1867–1884 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1887), 85. 104 Reba Soffer, “Nation, Duty, Character and Confidence: History at Oxford, 1850–1914”, Historical Journal, 30, no. 1 (Mar., 1987): 91–2. 105 F. W. Maitland, “William Stubbs, Bishop of Oxford”, English Historical Review, 16, no. 63. (July, 1901): 425.

91 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

thinking about the future and divining the destiny which is reserved for us’.106 The state was

the vital subject of contemplation, but not as Geist and ontology, rather, as the empirical

entity from which the causal ‘laws by which states rise, expand and prosper or fall in this

world’ may be determined.107 Its philosophical core was firmly Naturwissenschaften, in the

inductive-science manner of Comte and Mill, not Geisteswissenschaften in the idealistic and

hermeneutic manner of Hegel and Droysen. It was, however, a challenge not widely accepted

by his colleagues—though, it did generate strong political and public interest, and his system

of ideas and analytical method did strongly influence subsequent imperial scholarship.

Firth at Oxford, Acton and then Bury (and Maitland) at Cambridge, also left distinctive

and different legacies. Maitland’s was a subtle, quietly philosophical, legacy which

illuminated, through his scholarly work in legal intellectual history, the deeply conceptual

nature of historical inquiry. He exerted great influence in the field of legal history, but on the

larger discipline, other than set an exemplary standard of scholarship, he had little effect—not

that influence was something Maitland sought.108

Of the Regius Professors, it was only Bury who worried philosophically about history’s

mission and methodology. He understood, he said, that history was not a ‘higher zoology’,

that fact-gathering was not an end in itself—not that colleagues such as Acton, Seeley,

Maitland, or Firth could be accused of that assumption—but found it difficult to reconcile his

intuitive notion of history as Geisteswissenschaften with his firm belief that facts came first:

that principles must not be ‘superimposed upon the phenomena’, but be ‘given by the

phenomena’.109

At his inaugural lecture, Bury had sought to promote history as science, but one year

later acknowledged Geist to be essential to historical research:

106 J. R. Seeley, The Expansion of England (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1971), 7. 107 Ibid., 11, 107. 108 See discussion below. 109 J. Bury, “The Place of Modern History in the Perspective of Knowledge (1904)”, in Selected Essays of J. B. Bury, ed. Harold Temperley (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1930), 48.

92 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

The interpretation of history that shall be more than a collection of plausible labels must grasp the vital process, perceive the breath and motion, detect the undercurrents, trace the windings, discern the foreshadowings, see the ideas travelling underground, discover how the spiritual forces are poised and aimed, determine how the motives conspire and interact … history as a disclosure of the evolution of thought has an independent realm of its own and demands a distinct interpretation, to prepare for which is the aim of historical research.110

It could have been Humboldt, or Ranke, or Burckhardt speaking, but Bury’s motivation

remained, primarily, deeper rational understanding, not deeper holistic (intuitive/rational)

understanding.

Despite Bury’s idealistic counsel, British historiography remained firmly literary and

moralistic—though it had other critics. In an unpublished address, with Macaulay and Froude

in mind, York Powell observed that:

Unfortunately, history is frequently written as a party pamphlet or as a treatise on morality; but the proper view is to treat history as an accumulation or assemblage of facts respecting humanity en masse, and not respecting single individuals. Literature, on the other hand, is concerned with the expression of human emotions in an artistic manner. A history may, of course, be a model of exposition, but that is not its true raison d’être. Such histories are usually untrustworthy and should be read for their style and not for their history. Darwin’s excellent faculty of exposition is an advantage, but it is not the end of his works.111

But York Powell, despite ‘his vast knowledge and his ready, many-sided brain’,112

never was able to say what he thought the raison d’être of an accumulation of facts was.

Science’s raison d’être seemed clearer to York Powell than history’s. Three years later he

stated his view that as history was ‘a scientific pursuit … a branch of anthropologic science’,

then ‘philosophy of history’ was the search for some form of predictive understanding, which,

110 Ibid., 52, 59. 111Oliver Elton, Frederick York Powell: A Life and a Selection from his Letters and Occasional Writings, Vol. 1 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1906), 409. Like Bury, York Powell was interested in creativity and artistic expression. 112 Charles Oman, Inaugural Lecture on the Study of History (London: Methuen & Co. 1939), 13.

93 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

ultimately, must ‘remain insoluble by the legitimate processes of history’.113 York Powell

could describe history’s form, but not its purpose. Unlike Droysen, he had not perceived the

methodological distinction between explanation and understanding; that history required both

empirical evidence and hermeneutical understanding. But that is not surprising. In Germany,

hermeneutic theory had been intrinsic to academic religious and classical scholarship since

the Reformation; in Britain, there was an academic tradition of religious and classical

exegesis, but not hermeneutics.

Maitland, who had a high regard for German scholarship, had always understood,

working as he did in legal history, that historical research was interpretive and conceptual.

But Maitland too, like York Powell and Bury, could not escape the British positivist episteme.

In 1890, when reading Otto Gierke’s Political Theories of the Middle Age, he had complained

that ‘Gierke’s great book … is a splendid thing though G. is too metaphysical’.114 But the

more he looked into English legal understandings of such notions as ‘the State’ and the

‘Corporation’, or ‘the Crown as corporation’ (‘the king is dead, long live the king!’), for

example, the more he saw that behind them lay—unarticulated and undefined—the

metaphysical notions of matter, form, agency, and purpose that had long preoccupied the

Germans. But England, he realized, unlike Germany, lacked the conceptual framework to

link the ontological with the practical.115

In 1900, while translating Gierke’s book for British publication, Maitland had

commented to Henry Sidgwick that

I shiver on the brink of an Introduction … T. H. Green and his disciples have not properly prepared the British public for a vast number of ‘general wills, or I should like to say, ‘group-wills’; but if they stop short at giving the State (or more vaguely ‘the Community’) a ‘real’ will, surely they make philosophic shipwreck. Every community, though it be a ‘one-man

113 Frederick York Powell, “Preface”, Ch. V. Langlois and Ch. Seignobos, Introduction to the Study of History (London: Duckworth & Co., 1898), vi, xii, xiii. 114 Letter to Frederick Pollock, 18 October 1890, The Letters of Frederic William Maitland, ed. C. H. S. Fifoot (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965), 86. 115 Frederic William Maitland, “Translator’s Introduction”, in Dr. Otto Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle Age (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1900), for example, vii–xii, xv– xviii.

94 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

company’, must have its group-will … All this means that, were I in Cambridge, I should plague you with questions. There are a lot of very interesting ‘juristic’ theories going around—in America the conflict has practical consequences—and, so it seems to me, the choice must lie with the philosopher who will tell us what is real.116

Fortunately for Maitland, he didn’t become ensnared in Green’s and Sidgwick’s distinctively

English ethical reworking of Hegelian and Kantian thought. Those speculations would have

been of little help to his quest. It was better understanding of common understanding that

Maitland sought, not metaphysical speculation. Applied research, not basic research, was the

means to the end he sought.

V

During the nineteenth century, British scholarship made no original contribution to

speculation about the nature and scope of historical knowledge and, despite Bury’s sustained

epistemological probing, did not until Collingwood.117 In England, history professors, in their

renewed efforts to overcome academic scepticism regarding modern history’s intellectual

legitimacy as a university discipline, sought to emphasise research credentials and used the

German model as their reference for research practice. They sought to demonstrate specialist

knowledge, and by that means justify the discipline’s position in the academy. The research

emphasis was on technical craftsmanship—the learning of a research trade and the hard-won

knowledge that accreted through familiarity with sources. However, the motivation and

context for German historical research was opposite from that of English historical research.

German historical research resulted from idealist inquiry into knowledge of ‘being’.118

German historical research was a means to deeper epistemological and ontological

understanding of Geist and Kultur. It was driven by the instinctive, irrational, desire to know

more profoundly. German research was basic research from which intellectual discovery

116 Letter to Henry Sidgwick, 22 January 1900, The Letters of Frederic William Maitland, 209. The issue in America was that of the authority and ‘rights’ of the financially aggressive and predatory private corporations. 117 See Doris S. Goldstein, “J. B. Bury’s Philosophy of History: A Reappraisal”, American Historical Review, 82, no. 4 (Oct., 1977): 896. 118 In Göttingen, scientific method was favoured. See , Man on His Past (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1955), 39–42.

95 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

came. In contrast, English historical research resulted from the conviction that history was

both practical and morally uplifting, and that causal connections could be found that would be

useful to both society and government. English historical research was the means to a more

professional narrative of British political, institutional, and social evolution. English research

was applied research whose purpose was to aid scholarship.

In Germany, by the end of the nineteenth century, understanding itself had become

historicized. The conception of understanding as a process meant that there was no longer

even a methodological gap between history, hermeneutics and ‘research-science’.119 The

work of academics such as Wundt, Simmel, Droysen, Burkhardt, Dilthey, Windelband and

Weber effectively combined history, epistemology, psychology and social psychology.

Aesthetic and cultural critique were as important to historical understanding as history and

epistemology—and aesthetic and cultural critique needed historical and psychological

understanding. Mythology, archaeology, philology, anthropology, philosophy, psychology

and history were interdependent modes of inquiry used to advance knowledge of knowledge.

In England, disciplinary history was alienated from cultural and aesthetic critique.

Exploration of the conceptual and abstract was part of the literary discussion of art, culture

and taste. The justification of knowledge for its own sake derived from the literary

imagination of British Romanticism, not from public notions of national development. In

Britain, knowledge of knowledge became the province of an aestheticism which sought

disengagement from the values of the utilitarian, industrial, society that history sought to

explain and justify. The spirit of English conceptual inquiry was typified by the complex

Victorian Hellenism of such scholars such as Pater, Arnold, and Ruskin—just as the spirit of

German inquiry had been typified in the German Hellenism of such scholars as Herder,

Winckelmann and Boeckh. In Pater’s The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry, the one

modern discussed is Winckelmann who, for Pater, exemplified the ‘spirit’ of ‘enthusiasm for

the things of the intellect and the imagination for their own sake’.120

119 Schnädelbach, Philosophy in Germany: 1833–1933, 112. 120 Walter Pater, The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry, The 1893 Text (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), xxiv. The Victorian engagement with Hellenism was complex. See, for example, David DeLaura, Hebrew and Hellene in Victorian England: Newman, Arnold, Pater

96 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

History in the English academy was never seen as a means to deeper existential

understanding. History’s main purpose was didactic, and academic research’s main

justification was pedagogic. By concentrating on history’s form, and research’s method,

attention was diverted from the question of the epistemological purpose of historical research

and the ontological function of historical narrative. In Australia, with its different cultural

settings and pedagogic traditions, history’s ontological function came into clearer focus. But

research’s purpose as research, remained unexamined.

Discovery Under Different Skies

Whereas in England the translation of the German professional history research model had

elided its philosophical core and institutionalized research in purely methodological terms, in

Australia the translation of the derived English model elided the matter of the actual research

product and institutionalized research in terms of accreditation. The research product did not,

necessarily, have to demonstrate arcane knowledge and specialist technique—such as that

which Stubbs at Oxford and Tout at Manchester had accomplished—it should simply be

something that was published. The fact of publication, assuming a reputable imprint,

signified the required research competence. Research credentials were what was required for

professorial selection to the colonial academy in order to assure, and reassure, the ‘colonials’

that ‘antipodean’ was purely a relational term signifying geography, and not a metaphorical

one signifying academic standards.

But history in the Australian academy could never finally be history as it was in Oxford

or Cambridge, no matter how hard anyone tried to make it so. Any institution in Australia, if

it was ultimately to flourish and develop and have real social value, would need to adapt and

reflect the actual, not imagined, soil from which it grew; and even conscious imitation

(Austin: University of Texas Press, 1969); Frank Turner, The Greek Heritage in Victorian Britain (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1981). For Pater’s close connection to mysticism and the new ‘human sciences’ pioneered by the Germans, see Linda Dowling, “Walter Pater and Archaeology: The Reconciliation with Earth”, Victorian Studies, 31, no. 2 (Winter, 1988): 209–231.

97 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

produces change. British history, though shared, could not be seen with the same eyes.

Expatriate Britons could never know, what it felt like to be an Australian ‘vulgar’ in Oxford—

thus, how a ‘native-born’ Australian would ‘read’ the British historical narrative. Just as

native-born Australians could never know what it felt like to one from the centre now living at

a new, raw, periphery. Nevertheless, from its inception,121 the teaching of history in the

Australian academy was British. The history that was taught was the history taught at Oxford

and Cambridge. That history was considered essential to a liberal education, and through a

liberal education the new ‘currency’ elite could gain knowledge of the civilized world and of

the way the civilized world thought and acted.122 Such a framework did provide intelligibility

and coherence for almost eighty years, since, as seemed self-evident, Australia’s history was

the history of Britain and the British in Australia. The raising of awareness, not discovery,

was the main goal. But the light was different here, and one saw differently.

Nevertheless, for many years, historians in Australia were never much concerned with

interrogating the purpose and function of the discipline, and even when they did, there was

more than enough work to be done just establishing the discipline and securing its sources

and resources. Further distracting them from disciplinary self-reflection was, with the rise of

a national culture and the establishment of the nation-state, the discovery of Australian and

colonial history as rich fields of their own, with their sources as yet unordered and unexplored

(‘enormous and unsifted’ was George Arnold Wood’s description),123 but requiring

incorporation into the public record as quickly as possible. If working with original sources

was the core of research activity, as they had been told, then ordering the national documents

into a scholarly narrative of the ‘the Australian story’ was research’s clear purpose.

Ultimately, however, such history risked losing a ‘serious’ purpose. It appeared that

way to the Australian historian . In a reflective article in 1962 he wrote that

121 With W. E. Hearn at the University of Melbourne in 1855. 122 ‘’Currency’ lads and lasses’ was the ambivalent term used by the British-born to describe the local-born. 123 Wood to James Tait, 9 May 1924, quoted in R. M. Crawford, ‘A Bit of a Rebel’: The Life and Work of George Arnold Wood (Sydney: Sydney University Press, 1975), 356. Wood was then the Challis Professor of History at the .

98 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

‘Academic history seemed all too often to be supremely efficient in ascertaining facts and

ineffective in using them for any serious purpose’.124 He had told his students that if the

historian is ‘to offer any explanations of the problems intelligent people want to solve’, then it

is more than just the story of ‘Lilliputian governors’ that those people desire.125 His search

‘for a legitimate history’ led him, he said, to ’s ‘sense of a history that might help

one, not only to know, but to understand’.126 It was an issue that would receive intense

debate when another Australian historian, Manning Clark began to publish his magisterial but

controversial six-volume work: A History of Australia. Clark’s was messianic history. Early

historians of Australia , Clark wrote, had not understood the proper ‘ends’ of their task; they

‘had not observed the dictum that the whole point of telling the truth about the past was to

help the people dispense with the past’. They had not challenged the myth of our derivative,

British, past. ‘They had not essayed the task of writing the history of that Australia which

was coming to be.’127 For Clark, like the Prussian nationalist historians such as Trietschke,

history should shape as well as describe. The historian had a role as prophet.128

In England, with its social and institutional robustness and common-sense-confidence,

the question of history’s spiritual function and focus could remain somewhat peripheral to

academic practice—despite the perennial history-as-science-or-art argument, which was

mainly an argument over form. In England, form, content, and function remained aligned to

personal style. But in Australia, the question of history’s purpose and focus—Whose past?

What past?—became more problematical. For there is an anxiety which is real, even if its

cause is imagined, induced by being thought of as ‘peripheral’ to the civilised world’s

‘centre’—being thought of as derivative and culturally ‘thin’. In Australia, with this

subterranean current of existential anxiety, ‘spirit of place’ and symbolic meaning became

124 R. M. Crawford, “The School of Prudence, or Inaccuracy and Incoherence in Describing Chaos”, Historical Studies, 15, no. 57 (Oct., 1971): 31. 125 R. M. Crawford, “Theory Method Folder (sic)”, Crawford Papers, University of Melbourne Archives, Box 38. 126 Crawford, “The School of Prudence”: 28, 29. 127 C. M. H. Clark, A History of Australia, vol. 5, 137–8. 128 See Charles E. McClelland, The German Historians and England: A Study in Nineteenth- Century Views (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971), 236.

99 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

central to the elucidation of the national Geist and national Kultur. The questions: Who are

we? What is Australia? Where do we belong? were questions deeply embedded in local

webs of meaning and collective sensitivities. The question of what should be academic

history’s deeper purpose in Australia was not easily answered. In exploring the country’s

cultural meaning and existential anxieties, literature and poetry were being used just as

effectively as vehicles for understanding. For Australian-history (as distinct from history in

Australia) the boundaries between literature and history were amorphous when historians

tried to capture that existential edge, that special ‘consciousness’.

With any national or ethnic history, that history can only be explained adequately

through both material and psychological terms—through Kultur and Geist. In Australian

cultural memory, such notions as loss, dislocation, failure, trust, distance, ‘home’ have an

inflection that is both local and existential. Niebuhr, Ranke, Droysen and Burckhardt had

always understood that if understanding was the purpose of historical inquiry, then it was the

spirit and cultural consciousness of the people or site under investigation which was the

research focus—that the material facts were merely the phenomenal manifestation of the

Kultur’s animating spirit and consciousness. Thus, certain truths are better told by artists than

technicians, for it is as much through image and metaphor as factual terms that the ‘psychic

currency’ within a community is understood. For Australians, the psychological effect of

light and landscape, or the connotative impact of the words ‘convict’, ‘bush’, or ‘England’,

are not simply explained. But historiography without them is mere antiquarianism or arid

scholarship. ‘If a poetical work unites content and pure form’, said Ranke, ‘everybody is

satisfied’.129 The power and influence of both Keith Hancock’s Australia, though written as a

history, and ’s The Legend of the Nineties, though written as cultural criticism,

derived from their capture of an authentic, deep, Australian ‘spirit’. Max Crawford

throughout his Knaplund Lectures at the University of Wisconsin used selections from

Australian poets to capture and convey essential Australian perspectives. He concluded his

129 Leopold von Ranke, taken from Ranke’s “Analecta” to the Französische Geschichte, vornehmlich im sechzehnten und siebzehnten Jahrhundert, quoted in Rudolph Vierhaus, “Historiography between Science and Art”, in Leopold von Ranke and the Shaping of the Historical Discipline, eds Georg G. Iggers and James and M. Powell, 61.

100 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

lectures with two verses from James McAuley’s poem ‘Terra Australis’.130 Poetry captured

that Australian ‘lived experience’; and it was only ‘lived experience, as Dilthey saw, that

could connect emotion to reason and transform mere explanatory understanding into meaning

and understanding that was visceral.

However, as the Australian experience was to show, this subjective, literary, element

introduced a danger. Unless there was a rigorous understanding of, or at least agreement on,

the theoretical and philosophical foundations on which historical knowledge and historical

understanding were based, then incorporation of spiritual intuitions will cause confusion

regarding the form and purpose of history, and consequently confusion over the substance of

historical research.

For Manning Clark and Max Crawford, knowledge through poetic understanding

(feeling and intuition) and understanding as ontological insight were central to history’s

meaning and purpose, and for both historians, history’s literary foundations were central to

history’s larger function. ‘Neglect of the art of narrative or even blindness to the existence of

such an art’ is as much a danger as its opposite, Crawford had concluded; but was unclear

how the dangers could be mitigated. The selection of an appropriate interpretive framework

was a dilemma: to operate without a framework was to choose ‘inaccuracy and incoherence

in describing chaos’, but to operate within an unsound one was ‘to choose intelligibility and

coherence in describing a myth, and then to baptize the myth as history’.131

But for Clark, the literary imagination was primary to history’s effectiveness; history

and literature were one. To be great history, history had to be great literature. In a lecture in

1954 Clark had declared that ‘to be great as literature—the aim of all historians—it must be

written by someone … who has pondered deeply over the problems of life and death.132

Writing in 1990, a year before his death in 1991, he re-iterated that history should be about

130 R. M. Crawford, An Australian Perspective (Madison: The University of Wisconsin Press, 1960), 76 131 J. H. Hexter, Reappraisals in History (London, 1961), 14, quoted in Crawford, “The School of Prudence”, 42. 132 Manning Clark, “Rewriting Australian History”, in Manning Clark, Occasional Writings and Speeches (Melbourne: Fontana Books; 1980), 19.

101 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

those deeper, more profound, emotional and psychological forces that shape the ‘human

heart’ and society:

The story of the past should have the effect of all great stories. It should increase wisdom and understanding. It should make the reader aware of what previously he had seen ‘through a glass darkly’. It should turn the mind of the reader towards the things that matter. It must bring the reader to the frontier where music takes over from words.133

His six-volume A History of Australia was true to his espoused philosophy, and all six

volumes attracted strongly divided opinion on their merit as history. Many critics declared it

worthless as history. For one it was ‘history without facts’,134 for another it was bereft of

‘objective historical truth’ and was purely Clark’s ‘preconceived vision which he wished his

fellow Australians to absorb’.135 But it also had many supporters. One historian felt that

‘Clark’s great achievement was to imagine Australia … so well he helped us all to do it’.136

A literary critic wrote that Clark’s prose ‘soars, not with the coloured phrases of the novelist

[a pejorative phrase of the vitriolic critic, Peter Ryan] but with the attempt to generalise, and

in generalising to imagine, one deeply felt, highly contestable, truth about his country’.137

The controversy made evident the fact that the question of what history was for, could be no

more easily agreed than what history was. What knowledge of the past were Australians

seeking? What ‘truth’ did they seek? What was to be discovered?

Clark was unwavering in his view that it was from the subjective exploration of the

‘mystery at the heart of things’ that meaningful truth would be discovered. The type of truth

determined the type of evidence—an expression in a portrait; the ‘spirit’ of a landscape. For

Clark, like Ranke, the most subjective was at the same time the most general truth. Truth was

133 Manning Clark, A Historian’s Apprenticeship (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1992), 9. 134 M. H. Ellis, “History without Facts”, Bulletin, 22 September 1962, 36–7, in Manning Clark: Essays on his Place in History, ed. Carl Bridge (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1994), 70. 135 Ryan, Peter, “A Reply to my Critics”, Quadrant, 37, no. 10 (1993): 11, and Ryan, Peter, “Manning Clark”, Quadrant, 37, no. 9 (1993): 11. 136 Weekend Australian, 28–9 August 1993, quoted in Peter Craven, “The Ryan Affair”, in Manning Clark: Essays on his Place in History, ed. Carl Bridge (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1994), 179. The historian was . 137 Peter Craven, “The Ryan Affair”, 178.

102 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

not found by logic, it was apprehended. It was the artist’s truth, truth about ‘life’, not the

scientist’s truth. For Clark, the ‘measurers’ and ‘engineers of the human soul’—such as the

Marxist historians—were the ones ‘who would silence the uproar, the clatter of life, the

collision of mighty opposites; the ones who wanted to substitute a superficial certainty for a

profound doubt’. As would the social scientist historians, who were ‘distinguished by their

shallow and perfunctory treatment of the problem of human evil’. ‘There had been an earlier

attempt’, he said, ‘to write a textbook history—which would be very ‘yes and no’ in the

accepted textbook style, and very dull. But that sort of truth was not within me. Now I

wanted to write history as a story—history as an art’.138 Imagination and subjectivity were to

be as important as empiricism in mining the past; and even Clark’s most vituperative critic,

Peter Ryan, acknowledged that Clark had a subtle and cultivated mind.

Max Crawford, also, had retreated from ‘measured’ history. By the end of 1958, when

he gave his Knaplund lectures, Crawford was reaching towards what Robert Dare has

described as his ‘getting of wisdom’. According to Dare, Crawford had concluded some

years earlier that the historian’s intellectual modes were intuitive rather than syllogistic and

that thinking historically is, to quote Crawford, ‘a training in seeing things as they really

were’, which is ‘inevitably and inescapably a training in moral sensitivity’.139 Crawford had

concluded that a historian needed to see beyond facts to the significance given to the facts by

human values; human values transcended reason and included, amongst other things,

empathetic understanding and an intuition of transcendental moral values.

The issue that remained unexplored, however, was the relationship of history to the

academy. Was academic research needed for writers to produce (Clark’s) history as art, or

(Crawford’s) history as training in moral ‘sentiment’? Conversely, was historical research

needed for the academy’s larger research mission of advancing epistemological and

ontological understanding? Alternatively, was history in the academy primarily for research

138 Clark, A Historian’s Apprenticeship, 4, 5, 19. 139 R. M. Crawford untitled lecture of 1949, Crawford Papers, University of Melbourne Archives, Box 38, quoted in Robert Dare, ‘Crawford on theory and methods of History’, in Max Crawford’s School of History, eds Stuart Macintyre and Peter McPhee (Parkville: History Department, The University of Melbourne, 2000), 37.

103 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

purposes, or purely for purposes of liberal education with research its disciplinary

complement? The questions were never asked, since it was assumed, it seemed, that history

was a form of coherent knowledge whose function was edification and instruction.

II

The incumbent of the first (solely) history chair in Australia, the Challis Professor of History

at the University of Sydney, was the Balliol-trained Englishmen, George Arnold Wood.140 A.

L. Smith, Wood’s Balliol tutor, had described the young Wood as the typical Manchester

product ‘dyed in the wool with Puritan nonconformity, Cobdenism, Gladstonianism,

Liberalism, the humanitarian ideals of John Bright and the political philosophy of John

Morley.141 In his inaugural lecture in 1891 Wood had expressed his conviction that the best

historical writing ‘of to-day’ was scientific in method, sympathetic in spirit, and utilitarian in

motive. But by utilitarian, Wood did not mean material utility. The scientific method would

teach a student to think ‘clearly’, but the sympathetic spirit would enable the historian to

‘teach’ what is more important: ‘to feel strongly, and to feel rightly’.142 ‘We should enlarge

our conception of the study of History,’ he said, from the endless reading of works of

‘historical artisans’ (he was referring to Stubbs and Freeman); that was not the purpose of a

school.143 After his death, in 1928, a colleague described him as ‘a good deal of a

Fransciscan, a humanized puritan’.144

Wood’s assumption of a moral imperative metamorphosed in Crawford into the

assumption that moral sensitivity was history’s transcendent purpose (Crawford had been

taught by Wood, and Wood had sent Crawford to Balliol). But for Wood, unlike Crawford,

the nature of historical knowledge and the purpose of historical understanding were

140 George Arnold Wood (1865–1928). Challis Professor of History, University of Sydney, 1891–1928. 141 R. M. Crawford, ‘A Bit of a Rebel’: The Life and Work of George Arnold Wood (Sydney: Sydney University Press, 1975), 47. This was a reminiscence of a reminiscence, thus hearsay. 142 Crawford, ‘A Bit of a Rebel’, 128, 131, 132. 143 George Arnold Wood, “The Study of History in relation to Culture”, The Australian Teacher, no. 38 (Oct., 1901): 1–9, quoted in Crawford, ‘A Bit of a Rebel’, 87. 144 Crawford, ‘A Bit of a Rebel’, 371.

104 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

unproblematic. For Wood, the purpose of historical understanding was ethical education, and

morality was the highest educational purpose. For Crawford, the purpose was less didactic,

but it still related—as it did for Wood (and also for Acton)—to moral ‘being’, not

epistemology.

At the University of Adelaide, the Balliol-trained Australian, George Henderson,

anticipated Wood by establishing, in 1906, ‘systematic and scientific’ research into Australian

history.145 ‘Systematic and scientific’ were the words he used for the kind of historical

training he advocated. Seeley had been for Henderson (as for Tout) inspirational.146 ‘Such a

man switches on the electric light in the dark chambers of history’, he declared. ‘The great

facts of history’, he said ‘may be like the great facts of human nature—outward

manifestations of great laws working in and through the national mind.’147 Later, in 1941,

reflecting on forty years of research and writing, Henderson’s conclusion was less scientific

and less Seeley-like: that those who would understand the history of a people should live with

them long enough to understand their point of view.148 Henderson had completed a two-

volume history of government in Fiji, and the years he had spent there affected him deeply.

He now saw the need to see beyond historical ‘facts’ to a wider knowledge of Geist and

Kultur. He encouraged his students to see that anthropologists and historians had much to

offer each other.149

In 1913, in Melbourne, the Englishman , a ‘self-taught exile’, journalist,

and free-lance historian with no university training but with two published works of

Australian history to his credit, succeeded Elkington150 as Professor of History. He was to

remain in the chair for twenty-three years and establish the history school at the University of

145 See Elizabeth Kwan, “G. C. Henderson: Advocate of ‘Systematic and Scientific’ Research in Australian History”, in The Discovery of Australian History, 1890 – 1939, eds Stuart Macintyre and Julian Thomas (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1995), 31. 146 F. M. Powicke, “Memoir”, in Tout, The Collected Papers, 3. 147 Kwan, “G. C. Henderson”, 38 148 Ibid., 46. 149 Ibid., 46. 150 Who had succeeded Hearn in 1879. Elkington produced no original historical scholarship in those thirty-three years.

105 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

Melbourne as a centre of Australian historical scholarship. Scott continued to teach British-

history-based survey courses, but emphasized the study of primary sources and the process of

historical interpretation.151 But it was positivist history which Scott championed—its method

was ‘the testing of evidence in the same way as a man of science tests his materials and

checks his experiments’.152 He admired Ranke and what he assumed was Ranke’s

objectivity. Research was the preparation required of the historian in order to create the

objective historical record. Scott, though interested, was untroubled by theoretical questions.

His aim was to settle, not to add to, uncertainty. The purpose of history, he stated, was ‘to

mark the stages of human progress’.153

Researchers in Australia, at least until Hancock,154 were not troubled with technical or

conceptual problems. And for Hancock, the issues were not conceptual problems as such;

they were just the result of a natural bent and a Balliol training which caused him to

‘concentrate on particular questions which might illuminate the whole’.155 For Hancock, as

for Australian historians, it was a liberal, humanist, empiricist ‘whole’, not an epistemological

or ontological ‘whole’ which the Germans had been, and were, interrogating. And for

Australian-history research, specialist technique was not required as it was for the English

medievalists. The language was English and modern, the location of material and its

authenticity unproblematic, and the matter unsubtle being as it was the record of

comparatively recent administrative, economic and political action. There were practical

problems such as limited resources, and large volumes of unorganized material, but no

problems of conceptual interpretation, or technical difficulty. The epistemological

foundations of the discipline were never problematic.

151 Stuart Macintyre, ‘Ernest Scott’ (1867–1939), in The Life of the Past: The Discipline of History at the University of Melbourne, eds Fay Anderson and Stuart Macintyre (Melbourne: University of Melbourne. Dept. of History, 2006), 20–21. 152 Ernest Scott, History and Historical Problems (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1925), 111. 153Ibid., 19. 154 Sir Keith Hancock (1898–1984). 155 J. D. B. Miller, “Hancock, Mansergh and Commonwealth Surveys”, Historical Studies, 13, no. 51 (Oct., 1968): 397. Hancock will be discussed in Chapter 5.

106 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

Of all the academic ‘historians’ in Australia charged with disciplinary responsibility,

from Hearn to Crawford, it was only Crawford who had worried about the philosophy of

history, and that worry translated (as discussed earlier) into confusion over disciplinary

direction and professional purpose. As he later reflected:

Any one of us might have found it difficult to state precisely what we were about … We were certainly interested in anything which might be termed ‘philosophy of history’, though well aware that respectable historians regarded it as ‘sheer drivel’.

By ‘respectable historians’ he meant eminent historians from the British school of historical

positivism. In 1938, the year after he succeeded Scott at the University of Melbourne,

Crawford introduced a new Theory and Method unit for Honours students, but that unit, as he

said, was ‘tired work’ from the start, and never provided any of the answers he was looking

for. The preoccupation with orthodox historical forces and structures did not explain, as he

later said, the ‘the drama [italics added] of necessity and freedom’.156 Explanation, he

argued, had to go behind the epiphenomena of agency and structure. In the Theory and

Method classes students compared the positivism of such thinkers such as Dray and Hempel

to the idealism of such thinkers as Croce and Collingwood. From Croce they learned that

history was elaborated ‘as intuition and imagination’, and that it was always contemporary.

History was not science, but the past re-lived, Croce had argued. From Collingwood they

learned that 'all history is the history of thought’.157 It was the same conclusion that the

German scholars of the eighteenth and nineteenth century had reached. Historical

understanding was about meaning in lived experience, and Geisteswissenschaft was the

method.

There was, however, a profound difference between the philosophical frameworks of

the nineteenth-century German academy (in Berlin), and the twentieth-century academy in

156 R. M. Crawford, The Study of History: A Synoptic View (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1939), 17 157 Benedetto Croce, History: Its Theory and Practice, trans. D. Ainslie (New York: Russell & Russell, 1960), 51–5, 106–7, 310; R. G. Collingwood, An Autobiography (London: Oxford University Press, 1939), 110, quoted in Robert Dare, “Theory and Method”, in The Life of the Past, eds Fay Anderson and Stuart Macintyre, 345–6.

107 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

Melbourne (and Oxford and Cambridge). To the academy in Melbourne, the fact of inquiry

such as that pursued in Theory and Method unit demonstrated the rigorous nature of a

discipline whose foundations, thus, were assumed to be sound, and whose purpose was

assumed to be educational. It was inquiry within a moral and humanist frame. Historical

inquiry was not, as it was initially in Berlin, one aspect of the search for knowledge of

knowledge beyond culture and morality.158 Historical research in the Australian academy

was not basic research. It was research within cultural boundaries whose object was to

expand the number and quality of educational history-products.

The question of what kind of knowledge historical research provided, and why that

knowledge was wanted, remained open.

IV

In 1991, looking back (from the ‘incipient post-post-modernist age’) on eighteen years of

professional practice, Greg Dening concluded that behind his professing of history was the

belief that the ‘ultimate forgery is positivist realism’.159 Hearing, reading, learning, making

history was the antidote, he argued, to ‘the forgeries inherent in modernism, especially

virulent, blind positivistic modernism’. He was repeating, he said, what he had said in 1972

in his inaugural lecture: that history was a social system. For Dening, history was an active

(subjective and inter-subjective) process that expanded our sense and ways of knowing. In

2007 he wrote:

I suppose that if there is anything central to what I do as I see it, it is that: exploring the smallness and largeness, the particularity and generality, of every cultural act. I've gone to those disciplines of knowledge that respect the wholeness of human living.160

158 Boeckh once explained that the purpose of this study was ‘to know my own knowledge of the knowledge of the [alien] past; for only then can I assign it a place in my own thought, which is an act of judgement’. August Boeckh, “Idee der Philologie”, in E. Bratuschek, ed., Encyklopädie und Methodologie der philosophen Wissenscchaften (Leipzig, 1877), 10–11, quoted in Gossman, Between History and Literature, 278. 159 Greg Dening, “Claptrap, Art & Science: Representation, Realisation, Reflection”, Melbourne Historical Journal, 21, 1991, 95–103, 97. Dening (1931–2008) was Max Crawford Professor of History, University of Melbourne from 1972 to 1990. 160 ‘A personal profile by Greg Dening’, http://www.anu.edu.au/culture/staff/dening_g.php. [12

108 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

In his inaugural lecture he had been highly critical of rigid disciplinary specialization

which ‘make interdisciplinary dialogue and activity virtually impossible’; where the

disciplines were ‘erroneously conceived of as logical universes, rationally distinct in object

and method’.161 He was not, though, advocating ‘another form of ‘academic ideology

celebrating the unity of knowledge’. There are, he said, ‘other ways of discussing theory and

method of history and interdisciplinary relations than in a philosophical and epistemological

mode’.162 History was an active, present-centred, process: ‘ethnography and history are not

something one learns: they are something one does’. History was performed through

imaginative reflection on the representation of the past that was being read or heard. In that

way, and only in that way, was the representation realised as history.163 Imagination was the

vehicle for understanding. ‘Empowering imaginations’ was the aim of his teaching.164 Ways

of seeing were ways of knowing. Earlier he had reflected that

History … is, I think, only a sentence in a conversation about ourselves … It reflects the reality that in our present is all our past and in our person is all our culture. Like every sentence in a conversation, it ends a part but not a whole. Nothing more.165

History was in our head. For Dening, culture was the form and history the glue of an

active, constructed, social reality. ‘History’ was training in cultural sensitivity which

intensified the individual’s historical consciousness, and through that heightened

consciousness the past and the present were brought together in a ‘living’ collaboration.

History enabled a higher awareness of a cultural living-in-the-world which would lead, in

turn, to a more holistic humanism. In this vision, history is a strategy for anchoring reality in

the human subject and in intersubjective relations. It works deliberately within an

ontologically firm sense of ‘being’ in the world, and within an epistemologically stable moral

frame. It acknowledges the ontological and epistemological unknown, but does not seek to

August 2008]. 161 G. M. Dening, “History as a Social System”, Historical Studies, 15, no. 61 (1973): 685, 673. 162 Ibid., 674. 163 Dening, “Claptrap, Art & Science”, 96. 164 Greg Dening, Readings/Writings (Carlton South: Melbourne University Press, 1998). 165 G. M. Dening, Islands and Beaches: Discourse on a Silent Land Marquesas 1774–1880 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1980), 6.

109 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

look beyond the selected humanist frames. Rather, the search is for answers to what it is to

be human. For Dening, history’s task is to enrich an understanding of our humanity, of how

to be human, of how to live.

Dening’s was a particular vision, which he pursued with energy and conviction and he

has been an influential voice in the Australian academy. However, his philosophy of history

and research focus raises again the question of research in the research university, and history

in the research university. What role does historical research have in a broader basic-research

program, and what necessary function does the academy perform in the realization of

historical research?

In the formal definition of ‘Research & Development’, a distinction has been drawn

between basic research, strategic basic research, applied research, and experimental

development; ‘Production’—producing useable products—is a separate category with its own

sub-category definitions. With his intuitive sense of holistic knowledge and rejection of

rationally distinct disciplinary universes, and in his refusal to accept limits to ways of

understanding, Dening’s work reflects the spirit of pure inquiry which defines basic research.

But his research, with its deliberate (and orthodox) assumption of a humanist, moral frame,

and with its pedagogical focus, is not, strictly, basic research. If advance in knowledge and

understanding through discovery is the focus of basic research, then basic research would

imply exploration at epistemological and ontological boundaries. Dening’s enlargement of

humanist understanding enables the subject as cultural-being to see that being more clearly,

but that clearer vision is more the enhancement of bounded understanding than advancement

of a basic research edge. As cultural beings, history is the air we breathe, but history as basic

research in the research university is not that history. In basic research, history and historical

consciousness are a field and a mode of inquiry. Nevertheless, Dening’s work problematizes

the ethos of basic research. What does ‘advance’ mean? What do we want new knowledge

for? Is the following of an irrational urge to ‘know’ (curiosity-driven basic research by

‘“knowledge-intoxicated” men’)166 intelligent behaviour? Research alone is not sufficient;

166 The phrase is from: Australia, Committee on Australian Universities, Report, September,

110 Ch. 2: Research and Scholarship

there remains the need for the ‘experimental development’ of products to assist us to

determine how we should behave in our particular cultural moment.

In the twenty-first century, if it is accepted that research is the distinctive competence

of the research university, then the question of what ‘advance’ means in relation to

knowledge and understanding, and what role history research might play in that advance,

remains central to history’s future in the academy, and to the direction of history research.

1957 (Canberra: Govt. Printer, 1958), 10.

111

112

CHAPTER 3

KNOWLEDGE AND UNDERSTANDING

It is said that there are, besides Dr. Einstein himself, only two men who can claim to have grasped the Theory in full. I cannot claim to be either of these. But I do know a good thing when I see it … the attempt to conceive Infinity has always been quite arduous enough for me. But to imagine the absence of it; to feel that perhaps we and all the stars beyond our ken are somehow cosily (though awfully) closed in by curtain curves beyond which is nothing; and to convince myself, by the way, that this exterior is not (in virtue of being nothing) something, and therefore—but I lose the thread. —Max Beerbohm: The Incomparable Max1

By contrast, Schrödinger never repeated his 1926 coup with the five papers on wave mechanics ... Certainly, he remained one of the major participants in the professional dialogue about quantum physics right up to 1940 … But, increasingly, he was inclined to cross the line between problems that were soluble and questions whose answers were out of reach … [this biography] shows us how easily this can happen, and how a scientist's personality and nonscientific beliefs can help direct—or misdirect—his intellectual attention. —Stephen Toulmin: ‘A Question of Character’2

I do not suppose that I have gifts as a “political theorist.” There is, perhaps, too much sensibility mixed up with my thought—a relapse into an “English idiom” which may confuse international exchanges. Yet the experiences of my lifetime are ones which require a response which cannot be simply negotiated within the stratagems of “Theory”. —E. P. Thompson: The Poverty of Theory:3

History and Function

One particular problem for the academic history enterprise is that because the academy has never actively tried to integrate disciplinary research, nor differentiated between research, development, and production, the end to which academic history research has been directed has been discussion within history—either through specialist research articles, or developed

1 Max Beerbohm, “A Note on the Einstein Theory”, in The Incomparable Max: A Collection of Writings of Sir Max Beerbohm (New York: Dodd, Mead & Company, 1962), 311. 2 Stephen Toulmin, “A Question of Character”, review of Schrodinger: Life and Thought by Walter Moore, The New York Review of Books, 37, no. 11, 28 June 1990. 3 E. P. Thompson, The Poverty of Theory and Other Essays (London: Merlin Press, 1978), iii.

113 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

pedagogical study-material, or commercially-published monographs. Consequently, the

question of where the discipline’s research edge might lie in relation to the wider

epistemological and ontological research edge, has not been articulated—other than in the

sense of general acknowledgement that any sub-disciplinary field is a form of intellectual

history,4 and an awareness that ‘theory’ does challenge many traditional professional

assumptions. ‘Advance’ has implied the development of specialist historical knowledge

within the discipline. Thus the question of how the discipline as a whole might evolve, has no

champion. Attention is focused more on locating and then developing particular threads and

topics within the styles and genres of historical writing and argument. Those styles and

genres do evolve, but their evolution results from the evolution of the cultural community in

which they function, rather than from an intellectual response to a moving research edge.

Even further from the attention of either the discipline or the academy is the question of how

the discipline might evolve as a mode of inquiry within the research community. Instead,

disciplinary focus has been on the technical task, and on the role of academic history in the

authentication of a particular type of cultural knowledge. The foundational assumption has

always been that academic history research would work within a disciplinary boundary—it

would be research in history that advanced ‘historical’ knowledge. The claim that it is more

than that, as Droysen and Treitzske, or Clark and Dening, or theorists such as White and

Ankersmit, for example, have suggested, has always either been treated sceptically or ignored.

Those arguments, however, remain arguments about the function of history in culture.

There remains the question of history’s basic research function outside culture, and also the

question of history’s function in the ‘development’ activity the academy undertakes on its

basic research ‘discoveries’ in order for those discoveries to result in useful social products.5

4 See, for example, William J. Bouwsma, “From History of Ideas to History of Meaning”, Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 12, no. 2 (Autumn, 1981): 279–291. 5 When research and development are discussed hereafter, the following terms will be used to discriminate between the different types of activity: ‘pure basic research’, ‘strategic basic research’,’ applied research’, and ‘experimental development’. The terms comply with those used by the OECD and Australian Bureau of Statistics for classifying R&D (and as defined initially in the ‘Frascati Manual’—the experts met at the Villa Falcioneri in Frascati, Italy, in June 1963). ‘Innovation’ is a category connected to, but separate from, R&D and is classified in accordance with the OECD ‘Oslo Manual’. See OECD, The Measurement of Scientific and Technological Activities; Proposed Standard

114 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

I

Mainstream academic history, particularly in Britain and Australia (and North America), has

been very aware of the theoretical discussion concerning the nature of historical knowledge

and the function of historical narrative but, distrusting theory, has left participation in that

discussion to the small sub-set of historians, philosophers and social theorists to whom it

appeared to be of interest. Mainstream historians tended simply to concentrate on the practice

of writing an orthodox history which matched the expectations of its particular interpretative

community. The result in Britain, according to (a young) Gareth Stedman Jones (writing in

1967), was that ‘the progress of British historiography in the last 100 years provides a

spectacular case of arrested intellectual development, and conceptual poverty’. Michael

Bentley, in 2003, was more generous:

the profession largely ignored [the theorists] et hoc genus omne and forged a common-sense notion of truth and factuality out of a daily engagement with historical sources … History expanded its sense of itself as a disciplinary practice rather than a style of meditation.6

Earlier, in the 1980s, Dominick LaCapra had voiced his deep frustration with his fellow

“practicing” historians’ method of ‘operating primarily’ according, he said, to ‘archival

fetishism; a reliance on tacit, craft-like procedures; and a marked resistance to theory’. He

wanted to ‘wake historians from their dogmatic slumber’ and have them ‘respond creatively

to newer challenges in contemporary thought’.7 Nevertheless, Stephen Bann noted that ‘few

Practice for Surveys on Research and Experimental Development: Frascati Manual; 2002 (Paris: OECD Publications, 2002); 1297.0 – Australian Standard Research Classification (ASRC), 1998; and OECD and Eurostat, The Measurement of Scientific and Technological Activities; Oslo Manual: Guidelines for Collecting and Interpreting Innovation Data; Third Edition (Paris: OECD Publications, 2005). 6 Michael Bentley, Modernizing England’s Past, 209–210. This glosses over, somewhat, the influence of Marxist theory on some British history after World War One, and the intense arguments in the 1960s–1980s between Marxist and non-Marxist historians, and between marxisant historians and intellectuals such as E. P. Thompson (and Stedman Jones), and others—often through the New Left Review. 7 Dominick LaCapra, Rethinking Intellectual History (Ithaca N.Y, 1983), 72. Dominick LaCapra, Soundings in Critical Theory (Ithaca N.Y, 1989),206. Dominick LaCapra, History and Criticism (Ithaca N.Y, 1985), 9. All quotes from John H. Zammito, “Are We Being Theoretical Yet? The New Historicism, the New Philosophy of History, and “Practising Historians””, Journal of Modern History, 65, no. 4 (Dec., 1993): 783 n. 2.

115 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

practicing historians are incommoded … by the lack of a philosophic base’. But he did feel

that ‘historians should be thinking more carefully about their area of study’.8 Patrick Joyce

noted that his own article in Past and Present in 1998 was ‘the first contribution on

postmodernism and history to be published [in that journal] since the single exchange on the

subject in 1991–2’.9

Regardless of the ‘common-sense notion of truth and factuality’ which the profession

may have had, it could not ignore the general turn from an analytical–philosophical

understanding of historical fact and truth, to the linguistic–philosophical understanding which

occurred through the 1970s and beyond. Language could not be ‘looked-through’ to the

empirically verifiable explanation underneath. History was linguistically constructed

meaning. Nevertheless, even if the historian’s works were constructions of the past rather

than reconstructions, their purpose was still to provide new knowledge about a shared reality,

and that construction still required the collection of ‘facts’; archives still needed searching,

actual documents still required verification and validation, objects still needed to be sighted.

The change, though, was that the accumulation of facts which Bury, York Powell and Acton

saw as the way a universal history was to be realised, has now become simply the means by

which the discipline finds conceptual answers to present-centred hermeneutical questions.

Nevertheless, the question of what ultimate research purpose or cultural purpose those

answers serve remains open. It cannot only be increased awareness of the historically

constructed nature of cultural and social consciousness. Raised awareness must have some

purpose. If it is (as from time to time one sees it said) ‘to enable us to know better who we

are’, then postmodernist scepticism of grand explanatory narratives, and now biological

anthropology and genetic engineering, has meant not only that identifying what ‘we’ means is

problematical but also that historical-consciousness-within-culture is itself the object of

research. Research always stands ‘outside’ the research object.10 If history’s purpose is, as

8 Stephen Bann, “Toward a Critical Historiography: Recent Work in Philosophy of History”, Philosophy, 56, 1981, 365, quoted in John H. Zammito, “Are We Being Theoretical Yet?”, 783 n.2. 9 Patrick Joyce, “The Return of History: Postmodernism and the Politics of Academic History in Britain”, Past and Present, no. 158 (Feb., 1998): 207. 10 The philosophically problematical nature of this statement is understood and will be discussed

116 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

Dening, Clark, and Crawford decided, an enriched living-in-the-world, then its basic research

status is problematical. History as basic research must be other than training in cultural and

social sensitivity. As research ‘outside’ culture, it must be part of a larger, more holistic,

epistemological and ontological exploration.

II

The question, however, of what is valid ‘knowledge’, or how new knowledge differs from

simply more knowledge is not easily answered. Nor is the related question of how

‘advancing’ knowledge differs from ‘extending’ knowledge. ‘Discovery’ can be as much

seeing existing facts in new ways—and thereby producing new understanding, hence new

knowledge—as discovering new relations and new phenomena. Intellectual advance has

often been made in that former way, as the influence of Burckhardt and Collingwood

(discussed below) has shown.

In Britain in the nineteenth century, once history had been established as an academic

discipline, intellectual attention turned toward specialization within the discipline’s

institutional frame, rather than interrogation of either that discipline’s ideological and

theoretical assumptions or its intellectual focus—a pattern that was replicated in Australia in

spirit if not in scale.11 The opening up of new lateral fields such as social history, imperial

history, and economic history, for example, and each with its own journals, societies and

practitioners, tended to deflect attention from the question of the exact nature and purpose of

historical understanding to that of developing the new institutional specialties. By contrast,

the research philosophy which Fichte, Schleiermacher and Humboldt had defined for the

University of Berlin—the acquisition of deeper ontological understanding through

epistemological discovery (to culminate in some incompletely understood fusion of subject

with object in absolute understanding)—produced in historians the conviction that authentic

history was below the surface of the historical. That authentic history was accessed through

later. 11 Australia followed in most areas, though the development of a history of Australia was not a subordinate part of colonial history, but an independent response to a local need.

117 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

historical research, but the search for deeper understanding meant the research focus was on

ways of seeing and the mechanics of signification, rather than simply the excavation and

exposition of a broader range of historical information. Burckhardt’s work demonstrated, as

Niebuhr’s had done, that disciplinary advance was achieved through making that disciplinary

study intellectually richer and deeper, rather than simply broader.

Burckhardt’s exploration of past cultural self-perception and expression as the vehicle

for deeper present epistemological understanding, both expanded and deepened academic

history’s understanding of itself as a mode of intellectual inquiry. The underlying spirit of

open intellectual inquiry which pervades his research has meant that it still has a freshness

which enables it to be read today as a work whose intrinsic value is intellectual rather than as

archaic historiography—the fate of much other nineteenth-century specialist history. It is not

the facts he presents that have continuing value, but the new perspectives his use of those

facts reveals.12 Burckhardt used architecture, sculpture and painting as Ranke used

documentary sources, but not as an art historian, rather, as a ‘searcher’ who wished to

understand more deeply and for whom the fine-arts and the built environment were means to

that end. In The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy, he explored the ways that mystery,

allegory and symbolism were used to make the Renaissance society’s past familiar to that

society’s members; and in so doing illuminated for the reader the living ‘whole’, not the parts

alone. For Burckhardt, visual and ideal values were inseparable in whole culture. He showed

how culture, politics, and religion were an active whole, but, he famously argued, it was in

the Renaissance that for the first time ‘both sides of human consciousness’—the objective and

subjective—joined to produce ‘a spiritual individual [italics in original]’.13

Burckhardt did not so much discover new historical ‘facts’ as introduce new ways of

‘seeing’ previously known facts; and in so doing deepened understanding, thus advanced

12 He was conscious of the personal imprint on selection and interpretation. ‘This work bears the title of an essay in the strictest sense of the word’ he wrote, ‘the same studies which have served for this work might easily, in other hands, not only receive a wholly different treatment and application, but lead also to essentially different conclusions.’ Jacob Burckhardt, The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy (London: Penguin Books, 1990), 19. 13 Ibid., 98.

118 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

rather than broadened knowledge. Burckhardt created a new dimension to Kulturgeschichte

not because he sought to add to specialist art-history, but as a consequence of his desire to

understand more deeply. Kulturgeschichte was the means to epistemological and ontological

inquiry. But his was not traditional history. On publication, The Civilization of the

Renaissance in Italy was criticized for its limited use of official documents and for its reliance

on literary sources.14 However, with his approach to history as a mode of inquiry and with

his emphasis on signification, Burckhardt’s practice connects directly to postmodern

intellectual inquiry. He was modern in ways that, say, Stubbs or Freeman, and many of their

English contemporaries, were not. By emphasizing historical research as a mode of

intellectual inquiry, Burckhardt was effectively identifying the history specialist’s function in

the larger quest for more integrated knowledge.

Burckhardt had shown how culture shapes both the organization of the senses and the

ideas that emerge from that shaping, and how in turn those ideas shape culture. With his

introduction of imaginative beholding as a research means to understand Geist and Kultur

more profoundly, he had advanced the research boundary. It was from that new edge that

Heinrich Wölfflin, Burckhardt’s pupil, produced his classic study (Kunstgeschichtliche

Grundbegriffe (1932)). Introducing that work, Wölfflin wrote

It goes without saying that the mode of imaginative beholding is no outward thing, but is also of decisive importance for the content of the imagination, and so far the history of these concepts also belongs to the history of the mind … The course of development of imaginative beholding is, to use an expression of Leibniz, “virtually” given, but in the actuality of history as lived, it is interrupted, checked, refracted in all kinds of ways. The present book therefore is not intended to give an extract of art history; it merely attempts to set up standards by which the historical transformations (and national types) can be more exactly defined.15

In his study, Wölfflin drew attention to the change of emphasis from form, as in

14 Asa Briggs, “History and the Social Sciences”, in A History of the University in Europe, ed. Walter Rüegg (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 464. 15 Heinrich Wölfflin, Principles of Art History: The Problem of the Development of Style in Later Art, trans. M. D. Hottinger (New York: Dover Publications, 1950), vii.

119 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

classical art, to movement, as in sixteenth-century art. The significance, he argued, was that:

‘The idea of reality has changed as much as the idea of beauty.’16 Consequently, he argued,

one could see that ‘national differences of the eye … contain the bases of the whole world

picture of a people’. Therefore, he concluded, ‘That is why the history of art as the doctrines

of modes of vision can claim to be, not only a mere super in the company of historical

disciplines, but as necessary as sight itself’.17

To understand human history was to understand that in human action reason,

imagination, sense, and emotion, operated simultaneously, not separately. Human experience

was both Geist and Natur, and both irrational and rational. Understanding human experience

could not come from narrow rationality alone.

Collingwood also, unarguably, extended epistemological limits. For him, as for

Burckhardt, history was a mode of inquiry. To understand history was to understand human

action and to understand human action was to understand the historical. Action was history

and history was past action.18 Historical inquiry was epistemological, and it was ontological.

Collingwood understood also, as Burckhardt had, that for any meaningful understanding of

human action, the full range of human experience had to be studied. ‘The only philosophy

that can be of real use to anybody’, he wrote, ‘is a critical review of the chief forms of human

experience’.19 Art, religion, science, history, and philosophy were, for him, the basic

experiential categories, but, he concluded, ‘there are no autonomous and mutually exclusive

forms of experience, and, what is more, it is in no one’s interest to assume that there are’.20

Collingwood studied fairy-tales, folk-tales, and magic and applied ‘philological, functional,

and psychological’ methods to determine their significance. The Romantic revolt against

‘naturalistic positivism’ was of particular interest. He described (in ‘Aesthetic theory and

artistic practice’ (1931)) how Thomas Hardy had ‘turned his back on naturalism and

16 Wölfflin, Principles of Art History, 229. 17 Wölfflin, Principles of Art History, 237. 18 Stein Helgeby, Action as History: The Historical Thought of R. G. Collingwood (Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2004). 19 R. G. Collingwood, Speculum Mentis, or The Tree of Knowledge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1924), 9. 20 Ibid., 306.

120 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

conceived life as a drama whose actors are spiritual forces working within the mind of man’.

He saw in Hardy’s work that the spiritual forces were the main ‘facts’ of life. The artist

constructed in his imagination an object whose purpose was to be significant or expressive—

‘an intuition and therefore an expression’, Collingwood wrote. Consequently, physical

objects were no longer needed as the ‘fixed point’ round which the work of art would

‘crystallize out’. Past facts were as much intuitions as they were the ‘residue of naturalism’.21

He was not concluding, as Dening would, that positive realism was the ‘ultimate forgery’, but

he was arguing that the imagination was as substantial as reason in the drama of social reality.

Collingwood, like Burckhardt, had concluded that any meaningful experience is the

matter of historical reality. Expression and experience outside language were as important to

human understanding as articulated, rationalized, experience. With meaning, how one feels

about an experience is more important than the actuality of the experience. The heart

determines meaning in ways that the head cannot.22 Roger Fry, writing at the same time as

Collingwood, commented that the critical distinction between science and art was that poetry,

music, or painting was ‘the only means by which human beings can communicate to each

other the quality and quiddity of their experiences’. Science summed up experience in a

statement of fact: ‘The solution turned blue!’ But science, he said, was ‘not interested in the

feeling tone which the sensation of blue gave’.23

Thus, music, too, as a mode of imaginative beholding can determine the content of the

imagination and contribute to shared cultural understanding. Music is expression which is

simultaneously visceral and intellectual; how one hears can enable one to ‘see’ differently.

Music can extend meaning. Karlheinz Stockhausen’s exploration in the mid twentieth-

century of the fundamental and distinctive acoustical and psychological aspects of sound

profoundly challenged accepted criteria for musical form, and has since profoundly altered

21 This unpublished work is in R. G. Collingwood, The Philosophy of Enchantment: Studies in Folktale, Cultural Criticism, and Anthropology, eds David Boucher, Wendy James and Philip Smallwood (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005). Quote is from page 107. 22 ‘Genuine poetry can communicate before it is understood.’ T. S. Eliot, ‘Dante’, Selected Essays (London: Faber and Faber, 1972), 238. 23 Slade Professor lectures (undelivered). Roger Fry, Last Lectures (Boston: Beacon Press, 1962), 11.

121 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

notions of what constitutes legitimate musical form and genre—of what ‘music’ is or can be.

The idea that a musical work need not be conceptually harmonious creates awareness of the

complicated relationship between notions of musical autonomy and historically determined

social convention. It also creates awareness that the subversion or extension of convention

can provide new understanding. A musical work can operate ‘musically’ as notes, as

phrases, or as an entity; but also, as Adorno observed, as a work which can have the

appearance of being self-sufficient and harmonious and yet be a profoundly non-harmonizing

social ‘cipher’24—as Richard Wagner’s music can be, for example.

Unarguably, art or literature can open up new possibilities for perception, thus

possibilities for new understanding, and those possibilities are multiplied when genre is

extended or subverted, rather than faithfully reproduced. The perception of ‘newness’ of

Chardin’s still-lifes, or Joyce’s novels, or Stockhausen’s music—actuated by their location

outside contemporary expectation—has the effect of expanding contemporary knowledge by

extending the frame in which understanding operates. ‘Modernism’ like Romanticism was a

new, affective, perceptual frame for shared understanding. The new perception becomes the

new historical reality in the way Wölfflin described. Which is why John Toews, when

seeking to explain Ranke’s ‘conception of human existence as essentially historical’, was led

into his ‘broader synchronic examination’ of the architecture of Schinkel, the musical

compositions of Mendelssohn, and the linguistic–ethnographic studies of Jacob Grimm, in

order to understand the ways in which Ranke addressed questions of historical self-

consciousness and historical identity. Architecture, ethno-cultural identity, and music, Toews

showed, critically affected those conceptions.25 Any form of change to imaginative

beholding can be considered part of the process of cognitive transformation so central to

historical transformation and hence to contemporary understanding of that past history.

But there is a ‘double hermeneutic’ operating here. To identify perceptions of

24 Lydia Goehr, The Quest for Voice: On Music, Politics, and the Limits of Philosophy (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998), 15. 25 John Toews, Becoming Historical: Cultural Reformation and Public Memory in Early Nineteenth-Century Berlin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), xvi–xvii.

122 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

‘newness’ in historical agents’ perceptions is to ‘discover’ new evidence from which new

contemporary knowledge can be derived. But the ‘new’ evidence is new only because of a

new research perceptual frame, not because new historical raw data (‘residues of naturalism’)

have been discovered. For example, in the foreword to his The Europeans in Australia, Alan

Atkinson explained that his history was

a history of common imagination in Australia, and by ‘common’ I mean both ordinary and shared. It is an attempt to describe the day-to-day intellectual notions associated with life as an Australian among Australians, one of the conquerors of a new world, the denizen of a certain space, a subject and a social being.26

The new environment induced new perceptions and, hence, new realities for the denizens of

that certain space. The new ‘ordinary and shared’ intellectual notions defined a distinctively

Australian ‘subject and being’ for whom European notions shared previously, assumed new

shared meaning. ‘Affect-imbued ideas’27 were folded back into culture. In Australia, natural

environment was, ultimately, the strongest cultural element. In this work of Atkinson, the

research was new, and that new research produced a ‘new’ history, but Atkinson’s

‘discovery’ was a new beholding, rather than new archival material that changed previously

held views. Clearly, discovery can be made of new primary material, but as has been long

recognized, perception of something as something, precedes understanding (historians needed

to understand that ‘it is less important to discover new materials than to see the meaning of

old’, Tawney said).28 New understanding, thus new knowledge, presupposes new perception

and not simply new material.29

The issue that arises is that if, as research, history’s primary contribution were to be the

opening of new perceptual possibilities within culture, or the raising of cultural, aesthetic, or

26 Alan Atkinson, The Europeans in Australia: A History, vol. 1 (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1998), ix. 27 The phrase is from William Connolly, “The Radical Enlightenment: Faith, Power, Theory”, Theory & Event, 7, Issue 3, 2004, http://muse.jhu.edu/login?uri=/journals/theory_and_event/v007/7.3connolly.html. See full quote below (page 144). 28 R. H. Tawney, “The Study of Economic History”, Economica, 39. (Feb., 1933): 13–14. 29 This statement will be discussed next section.

123 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

moral sensitivity, then it becomes indistinguishable from the other ‘arts’. Not only is its

distinctive basic research function then lost, but it risks having its test of relevance become

the effectiveness of its public engagement. Conversely, if the opening of new perceptual

possibilities within culture is a valid basic research function, then the creative and performing

arts are integral to any basic research.

III

If history were an ‘art’ directed to public engagement, then it can be strongly argued that

literary fiction, poetry, drama, or film are more effective vehicles for negotiating life’s subtler

reality—for seeing things as they really are and for being able to exercise moral imagination

and moral choice effectively. Lionel Trilling has argued that ‘the most effective agent of the

moral imagination has been the novel of the last two hundred years’. For Trilling, the novel’s

‘greatness and practical usefulness’ lay in the way that it involved the reader ‘in the moral

life, inviting him to put his own motives under examination, suggesting that reality is not as

his conventional education has led him to see it’.30 Literature has always been concerned

with lived reality:

All literature tends to be concerned with the question of reality—I mean quite simply the old opposition between reality and appearance, between what really is and what merely seems. ‘Don’t you see?’ is the question we want to shout at Oedipus as he stands before us and before fate in the pride of his rationalism.31

Recently, the acclaimed British novelist Zadie Smith reflected that she has concluded that

the novel—writing a novel, reading a novel—is an ethical enterprise, a practice place for morals where we watch, in safety, people choosing what they must do, and what they lose when they choose wrongly; that is the closest possible rehearsal for the real thing, which is the most important thing of all.32

30 Lionel Trilling: The Liberal Imagination: Essays on Literature and Society (New York: The Viking Press; 1951), 222. 31 Trilling: The Liberal Imagination, 207 32 Quoted in Age Review (Melbourne), 17 September 2005, 3, from article by Aida Edermarim, Guardian.

124 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

Film, as argued earlier, also can claim strong credentials as an effective cultural agent for the

exploration of the ethical and existential complexity of ‘life’. History, of course, can also

claim that function, but that function, as with those other media (poetry, prose, film, etc.), is

performed through a ‘developed’ product that has been fashioned for public consumption.

That function has many capable potential providers outside the academy, and it is at the

opposite end of the research-development-production spectrum to basic research. The

question of history’s basic research function remains.

For Manning Clark, that question was irrelevant; history was wholly a public product.

For him, history’s true mission was assuaging spiritual hunger and enabling people to see new

possibility by removing the blinkers of the past. ‘It is the task of the historian and the myth-

maker’, he said, ‘to tell the story of how the world came to be as it is’;33 and it was also ‘the

‘story of what might be’. If this were so, then history and the literary and creative arts

become complementary in the task of cultural enrichment and renewal. Through play, a

function of the literary and creative arts, myth’s meaning can be extended and possibilities

explored, and the historian, as historian, by showing how the myth came to be, removes the

ground for its necessity and thus ‘warrants’ the legitimacy of these new possibilities. How

the past is experienced and understood through historical representation and signification

does play a significant role in enabling people to acquire a sense of the existential choices

open to them. The historical work can play a significant role in indicating modes of historical

change and future possibility. The historian can shape, with the artist, the form of these

possibilities.

But again, in this role ‘history’ is a developed public-domain product which functions

as a vehicle for shared communal understanding. In that role it is not a mode of inquiry

which functions ‘outside’ culture as a basic research tool, but is itself an object for research.

The problem is that history has both functions, and both are required in the academy, but only

one is a basic research function. Alan Atkinson’s new research-based ‘history of Australia’,

33 C. M. H. Clark, A History of Australia, vol. 6 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1987), 500.

125 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

as a history of Australia, is a text within culture whose primary purpose is richer cultural

understanding; it is not a basic research document whose primary purpose is the advance of

epistemological and ontological knowledge. That is not to deny that it is a legitimate, socially

valuable, academic product: it is only to argue that the location of the academic product in the

basic-research to developed-product spectrum determines the type of knowledge it creates.

The basic research project has a different purpose to the pedagogic or cultural project. Basic

research seeks Boeckh and Schleiermacher’s ‘knowledge of knowledge’.

Myth (as explanatory narrative or dynamic model), imaginative beholding, and shared

understanding are as central to epistemological and ontological inquiry as analytical

philosophy and empiricism. Thus, intrinsically, Atkinson’s work could be part of a basic

research program. Knowledge is more than objective reality. Since the ontological

speculation of Spinoza and Descartes in the seventeenth century, and the epistemological

critique of Kant in the late eighteenth century, inquiry has developed an increasingly ironic

stance towards subject-centred reason and its desire to find secure grounding in an objective

reality. The philosophical discourse of modernity which emerged now accepts as

foundational the mutually constitutive relation between reason and the historical moment.34

It accepts that we are both products and producers of history and that epistemic structures are

as much historically constituted as they are rationally constructed. That philosophical

discourse recognizes that myth and imaginative beholding are as important to historical

understanding as reason, and that advances in epistemological and ontological understanding

cannot be achieved without historical understanding.

Hans Blumenberg goes further and argues that all those elements are interdependent.

He argues that reason requires the harmonization of the rational with the irrational, and that

myth and rationality are complementary, not mutually hostile as ‘enlightened’ thought has

insisted. Not only are they complementary, but rationality is destructive ‘when it fails to

34 The discourse has no real start or end, but here is meant that discourse exemplified by such thinkers as Hegel, Marx, Nietzsche, Weber, Heidegger, Adorno, Foucault, Habermas, Lyotard, Luhmann, Jonas, Blumenberg, for example.

126 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

recognize the rationality of accepting things for which no rational foundation is given’.35 It is

not a question of rationality inevitably dissolving enchantment; both enchantment and

rationality are needed for mankind to face what Blumenberg calls ‘the absolutism of reality’.

Mankind can never master the absolutism of reality through reason, thus will always feel

insecure (in T. S. Eliot’s words: ‘The backward look behind the assurance/Of recorded

history, the backward half-look/Over the shoulder, towards the primitive terror’).36 Myth

enables a particular ‘mastering of reality’ that ‘rational self-assertion’ alone cannot provide

and without which human life would be impossible. He argues that myths such as

Prometheus, Faust, and Oedipus are so powerful and pregnant with meaning because of the

long process of cultural selection and refinement which they have undergone.37 Because they

portray the human predicament so holistically and indelibly, they are essential ontological

keys that are maintained and honed through time. ‘History’, Blumenberg concludes,

‘whatever else it may be, is also a process of optimization’.38

Regardless of whatever cultural or pedagogical function it might have, history has a

distinctive role to play in academic basic research. That research, by virtue of being

‘academic’, is research into that ‘absolutism of reality’ which Blumenberg identified; it is

research at the edge of epistemological and ontological understanding. But, since the

infiltration of theory and the theoretical discourse of modernity and postmodernity into

almost all academic discourse, historicism (in its genealogical sense) and historical

consciousness have become entrenched in nearly all humanities, arts, and social science

disciplines (as, to a lesser extent, has the Continental form of philosophy). Thus, the history

discipline does need to be clear on its particular and necessary role within the basic research

35 Hans Blumenberg, Work on Myth, trans. Robert M. Wallace (Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 1990), 163. 36 Lines 101–3 of “The Dry Salvages”, T. S. Eliot Four Quartets (London: Faber and Faber, 1972). P. 39. 37 William Bouwsma uses Prometheus to illustrate the active contemporary function myth performs; see William J. Bousma, “The Renaissance and the Drama of Western History”, American Historical Review, 84, no. 1 (Feb., 1979): 10; and Donald Kelley begins his essay on Marx citing Prometheus’s influence on Marx; see Donald R. Kelley, “The Metaphysics of Law: An Essay on the Very Young Marx”, American Historical Review, 83, no. 2 (Apr., 1978), 350–367. 38 Blumenberg, Work on Myth, 165.

127 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

program if it is not to become fragmented and then subsumed within more intellectually

innovative and coherent research ‘branches’.

The discipline’s role in the basic research program requires it to stand ‘outside’ culture

and operate not as a liberal, humanist, cultural narrative, but as a mode of inquiry working at

the epistemological research edge. In this role its function is specialist inquiry whose field is

the past and mutation, whose subject is meaning, and whose method is interpretation—all

warranted by specialist expertise in historicity and historical consciousness gained through

deep familiarity with specific historical ‘specimens’.39 In this form, its output becomes part

of, but integral to, the basic research program, since any epistemic ‘advance’ requires

historical understanding—as does any agreement on what ‘advance’ means.

The question, though, of what ‘advance’ means with regards to knowledge, remains

problematical. In research, ‘discovery’ implies the bringing to awareness of new knowledge,

but the distinction between new knowledge and simply more knowledge is not clearly

defined. Nor is it obvious how what may count as ‘valid’ new knowledge, is legitimized. In

our current ‘age’ of science, legitimacy usually requires the imprimatur of scientific method;

but, as discussed, knowledge is more than evidence-based reality.

Knowledge and Reason

In Western society from around the sixteenth-century, science has been increasingly

influential in the elucidation and justification of the concept of ‘valid’ new knowledge. The

modern understanding of research, based as it is on Western scientific practice regarding

method, evidence and objectivity, accepts that, when properly practised, science will deliver

‘true’ knowledge. Thus knowledge obtained through belief, revelation, or intuition is not

considered valid knowledge in the sense of objective knowledge. Nevertheless, as Thomas

Kuhn observed,

39 By ‘specific’ is meant particular time, place, or theme subjects.

128 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

Myths can be produced by the same sorts of methods and held for the same sorts of reasons that now lead to scientific knowledge … Observation and experience can and must drastically restrict the range of admissible belief, else there would be no science. But they cannot alone determine a particular body of such belief. An apparently arbitrary element, compounded of personal and historical accident, is always a formative ingredient of the beliefs espoused by a given scientific community at a given time.40

How we know, and how we determine the categories by which we legitimize knowledge—

identify ‘admissible belief’—are not, themselves, ‘scientific’. In science, the role of intuition

in forming fruitful scientific hypotheses is accepted. Scientists acknowledge that induction is

central to scientific thought, and accept that it is a complex mix of methodological practices

and beliefs.41

The scientist and Nobel laureate, Peter Medawar, describes the inductive process as ‘a

rapid reciprocation between … imaginative conjecture and critical evaluation’.42 It is a

process, he claims, which is based on two central premises:

(a) Observation is the generative act in scientific discovery. For all its aberrations, the evidence of the senses is essentially to be relied upon …

(b) Discovery and justification make one act of reasoning, not two. Inductive logic embodies both a rite of discovery and a ritual of proof. Scientific inference can always be made logically explicit, in retrospect if not at the time it was actually carried out.43

40 Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), 2, 4. 41 P. B. Medawar, Induction and Intuition in Scientific Thought (London: Methuen & Co., 1969), 42. 42 Ibid., 44 43 Ibid., 42. The debate regarding the place of induction in scientific method and the acquisition of ‘true’ knowledge is, of course, a long one. For example, Leibniz’s criticisms of Kepler’s laws, then Hume, Kant, the prolonged debate between William Whewell and John Stuart Mill (see E. W. Strong, “William Whewell and John Stuart Mill: Their Controversy about Scientific Knowledge”, Journal of the History of Ideas, 16, no. 2. (Apr., 1955), 209–231), and Paul Duhem. In the twentieth-century, the Vienna Circle debated extensively the foundations of positivism and sought to secure its foundations, but by the 1930s the separation of the context of justification from the context of discovery became problematical, and by the 1950s, became insupportable. The work of Kuhn and W. V. Quine, in particular, dissolved the distinction. (The influential Quine-Duhem thesis, for example, argues that empirical evidence cannot force the revision of a theory, since there are innumerable possible explanatory hypotheses and evidence cannot guide choice between rival theories or hypotheses). For a detailed historical and critical account of the positivist debates see John H. Zammito, A Nice

129 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

Thus, significance in data can be seen through imaginative beholding, and seeing is believing.

The scientist either ‘notices’ significance, or looks for it, but in each instance significance is

measured against a pre-conceived template. Bruno Latour and Steve Woolgar’s famous

sociological study of a neuroendocrinology research laboratory at the Salk Institute showed

that a typical experiment produces only inconclusive data and that a large part of scientific

training involves learning how to make the subjective decision of what data to keep and what

data to throw out.44 Consequently, the decision to retain data that contradicts scientific

orthodoxy cannot be one made through purely scientific reasoning: it also involves an

intuitive feel for the soundness of particular currently held beliefs. Underlying that intuition

is a conscious or unconscious awareness of the genealogy of current understanding: of how

and why those beliefs are held—thus why change may be required, why new reasons may be

stronger than old reasons. Despite the crisis of positivism during the 1950s and after,

precipitated in part by Kuhn and Quine’s arguments in the philosophy and sociology of

knowledge (reflected in Latour and Woolgar’s study), the efficacy of empirical inquiry could

not be denied, even if there appeared to be no sound theoretical basis for it. It seemed

ultimately to matter little to genuine scientific advance in what order belief and beholding

occurred.

Just as to see can be to believe, so to believe can be to see. Brian Levack noted in a

study of witchcraft and the law in Early Modern Europe how a person’s religious creed

affected what they saw. Calvinists, Lutherans, and Catholics, witnessed different

manifestations of demonic possession and witchcraft.45 One can believe even if seeing by

proxy. Charles Zika noted the way in the sixteenth-century pastors and theologians, through

their ability to interpret the illusions and invisible deeds of the devil, established themselves

as ‘arbiters of the seen and the unseen, of what are true and false worlds, true and false

Derangement of Epistemes: Post-positivism in the Study of Science from Quine to Latour (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2004). 44 Bruno Latour, Steve Woolgar, Laboratory life: the Construction of Scientific Facts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, c1986). 45 Brian Levack, “The Murder of Janet Cornfoot: Witchcraft and the Law in Early Modern Scotland”, seminar paper, University of Melbourne, 23 May, 2006.

130 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

gods’.46 To ‘see’ required specialist expertise. Thus, belief and experience are both adjusted

until their paired meaning reconciles with the individual’s intuited ontological and

teleological framework. Reason modifies that framework, but can never establish it—reason

cannot explain why there should be reason. It can only be through intuition that the

individual identifies the ‘self’ as ‘subject’ ‘experiencing’ the experience, and locates that self

within a larger absolute ‘reality’ (Kant’s transcendental subject perceiving the ontological

difference between self and ‘other’—or Heidegger’s Sein and Dasein). The larger reality

determines the meaning, and hence the validity, a particular belief will have. The human

being is simply ‘the place of meaning’ in which aestheticism (metaphor, metonymy, visual

representation) and perception are as fundamental to meaning constitution as empirical

rationality. Intuitive epistemological and ontological apprehension is prior to decisions

regarding the external world. Consequently, final determination of the validity of particular

truth and knowledge claims is through ontological intuition.47

Paul Feyerabend noted in a series of lectures in 1966 that ‘the development of church

dogma shares many features with the development of scientific thought’, and later argued that

empiricism shared certain problematic features with .48 Feyerabend’s notorious

(or celebrated) attacks on scientific positivism were based on his view, from experience with

scientists and philosophers of science, that there is no such thing as the scientific method. To

Feyerabend, great scientists are ‘epistemological anarchists’—methodological opportunists

who use any approach they think of, even if they thereby violate canons of empiricist

methodology.49 But his argument that the scientific outlook is itself just one approach to

46 Charles Zika, “The Devil’s Hoodwink: Seeing and Believing in the World of Sixteenth- Century Witchcraft”, in No Gods Except Me: Orthodoxy and Religious Practice in Europe 1200–1600, ed. Charles Zika (Parkville: History Department, University of Melbourne, 1991), 5. 47 Leonard Krieger observed that: ‘what constitutes the grounds of credibility for … historians … have changed from community to community and especially from period to period … the credibility of historians has entailed what was noteworthy of belief as well as what was entitled to belief.’ Leonard Krieger, Time’s Reasons: Philosophies of History Old and New (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1989), x. 48 Paul Feyerabend, Science in a Free Society (London: New Left Books, 1978), 137–8. 49 See, for example, Paul Feyerabend, Against Method (London: Verso, 1975). At this time Feyerabend’s purpose was not to dismiss empiricism but to argue for a ‘theoretical pluralism’—theory competition—where individual theories would be rigorously tested against alternatives, hence their empirical content enhanced. It was later that his views became more extreme and he was branded as an

131 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

making sense of the world—that it is not self-evidently superior in all respects to other

approaches—could not refute the fact that science ‘worked’ impressively and seemed

superior to alternatives for predicting natural phenomena. Science’s concern was with new,

unselfconscious, understanding derived from the validation or modification of a theory, not

with its epistemology, ontology, or the constitutive nature of language. ‘I can rejoice even in

the falsification of a cherished theory’, declared the neurophysiologist (Sir) John Eccles,

‘because even this is a scientific success’.50

Science does not seek, as a result of new understanding, to modify the epistemological

and ontological framework within which the new knowledge was derived. It assumes a

positivist ontology and an empiricist epistemology and takes for granted the legitimacy of

both its ontological assumptions and its self-authorization of the validity of its own

knowledge. Science is unconcerned also with language theory: thus science’s propositions or

theories can be tested for their explanatory truth value by other assertions and derivations and

can be re-described in other ‘primitive’ propositions which explain function or functional

purpose within this ontologically bounded and epistemologically defined domain.51

Physicists’ arguments on the creation of the universe do not question the existence of the

universe—thus they do not question epistemologically and ontologically the referential

statement that the universe exists—they only question the form of that universe and the

effectiveness of existing laws to enable them to explore that form. They accept that their

knowledge may be wrong because the existing laws and models may be inadequate and that

there may be discovered laws which overturn accepted notions of how the universe is to be

explained. For science, it is not what is believed which is of central importance, but how it

has come to be believed.52 Predictive power and verifiability are the criteria by which

entrenched cultural relativist. 50 Quoted in Karl R. Popper, Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1972), 2. 51 The terms, but not the statement, used here in relation to science’s logic are from Karl R. Popper, Conjectures and Refutations, 19. 52 Stephen Toulmin emphasizes the point that it is not what is believed, but how belief can change. ‘Questions of “rationality” are concerned, precisely, not with the particular intellectual doctrines that a man—or professional group adopts at any given time, but rather with the conditions on which, and the manner in which, he is prepared to criticize and change those doctrines as time goes on

132 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

scientific belief is validated.

The philosophical soundness of science’s epistemological assumptions is of interest to

science, but peripheral as long as advances are being made.53 Philosophical enigmas such as

continuity and infinity are of interest, but are not problematic regarding ‘advancing’ scientific

knowledge. Mathematics has always specified its own ‘absolutes’—‘infinity’, ‘a point’, ‘a

singularity’—unconcerned that they are purely artificial constructs necessary for practical

ends, but which are beyond conception. Although it is unclear how mathematics is possible,

why it works, advance in mathematics is unhindered. Rational meaning in mathematical

systems is irrelevant: for example, spatial intuition has no relevance to the truth of particular

geometries, as Henri Poincaré explained:

What, then, are we to think of the question: Is Euclidean geometry true? It has no meaning … One geometry cannot be more true than another; it can only be more convenient … whichever way we look at it, it is impossible to discover in geometric empiricism a rational meaning.54

Carnap, extending Poincaré’s observation to mathematical logic itself, concluded that it was

irrelevant whether the system or calculus’s foundation was logicist, formalist, or intuitivist. It

was convenience not correctness, he concluded, which was relevant.55 No system was more

‘correct’ than any other. Once the impediment of striving after correctness was overcome,

then, Carnap declared, ‘before us lies the boundless ocean of unlimited possibilities’.56

Gödel’s incompleteness theorem—from his proof that the distinction between logical and

physical rules can only be drawn within a meta-language that transcends the mathematical

[italics in original]. The rationality of science (for instance) is embodied, not in the theoretical systems current in it at particular times, but in the procedures for discovery and conceptual change through time.’ Stephen Toulmin, Human Understanding (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972), 84. 53 Ernst Mach, in a lecture in 1895 commented: ‘most scientists today adhere to a materialist philosophy of 150 years’ standing, whose inadequacy has long since been recognised not only by professional philosophers but by any laymen not too cut off from philosophic thought.’ Ernst Mach, Knowledge and Error: Sketches on the Psychology of Enquiry, trans. Thomas J. McCormack (Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1976), 3. 54 Henri Poincaré, Science and Hypothesis, trans. W. J. G. (sic) (New York: Dover Publications, 1952), 50, 79. 55 Michael Friedman, “The Re-evaluation of Logical Positivism”, Journal of Philosophy, 88, no. 10. (Oct., 1991): 516. 56 Rudolph Carnap, The Logical Syntax of Language, trans. A. Smeaton (New York: Routledge, 1937), xv, quoted in Michael Friedman, ‘The Re-evaluation of Logical Positivism’, 517.

133 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

rules being used—did not induce mathematical paralysis but acted as a spur to further

research using the rules.

For science, reality does not have to be conceivable. Superstring theory, which was

developed towards the end of the twentieth century, works in a space-time manifold of ten

dimensions and with vibrating ‘strings’ which are postulated to be the universe’s fundamental

building blocks. The strings are calculated to be one hundred-billionth of one hundred-

billionth of one hundred-billionth of one centimetre long (10–33 cm). Science is confident that

it can model an inconceivable reality; and that it can continue to refine the model regardless

of the fact that the model indicates an increasingly inconceivable reality. Science’s interest is

in the physical implications of these ontological discoveries—it is not in the ontological

implications of those ontological discoveries. Their inquiry is secured by a distinctive faith

regarding the cosmos and reason: the cosmos does not have to correspond to sensible

experience, or reason, but understanding the cosmos can be advanced through the logic of

reason and sensible experience in the form of experiment. There is not the unknowable, only

the unknown. They have faith that incrementally more and more can be known of that

knowable whole, and they make truth and knowledge claims without hesitation or doubt

regarding either the transparency of language or the value of those claims. In science, theory

follows practice. Science, as practice, does not stop or go round in circles because of

difficulties with theory; certainly not poststructuralist and postmodernist theory.

Incommensurability, the ‘indeterminacy of translation’, and the ‘indeterminancy of

interpretation’ are not problems in practice. Scientific understanding accumulates.

Ironically, it was for the humanities and human sciences that theory—the critical and

cultural theory that emerged from the combination of post-Kantian metaphysics, the

philosophy of language, and the sociology of knowledge—proved disabling to the belief in

unified, objective, knowledge. In those disciplines there developed a ‘rhetoric of

impossibility’ towards the ‘advance’ or accumulation of knowledge.57 Concerned, as they

57 The expression ‘rhetoric of impossibility’ is Eva M. Knodt’s. Eva M. Knodt, Foreword in Niklas Luhmann, Social Systems, trans., John Bednarz, Jr. with Dirk Baecker (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1995), x.

134 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

were, with understanding and meaning (in the Geisteswissenschaften sense), any meaningful

communication depended on the determinancy of language, translation, and interpretation.

As Kant had famously observed: ‘Concepts without empirical intuition (observation)

are empty phrases; empirical intuitions without concepts are blind’.58 The search by the

logical positivists (starting with the scientists and philosophers of the Vienna Circle and

ending with the language philosophers of Oxford) to define exactly what types of phrases are

empty, and what are not, led them away from logical positivism and, eventually, to

Wittgenstein’s ‘rule following’. However, Wittgensteinian ‘rules’, far from being abstract

standards by which language could represent reality, were simply the practical conventions of

learned intersubjective behaviour. The criteria for soundness was meaning, not the ability to

point to an objective reality, even if the pointing and the reality were accepted. By the end of

the twentieth century, Geisteswissenschaften ‘theory’ had produced ‘a derangement of

epistemes’ which seemed ‘to disavow the very core of common sense’.59 Theory had become

so reflexive that it had, in John Zammito’s words, ‘plunged “all the way down” into the

abîme of an almost absolute scepticism … Hypberbolic “theory” threatens especially the

prospect of learning anything from others that we did not already presume’.60 Earlier,

Murray Krieger, reflecting on his long experience as a literary theorist in the American

academy, observed:

We were made aware of both critical and theoretical circularity in our arguments … the reading of the work is determined by the criticism, which is determined by the theory, rather than the other way around. And theory is itself determined by sociopolitical ideology. Thus, questions that turn out to be highly ideological will reveal in advance what, as interpreters, we have been seeking to find; and—lo and behold!—there it is.61

Nevertheless, there is general acceptance of ‘theory’s’ point that neither experience nor

58 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (London: G. Bell and Sons, 1929), 93; quoted in Martin Jay, ‘For Theory’, Theory and Society, 25, no. 2. (Apr., 1996): 173. 59 The phrase is John Zammito’s, the clause is Willard Quine’s and quoted by Zammito. Zammito, A Nice Derangement of Epistemes, 275. 60 Ibid., 275. 61 Murray Krieger, The Institution of Theory (Baltimore and London: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994), 12–13.

135 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

observation is neutral. Empirical data cannot be free from theoretical frameworks, nor can

language be assumed to be univocal or transparent. ‘Scientific’ and ‘unscientific’ beholding

cannot be separated. Culture and science change together. Consequently, discourse which

critiques culture and science within culture, is neither monolithic nor totalizing; it is altered as

much by science as it alters science—which it does through the constitution of the objects and

problems which science investigates. In the academy, research in the humanities and social

sciences, concerned as it is with epistemology, subjectivity, causality and historical

consciousness, cannot ignore research in neurophysiology and psychology (or physics and

mathematics) if it is genuinely to be research at the edge of understanding. If the historian’s

concern is with past subjectivities and experience mediated through individual consciousness,

then clearly it is affected by new understanding in those scientific domains.62 Conversely, the

assumptions behind scientific inquiry need to be probed continuously; the issue of how,

culturally, objects for investigation are constituted and understood is not something science

can answer. Knowledge boundaries and disciplinary means have never been, are not now,

nor will be, either impervious or static.

II

The issue remains, though, that central to the idea of research is the notion of discovery—the

bringing to awareness of new knowledge. The implication here is that new knowledge leads

to new understanding. But that distorts the true relation between knowledge and

understanding since there can be no comprehension that knowledge is new unless it has

changed or confirmed existing understanding. In this sense, new knowledge is a product of

new understanding. New understanding warrants knowledge as new. Therefore, central to

the notion of research as discovery is the perception in the researcher, and then the wider

interpretative community, of new understanding.

The attempt, however, to understand the process whereby existing belief—the subject’s

epistemological ‘steady-state’ condition—is changed to a new steady state, to new belief, has

62 Anthony Grafton, “History’s Postmodern Fates”, Daedalus, 135, Issue 2. (Spring, 2006): 67.

136 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

been the very essence of philosophical inquiry since, at least, Descartes. Increasingly during

the seventeenth century and after, the importance of physiological and anthropological

considerations in any inquiry into the nature and limits of understanding was accepted. In the

twenty-first century, inquiry into the nature and limits of human understanding involves

neurophysiology and psychology as much as it does philosophy. But it also involves

mathematical research and research in computer science and artificial intelligence. Research

in those domains into the way information is extracted from ‘noise’, and how information is

processed in ‘learning’ systems, forms an integral part of the philosophical discussion,63 and

provides useful insight into the question of how belief can be changed.

In natural science it has been established that, physically, it is only changes to a steady-

state that can be sensed—the ‘state’ of the equilibrium state itself cannot be sensed. In the

physical world, data only becomes new data, rather than steady-state ‘background’ data, if it

provides new information. And it is only either difference between incoming data and

‘background’ data, or change to the nature of the incoming data, which classifies otherwise

unremarkable data as new data, thus, the carrier of new information. With living organisms,

visual, aural, olfactory, or tactile data that do not differ from their background are unnoticed;

with humans, noise, odour, or force, for example, that stays unchanging quickly ceases to

register in consciousness. Thus new information is produced either through spatial

(synchronic) difference, or temporal (diachronic) difference. Therefore, arguing by analogy,

in the higher levels of human cognition it is understanding which is the meta-frame—the

Archimedean point—by which information is judged either to be new or not new. The

information is either of value, and thus changes or reinforces understanding, or else

superfluous, thus has no affect. This processed information is stored as new knowledge if the

result of cognitive processing is new understanding. Like data in the physical world,

information in the cognitive world only leads to new understanding if there is either

comparative difference or temporal difference. In the context of humanities disciplinary

inquiry: difference is identified through either comparative or historical analysis. Most

63 For example, Alan Turing’s mathematical studies on machine intelligence and John Searle’s arguments concerning intentionality and artificial intelligence.

137 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

information, like most data, is superfluous. However, whereas superfluous data is filtered out

unconsciously at the physiological level, superfluous information requires conscious

cognitive processing before erasure (forgetting) or relegation as more information (to a

particular location in memory).64

There remains a critical difference between physiological data and intellectual

knowledge. Knowledge is data transformed cognitively to two orders higher in abstraction.

First, data must be placed within context to provide information—and only when data is

placed in a particular context does it provide information. However, the same data in a

different context will produce different information. Thus information is data that has been

transformed or ‘differentiated’ in relation to some selected base parameter (just as in

mathematical calculus where velocity, for example, is the first differential of distance if

distance is differentiated with respect to time). Then, for information to be transformed into

knowledge, it must be placed in a higher, but particular, context. The same information

placed in a different higher context will produce different knowledge. Knowledge is

information that has been transformed through differentiation against a selected higher-order

parameter—the equivalent of the mathematical double-differential (for example, acceleration

which is distance differentiated twice with respect to time: distance to velocity, velocity to

acceleration). In the human world, first-order context is a category or domain—such as the

physical, temporal, subjective, social, political, or cultural fields. Second-order context,

however, is the conceptual or ‘theoretical’ frame in its explanatory form (current cognitive

‘stance’ prior to possible modification as a consequence of the ‘second-differential’).

In this sense, theory is simply second-order reflection; an instinctive process whereby

knowledge is processed. Hans-Georg Gadamer describes ‘modern theory’ as ‘a tool of

construction by means of which we gather experiences together in a unified way and make it

64 Walter Pater identifies the experience of difference in sensation (‘the moment … of delicious recoil’), not sensation itself, as the key to aestheticism and the aesthetic life, and how ‘the flood of external objects’ is reduced to groups of impression by the ‘thick wall of personality’. Walter Pater, The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry, The 1893 Text, ed. Donald L. Hill (Berkeley: The University of California Press, 1980), 186, 187.

138 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

possible to dominate them’.65 Herbert Simon has described a theory as: ‘if not a theory, at

least a point of view that has been proving fruitful over a wide range of applications’.66 The

theoretical frame may be a restricted form suited to particular domain knowledge (geology,

say), or it may be a totalizing form, for example, historical materialism, or . Thus,

for example, Clifford Geertz’s ‘thick description’ would, as cultural anthropological critique,

be second-order output in Geertz’s ‘life-world’, and the ‘thick’ object of his description

would be second-order output in the life-world of the people whose conceptual frame he had

analysed. If this reasoning is accepted, then one must conclude that cultural knowledge is a

product of cultural theory.

For the history discipline, the epistemological process could be said to be not the

ordering of historical facts into a coherent narrative, but the transformation of past facts (data)

into historical facts (information), and then historical facts into interpreted historical facts

(history as knowledge). Marc Gaboriau’s argument that ‘biographical and anecdotal history

… is low-powered history, which is not intelligible in itself and only becomes so when it is

transferred en bloc to form a history of a higher power than itself’, recapitulates this

proposition.67 However, the resulting ‘higher power’ knowledge is only relevant to a

particular referential understanding. Accordingly, there is a wide range of domains of interest

and conceptual frames. Postmodernist privileging of linguistic and rhetorical codes over

‘grand narratives’ represents a clash of theoretical perspectives, and one where the primacy of

synchronic (spatial) understanding over temporal (diachronic) understanding is championed.

Significantly, however, postmodernist argument, as the name conveys, locates itself

historically and relies on historical understanding to argue its case; it doesn’t claim directly

that temporal difference is irrelevant, only that there is no way other than through language

and cultural or social rhetoric to produce knowledge from that difference.

Nevertheless, historical consciousness grounds postmodernist argument, as it does any

65 Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method (London: Continuum, 2006), second revised edition (1989), 450. 66 Herbert A. Simon, “The Architecture of Complexity”, Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 106, no. 6. (Dec. 12, 1962): 467. 67 Quoted in Leonard Krieger, Time’s Reasons, 156.

139 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

synthetic argument. Human understanding is unavoidably historically conditioned, since, at

the most basic level (if the evidence of neurological science is accepted), the mind is moulded

through learning which is embodied through the temporal conditioning of the neural

network.68 Since knowledge of phenomena that are independent of the knowing subject can

be verified (and it is only things independent of the knowing subject which can), there is

confidence, epistemologically, that external stimuli—external actualities—play an essential

role in the neural conditioning. Further, it is sequence detected within otherwise

asynchronous phenomena that is significant. However, any consciousness of the temporal

‘spacing’ of neural stimuli is merely primitive consciousness of time-based phenomena: it is

not historical consciousness in the sense of a higher consciousness derived from historical

knowledge. ‘Experience’ is consequently of two forms: simple—remembering sequences of

apparently linked time-based physical phenomena (simple causality as a function of past,

present, future action), and complex—social and cultural ‘lessons’ learned from higher-order

experience as mediated through historical consciousness.69 Reinhart Koselleck argues that

history can only be a ‘science of experience’:

There is no history which could be constructed independently of the experience and expectations of active human agents … the categories “experience” and “expectation” … claim an indispensable application. Here they resemble, as historical categories, those of time and space.70

Thus, complex understanding implies historical consciousness—in Georg Lukács’

words: ‘When the problem of connecting isolated phenomena has become a problem of

categories, by the same dialectical process every problem of categories becomes transformed

68 The following discussion acknowledges that the intersection of cognitive science and the philosophy of memory is a very active and extensive specialist study, and one which has a long history in philosophy and neuroscience. For example, see David G. Stern, “Models of Memory: Wittgenstein and Cognitive Science”, Philosophical Psychology, 4, Issue 2 (1991): 203–218. 69 F. R. Ankersmit has recently argued for wider recognition of the primary nature of historical experience (‘sublime’ historical experience is his expression). He wants theory and its mediating function removed from historical cognition so that intuition, experience, and historical consciousness connect directly. Ultimately, he argues, sublime experience can erase the difference between past and present and in creating that felt unity enable us to discover ‘something that has been inscribed in our minds a long time ago already.’ Frank Ankersmit, Sublime Historical Experience (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005), 188. 70 Reinhart Koselleck, Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time, trans. Keith Tribe (Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 1985), 269.

140 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

into a historical problem’.71 Pierre Duhem observed that ‘To give the history of a physical

principle is at the same time to make a logical analysis of it’.72 Ernst Mach declared that

there was ‘only one way to (scientific) enlightenment: Historical studies!’73 The implication

of Lukács, Duhem and Mach’s statements is that changes in conceptual categories are what

history is. Isolated facts in isolated categories are objects ‘in’ consciousness, but not objects

in historical consciousness. Judgement requires historical consciousness. Hence if

‘judgement provides the bridge between understanding and reason’ (as Gadamer,

summarizing Kant, concluded), then historical consciousness is central to any sophisticated

use of reason.

Historical consciousness is not, therefore, awareness of physical time, but

conceptualization arising from perceived difference. For Koselleck, the two fundamental

‘anthropological givens’ are experience and expectation and it is the tension between these

which, ‘in ever-changing patterns, brings about new resolutions and through this generates

historical time’.74 Further, the ‘higher order’ recollection of historical time can be quite

independent of the way in which event sequences were burnt into the neural network, as

Proust, in particular, has communicated so powerfully. In recollection we can ‘fold’ the

ribbon of time so that ‘nearness’ is not related to temporal distance along the ribbon but to

contiguity which, in the folding, aligns memory with relevance. Thus, contemporaneity and

anachronism are more complex notions than elapsed time, as are those of duration and ‘flow’.

Our cognitive experience of time—time as ordered in our higher inner-sense—is of the folded

form, not the linear version. Michel Serres describes it as

[A] kind of crumpling, a multiple, foldable diversity … this intuition is clearer than one that imposes a constant distance between moving objects, and it explains more. Everyone is amazed that after 1935 the Nazis, in the most scientifically and culturally advanced country, adopted the most

71 Georg Lukács, History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics (London: Merlin Press, 1971), 186. 72 Pierre Duhem, The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, trans. P. P. Weiner (New York: Atheneum (1914) 1962), 269. Quoted in Mary Tiles, Bachelard: Science and Objectivity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 3. 73 Ernst Mach, History and Root of the Principle of Conservation of Energy (Chicago, 1911), 16. 74 Koselleck, Futures Past, 275.

141 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

archaic behavior. But we are always simultaneously making gestures that are archaic, modern, and futuristic.75

For many people in the twenty-first century there remains, coexistent with the belief in

science, a belief in transubstantiation; for others, including several U.S. senators, there

remains a belief in satanic powers.76

It is the time-based nature of both simple and complex experience, and awareness of

the contingent nature of both types of experience, that ground any second-order reflection

concerned with meaning and understanding—including postmodernist discourse, despite that

discourse’s questioning of the primacy or legitimacy of any particular ordering schemes

resulting from second-order reflection. Neither experience nor discourse can belie the fact

that the physiological, psychological, and cognitive processes are inseparable, and that

theoretical and historical conceptualization are interdependent. No theoretical discourse can

be without an intellectual genealogy, and history as knowledge—doubly transformed past

facts—must be grounded in theory. The transformation of selected historical facts into

interpreted historical facts can only occur within a selected or assumed (conscious or

unconscious) theoretical frame.77

III

There has long been awareness, at least since Aristotle and the Stoics, that more than intellect

is involved in human understanding; that the human being as creator of meanings is more than

a hierarchy of discrete faculties with reason at the top. We need to ‘plow with another heifer

than our reason’, Hamann observed.78 For Ernst Cassirer symbolic understanding, not reason,

75 Michel Serres, Conversations on Science, Culture, and Time, with Bruno Latour, trans. Roxanne Lapidus (Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 1995), 59–60. 76 Anne Summers, “Hillary’s presidential remake leaves the Clinton heartland cold”, Age (Melbourne), 14 January 2006. 77 As R. H. Tawney observed:‘Theories have a history’ (R. H. Tawney, “The Study of Economic History”, Economica, 39. (Feb., 1933): 14. And as Gareth Stedman Jones observed: ‘Those who tried to create theory out of facts, never understood that it was only theory that could constitute them as facts in the first place.’ Gareth Stedman Jones, “The Pathology of English History”, New Left Review, no. 46 (Nov–Dec., 1967): 42. 78 Johann Georg Hamann. Sämtliche Werke, vol. 2, ed. Josef Nadler (Vienna: Herder, 1946– 57), 65; quoted in James C. O’Flaherty, Johann Georg Hamann (Boston: Twayne Publishers, 1979), 49.

142 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

was the common denominator of all human thought, imagination and experience,79 and for

rational thought itself, Hans-Georg Gadamer’s view was that the ‘supersensible substrate’ was

an active element in judgement.80 Understanding forms first in that substrate—as T. S. Eliot

observed with his comment that ‘genuine poetry can communicate before it is understood.81

Life’s deeper meanings do not require discourse for their understanding. Seamus Heaney

spoke recently in an interview of the need for poetry to have ‘some sort of covenant with the

irrational’. ‘The reason I like the last poem’, he said, ‘[is because] it’s kind of a different

stage of life. You’re beginning to be aware of the underground journey a bit more’.82

From the last decades of the twentieth century, increasing research attention has been

paid to emotions and their role in cognitive processes. Emotions are being seen as an integral

part of the evaluative response to objects whereby the concerns, interests, and well-being of

the subject are harmonized. In this role emotion is a form of beholding which enables the

subject to ‘see’ objects in complex ways (it has been defined by others as ‘serious concern-

based construal,83 and ‘rich and dense perceptions’84). The response of fear or anger toward

an object is a complex response which can be understood only as an integration of

physiological, psychological, and rational/cultural processes. In that integrated process,

difference is transformed into ‘otherness’, which is classified as hostile, suspicious, or

marginal, for example.85 Reflection and judgement are neither purely culturally constructed

nor materially determined. For William Connolly, the inseparability of the

79 Cassirer, while an active member of the Vienna Circle, had published his three-volume Philosophy of Symbolic Forms from 1923–1929; by 1930 the book was already being recognized as a seminal publication in the philosophy of culture. Quine had described his time in Warsaw and in 1932 (with members of the Vienna Circle) as ‘the intellectually most rewarding months I have known’. Quoted in Alex Orenstein, ‘Quine, Willard Van Orman (1908–2000)’, in The Shorter Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Craig (Abington: Routledge, 2005), 869 80 Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 48. 81 T. S. Eliot, “Dante”, op. cit. (footnote 22). 82 Quoted in Sam Leith, “Back on home turf”, Age (Melbourne), A2 Supplement, 27 May 2006. Reprinted from the Daily Telegraph. 83 Robert Roberts, “What an emotion is: A Sketch”, The Philosophical Review, 97, no. 2 (Apr., 1988): 184. 84 Martha Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 65. 85 Stephen K. White, “Book Review” [of William Connolly, Neuropolitics], Perspectives on Politics, 1, no. 4. (Dec., 2003): 758.

143 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

‘body/brain/culture network’ means that ‘the classical distinction of kind between culture and

nature becomes translated into interacting layers of biocultural complexity’.86 He argues:

By attending to the body/brain/culture network we multiply the circuits of intercomposition to be studied. We are thereby encouraged to study how cultural disciplines help to shape the organization of the senses, how those experiences provide materials from which second order ideas are formed, how those affect-imbued ideas in turn fold back onto culture, and so on ad infinitum. You thereby come to see how important it is to engage the multimedia complexes of today in which image, sound, words, and rhythm mix together, becoming infused into cultural sensibilities and political orientations.87

Connolly is therefore identifying the need for integrated research. Research output

must satisfy both the specialist particular and the integrated whole. His interest (he is a

political theorist) is in the implications of the integrated whole to the nature and scope of

democratic politics and the normative grounds of judgement and action. His ultimate interest

is in enlarging the political imagination so that as a society we respond more ‘generously’ and

creatively to democratic possibilities, so that we rethink, within our new global contexts, the

ethos by which we enact liberal democratic structures and norms. As research in its broadest

sense, Connolly’s interest is in the practical application of basic research. In other words, he

is interested in the ‘experimental development’ of social products.

It can be seen that the question of how norms are formed, and how mechanistic

physiological models connect to whole person notions of intentionality, autonomy, and

ethical action, remain basic research tasks. The perennial basic research question of the

relation between structure and agency remains, though now science is no longer irrelevant to

that earlier, essentially philosophical, discussion. Science may now enable that ‘circle of

timeless confrontation’ (as Claude Lévi-Strauss described it),88 over the primacy of either

86 William Connolly, Neuropolitics: Thinking, Culture, Speed (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2002), 48. 87 William Connolly, “The Radical Enlightenment: Faith, Power, Theory”, http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory_&_event/. 88 Claude Lévi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology, vol. 2, trans. Monique Layton (New York: Basic Books, 1976), 276.

144 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

structure or agency, to be avoided.

Traditional inquiry was never able to resolve the problem of autonomy—of how agency

could be reconciled with Wittgenstein’s rule-following.89 Bourdieu’s ‘rules of the game’ and

‘habitus’, by which he meant embodied understanding of how to act, was one theory which

gestured towards today’s more integrated biocultural approaches. Habitus structured the rules

of the game, the rules by which one acted, not the action itself. Habitus was a form of

cultural preconscious which structured meaning. However, Bourdieu was never able to

convince sceptics that habitus avoided the problem of reductive mechanism and causality.

His problem was that the question was still considered to be, at its core, philosophical. But

his motivation had been, he said, to try and find an alternative to the

Fictitious alternative between a subjectivism which persists in attempting to find the place of pure origin of a creative action which cannot be reduced to structural determinisms, and an objectivist pan-structuralism which hopes to generate structures directly by a sort of theoretical parthenogenesis.90

Today, with the insights gained from the new biocultural research, we can see that the real

issue is not one of primacy of structure or agency, since they are—like physiology,

psychology, and culture—indivisible and operate within, and as part of, that integrated

biocultural whole.91

By treating culture and nature as interacting layers of biocultural complexity, the basic

research task becomes one of investigating the ‘circuits of intercomposition’. A ‘structure’ in

this model is a higher-order system of differentiation (in effect, a system of transformation)

which allows individual and intersubjective meaning to be produced from heterogeneous

89 Wittgenstein’s rule, though, were social/cultural intuited understandings, not behavioural algorithms. 90 P. Bourdieu, Introduction to P. Bourdieu, L. Boltanski, R. Castel, J-C Chamboredon, Un art moyen, Essai sur les usages sociaux de la photographie (Paris: Minuit, 1965), 22, quoted in Louis Pinto, “Theory in Practice”, in Bourdieu: A Critical Reader, ed. Richard Shusterman (Blackwell Publishers, 1999), 96. 91 Actor-network-theory’s attempt to fuse agency with structure by subsuming them into a larger process of self-organization in complex social systems, is a current approach. See Bruno Latour, Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005).

145 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

information and other-system knowledge (where there is meaning, there must be a system or

structure since meaning can only be immanent and relational—there is no transcendental

meaning). Agency is the subject’s complex reaction to that produced meaning, and reaction

is the complex feedback mechanism whereby harmonization of the body/mind/culture

‘circuits of intercomposition’ is achieved. Thus meaning is generated through the

relationship between structure and agency, and the agent’s second-order reaction to meaning

adjusts structure. The second-order reaction is the confirmation or modification of ‘theory’.

Thus, theoretical frames change meaning, but new meaning affects theory—the Gadamerian

hermeneutical circularity—whereby we come to understand the whole from the parts and the

parts from the whole.92 Similarly at the intersubjective level: because no two individual

understandings are exactly the same, no two cultural contexts are exactly the same, and no

two reactions are exactly the same, so intersubjective and cultural understanding are being

constantly adjusted together and unpredictably. Thus prediction of behaviour as a research

goal makes no sense in any study of this biocultural complexity. Possibility, not prediction, is

the more appropriate goal.

By studying the circuits of intercomposition, rather than subjectivity or meaning-

structures independently, a more holistic perspective can be gained on purposeful human

action. For, clearly, although systems make things possible, they make nothing actual; the

actual requires creative input for its coming to being. Joyce’s Ulysses cannot be explained as

a product of a system; but neither can it be explained as the product of an isolated individual

talent. Nor can political reactions to sociopolitical problems be so explained. The basic

research task becomes one of exploring the interaction of agency and structure—thus how

systems first come into being and, second, change (change which in turn generates new

systems that make new meaning possible, and so on). But by investigating the conditions

intrinsic to structural and creative change, basic research’s actual research objects are the

processes of self-fashioning, not transcendent truth or absolute reality.

92 In William Bouwsma’s words ‘the creative interpretation of experience also shapes experience’; William J. Bouwsma, “From History of Ideas to History of Meaning”, 283. And to which could be added Anthony Giddens’s ‘double hermeneutic’: the agent being interpreted reacts to the interpretation of the interpreting agent (who is aware of that reaction).

146 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

Nevertheless, basic research still remains ‘open’ and at the epistemological and

ontological edge ‘prior’ to any specific subjective or cultural self-fashioning. Basic research

evolves—if for no other reason than that science remains intrinsic to basic research and is a

major force of change both to research’s objects and to the research community’s own

physical/psychological/cultural self-fashioning. History, as the specialist study of cultural

mutation (in effect the study of the mutation of meaning), remains fundamental to any basic

research. Why certain meanings arise, persist, and collapse at particular times and in specific

sociocultural situations is the very matter of academic history.93

Research and Purpose

The quality of ‘openness’ in basic research, while essential, is not sufficient to satisfy the

basic research ethos; that ethos, inflected as it is towards natural science, implies also a sense

of direction. Openness could simply lead to an endless hermeneutical circularity, whereas

progress implies advance, through discovery, towards some objectively meaningful

awareness. Again, this does not mean that the object is the attainment of transcendent

understanding—the fate of Fichte, Schelling and Hegel’s Absolute Idealism warns against

that—but merely to observe that ‘discovery’ implies a continual moving beyond current

boundaries. Hence the discovery of new knowledge implies moving beyond current

boundaries of understanding. Inquiry can never be free from cultural assumptions, for

cultural background can never be entirely transcended, but that does not mean that current

boundaries cannot be transcended at all. Michel Foucault, reflecting on humanistic inquiry,

concluded that all that inquiry could be was an experiment in exceeding current boundaries:

The critical ontology of ourselves has to be considered not, certainly, as a theory, a doctrine, nor even as a permanent body of knowledge that is accumulating; it has to be conceived as an attitude, an ethos, a philosophical

93 The main clause in this sentence is John Toews’, but he was referring to intellectual history and drawing a distinction between it and radical hermeneutics. See John E. Toews, “Intellectual History after the Linguistic Turn: The Autonomy of Meaning and the Irreducibility of Experience”, American Historical Review, 92, no. 4 (Oct., 1987): 882

147 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

life in which the critique of what we are is at one and the same time the historical analysis of the limits that are imposed on us and an experiment with the possibility of going beyond them.94

Could humanistic inquiry then be simply a process of self-fashioning—in Francesco

Varela’s words: a ‘pragmatics of transformation’ in the manner of the Eastern wisdom

traditions such as Confucianism, Taoism, and Buddhism? 95 Perhaps, but only if that inquiry

could be reconciled with the notion of advance. But for the humanities and arts research

communities, what advance means (in the common Western sense of advance) in relation to

going beyond current understanding, is problematical. What is the referent against which

advance is measured? What constitutes valid ‘advancing’ knowledge? In science, advance is

recognized as improvement to the efficacy of models and techniques that explain, predict, or

calculate the performance of empirically verifiable phenomena. But in humanities and arts

research, prediction is an incompatible criterion. Such research can be scholarship whose

purpose is the bringing to awareness of existing knowledge, of things long known—of what

has been thought and said. Scholarship connects to human wisdom and understanding in

culture, of ways of being in the world. Lucien Febvre, reflecting on history and critical

method in humanistic inquiry, considered history to be part of ‘the great endeavour,

transcending history and unifying all the disciplines, of man’s knowing how to think and how

to live’.96 How to be is the focus here.

If, given the finiteness of life, meaning in life was determined to be the purpose of

reflection, then since meaning is relational and constructed, rather than discovered, discovery

might seem to have little relevance to research in the humanities. Geisteswissenschaften

knowledge would change but there would be no apparent independent parameter against

which ‘advance’ could be measured—or the notion of ‘advance’ made meaningful. By this

94 Michel Foucault, “What is Enlightenment?” in The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul Rabinow (New York: Pantheon Books, 1984), 50. 95 The expression was used in a public lecture where Varela argued for ‘re-enchantment of wisdom, understood as non-intentional action’. For Varela, ethics is closer to wisdom than to reason. Francisco J. Varela, Ethical Know-How: Action, Wisdom, and Cognition (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1999), 3–4. 96 The words are Krieger’s: Leonard Krieger, Time’s Reasons, 149 (ref. Lucien Febvre, Combats pour l’histoire (Paris: 1953), 24, 30–33, 55–60).

148 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

reasoning, ‘advance’ in the humanities and arts equates more to recontextualisation than

refinement and accumulation.97

Richard Rorty, like Foucault, has long argued for the abandonment of any notion of

advance towards any objectively meaningful awareness (in the sense of progress towards

awareness of a mind-independent reality). For Rorty, the role of humanistic inquiry is simply

to ‘continue the conversation which constitutes our culture’:

If we see knowing not as having an essence, to be described by scientists or philosophers, but rather as a right, by current standards, to believe, then we are well on our way to seeing conversation [italics in original] as the ultimate context within which knowledge is to be understood. Our focus shifts from the relation between human beings and the objects of their inquiry to the relation between alternative standards of justification, and from there to the actual changes in those standards which make up intellectual history.98

In sum, therefore, conversation and the right to believe, combined with an understanding of

the sociocultural conditions that make belief and shared meaning, and thus justification,

possible. Rorty’s advocacy was for cultural self-fashioning through an engagement with

possibility. Thus the long journey to absolute knowledge finds its end in the cultural

community where it began. In an interview eighteen years later, Rorty remarked that

knowledge was not a matter of ‘getting reality right’, but was a practical matter of learning

how to cope with the world. Instead of talking about ‘truth’, he said, we should talk about

how well our ideas suit our purposes. ‘There are no neutral standards’, he argues.

If you want to convince people of leftist values, you tell them stories about the sufferings of the poor, women, gays and the colonised—all the usual stories. If that doesn’t work, then giving them a philosophical theory is not going to work either.99

97 Richard Rorty argues in just this vein. See Richard Rorty, “Inquiry as Recontextualisation”, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers, vol. 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 102. 98 Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), 389–90. 99 Quoted in Sean Sayers, “Is the Truth Out There” The Australian, Higher Education Supplement, 18 June 1997. The article first appeared in Times Higher Education Supplement.

149 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

The many arguments by critics against what they saw as his empty relativism left him

unmoved. For Rorty, there is no alternative to accepting that essentialism is outmoded.

Intellectual life should be pursued ‘without much reference to the traditional distinctions

between cognitive and noncognitive, between “truth” and “comfort”, or between the

propositional and the nonpropositional’. By so doing we can start ‘thinking of the entire

culture, from physics to poetry, as a single, continuous, seamless activity in which the

divisions are merely institutional and pedagogical’.100

In a similar pragmatic vein, Voltaire had concluded that true knowledge concerned the

practical matter of learning how to cope with the world. At the end of Candide, Martin, the

character who speaks for Voltaire, concluded that life’s secret was to cultivate one’s own

garden and to work without arguing. ‘That is the only way to make life bearable’, Martin

declares.101 It is timeless wisdom. In his 1996 , the Belgian–Australian

scholar Pierre Ryckmans used that precept of Voltaire’s to support his argument for the need

to cultivate the gardens of our minds, to ‘come home’ after life’s long journey ‘into a

discovery of the inner self’.102 In other words, to discover that understanding beyond

instrumental rationality was needed for us to ‘see’ the true human reality. Culture, Ryckmans

claimed, was the means through which we realised the ‘fullness of our humanity’.103 Seeing

the deeper reality of life was ultimately an act of faith. ‘The saying’, Ryckmans said, ‘”to see

is to believe” must be reversed: to believe is to see [italics in original]’.104

These are conclusions reached by eminent researchers after a lifetime of research.

They are their research findings to the question: Why know? But the question of the nature of

academic basic research remains. If ultimately it is wisdom regarding how to act which is the

proper object of knowledge, then current notions of research, tied as they are to notions of

100 Richard Rorty, “Pragmatism without Method”, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 76. 101 Voltaire, Candide; or Optimism, trans. John Butt (London: Penguin Books, 1964), 143–4 102 Pierre Ryckmans, The View From the Bridge: Aspects of Culture (Sydney: ABC Books, 1996). The Boyer Lectures are annual lectures commissioned by the Australian Broadcasting Commission. 103 Ryckmans, The View From the Bridge, vii–viii. 104 Ibid., 9.

150 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

open-ended inquiry and the accumulation of ethically-neutral knowledge, appear to be

flawed. This is particularly the case if the instrumental result of that knowledge is not able to

be identified. If wisdom were to be considered the desired outcome of knowledge, then the

relevance of newness and progress in relation to knowledge and research, is obscure. But

alternatively, if the purpose of humanistic inquiry were to be the attainment of a certain state

of mind through discovery of the inner self, then ‘research’ becomes something quite

different—transcendental meditation, perhaps. Humanistic knowledge, though, is only one

part of the whole knowledge spectrum. Scientific knowledge is the other part. Whatever

form or direction humanistic inquiry might legitimately take, ultimately it must be

reconcilable with scientific knowledge. Both forms of knowledge are integral parts of a

larger epistemological whole, they are not mutually exclusive forms.

In order to maintain a clear research direction and purpose, a strong distinction needs

to be maintained between the two ends of the ‘research’ spectrum: at one end, basic

research—unbounded exploration seeking to move beyond the current edge of

understanding—and at the other, development—the process of transforming new

understanding to ‘valuable’ social ends. It is a process continuum, like Rorty’s

epistemological continuum; the parts are meaningless without the whole, but they are distinct

parts. In the humanities, for whom the individual and society is both the research object and

the end user of that research, it is particularly difficult not to conflate the different processes,

as Ryckmans, Rorty, and Voltaire have done. For governments, which clearly have the

responsibility and authority to specify the purpose of government-funded research, the

question: ‘What is research for?’ is a question that should be directed to development, not to

basic research. The public value of basic research cannot be judged directly: judgement can

only be made of the value of the end product—the developed product—of that basic research.

The problem is that the whole range of intellectual activity, from introspective

discovery to social application of conceptual discovery, is termed ‘research’. The failure to

differentiate between such a complex spectrum of activity means that effective management

of that activity is confused. The mistake governments make is to attempt to direct the

151 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

research itself, not the development based on research. Basic research, by definition, cannot

be directed, it has no intrinsic purpose. The principal drive to acquire knowledge of the

unknown and the inconceivable is visceral—physical and psychological—not rational in the

sense of ‘reasonable’ or ‘purposeful’. Its motivation is satisfaction of the intuitive desire to

know. It is a physiological response to the ‘impulse of curiosity’.105 That is its engine. For

the funding institution, however, the purpose of the open search for new understanding is the

assumption that the results of that search can be instrumental in the achievement of some

‘valuable’ institutional, national, or international objective. As time and resources are never

unlimited, the research and development program at the institutional level will be directed,106

and its elements prioritized. The notion, however, of directed basic research is oxymoronic.

Basic research is ‘open’ thinking which seeks to go beyond current epistemic limits in any

part of the epistemological continuum. Introspection is as ‘functional’ as experimentation in

this task.

II

There are, however, clear and obvious limits to inward-directed research. As Michel Serres

has observed,

Solitude slides so quickly toward inventive delirium and error that the site of knowledge production is never a relation between an individual and his object, but rather one between a growing body of researchers checking on one another and a carved out specialty, defined and accepted by them.107

Research as funded activity must enable knowledge to be derived from it that is both

transferable and verifiable. Similarly, that derived transferable knowledge must have value to

more than the individual researcher. The knowledge must have relevance to ‘normal’ human

contexts, and for the individual researcher to maintain a sense of the ‘normal’, the researcher

105 This is Paul Ricoeur’s expression (and his conclusion, also). Jean-Pierre Changeux and Paul Ricoeur, What Makes Us Think? A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue About Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain, trans. M. B. DeBevoise (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998), 244. 106 Through the identification of ‘strategic basic research’, then ‘applied research’, then ‘experimental development’, etc. This will be discussed further in later chapters. 107 Michel Serres, The Natural Contract (Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 1995), trans. Elizabeth MacArthur and William Paulson, 20.

152 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

must acknowledge the collaborative research body of knowledge as the ultimate benchmark

against which the value of the new knowledge is judged. How otherwise can the individual

be sure that increased understanding through intense introspection or cerebration is not, in

fact, the slippery slope to either the inventive delirium Serres identified, or even madness?

Louis Sass has remarked:

A particular, though common, image of insanity … [is] one that views insanity as necessarily involving mental defect, regression, or some other kind of loss of mental clarity and capacity (a “darkening”). This is an unfortunate over-generalization. For there are, in fact, forms and phases of insanity that may involve not diminished but heightened forms of consciousness and even self-consciousness, not loss of logical capacity so much as an inability to temper and apply reason in accordance with the demands of practical contexts. The insanity of at least some types of schizoid and schizophrenic individuals ... can involve disturbing forms of hyperawareness, and the propensity to let logic ride roughshod over common sense.108

Might, in fact, madness only be an impediment to the ‘downstream’ processes and not to

basic research? Sass was discussing the case of the young nineteenth-century Viennese and

Jewish philosopher Otto Weininger, and was using the case to explore issues of autonomy,

self-consciousness, rational control, psychosis and culture. In Weininger, all these issues had

come into catastrophic collision.

In 1903, in Vienna, Weininger had published an extraordinary book entitled Sex and

Character: An Investigation of Principles.109 The book was a re-working of his Ph.D.

dissertation for which the University of Vienna had awarded him his degree the year earlier.

The dissertation was a philosophical investigation of the biological, psychological, and

logical grounds of sex, sexuality, and character. The examiners, Friedrich Jodl and Laurenz

Müllner, had commented on the dissertation’s denigration of women, and questioned its

108 Louis A. Sass, ‘“A Falling Star”: The Sovereign Self in Otto Weininger” (unpublished draft paper dated 28 January 2004), 6. See also Louis A. Sass, “Introspection, Schizophrenia, and the Fragmentation of Self”, Representations, no. 19, Summer, 1987: 1–34. 109 Otto Weininger, Sex and Character (London: William Heinemann, 1906); [authorised translation of the sixth German edition]

153 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

metaphysical conclusions and its affinity with the worst of German idealistic psychology, but

accepted the dissertation. It was an extraordinary thesis which was made more extreme in the

book.110

Weininger had identified ideal-typical modes of being (characters) emerging from a

duality of biological and ‘vital’ substances that were unevenly distributed across the entire

spectrum of plant, animal, and human life.111 He determined that ‘masculinity’ represented

‘being’ and ‘femininity’ represented ‘non-being’, and by aligning this radical

masculine/feminine polarization with a radical racial/cultural polarization of Aryan and

Jewish types, Weininger advanced the thesis that women and Jews did not possess a rational

and moral self and accordingly deserved neither equality with Aryan men and Christians nor

even freedom. At one point he went further: ‘At this stage it may well be asked if women are

really to be considered human beings at all, or if my theory does not unite them with plants

and animals?’112 Earlier he had observed ‘A female genius is a contradiction in terms, for

genius is simply intensified, perfectly developed, universally conscious maleness’.113 In

Weininger’s final analysis, the ideal-typical woman was reduced to sexuality alone, and he

argued that anyone who failed, or was unable, to pursue the higher, masculine, destiny of

mankind, did not deserve to live. ‘Logic and ethics are fundamentally the same, they are not

more than duty to oneself’, he wrote.114 Three months after the book was published he shot

and killed himself; he was twenty-three years old.

Sex and Character itself came to be so widely read and discussed after Weininger’s

suicide that twelve editions of it were published between 1903 and 1907. His posthumous

reputation and writings became popular points of discussion in Viennese intellectual life.

Herman Broch described Weininger as ‘the most passionate ethical thinker since Kant’.

110 See Chandak Sengoopta, Otto Weininger: Sex, Science, and Self in Imperial Vienna (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2000), 13–20 111 John E. Toews, “Refashioning the Masculine Subject in Early Modernism: Narratives of Self-Dissolution and Self-Construction in Psychoanalysis and Literature, 1900–1914”, Modernism/Modernity, 4, no. 1 (1997): 32. 112 Weininger, Sex and Character, 176. 113 Ibid., 115. 114 Ibid., 96.

154 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

Wittgenstein had written to G. E. Moore: ‘I can quite imagine that you don’t admire W very

much … It is true that he is fantastic, but he is great and fantastic … the greatness lies in that

with which we disagree. It is his enormous mistake which is great’.115 John Toews has

described the phenomenon as ‘one of those literary events that bring apparently disparate

cultural trends into striking focus, that gather the inchoate anxieties and obsessions of an age

(or its literate, self-styled spokespersons) into provocative, synthesizing outline’.116 Despite

wide debate on what Weininger’s story meant—was it just a case of psychosis, or was it

emblematic of modernist anxiety regarding consciousness and identity—there appeared to be

agreement that Weininger’s suicide was the logical product, or, in Louis Sass’s words,

‘almost the corollary’, of the unyielding ethical principles Weininger presented.

In Weininger, it seems likely that narrow rationality and logic had over-ruled wisdom

and common sense to the extent that the fine line between intense intellectualism and insanity

had been crossed. But was Weininger ill? If so, and if, as Foucault has argued, there is as

much a social locus as a medical one to the classification of madness, was then Weininger’s

‘illness’ more cultural than physical? Karl Krauss had described fin-de-siècle Vienna as a

‘research laboratory’ or ‘proving ground for world destruction’.117 That early modernist

intellectual culture was self-reflexive, experimental, and transitional. In a review of Carl

Schorske’s study Fin-de-Siècle Vienna: Politics and Culture, Michael Roth observed:

There is no conclusion to Fin-de-Siècle Vienna. With Kokoschka and Schoenberg, the journey from political to psychological became a new form of engagement; the voyage intérieur became a struggle to express the truths of the instincts without the mediations required by society. Indeed, the modernist artists gazing inward gave up on society and its history as field from which meaning could be made.118

115 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Cambridge Letters: Correspondence with Russell, Keynes, Moore, Ramsay, Straffa, eds Brian McGuiness, G. H. von Wright (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995), 250, letter dated 23 August 1931, quoted in David G. Stern and Béla Szabados, “Reading Wittgenstein (on) Reading: An Introduction”, in Wittgenstein Reads Weininger, eds David G. Stern and Béla Szabados (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 2. 116 Toews, “Refashioning the Masculine Subject”, 31. 117 Sass, “A Falling Star”, 4. 118 Michael S. Roth, “Performing History: Modernist Contextualisation in Carl Schorske’s Fin- de-Siècle Vienna”, American Historical Review, 99, no. 3 (Jun., 1994): 734.

155 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

Weininger demonstrated that the socially unmediated inward gaze was not without

problems. Nevertheless, Vienna at that time was a centre for a stellar cast of intellectuals of

every discipline, including Arnold Schoenberg, Adolf Loos, Karl Kraus, Ludwig

Wittgenstein, Oskar Kokoschka, Sigmund Freud, Georg Trakl, Franz Kafka, Heimito Von

Doderer, Hermann Broch, and Robert Musil.119 In such an environment, intellectual

innovation and new ways of ‘seeing’ were bound to emerge. Wittgenstein judged

Weininger’s views ‘fantastic’ rather than mad.120 Weininger’s publisher declared that ‘It may

be noted with satisfaction that the book is by no means in harmony with contemporary

thought’. Nor was Weininger insensitive to the ‘abnormality’ of his views. In the Preface he

sought to explain that his interest was the ideal and concerned ‘meaning in the universe’, not

the mundane and personal. Thus he sought, he said, to go ‘beyond simple and superficial

phenomena’ but acknowledged that such explanation ‘cannot in the smallest way rehabilitate

me in the minds of women’.121 He defended his work against accusations of unproven

speculation by arguing that if one’s object was to look behind phenomena, then understanding

‘cannot arise … although every age expects it, as a synthesis of however great a sum of

empirical knowledge’. ‘Proof’ in such investigations as his, he argued, ‘means no more than

the agreement of new experience with old experience’; knowledge produced by experience

and imagination—‘the creative hand of nature’—was as valid as that ‘produced

experimentally by men’.122

From the evidence, it is beyond debate that Weininger was highly intelligent, but that

fact by itself provides little useful information. Weininger certainly makes problematical the

nature of the relationship between intelligence, rationality, sanity and survival. But his case

also makes clear that any attempt to make sense of it requires first an understanding of that

complex intersection of cultural, social, intellectual and personal forces that was Weininger,

his world, and his audience.

119 Toews, “Refashioning the Masculine Subject”, 31. 120 See footnote 115 above. 121 Weininger, Sex and Character, iii, v. 122 Ibid., v, vii.

156 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

Weininger also makes problematical the relationship between ‘pure’ inquiry and the

form in which the results of that research are transmitted and used by a non-specialist public.

Weininger understood that ‘pure’ inquiry required getting outside normative intellectual and

cultural assumptions; new understanding required, as he said, to get ‘outside’ empirical

knowledge. And as John Toews has commented, the Weininger ‘phenomenon’ had ‘an

enormous impact all across Europe in setting the terms for the discussion of gender, sex, and

race’.123 But Weininger’s scholarship makes clear that ‘meaning in the universe’ required

greater epistemological balance than he demonstrated. Absent from his writing is any

acknowledgement of the historically conditioned nature of philosophical and ethical argument

on which his thesis rests. There is a superfluity of Kantian self-consciousness and Absolute

Idealism, but no historical consciousness. The very ‘purity’ of his analysis demonstrated a

lack of balance, thus understanding arising from it alone would be unbalanced.

Understanding ultimately requires more integrated knowledge; and when that understanding

is transmitted outside the research environment, some idea of the purpose that understanding

will serve, is required.

III

If research is exploration at the epistemological and ontological edge, then Weininger’s thesis

is very much within the boundaries of basic research. His might be research which falls at the

early hurdles of either validation or specialist credibility, but it remains the output of a

research specialist. What it does show definitely is that unbounded research, while remaining

undirected and unbounded, needs to operate within a larger management frame that performs

three necessary functions which unbounded research, by its nature, cannot perform. A

process is needed to validate the research, judge the potential value of further research in the

chosen specialist area, and identify the purpose which products developed from that research

123 John E. Toews, “Review [Untitled]” Journal of Modern History, 74, no. 4 (Dec., 2002): 823. The wide range of writers, philosophers, artists, musicians, and other thinkers included, as well as Wittgenstein: Karl Kraus, August Strindberg, Oswald Spengler, Arnold Schoenberg, Karl Popper, and Herman Broch (who called Weininger ‘the most passionate ethical thinker since Kant.’), Franz Kafka, D.H. Lawrence, Oskar Kokoschka, James Joyce, Robert Musil, Italo Svevo, Gertrude Stein, Heimito von Doderer, Elias Canetti, Djuna Barnes, Georg Trakl, William Carlos Williams, Ford Madox Ford. See Jacques Le Rider, op. cit. and Wittgenstein Reads Weininger, op. cit.

157 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

will serve. In this larger frame, judgement of research value is made against assessments of

research fecundity, not the research’s compliance to social or cultural norms. ‘Normality’ in

the social sense is irrelevant within the basic research enclave; within research’s purview,

normativity is an epiphenomenon to be inquired into like any other. However, outside the

research domain and inside the development domain, notions of ‘normality’ are intrinsic to

questions of value and purpose and decisions regarding the ‘riskiness’ of the research

questions, and hence to decisions regarding the allocation of limited funding. In for-profit

companies, the business model defines ‘normality’ through its mission statements and market

definitions, but the owners of that model may adjust those statements and definitions if they

judge that research has created new business opportunities. New markets are created often by

new ‘abnormal’ products. Many companies deliberately strive for products that are

revolutionary. For many, the competitive strategy is to produce unorthodox, socially

innovative, products. But that judgement is made through instrumental reasoning concerning

developed products, not from the impulse of curiosity.

For research in the academy, research which deliberately operates as much outside

social or cultural norms as within them, and whose research transforms social consciousness

and common understanding as much as it informs them, the need for a well defined,

conceptually complex, and effective research management structure, is essential. Yet there is

no such formalized structure in evidence. In Australia, neither Government nor universities

have distinguished between research, development, ethical-political-requirements definition,

and knowledge application in any way that enables unbounded and undirected research to

exist comfortably within a socially responsible, economically sensible, and commercially

efficient funding structure. Research into aspects of infant health competes equally (though

through separate funding bodies) for support with research into notions of transcendence in

Beowulf. Infant health researchers need not fear for their funding. And yet questions such as

‘What is knowledge?’, ‘What do we understand?’ and ‘What do we want knowledge for?’

remain just outside the edge of understanding—despite Government’s insistence that they

know.

158 Ch. 3: Knowledge and Understanding

159

160

DOES HISTORY HAVE A FUTURE?

An Inquiry into History as Research

PART II: FUTURE

161

162

CHAPTER 4

INTEGRATED PURE INQUIRY

Being a humanist means that you try to behave as decently, as honourably, as you can without any expectation of rewards or punishments in an after-life. When we had a memorial service for Isaac [Asimov] a few years back, I spoke at it and said at one point, ‘Isaac is up in heaven now’. It was the funniest thing I could think to say to an audience of humanists. Believe me, it worked—I rolled them in the aisles. If I should ever die, God forbid, I hope people will say, ‘Kurt is up in heaven now’. That’s my favourite joke. —Kurt Vonnegut Jr.1

It is not the human, then, that is under interrogation but the “human”—the process that produces the name, and everything that that has been done in that name … The “human” and its accompaniment, the ideology of “humanism”, are the metaphysical shields protecting us from an inclement environment. If we were to peer inside the epithelium of the “human,” what would we find there, hidden behind the metaphysics of subjectivity? —Paul Sheehan: Becoming Human2

By the late twentieth century, our time, a mythic time, we are all chimeras, theorized and fabricated hybrids of machine and organism; in short, we are cyborgs. The cyborg is our ontology; it gives us our politics. The cyborg is a condensed image of both imagination and material reality, the two joined centers structuring any possibility of historical transformation … The cyborg incarnation is outside salvation history … In a sense, the cyborg has no origin story in the Western sense; a ‘final’ irony since the cyborg is also the awful apocalyptic telos of the West’s escalating dominations of abstract individuation, an ultimate self untied at last from all dependency, a man in space. —Donna Haraway: ‘A Manifesto for Cyborgs’3

Inquiry’s Moving Edge

If the academy can be accused of failing to differentiate adequately between research and its application, then equally it can be defended by observing that not only are those entities not

1 Quoted in John Preston, “Die? I’d rather laugh”, Sunday Telegraph, reprinted in Age (Melbourne), 18 February, 2005. 2 Paul Sheehan, ed., Becoming Human: New Perspectives on the Inhuman Condition (Westport: Praeger Publishers, 2003), 8. 3 Donna Haraway, “A Manifesto for Cyborgs: Science, Technology, and Social Feminism in the 1980s”, in The Postmodern Turn: New Perspectives on Social Theory, ed. Steven Seidman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 83, 84.

163 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

easily separated, they also are interdependent and dynamic.4 The research ‘edge’ is

continually moving, which means that the application boundary is continually moving also.

Yesterday’s basic research is today’s experimental development and tomorrow’s new

technology and new legislation. Thus the contents of both the research and application

domains are inextricably affected by the historically contingent ‘space of experience’ and

‘horizon of expectation’ of the research community and the society of which that community

is part.5 Michel Foucault, in his advocacy of a new ‘critical ontology of ourselves’ (a form of

strategic basic research or applied research)6, acknowledged this historical contingency in his

observation that ‘the critique of what we are is at one and the same time the historical analysis

of the limits that are imposed on us and an experiment with the possibility of going beyond

them’.7 Our notions of ourselves evolve and change in response to our times, and with that

evolution the research subjects and the application areas change also. Basic research, no

matter how epistemologically and ontologically ‘unbounded’ it may strive to be, is inevitably

shaped by what society takes to be natural or self-evident, even if those understandings form

the point of departure for basic research’s conceptual inquiry. Basic research is shaped by

historical contingency even as its content is created from the free-play of curiosity and

creative reason. Further, the nature of the academy’s relationship with government and

society means that basic research, ultimately, must connect to the acquisition of ‘valuable’

socio-cultural products. The connection might be indirect and delayed, but there must be

one—as clearly there is, since new technology, new perceptions, and new legislation are

unavoidably shaped by the ideas and conceptual ‘paradigm shifts’ that emerge from research

at the epistemological and ontological ‘frontier’.

The issue for the academy if it is to retain a distinctive and unique connection to the

creation and transfer of knowledge is how to manage effectively the subtle differences

4 Problems with classification and measurement of the various research and development categories is a central theme of the Frascati Manual. 5 The quoted phrases are from Reinhart Koselleck, Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time (Cambridge MA.: The MIT Press, 1985), 267. 6 These classifications will be discussed below. 7 Michel Foucault, “What is Enlightenment?” in The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul Rabinow (New York: Pantheon Books, 1984), 50

164 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

between the different activities that form the research, development, and innovation

continuum. At one end of that continuum is basic research which is motivated by the desire

simply to understand more deeply (‘pure’ inquiry): at the other is the transfer of valuable

ethical, political, cultural and technological products into the national or international ‘user’

community. One end is grounded in the continual probing of the foundations of

understanding regardless of where ethically or politically that inquiry might lead, the other is

grounded in the application of normative humanist understanding to pragmatic social ends.

The twenty-first century, however, presents new difficulties for our understanding of

what ‘humanist’ and ‘pragmatic social ends’ might mean. Bio-engineering and genetic

engineering raise questions on what in future ‘human’ and ‘intelligent’ might mean, and

environmental degradation and climate change raise questions on what in future ‘pragmatic’

and ‘intelligent action’ might mean. It seems that new conceptual frames are required if

society is to adapt successfully to the new global environment, and it is the university which

is best able to assist society make that intellectual transition.

II

For the humanities, for whom society is both the research object and the end user of its

products, it is particularly difficult not to conflate the research and development processes.

Since Kant’s response in 1784 to the question: ‘What is Enlightenment’ (which he concluded

was ‘the courage to use your own understanding’)8 the question of the nature of the ‘modern’

present and what an intelligent response to that present should entail has been at the centre of

humanities inquiry. By the end of the nineteenth century, attempts to answer the question of

what modernity (Enlightenment’s product) meant had become central to

Geisteswissenschaften and drawn further attention to the problems inherent in the separation

of scientific and humanistic studies. Max Weber took the question of how the modern world

came to think of itself as modern as the central research problem. For him, both agency

8 I. Kant, “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?”, letter dated 30 September 1784, http://www.english.upenn.edu/~mgamer/Etexts/kant.html, [19/3/08]. The letter was to the influential Berlin newspaper Berlinische Monatsschrift who posed the question.

165 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

(autonomy, intentionality—Geist) and structure (mechanism, causality—Natur) were

involved in the answer, and any answer would require their integration. His ‘ideal-types’

were the structure whereby the rational/irrational agent’s actions could be interpreted.9

Weber’s main motivation, however, was not inquiry as basic research, but the application of

the knowledge gained to a better understanding of how to live. H. Stuart Hughes comments:

As his widow put it, he took it upon himself “to bear” without flinching “the antinomies [italics in original] of existence”—to live without illusions … When he was once asked what his learning meant to him, he answered quite simply: “I want to see how much I can endure”.10

By the latter decades of the twentieth century, and now in the twenty first century, the

question of the nature of the present and what an intelligent11 response to that present should

entail has been at the core of the ‘modern–postmodern’ debate—as Wayne Gabardi has

observed:

It is in the philosophical and political tension between "modernity" (centered on the Enlightenment project of critical rationality and human emancipation) and "postmodernity" (with its radical cultural and epistemological critique of modernity) that our transitional time has been defined.12

The task is both to inquire into one’s time, and respond to it. Thus, no matter how basic the

research, it is unavoidably part of the discourse of how to act in the present.

The reaction in the nineteenth century against ‘pure’ Hegelian and Fichtean inquiry

resulted from the desire to reorient inquiry toward practical action.13 Marx’s criticism of

Feuerbach’s (and Hegel’s) philosophical Idealism was that it ‘[did] not grasp the significance

9 See, for example, Wolfgang Schluchter, Paradoxes of Modernity: Culture and Conduct in the Theory of Max Weber, trans. Neil Solomon (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1996), 179–243. 10H. Stuart Hughes, Consciousness and Society: The Reorientation of European Thought 1890– 1930 (London: Macgibbon & Kee, 1959), 290, quote from Marianne Weber, Max Weber: Ein Lebensbild (Heidelberg, 1950), new edition, 731. 11 What ‘intelligent’ might mean in the modern/postmodern world is discussed in a later Section. 12 Wayne Gabardi, “Review Essay: The Philosophical Politics of the Modern–Postmodern Debate”, Political Research Quarterly, 47, no. 3 (Sep., 1994): 769 13 John Toews has remarked, however, that: ‘the belief that the problem of transition from theory to practice first arose around 1840 and marked a new departure in the Hegelian tradition is clearly based on ignorance of earlier developments.’ John Edward Toews, Hegelianism: The Path Toward Dialectical Humanism, 1805–1841 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980), 3.

166 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

of “revolutionary”, of “practical–critical”, activity’—that ‘philosophers have only interpreted

the world … the point is to change it’.14 The purpose of critical theory, which derived from

Marxist (and Freudian) theory, was political and social action. The conceptual exploration of

the implications of Marxist and Freudian theory by the ‘Frankfurt school’ of researchers was

the means only to the desired end which was immanent critique.15 In 1937 Max Horkeimer

had stressed the need to distinguish between traditional theory and critical theory; the former,

he said, meant ‘the sum-total of propositions about a subject, the propositions being so linked

with each other that a few are basic and the rest link with these’, the latter was ‘the unfolding

of a single existential judgement’ that it need not be so; man can change reality’.16 In this

definition research and development (or theory and its experimental application) are one

activity, but in his emphasis on human self-assertion, justified by his conviction that the

dialectic of enlightenment was leading mankind into an abyss, Horkheimer was identifying

the application of developed theory—development—as the main task.

Similarly, R. H. Tawney—as Professor of Economic History in the University of

London (and adherent to Marxist and Weberian methods for social critique)—was insistent

throughout his inaugural lecture that ‘research is a means, not an end’.17 For him, ‘research

supplies the data’ and historians needed to understand that ‘it is less important to discover

new materials than to see the meaning of old’.18 For too long, he said, historians ‘have

preferred burrowing to climbing. They make a darkness and call it research’. But this last

criticism was generated by what (in his words: ‘with certain conspicuous exceptions’) he saw

as historians’ continual employment of ‘unanalysed concepts—nation, political power,

property, progress, commercial supremacy, and a host of similar clichés—with an

14 Notes 1 and 11 of Karl Marx, Theses on Feuerbach. 15 This is not to imply that critical theory was a coherent body of thought possessing thematic unity. Members and associates of the ‘school’ were, intellectually, relatively independent. See Dieter Misgeld, [Review] Untitled, New German Critique, no. 41 (Spring–Summer, 1987): 178–186 (see 178– 180), and Wayne Gabardi, [Review] Untitled, New German Critique, no. 41 (Spring–Summer, 1987): 166–178 (see 166, 167, 177, 178) 16 Max Horkheimer, “Traditional and Critical Theory” in Critical Theory: Selected Essays, trans. Matthew J. O’Connell et. al. (New York: Herder and Herder, 1972), 188, 227, quoted in Martin Jay, “For Theory”, Theory and Society, 25, no. 2 (Apr., 1996): 170. 17 R. H. Tawney, “The Study of Economic History”, Economica, 39. (Feb., 1933): 13. 18 Ibid., 20, 13–14.

167 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

exasperating naïveté’.19 Earlier he had emphasized that ‘It is obvious that the historian must

be interested in theory’, first, because of theory’s necessary hermeneutical function, and

second, because ‘Theories have a history’.20 With these remarks, Tawney was articulating

the timeless motivation for research—to understand—but for him the term ‘research’

described activity which was ancillary to the historian’s main task, specifically, the

illumination of research materials through conceptual critique, and the practical application of

that new knowledge.21 Tawney had a life-long belief in history as a human and humanizing

discipline;22 thus the single object of research was socially useful understanding, not the

‘advance’ of knowledge for the purpose of advancing knowledge. In Tawney’s schema,

discovery was a function of applied research. The application of historical research to social

action was the point of history. Social action was the rationale for research. Basic research

had no separate meaning.

If Tawney’s idea of history could be said to have fused a number of research and

development processes, then the idea of history espoused by historians such as George

Macaulay Trevelyan altogether occluded the notion of history research as epistemological or

ontological inquiry. Trevelyan expressly wished to separate history from that ‘scientific’

ethos. For him, history and ‘science’ should be seen as separate domains. In his rebuttal of

Bury’s view that history should be pursued in the spirit of science, Trevelyan had declared

that ‘It is not man’s evolution but his attainment that is the great lesson of the past and the

highest theme of history’.23 Trevelyan spoke as the historian-poet; he wrote of the ‘human

spirit’. History should celebrate living. It should acknowledge the progressive betterment of

society through the application of reason and the getting of civilization. And he was not

without supporters, even among the more scientific cohort of historians. Herbert Butterfield,

writing shortly before Trevelyan’s death, said that although Trevelyan ‘had not been the

19 Ibid., 19. 20 Ibid., 14. 21 Ibid., 19. 22 Michael Bentley, Modernizing England’s Past: English Historiography in the Age of Modernism, 1870–1970 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 131. 23 George Macaulay Trevelyan, Clio, A Muse and Other Essays Literary and Pedestrian (London: Longmans, Green and Co., 1913), 12.

168 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

greatest technician amongst our historians … I wonder whether he is not the one [historian]

who most definitely bears the marks of greatness’. Butterfield referred to what he called

Trevelyan’s ‘grandeur of the soul’ and continued:

From his combination of qualities—from the whole man—there comes a deep human wisdom which is his commentary on the story he narrates … few of his contemporaries achieved such moments of poetry … He belongs to an urbane world that is really Edwardian, and as a survival of that world he is beyond price.24

Deep human wisdom was not a product of scientific research. ‘Grandeur of soul’, not critical

method, was the most valuable aid to the study of the human world.

But it was just that notion of reason and progress promoted by Trevelyan which

thinkers such as Adorno and Horkeimer attacked (as Nietzsche had). For them the ‘humanist

project’ was both fundamentally flawed and historically exhausted.25 Inquiry’s edge had

moved on. Not only was the question of the ‘human condition’ problematic, so too was the

question of the rational grounding of normative critique. Where was that Archimedean point

from which any sense could be made of notions of reason and ‘progress’?

In the early clashes between modernists and postmodernists in the 1970s, the

underlying issue was whether critical reconstruction or radical deconstruction was the more

appropriate response to the ‘postmodern condition’. By the , the ‘second wave’ of this

polemical encounter was concerned less with polarizing polemics and more with synthesis.

In particular, the synthesis of critical rationality, ontological identity/difference, and political

action.26 There was a need, Richard Bernstein felt, to advance what he called ‘non-

foundational pragmatic humanism’. The question of how to navigate between ‘the Scylla of

24 Herbert Butterfield, MS, Box 73, “Historiography in England” [1962], 1–2, quoted in , G. M. Trevelyan: A Life in History (London: HarperCollinsPublishers, 1992), 212. 25 In their introduction to Dialectic of Enlightenment (1944), Horkheimer and Adorno wrote: ‘It turned out, in fact, that we had set ourselves nothing less than the discovery of why mankind, instead of entering into a truly human condition, is sinking into a new kind of barbarism … we still trusted too much in the modern consciousness’. Max Horkheimer, Theodor W. Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. John Cumming (New York: Continuum Publishing Company, 1993), xi 26 Gabardi, “Review Essay”, 770. For example, Gabardi cites the approach taken by thinkers such as Fred Dallmayr, Jürgen Habermans, and Richard Berstein.

169 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

“groundless critique” and the Charybdis of rationally grounded critique that “rests” upon

illusory foundations’ was ‘if not the central question—then at least a central question that is

at the very heart of the “modern/postmodern” debates [italics in original]’.27 The concern,

therefore, was with how to better integrate the research, development, and innovation

processes.

Today, with issues such as environmental degradation, global warming, genetic

engineering, and biotechnology, inquiry’s edge has moved even more dramatically and the

new focus has brought even more urgency to the need for the synthesis of praxis and action,

and for the synthesis of scientific and humanistic inquiry. Now the question is not ‘the

human condition’, but what ‘human condition’ means. Does the term ‘human nature’ still

provide any useful information, or is it simply an ideological term from an outdated

anthropocentric intellectual heritage? Current bioethical and environmental issues demand

decisions by governments and society on how to act intelligently, but what ‘intelligent action’

means in the new bioethical and ‘biospherical’ world needs clarification. Explanation using

only current notions of normativity, is not sufficient. The normative ‘space’ itself requires

interrogation (and expansion).

III

In 2006, a leading Australian representative of technocracy and ‘free enterprise’ was

presenting his version of the new reality to a select group. Don Argus, the chairman of the

global resource company BHP-Billiton, was addressing a business investment forum, but was

warning that economic measures of ‘value creation’ were too narrow, that society looked at

much broader ideological indicators before it ‘rewarded’ companies.28 He warned of

‘militant activism’ (he referred to the destruction in France of a McDonald’s outlet) and

concluded it would become more prevalent.

27 Richard J. Bernstein, The New Constellation: The Ethical–Political Horizons of Modernity/Postmodernity (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991), 2, 8. 28 Speech delivered at the (Australian) Investment and Financial Services Association conference, Gold Coast Convention and Exhibition Centre, 2–4 August 2006.

170 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

I’m sure the world is going to see more and more of this type of behaviour as we start to enter the complex debates on global warming and energy shortages and water conservation that will be required for nations to survive.29

The subject was now the clash of existential values and basic survival. The object was not

spiritual nourishment, but access to sufficient drinking water. Narrow economic rationality is

now being replaced by a broader reasoning. The seemingly benign term ‘modern economy’,

for most of the twentieth century simply the neutral description of a self-evident ‘good’, is

now seen to be no less historically contingent and ideological than the capitalist ideology on

which it is based.

The chairman of a company such as BHP-Billiton does not speak inexpediently in

public. No matter how frank or speculative the words may seem, they are advised and reflect

considered opinion. Business opinion tries to anticipate the deep undercurrents in society that

are only half articulated, but which indicate ‘the direction the wind will be blowing’ in the

future. The wind, they sense, will be blowing from a more sombre direction. The metaphors

being used in society are now more biological, the note is survival not celebration, the focus

is on species and basic needs not ‘man’ and the grandeur of his soul and his attainments.

Notions of human reality itself are changing.

Peter Doherty, who in 1996 was awarded the Nobel Prize for Physiology or Medicine,

spoke, as a scientist, of the new human reality:

The application of hygiene, the development of vaccines, the discovery of antibiotics, and improvements in agriculture have led to an explosion in human numbers. There are six times more people on the planet than there were in 1800 at the beginning of the industrial revolution. Forests are being cleared with extraordinary rapidity, soil quality is being degraded, the oceans are being fished out and we are losing biological species at an incredible rate. So far as the natural world is concerned, it would be better

29 Marc Moncrief, “More to returns than profit: BHP head”, Age (Melbourne), ‘Business’, 5 August 2006.

171 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

if human beings had remained mired in superstition, ignorance, and the early and unpredicted death that goes with those approaches to life.30

The humanist John Gray, provoked recently by the same issues Doherty identified, described

his perception of the new reality:

History is not an ascending spiral of human advance, or even an inch-by- inch crawl to a better world. It is an unending cycle in which changing knowledge interacts with unchanging human needs.

He then declared his somewhat apocalyptic conclusion:

History may have no meaning … but ‘we’ can give it one. ‘We’ are not mankind, however; and the human animal is itself only a passing tremor in the life of the planet. The meaning believers in progress imagine they can impose on history is an expression of their hopes and fears, and bound to be lost in the drift of time. Fortunately, the Earth is larger and more enduring than anything produced by the human mind. For humans, the growth of knowledge means only history as usual—if on a rather larger scale of destruction. For the Earth, it is only a dream, soon to end in peace.31

This is the universe looking down. ‘We’ is not us. It is not a ‘human’ perspective but a

perspective of the human. The centre of consciousness in Gray’s scenario, and the

Archimedean point from where the eye of judgement surveys, is located outside human

consciousness. ‘Spirit’ here is more than just human spirit. Its focus is not the individual or

the society, nor even the nation or nations: it is the ‘biosphere’. The boundary is no longer

simply the limit of anthropocentric thought. The edge is beyond anthropocentricity. Thus, as

Michel Serres has argued: the Hobbesian ‘social contract’, for so long the concept central to

society’s understanding of itself, has ‘made us leave the state of nature to form society … as

if [society was] no longer rooted in anything but its own history’. Serres argues that contract

must now be replaced with a ‘natural contract’.32 The domination of nature is not progress,

he says. ‘At stake is the Earth in its totality, and humanity, collectively. Global history

30 Peter Doherty, “Plagues, Pestilence and How we Deal with Them”, MDHS Dean’s Lecture, University of Melbourne, 1 August 2006. 31 John Gray, Heresies (London: Granta Books, 2004), 14. Earlier quote, 3. In 2004, Gray was Professor of European Thought at the London School of Economics. 32 Michel Serres, The Natural Contract, trans. Elizabeth MacArthur and William Paulson (Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 1995), 34

172 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

enters nature; global nature enters history: this is something utterly new in philosophy.’33

It is also something utterly new in history. History here has a different meaning. Old

boundaries fail. Anthropocentricity becomes an historical concept. But if we were to

properly explain anthropocentric belief—either rationalized or intuitive—how deeply should

we trace? Daniel Dennett has submitted that the emergence of belief was ‘Somewhere

between a hundred million and three million years—depending on when we decide to date the

birth of human culture.’ As he observes, it took roughly the same length of time to create

homo sapiens as it did to create ‘daisies and snail darters, blue whales and spotted owls …

We correctly intuit a kinship between the finest productions of art and science and the glories

of the biosphere’.34 Body, brain, culture and biosphere are one indissoluble whole. As

Maitland famously remarked, ‘such is the unity of all history that any one who endeavors to

tell a piece of it must feel that his first sentence tears a seamless web’.35 But Maitland’s

descriptor ‘all’ now has a wider meaning. There are no obvious boundaries to any

disciplinary inquiry.

IV

The exploration of ‘humanity’ and its future seems now more connected to

understanding the whole which is culture and nature—Geist-Natur—than each separately.

Basic research would now seem necessarily to have to place its point of observation not just

outside culture, or society, or nature, but to somewhere outside the combined entity. And if

‘humanity’ is to survive, it would seem that effective management of the processes whereby

research and development processes are meaningfully integrated with the processes for social

and political innovation and action, is now critical.

The relationship between intelligence and survival itself requires research—as the case

of Weininger demonstrates. Is survival the highest ‘human’ (cultural-being) goal? One does

33 Ibid., 4. 34 Daniel C. Dennett, Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1995), 511. 35 F. W. Maitland, “A Prologue to a History of English Law”, The Law Quarterly Review, 14 (1898): 13.

173 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

not live solely in order to survive. An enriching aspect of ‘humanness’ is acceptance of one’s

short span; of the limits imposed by death on life; that life’s meaning is in the understanding

of its finitude; that ‘life’ is in its living. To be ‘human’ is to accept that individual survival is

not the highest priority in anything other than a primitive biological sense. Love for others,

honour, loyalty, are just some of the reasons countless people in the past, now, and in the

future have demonstrated and will demonstrate that this is so. At a sociocultural level, self-

preservation means more than raw instinct. Sociocultural notions of human dignity and self-

respect are as powerful as fear and hunger in determining human action. As Jürgen

Habermas has identified,

The ‘clearly defined' problem of death and a corresponding criterion of survival are lacking because societies never reproduce 'naked' life but always a culturally defined life.36

Intelligent behaviour here is the assigning of a secondary value to personal survival.

Is intelligence then a ‘human’ fatal flaw? The conclusion would depend on what

measure of ‘success’ was used: whether Geist or Natur. Biologically, intelligence may be an

impediment to survival, or at least ‘grandeur of soul’ may be. Humanity may have to rely on

the mean-spirited or squalid-of-soul if it is to have a future. Indeed, if it was the enrichment

of life, not its prolongation, that was humanity’s highest goal, should research priorities, thus

Government research funding, be changed? Might the current proportions of funding

between medical research and the creative arts be reconsidered? How should intelligence be

judged? What knowledge is valuable? These questions are not simply issues of

administration, but neither are they questions within the capabilities of the single researcher

or single discipline to answer.

Current bioethical and neuroethical concerns demonstrate that even differences between

the human and the non-human are dynamic.37 There soon will be neither clear nor obvious

36 J. Habermas, N. Luhmann, Theorie der Gesellschaft oder Sozialtechnologie? (Frankfurt, 1971), 151, quoted in Thomas McCarthy, “Complexity and Democracy, or the Seducements of Systems Theory”, New German Critique, no. 35, Special Issue (Spring–Summer, 1985): 31. 37 Current issues being discussed by the (US) President's Council on Bioethics are those of enhancement vs. therapy, the definition of ‘human’, the nature of human dignity, the ethics of

174 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

answers to where the boundary between technology and the human lies. Natural science is

becoming embedded in the philosophy of subjectivity, and in the philosophy of difference,

and, consequently, in notions of autonomy and freedom. Jürgen Habermas has observed of

genetic engineering:

The manipulation of the makeup of the human genome … uproot[s] the categorical distinction between the subjective and the objective … Knowledge of one’s own genome being programmed might prove disruptive, I suspect, for our assumption that we exist as a body or, so to speak, “are” our body’.38

Advances in neurotechnology—particularly the technological enhancement and manipulation

of cognitive function—now mean that notions of autonomy and autonomous reason become

problematic. Similarly, biotechnology problematizes the traditional philosophical separation

of the animate and the inanimate. With the insertion of technology into the human body, and

technology’s ability, through enhancement or other manipulation, to reconstruct identity and

social function, technology is now a form of life. This instrumentalization of human nature

is, Habermas argues, initiating a change in the ethical self-understanding of the species. In

Habermas’s view, the new self-understanding is no longer consistent with normative self-

understanding that assumes as essential modes of living, self-determination and responsible

action.39

But whereas Habermas may be correct in identifying an inevitable change in normative

understanding, he is not correct if he is implying that the enhanced or altered ‘body’ is

incapable of responsible action. The blurring of the distinction between the ‘natural’ and the

manufactured means only that our notions of alterity need revision. Instrumentalization

means only that there is now no absolute alterity regarding ‘natural’ and ‘hybrid’ bodies.

neurotechnology etc. See http://www.bioethics.gov/. Jonathan Moreno, currently the director of the Center for Biomedical Ethics at the University of Virginia, considers the regulation of human enhancement, and neurotechnology, to be the major social policy challenges of this century (Jonathan D. Moreno, ‘Mind Wars: Brain Research and National Defense’, speech delivered to Human Rights for the 21st Century: Rights of the Person to Technological Self–Determination conference held 11–13 May 2007, New York). 38 Jurgen Habermas, The Future of Human Nature (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003), 42. 39 Ibid., 42.

175 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

Socially acceptable standards of behaviour can still be required of a ‘person’, regardless of

the person’s level of hybridity. The social boundaries that define the ‘person’ are set

normatively, not descriptively, they change as the society and its environment change. As

Rhana Pike has observed, except for the distinction between person and property, no current

legislative or statutory definition of the person exists. But even the distinction between

person and property is not universal—in the past slaves, women, and children have been

defined as property, and corporations as persons.40

What it is to be human—the ‘human measure’—has always been a judgement based on

intuition, social practice, and legal tradition, not science or philosophy.41 Ultimately it is how

the ‘other’ acts—whether the other can be trusted to exercise social or moral responsibility –

which fixes our judgement. Alterity is not judged physically but behaviourly. Hannibal

Lecter (the character in the novel Silence of the Lambs) and Rachel (the cyborg ‘replicant’ in

the film Blade Runner) represent, respectively, the existential nightmare and the existential

dilemma for the morally and psychologically ‘normal’ citizen. Lecter is human, but

‘inhuman’, whereas the gentle and sensitive Rachel, with her implanted ‘human’ memories

and self-doubt, elicits genuine compassion from the audience who witness her mistreatment

and her pain; to treat her as other than a person seems cruel and inhumane. Trustworthiness

is more important than genus in determining how we will react to ‘others’.42 Having

confidence that we will be treated by another as we expect to be treated, and as we would

treat them, would seem to be the customary rule-of-thumb—our interest is not so much

40 Rhana Pike, “Plenary Presentation: To Sail beyond the Sunset: Navigating the Uncharted Waters of Bioethics”, Science Editor, 27, no. 5 (Sep.–Oct., 2004): 150. These issues were behind much of Maitland’s inquiry. 41 Donald R. Kelley, The Human Measure: Social Thought in the Western Legal Tradition (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1990). Human Dignity and Bioethics: Essays Commissioned by the President’s Council on Bioethics (Washington D.C.: [President’s Council on Bioethics], 2008). Marcel Mauss had argued in his now classic essay (‘A Category of the Human Mind: The Notion of Person; the Notion of Self’ (1938)) that our culture’s notions of personhood originated in the Roman legal system. Maitland commented: ‘The idea of normalness [in judicial procedure] is an inappropriate and a delusive idea; it implies a comparison that we cannot make.’ Frederic William Maitland, “The Body Politic” in The Collected Papers of Frederic William Maitland, ed. H.A.L. Fisher (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1911), vol. 3, 302. 42 Two projects currently funded by the European Commission: ‘FEELIX GROWING’ (€ 2.5 million), and ‘LIREC’ (€ 8.2 million) are investigating the development of robot companions that attain ‘companionable’, useful, relationships with their human owners.

176 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

whether the ‘other’ is human, but whether it can be relied upon to be ‘human’. Should or

should not the chimpanzee with neurotechnologically enhanced cognitive function (through

an implanted brain chip) acquire the same rights as a person whose brain functions

similarly?43 In the future, will we have any more right to know whether someone is a

cyborg-human hybrid than we have now to know the details of someone’s medical history?

These issues are now real: with the speed of advance of genetic research, they have

moved from the realm of the fantastic to the possible within a generation. The theory and

politics of posthumanism are now mainstream academic topics.44 Lawyers, ethicists, and

scientists now discuss the ‘convergence of NBIC Technologies’ (NBIC is the abbreviation of

nanotechnology, biotechnology, information technology, and cognitive science).45 The issue

is not that of technology being forced on an unwilling public, but the opposite. How extreme

may requests from enthusiastic ‘consumers’ for enhancement or manipulation be (and which

are able to be satisfied promptly by an enthusiastic enhancement ‘market’), before they are

considered ‘irrational’ or ‘insane’? How far should the normative ‘space’ be expanded?

In the enhanced-human future, how might history elucidate who ‘we’ are and where we

have come from? What origin story will it tell?

Subjectivity, Embodiment, and Systems

In the introduction to his book The Shattered Self: The End of Natural Evolution, where he

describes the extraordinary possibilities now realizable through biotechnology, the

mathematician Pierre Baldi commented:

43 Pike, “Plenary Presentation”, 150. 44 For example, The theme of Cultural Critique, Issue 53, was ‘Posthumanism’. The essays for that special issue grew out of sessions on the politics and theory of posthumanism held as part of the Third Crossroads in Cultural Studies Conference, held in Birmingham in 2000. 45 Pike, “Plenary Presentation”, 150. Bert Gordijn, “Converging NBIC Technologies for Improving Human Performance: A Critical Assessment of the Novelty and the Prospects of the Project”, Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics (2006): 726–732.

177 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

Life does not really feel the same once we begin to see ourselves as “biological information-processing machines” … But exploring the universe, regardless of whether or not it is likeable, is also part of the human quest.46

Baldi commenced his introduction by identifying what he described as ‘the most significant

event in our history, and perhaps in the 3.5 billion-year history of life on Earth’. That event

was ‘mankind’ (with the completion of the Human Genome Project) staring for the first time

at its own genome. The human formula was now identified and able to be stored as

information that would open a vast new set of possibilities for biology, biotechnology,

medicine, and human development. Combined with this revolution was the fact, Baldi noted,

that,

Within the same generation, the human brain will face machines that surpass its raw computing power and an interconnected world of information processing devices that makes science fiction pale in comparison. Together these milestones raise profound and troubling questions about the nature and boundaries of life, intelligence, and who we really are.47

For many scientists, however, the questions were exhilarating rather than troublesome.

Earlier, Hans Moravec, a robotics scientist, had predicted that soon it would be possible to

download human consciousness into a computer, and that the development of super-

intelligent machines was inevitable.48 A consequence, Moravec speculated, was that

Rather quickly, they could displace us from existence. I'm not as alarmed as many by the latter possibility, since I consider these future machines our progeny, ``mind children'' built in our image and likeness, ourselves in more potent form.49

Ray Kurzweil, another scientist and technologist, reflected that hyper-intelligent machines—

46 Pierre Baldi, The Shattered Self: The End of Natural Evolution (Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 2001), 5. 47 Ibid., 2. 48 Hans Moravec, Mind Children: The Future of Robot Intelligence (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1988), 109–10. 49 Hans Moravec, “Robots, Re-Evolving Mind”, Carnegie Mellon University Robotics Institute, December 2000, http://www.frc.ri.cmu.edu/~hpm/project.archive/robot.papers/2000/Cerebrum.html, [29/9/08].

178 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

achievable through iterative, thus exponential, self-improvement—could and would

undertake social decision-making better than humans, and that within decades there would be

hyper-intelligent machines with human-like creativity.50 Moravec did concede that ‘the

available tools for peeking into that strange [machine-world] future—extrapolation, analogy,

abstraction, and reason—are totally inadequate.51

One central assumption in these speculations (apart from the ontological and cultural

ones regarding the nature of being, desire, language, power, etc.) is that information can

capture all that is essential about the human organism. Change the code and you change the

person. The physical body, by this logic, is merely the media—‘biomedia’—for information;

merely the material carrier for the information it expresses.52 Thus the non-corporeal

cyberperson is a wholly viable concept. Consciousness can be separated from embodiment.

If for one moment that extraordinary proposition was accepted, then by the same

reductive logic, disembodied thought would exist independently of the life-world,53 thus

wholly self-sufficient within its own wholly digital-noumenal world. If so, it is not clear

why, or how, it would engage with the phenomenal world, nor why the phenomenal world

would be bothered with it. Or, if it did engage with its life-world, that engagement would be

with, and inside, the cyberworld in which case, again, its relevance and value to the human

world is not obvious. ‘Disembodied thought’ is an oxymoron. By the second half of the

twentieth century the long philosophical journey onwards from Cartesian mentalism had

established that the ability to grasp meaning was not primarily through mental representation,

but embodiment. Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, Wittgenstein in particular (and Sartre, Bourdieu,

and others) had argued convincingly that, while the ability to manipulate symbols was

important, being-in-the-world was the primary epistemological and ontological ‘ground’.

Since then, work done in neuroscience, philosophy, history, cultural anthropology, critical

50 Ray Kurzweil, The Age of Spiritual Machines: When Computers Exceed Human Intelligence (New York: Viking Press, 1999). 51 Moravec, “Robots, Re-Evolving Mind”. 52 Eugene Thacker, “What is Biomedia?”, Configurations, 11, no. 1 (Winter, 2003). 53 ‘Life-world’ in the Husserlian sense, thus: the natural world by which the functioning subject involved in the circle of other functioning subjects grounds belief, sense, and meaning.

179 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

and cultural theory, and other areas, has further supported that conclusion. Body, brain and

culture form a unified whole. For intelligent machines to have any relevance to the embodied

world of humans, they would need to have, as part of their computation data-bases, a dynamic

representation of that dynamic, intercorporeal, intersubjective, intersociocultural world—

which, for a machine as machine, is impossible.

The context for considering biology and technology convergence, therefore, is more the

humanization of technology than it is the instrumentalization of biology. The ability to

understand the meaning of technology can only be achieved through humanistic discourse,

not science.54 Nevertheless, science changes ontology, as much as ontology changes science.

Any ‘critical ontology of ourselves’ that is undertaken cannot avoid being affected by science

and technology. Within that critical ontology, the idea of a fixed and finite human nature

must now be replaced by the idea of human nature which is unfinished and unbounded, and of

which science is as relevant to its understanding as were (and are) theories of the modern

disenchanted subject and theories of the postmodern decentred subject. Subjectivity and

embodiment, autonomy and causality, freedom and necessity, and intelligence and action are

not Geist and Natur binaries, but interrelated elements in a dynamic whole: Geist in Natur,

Natur in Geist. The basis for any effective critical ontology of ourselves can only properly be

undertaken through the integration of Geisteswissenschaften with Naturwissenschaften.

Further, and contrary to Pierre Baldi’s view, life does not have to feel different if we do

see ourselves as “biological information-processing machines”. A model of the human being

which defines that being as a complex adaptive organism driven by a complex hierarchy of

needs and desires (an organism for which belief is as fundamental as food), accommodates

most historical, normative, humanistic, conceptions. If the model definition was further

refined to ‘a complex learning system which has become ‘tuned’ to knowledge acquisition

and meaning’, even less conceptual change is required. Such a model does not affect the

centrality to social, cultural, and political life of critical reason, individual autonomy, or moral

54 Both modernist and postmodernist discourse, such as Horkheimer and Adorno’s Dialectic of Enlightenment, Jonas’s The Imperative of Responsibility, and Haraway’s Simians, Cyborgs, and Women.

180 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

responsibility. On the contrary, it identifies those characteristics and notions as the highest-

evolved elements of the complex ‘system of systems’ which is our life-world, namely, the

human-system in the system-of-humans in the biosystem. The ethical and political remain

central to thought and action. The normative remains as important as the naturalistic in

understanding the life-world. Such a definition is nothing more than acknowledgement of the

necessity for a broader investigative model. And a ‘systems’ model, as well as providing

conceptual utility, is infinitely ‘scalable’: it can be applied not only at the level of the subject,

but at the level of society, and so on. Furthermore, such a ‘systems’ model satisfies one of

the primary requirements for integrated study: it joins the material with the immaterial. It

joins Natur with Geist.

It might be argued that the promotion of ‘systems’ models is to regress to the

physicalism and reductionism which resulted in the discredited behaviourism of Skinner, or

the flawed functionalism of Talcott Parsons. But that would be to dismiss the power of the

system concept because of particular past experiences with its application, and it would be to

ignore the significant advances in understanding made since then of systems concepts.55

Systems theory remains a rich, if controversial, conceptual tool in social theory,56 but it is

also, as the advanced-technology development industries found, central to processes for the

integration of multidisciplinary effort. Thus a primary consideration in adopting systems

thinking, is not theoretical insight—though that is achieved—but practice with the integration

of scientific and humanistic studies.

Experience with the development of complex human/hardware/software systems since

the middle of the twentieth century—such as in the space program, nuclear program, the

55 Advance gained through experience such as that of the defence, aerospace, telecommunications, and software industries, and the systems-biology research industry (for example, The Simons Center for Systems Biology at the Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton). 56 Since the mid-twentieth-century, systems theory has been an established conceptual tool. In the 1970s and 1980s, the work of Niklas Luhmann, in particular, brought it to new prominence (Luhmann had studied Parson’s system theory, but discarded it as flawed, and developed a new theoretical systems framework). Notwithstanding the debates Luhmann’s work stimulated— particularly with Jürgen Habermas—it remains a productive, if partial, concept. See, for example, Thomas McCarthy, “Complexity and Democracy, or the Seducements of Systems Theory”, New German Critique, no. 35 (Spring–Summer, 1985): 27–53.

181 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

ballistic missile program, and now the convergence programs of the new ‘wired world’—has

led to the understanding that the system concept is the key to managing the synthesis of

immensely complex and diverse disciplinary effort. If the system concept could be adapted

for use in the management of academic research and product development, then the

management processes and frameworks developed by mature, proven, system development

organizations such as NASA or US Defense, could be utilized, first to better integrate

specialist research within each research category, and second to better manage the

relationships between categories.57 Notwithstanding the management benefit, the

technology-centred systems concepts also assist with notions of subjectivity and ‘society’.

II

To understand any system, the system’s parts,58 the interrelationships between the

parts, and the relation of the parts to the whole, require study. The definition of a system is

that it is a combination of parts which function as a whole, but the whole function is greater

than the sum of the functions of the parts. Properties ‘emerge’ that are extra to the parts.

Extra functionality is created through form and the nature of the attraction or tolerance that

exists between the parts.59 Form occurs through chance or design. The relation of the parts

to each other determines the whole, but the nature of the whole determines the types of parts

which will be coincident and how they will relate. A fish is very different from a bird, but in

each the parts are in harmony. A complex system can be anything from a mobile phone, say,

to a space shuttle, or a fruit fly to a human. A ‘person’ is a mind-body system, which is, in

turn, a subsystem of the larger social/cultural system which is the ‘society’, which is itself a

subsystem, and so on. The critical ontology of ourselves—the postmodern-era research

program—is research into our life-world’s components, parts, subsystems, wholes, and their

57 This latter aspect will be explored in Chapter 5. 58 Which may themselves be systems. 59 Maurice Merleau-Ponty, in Phenomenology of Perception, in trying to explain intentional action, uses the term ‘comportment’ of the parts (of the body) to describe the relation of the parts to the type of attraction or tolerance. He introduces an activity he calls ‘motor intentionality’ in which the agent, rather than aiming at success, feels drawn to reduce a felt tension. See Hubert L. Dreyfus, “A Merleau-Pontyian Critique of Husserl's and Searle's Representationalist Accounts of Action”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 100 (2000): 287–302.

182 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

interrelationships.

Complex systems, by exhibiting capabilities that are greater than the sum of the

capabilities of their parts, exhibit supervenient capability. The set of components constituting

a system always has, as the system-set, some characteristic or behaviour that cannot be

exhibited by any of its subsets; that is the definition of a system. The relationship between

the subsets, not the subsets themselves, determines the system functionality. The relationship

determines both the nature of interfaces and the nature of the information exchanges across

the interfaces. If they are not compatible, there will be no system. Each subset may work

perfectly, but the system will fail to perform. The US Department of Defense and NASA had

learned that lesson the hard way after expensive failures in their many development programs

in the 1950s and onwards. For them the new, fundamental, understanding was that

architecture (form), not components, was the key determinant of system capability—of the

system’s supervening features which were, of course, the point of the system. If they were

not, why develop a system? All one would need to do was procure the subsystems

individually and independently. Consider, for example, a naval combat system. The combat

system provides a system-level capability (a certain probability of survival for a particular

threat scenario). That capability could not be provided by the individual subsystems acting

independently.60

To an external observer, the combat system appears to be ‘thinking’ holistically in that

it detects, classifies, decides, and acts like a complex information processing organism

adapting to a particular environment. For its development, the ‘system’ is defined in a ‘top-

level’ specification comprised of, say, three thousand requirements. Perhaps two thousand of

those requirements can be ‘allocated’ directly to the sub-systems that comprise the system.

For example, requirements for detection of a particular threat may be allocated directly to one

radar subsystem. However, the remaining system requirements will be unallocatable because

they have no meaning for any of the subsystems individually, they only have meaning at the

60 The subsystems of a typical combat system are: sensor (above-water, below-water, electromagnetic), command-and-control (classification, threat evaluation, weapon assignment), engagement (weapons), and support (navigation, communication).

183 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

system level.61 Therefore, each of those requirements must be decomposed into a set of

derived requirements that can be allocated to the constituent subsystems—in other words,

have meaning for the subsystems. Thus there is a one-to-many mapping: the total number of

requirements needed to specify design parameters for the various subsystems will be a

multiple of the ‘top-level’ system specification. The art of the system architect, and the

subsystem design specialists, is ensuring that both the parts and the whole are ‘tuned’ to

ensure optimum performance of the integrated whole against defined threats. This may mean

that one or more subsystems are tuned to well below their potential capability, but that is

irrelevant. The ability of the system to interact with its external environment so that it

achieves a defined overall probability of survival is a result of the synergy of a particular

integrated relationship. That capability is immanent to the integrated whole; it is a

supervening feature.

The fact that a ‘system’ can be defined at any level of aggregation, means that it has

unlimited ‘scalability’, and hence great flexibility. Supervenience is a characteristic at any,

and all, levels. With the human system, consciousness can be conceptualized as system-level

functionality of a particular complex ‘open’ system.62 Mind is thus the emergent—

‘supervenient’—function of the integrated body subsystems.63 Subject and object are merged

in one system entity. Clearly we cannot stand outside the metaphysics of subjectivity; this

‘merged’ conceptualization is itself an object in consciousness, the psychological and Kantian

division of world into subjective and objective parts seems unavoidable. But that sense of

61 For example, the requirement: ‘the system shall provide defence against [defined] air and sea threats.’ 62 An ‘open system’ is simply one that allows information, energy, and matter to cross its boundaries. 63 It is striking how close the modern system-discourse is to the eighteenth-century ‘Enlightenment vitalism’ argument which sought to mediate between early eighteenth-century mechanism and animism. Peter Hanns Reill describes how Charles Louis Dumas (who coined the term ‘vitalism’) explained that this new approach to science was to rectify the misuse of physical laws which supported the “ancient sect’ of mechanists and the misuse of metaphysics which supported the equally ancient sect of spiritualists.’ Dumas, writing at the beginning of the nineteenth century, declared that the new vitalistic science ‘will derive all appearances of life neither simply from the material nor simply from the soul, but rather from a capacity that lies in the middle between both’. Peter Hanns Reill, “Science and the Construction of the Cultural Sciences in late Enlightenment Germany: The case of Wilhelm von Humboldt”, History and Theory, 33, no. 3 (Oct., 1994): 348.

184 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

phenomenal/noumenal duality does not mean that dualism is the self-evident ‘actual’

reality.64 As Alfred North Whitehead remarked:

Consciousness presupposes experience, and not experience consciousness … Locke inherited [from Descartes] the dualistic separation of mind from body. If he had started with the one fundamental notion of an actual entity, the complex of ideas disclosed in consciousness would have at once turned into the complex constitution of the actual entity disclosed in its own consciousness, so far as it is conscious—fitfully, partially, or not at all.65

Whitehead had no doubt that dualism was a false abstraction rooted in what he called the

‘theory of the bifurcation of nature’.66 The cause of the false abstraction is the reflexivity of

consciousness, and the abstraction would have existed from the time that self-awareness of

consciousness first emerged. The associated argument has existed at least since Plato argued

for the existence of soul as a separate entity from body, and Aristotle that they were one

integrated material whole.

In the work of Niklas Luhmann, the universal, ontological, whole is the life-world as

social system. Luhmann, in Social Systems, represents the complete life-world as a system of

psychic and communicative systems. He was not proposing a theory of communicative

action as Habermas had done (which assumes the interaction of a life-world with other

systems), he was asserting that the life-world is the supervenient result of interacting

subsystems.67 Society, in Luhmann’s theory, is neither individuals nor a collective: it is a

communicative system. Language is the medium and structure by which psychic systems

64 Niklas Luhmann, in proposing his own totalizing social systems theory, was perfectly aware of the problems with any theory that claims universality—that it appears as its own object—but noted that ‘at the same time, they [the theories] always learn something about themselves from their objects.’ Niklas Luhmann, Social Systems (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1995), xlvii. 65 A. N. Whitehead, Process and Reality, eds David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne (New York: Free Press, 1978), 53. Quoted in David Woodruff Smith, Mind World: Essays in Phenomenology and Ontology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 230. 66 This was a persistent theme, but in particular in Process and Reality. 67 Jürgen Habermas in his “Excursus on Luhmann's Appropriation of the Philosophy of the Subject through Systems Theory” commented that Luhmann had just replaced the philosophy of the subject with something else, and inherited the same problems of self-reference: ‘The system- environment relationship takes the place of the inside–outside relationship between the knowing subject and the world as the totality of knowable objects.’ Jurgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1987), 369.

185 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

(consciousness) interact (and harmonize) with communication (social) systems. Society is a

system of systems. In Luhmann’s schema, a ‘system’ is any organic, psychic or social form

that is self-organising, and self-creating. Within a system’s boundary, external complexity

has been reduced. The system’s active engagement with the chaotic external world results in

the transformation of (outside) ‘other’ into synthesized, ordered, system (inside) ‘matter’.

The process of transformation which occurs at the boundary means that the boundary is a

‘meaning’ boundary; the systems are meaning-systems that operate within networks of

systems. Social systems emerge because of the ‘double-contingency’ of the interface

between interacting agents seeking a meaning equilibrium (harmony). ‘Double contingency’

is the awareness of each interacting agent that they are free interpreters of the other’s

behaviour, and that each is aware of that fact.

Luhmann had taken systems theory to its ontological limit. He acknowledged that his

hypotheses were a ‘flight above the clouds’, but was seeking a unified theory of

consciousness and society.68 The Enlightenment paradigm of consciousness as

transcendental subjectivity, with the philosophy of subject developed from it, was exhausted.

Other attempts to theorize the nature of the intangible entity which was ‘society’, such as

those of Durkheim, Weber, Parsons, and Habermas, retained the idea of both the society and

the individual as a well-defined essence; an idea which continues to cause problems.69

Luhmann’s hypotheses regarding society may have been flights above the clouds, but they

were genuine exploration at the edge of understanding—his conceptual explorations were

pure basic research.

In theorizing the individual also, systems concepts have much to offer. In both the

human system and the manufactured system, teleological concepts such as wholeness, choice,

and purposeful action are valid. Both exhibit advanced capability regarding feedback of

corrective information and goal-seeking behaviour. In both, the concept of information

68 Quoted in Hans Herbert Kogler, “Review of Niklas Luhmann, Social Theory”, American Historical Review, 103, no. 1. (Jul., 1997): 271. 69 This is the subject of Stephen Turner’s article: “The New Collectivism”, History and Theory, 43, no. 3 (October 2004): 386–399, where he is skeptical of claims that the collective can be treated as a moral object in the way the individual can.

186 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

exchange as a distinct system component is central, as is the natural tendency of the

subsystems to settle towards a harmonized ‘equilibrium’ state (Merleau-Ponty’s ‘motor-

intentionality’70). Both operate in complex, ‘noisy’ environments, where rigorous filtering of

large quantities of information is required continuously—and both require expansionist and

synthetic, rather than reductive and deterministic, ‘thinking’ for their effective operation.

Biological systems with their highly evolved capacity for self regulation or homeostasis, are

supremely well-adapted open systems. Significantly, the crucial ability required of both

biological and manufactured systems for them to adapt and self-regulate is the ability to sense

difference. Equilibrium cannot be sensed. The human system, like the combat system, can

only sense change, and both systems are ‘tuned’ to ‘re-harmonize’ once change is sensed.

One key difference, of course, is that the manufactured system is a ‘top-down’ design,

whereas the biological/human system is a ‘bottom-up’, ‘trial-and-error’, evolution of

synergistic relationships between inorganic and organic parts.71

Another importance difference is that a system such as a combat system, while a self-

monitoring system, is not a learning system. But this is a design choice executed through the

selection of computing architectures and algorithms. Users do not want wilful combat

systems. The combat system operates through rules and repetition, but the other, the

‘intelligent’ biological system, operates through environmental cues and reinforcement.

Manufactured systems based on artificial intelligence principles are designed, increasingly,

using neural network architectures; this means they are tuned to pattern recognition,

identification of content in the pattern, and reinforcement. In other words designed as

learning systems which are ‘tuned’ to simple meaning. As such, they are systems capable of

purposeful action in a limited sense.

Nevertheless, the interrelationship of content and meaning is complex, regardless of

70 See footnote 59 above. 71 But even in top-down system design, the designers will first go through a series of iterations between system requirements and implied functionality (the ‘requirements-loop’) then an iterative mapping of required functionality to physical components (the design-loop’) then a return ‘back up’ to the ‘requirements-loop’, and so on until the overall design is harmonious and optimized against many organizational and technical criteria. Thus ‘bottom-up’ is an important feature here also.

187 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

whether that content or that meaning is simple or complex. And ensuring that a sound ‘feel

for the game’ evolves in the manufactured system so that its purposeful action is appropriate,

is problematical. Fallibility is a characteristic of intelligence.72 Thus the manufactured

learning-system needs, no less than the human system, a ‘parent’ to watch over it and show it

what behaviour is appropriate in different contexts—what ‘feel’ is required for the successful

negotiation of life’s game. In a related though opposed sense, Daniel Dennett has continually

challenged the assumption that human ‘belief’ and ‘desire’, so intimately related to

sociocultural meaning, are different conceptually from a computer’s design ‘stance’ (the

designed goals and sub-goals). For Dennett, there is no difference.73 Desire and belief are

proof of nothing other than certain body dispositions.

A significant difference between the technological learning system and the human

organism, and one that obscures recognition of the fundamental similarities, is the massive

complexity of the human system when compared with artificial systems. The human neural

network alone dwarfs any technological analogue; its design ‘stance’ is massively more

complex than any computer system’s. To perform only the edge and motion detecting

functions of the retina of the human eye requires approximately one billion computer

operations.74 To Allan Hobson, the implications of this complexity are apparent. While

describing the ‘wiring’ of the human brain, he commented:

Each of twenty billion elements [neurone and its axons and dendrites] generates messages at a rate varying between one hundred and two or three hundred signals per second; hence, each of the twenty billion citizens of our brain-mind is talking to at least ten thousand others at least once, and as often as one hundred times a second [thus a possible twenty-million-billion possible states per second]. With a chatterbox of such proportions it is to

72 Alan Turing noted that ‘if a machine is expected to be infallible, it cannot also be intelligent. There are several theorems which say almost exactly that. But these theorems say nothing about how much intelligence may be displayed if a machine makes no pretence at infallibility’. Alan Turing, ACE Reports of 1946 and other Papers, eds B. E. Carpenter and R. W. Doran (Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 1946), 124, quoted in Dennett, Darwin’s Dangerous Idea, 428. 73 See discussion in John Passmore, Recent Philosophers (London: Gerald Duckworth & Co., 1988), 101. 74 Hans Moravec, “Robot Predictions Evolution”, April 2004, http://www.frc.ri.cmu.edu/~hpm/project.archive/robot.papers/2004/Predictions.html, [29/9/08].

188 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

me just as incredible that such a system would not have awareness of itself as it is incredible that it does.75

This awareness of self, however, is not solely cognitive, it is also physiological. The

neurophysiologist, Antonio Damasio, has studied this interpenetration of brain and body, but

has noted an important asymmetry in the process. The brain as an organ of the body can be

‘doubled’ (Damasio’s term) as ‘body’ by the body, but the brain is also ‘mind’ (‘mind is what

brain does’76), and as mind the brain can do something which the body cannot. ‘The ideas in

the mind’, Damasio notes, ‘can double up on each other’. 77 Mind can have conscious states

and, when in a conscious state, mind can have ideas of ideas—what Damasio calls a ‘second-

order idea’. In other words: ‘intelligent’ cognition.78 The fundamental second-order idea is

self-awareness: the idea of self—which Damasio describes as ‘the idea of the relationship

between two other ideas—object perceived and body modified by perception’.79 Thus, given

that a consequence of neural activity is the ‘burning-in’ of modified sensory and

psychological states through reinforcement of neural pathways, meaning-perception is no

different from object-perception as a ‘burn-in’ trigger. The noumenal is as substantial as the

phenomenal to brain chemistry. And the vast number of the neural connections means that

vast numbers of previous noumenal and phenomenal states can be stored—to be ‘re-fired’ as

memory when required.80

The sheer vastness of the volume of sensor inputs, cognitive computational power,

cerebral storage capacity, and systemic complexity of the human system has produced a self-

reflexive system in which second-order cognitive function is as important as physiological

75 Allan Hobson, The Dreaming Brain, quoted in Derek Denton, The Pinnacle of Life: Consciousness and Self-awareness in Humans and Animals (St. Leonards: Allen & Unwin, 1993), 112. 76 Derek Denton, Howard Florey Institute, quoted in Geoff Strong, “The Mind Game”, Age (Melbourne), 8 October, 2003. 77 Antonio Damasio, Looking For Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain (Orlando: Harcourt Inc, 2003), 217. 78 The notion of intelligence will be discussed in the next section. 79 Damasio, Looking For Spinoza, 215. 80 What is stored is the connections and strengths between elements which allow the patterns to be subsequently recreated. There is debate as to the extent that new synaptic connections are made, rather than the altering of strength of pre-existing connections. See Howard Gardner, The Mind’s New Science: A History of the Cognitive Revolution (New York: Basic Books, 1987), 396.

189 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

function. Mind, through brain, affects physiology as much as mind, as brain, is affected by

physiology. Thus, applying the logic of systems theory, harmonization of the integrated

mind/body requires harmonization of physiological and higher-cognitive states. The body

will fail if the mind (brain in second-order state) cannot harmonize, just as the brain will fail

if the body is unable to harmonize. Subjectivity, meaning, and intentional action are

embodied system functions.

III

Of particular significance to cognition and recall is the fact that the sequence in which the

neural states were imprinted is retained. Thus the stored states are effectively ‘time-stamped’

though, clearly, there is no capture of time as time in this process. Nevertheless, the sequence

of acquisition must be retained if the stored images or states are to be useful. ‘Before’ and

‘after’ patterns must be recoverable for any predictive behaviour to be possible—whether that

be flicking the tongue out just before the fly arrives, or waiting for the mammoth to reappear.

Thus what is stored is what Damasio calls ‘a simple narrative without words’:

It [has] characters (the organism, the object). It unfolds in time. And it has a beginning, a middle, and an end … The imagetic representation of sequences of brain events, which occurs in brains simpler than ours, is the stuff of which stories are made. A natural preverbal occurrence of storytelling may well be the reason why we created drama and eventually books.81

The biological information-processing system is hard-wired for narrative just as it is

hard-wired for second-order thought. Thus the human system, operating in complex

socio/cultural environments, converts time-stamped sequences in the pre-conscious into

complex historically-ordered narratives in consciousness. Body, brain, and culture fold back

into each other and a central mechanism for this enfolding is history and narrative. Daniel

Dennett takes this thesis further. Not only, he argues, are time-ordered narratives intrinsic to

81 Antonio Damasio, The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness (New York: Harcourt Inc., 2000), 168, 188.

190 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

any conception of the ‘autobiographical self’,82 they are our key mechanism for control of our

psychic and social environment. ‘Our fundamental tactic of self-protection, self-control, and

self-definition’ he says, ‘is not spinning webs or building dams [as beavers do], but telling

stories, and more particularly connecting and controlling the story we tell others—and

ourselves—about who we are’.83

For William Connolly, Damasio’s research and conclusions constitute ‘the makings of

a complex model of human reflexivity, articulated through a neuroscience quite congruent

with a philosophy of immanent naturalism’. Connolly concludes that studies such as

Damasio’s (and others) ‘rattle established images of causality’ and ‘encourage us to rethink

the sufficiency of the alternatives between "scientific explanation" and "narrative

interpretation", often taken to represent the two fundamental options of inquiry in the human

sciences’.84 In this vein, Richard Harvey Brown has argued that science itself can be

subsumed under narrative logic—that paradigm shifts in science itself are reformulations of

cognitive traditions in terms of narrative logic.85 And in discussing another body of research,

Jonathan Gottschall argues that research indicates that literary universals are a function of

neuro-cognitive structures related to emotion, not culture.86 Emotions and feelings, research

shows, are more directly linked to rationality than previously thought. Just as the mind and

body are indissociable, so too are emotions, feelings, and rationality. The human system

82 William James noted the paradox that the self in our stream of consciousness changes continuously as it moves forward in time, even as we retain a sense that the self remains the same while our existence continues. Damasio calls the constantly modified self the ‘core’ self, and the self that seems to remain the same as the ‘autobiographical’ self. The paradox is solved, he says, by recognizing that there are two entities, not one. The core self is the self of self-consciousness, the self that is conscious of itself having experiences. The autobiographical self is the one ‘based on a repository of memories of fundamental facts in an individual biography that can be partly reactiviated and thus provide continuity and seemingly permanence in our lives’. Damasio, The Feeling of What Happens, 217. 83 Daniel Dennett, Consciousness Explained (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1993), 418, quoted in David Lodge, Consciousness and the Novel: Connected Essays (London: Secker & Warburg, 2002), 15. 84 William E. Connolly, “The Radical Enlightenment: Faith, Power, Theory”, Theory & Event, 7, Issue 3, 2004, http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory_&_event/. 85 Richard Harvey Brown, “Positivism, Relativism and Narrative in the Logic of the Historical Sciences”, American Historical Review, 92, no. 4. (Oct., 1987): 908–920. 86 Jonathan Gottschall, “Literary Universals and the Sciences of the Mind”, Philosophy and Literature, 28 (2004): 202–217.

191 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

interacts with its environment as a fully integrated whole and sentiments are as fundamental a

part of that interaction as rationality.87

Damasio has observed through clinical studies of brain-damaged patients that the

absence of emotions and feelings results in the breakdown of rationality. Emotion and

thinking are interwoven. Emotions and feelings appear to be the direct sensing of body states,

and as the body, as represented in the brain, appears to constitute the indispensable frame of

reference for the neural processes, loss of body reference data results in impaired cognitive

function, both conscious and unconscious. There is a direct link between the body and its

survival-oriented regulations enacted in conscious and unconscious action. Damasio

concluded that as conscious action reflected second-order sociocultural ideas,

Our organisms gravitate toward a “good” result of their own accord … organisms can produce advantageous reactions that lead to good results without deciding to produce those reactions.88

The implication is that human organisms are ‘tuned’ to make choices which the social mind

uses to construct rational behaviour.

The research has shown that rational behaviour is not simply logical behaviour. More

is involved in self-regulation and autonomous action than reason alone. Consequently,

‘intelligent’ thinking consists of more than the ability to reason logically. As William

Connolly has observed, ‘there is much more to thinking than argument’.89 If emotion and

intuition are absent, reason and judgement are impaired. Damasio’s patients were quite

capable of logical thought, but incapable of deciding what to do; practical reasoning

necessarily involves emotion.

The political theorist, Sharon Krause, reflecting on Damasio’s and other related

87 Damasio in particular has produced a large body of neurophysiological research on this topic. See Antonio, R., Damasio, Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain (London: Picador, 1994). 88 Antonio Damasio, Looking For Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain (Orlando: Harcourt Inc, 2003), 51. 89 William E. Connolly, Neuropolitics: Thinking, Culture, Speed (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2002), 73.

192 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

research, has observed that ‘the role of affect’ within thinking has ‘powerful implications for

how we conduct public deliberation and how we enact democratic citizenship’.90 Our notions

of what comprises legitimate content in intelligent debate and action require expansion.

Krause (like Damasio) concluded that

Practical reason necessarily incorporates affective concerns in reaching conclusions about what we ought to do. Norms are intrinsically, not contingently, connected to human motivations, and moral sentiment embodies this connection. Hence the sentiment-based account of democratic deliberation helps to clarify how the conclusions of public deliberation can be both normative for us and motivationally compelling.91

This, though, is more describing what has always been custom and practice rather than

enlarging future practice. Context, , empathy and intuition have always been

intrinsic to public and private judiciousness. But the research does provide more objective

evidence for the validity of that practice.

Similarly, in her study of intelligence and the emotions, the philosopher Martha

Nussbaum concluded that the research of Damasio and others (‘Lazarus, Ortony, and Oatley’)

confirmed that ‘emotions provide the animal (in this case human) with a sense of how the

world relates to its own set of goals and projects. Without that sense, decision making and

action are derailed’.92 For Nussbaum, emotions are intelligent responses to the perception of

value. Consequently, they ‘cannot be sidelined in accounts of ethical judgement … [and this

has] large consequences for the theory of practical reason, for normative ethics and for …

political thought’.93 Nussbaum concluded that:

If we think of emotions as essential elements of human intelligence, rather than just as supports or props for intelligence, this gives us especially strong reasons to promote the conditions of emotional well-being in a political

90 Sharon R. Krause, “Brains, Citizens, and Democracy's New Nobility”, Theory & Event, 9, Issue 1, 2006, http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory_&_event/. 91 Sharon R. Krause, “Affective Impartiality”, Paper prepared for delivery at the Political Theory Colloquium, Department of Political Science, University of California, San Diego, May 9, 2007, 22. 92 Martha C. Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 117. 93 Ibid., 1, 3.

193 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

culture: for this view entails that without emotional development, a part of our reasoning capacity as political creatures will be missing.94

And if society is constituted from these political agents, then social well-being must be

affected (if Nussbaum’s conclusion is accepted) by the degree to which the material,

emotional and spiritual social currents achieve balance in the community.

But our understanding of the process of inquiry will also be affected: what reasoning

processes are used, and how they are used in all of the research processes, from pure basic

research to experimental development. If our understanding of intelligence, and, by

implication, reason, is altered—to acceptance that language and logic are only some of its

dimensions—then so too must our notions of knowledge be altered. Since knowledge is

linked to ways of knowing, as much (though no more) than it is linked to an observable,

evidence-based, external reality, then new knowledge is both new things seen and new ways

of seeing. For example, Nussbaum argues that a genuine grasp of complex intelligence will

lead us to reassess literary and musical works as sources of ethical education.95 Wittgenstein,

also, had remarked that ‘people nowadays think, scientists are there to instruct them, poets,

musicians etc. to entertain them. That the latter have something to teach them; that never

occurs to them’.96 There is much knowledge outside language and reason; it too needs to be

accessed.

Expanded conceptions of intelligence must lead to the reassessing of categories and

modes of research-acquired knowledge. Valid knowledge—knowledge perceived to have

value—must now have a wider definition. Specialist research will always be the foundation

upon which new knowledge is built, but ultimately the interdependency of the knowledge

elements intrinsic to ‘normal’ human functioning must be reflected in the way knowledge is

discovered, created, and applied.

94 Ibid., 3. 95 Nussbaum devotes a large portion of her study to analysis of literary and musical works of such figures as Proust, Joyce, Mahler, for example. 96 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, 36/42, quoted in Béla Szabados, “What Is the Role of the Arts and Aesthetics in Wittgenstein’s Philosophy?”, AE, 10 (Fall, 2004), http://www.uqtr.uquebec.ca/AE/.

194 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

Unified Inquiry and the Unity of Knowledge

In human society, successful adaptation to one’s environment is generally considered a mark

of intelligence. The more complex the environment, the more complex the task of successful

adaptation. The ability to recognize and exhibit appropriate behaviour in the physical–

psychological–cultural network which is the human environment, in all its variety, subtlety,

and interconnectedness, places high intellectual demands on its inhabitants. In addition to

highly evolved genetically based biological mechanisms, there are needed ‘suprainstinctual

survival strategies’ that are several layers of abstraction above biology.97 The understanding

of performed meaning in historical or contemporary ritual such as a murder trial, a political

campaign, or a business merger negotiation requires the interpretation of multi-layered,

historically constituted, culturally specific, symbolic action. To act appropriately and

effectively in those contexts therefore requires immensely complex manipulations of second-

order (and higher) knowledge. The ability to comprehend, interpret, enact, and act on

symbolic behaviour at those higher levels is central to our ability to survive.

Ernst Cassirer had identified the centrality of symbols to higher-level cognition in his

seminal Philosophy of Symbolic Forms.98 Man was, he asserted, a ‘symbolizing animal’.

Myth, religion, language, art, science were both ‘symbolic forms’ and ‘symbol generators’.

Language, myth, art, religion, science are the elements [of thought and feeling] and the constitutive conditions of this higher form of society … [they are] the means by which the forms of social life that we find in organic nature develop into a new state, that of social consciousness.99

The ability to manipulate symbols, and the ability to interpret and use cultural symbols

effectively, was the mark of intelligence in the individual and the primary indicator of

potential in both the individual and society.

97 The term is Damasio’s. 98 Philosophy of Symbolic Forms (3 vols.) was published 1923–1929. 99 Ernst Cassirer, An Essay on Man: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Human Culture (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1945), 223.

195 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

The American developmental psychologist Howard Gardner has studied this notion of

intelligence in that broader sense of human social potential. Gardner worked with children

and adults to investigate how they dealt with various types of symbols. At first, to frame his

study, he defined intelligence as ‘the ability to solve problems or to create products that are

valued within one or more cultural setting’. But twenty years later he broadened his

definition to ‘a biopsychological potential to process information that can be activated in a

cultural setting to solve problems or create products that are of value in a culture’. Gardner

now perceived there to be multiple ‘intelligences’, not a single ‘intelligence’. Intelligences

were potentialities that may or may not be activated depending on the values of a particular

culture, the opportunities in that culture, and ‘the personal decisions made by individuals

and/or families, schoolteachers, and others’.100

Everyone, Gardner argued, possesses a number of relatively autonomous cognitive

modes (‘multiple intelligences’). The relative strength or weakness of the various

‘intelligences’ varies between people, but each person has a distinctive cognitive profile and

distinctive intellectual style. Gardner defined seven ‘intelligences’: musical intelligence,

bodily-kinesthetic intelligence, logical-mathematical intelligence, linguistic intelligence,

spatial intelligence, interpersonal intelligence (ability to read the intentions and desires of

others), and intrapersonal intelligence (access to one’s own feelings and emotions and

understanding of one’s ‘self’). Common to these intelligences was the characteristic that they

are ‘triggered’ by certain kinds of internally or externally presented information, and that they

are, as Gardner explains,

susceptible to encoding in a symbol system—a culturally contrived system of meaning, which captures and conveys important forms of information. Language, picturing, and mathematics are but three nearly worldwide symbol systems that are necessary for human survival and productivity. While it may be possible for an intelligence to proceed without an accompanying symbol system, a primary characteristic of human intelligence may well be its gravitation toward such an embodiment.101

100 Howard Gardner, Intelligence Reframed: Multiple Intelligences for the 21st Century (New York: Basic Books, 1999), 33. 101 Howard Gardner, Multiple Intelligences: The Theory in Practice (New York: Basic Books,

196 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

Recently, Gardner has argued for another intelligence, which he calls ‘naturalist’

intelligence (the capacity to make consequential distinctions between one plant and another,

etc.) and has speculated that there may be a ninth intelligence, which he calls ‘existential’

intelligence. The latter would exist, he argued, if there were certain regions of the brain

dedicated to the manipulation of representations of the vast and the infinitesimal. Existential

intelligence, he says, is ‘the most unambiguously cognitive strand of the spiritual’:

once one includes the understanding of the personal realm within the study of intelligence, such human proclivities as the spiritual must legitimately be considered … if the abstract realm of mathematics constitutes a reasonable area of intelligence … why not the abstract realm of the spiritual? 102

Gardner’s theses have been rejected by many psychology-researchers, but those

specialists do accept that traditional notions of intelligence require broadening. Gardner’s

theory has, however, been very influential with educationists, particularly those concerned

with the institutional tendency to use simplistic one-dimensional measures for the assessment

of children’s learning ability. To them, narrow definitions of intelligence fail to capture the

subtle variations in children’s intellectual strengths. It is the complexity of children’s

intelligence, they believe, which is not recognized.103

One particular insight that Gardner brings to the debate is his thesis that intelligence has

not one dimension, but two. The first is intelligence and the second, domain. ‘Intelligence,’

Gardner argues, comes from the biological sciences, whereas ‘domain’ is a cultural concept.

Every culture features disciplines, crafts, activities in which at least some members attain

expertise. ‘Any intelligence (like spatial intelligence)’, he argues, ‘can be drawn on in many

domains (ranging from chess to sailing to sculpture); and, in turn, any domain can involve

one or more intelligences (for example, chess presumably draws on spatial, logical, personal,

and perhaps other intelligences as well)’. Similarly, the possession of high bodily-kinesthetic

1993), 16. 102 Gardner, Intelligence Reframed, 53. 103 Anthony Feiler, “Intelligence Reframed”, British Journal of Educational Studies, 48, no. 4 (Dec., 2000): 454.

197 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

intelligence alone does not mean that one will become a good dancer.104

For researchers also, the possession of high linguistic intelligence alone, or high

logical-mathematical intelligence alone, does not mean that the individual will be a good

historian, or scientist. But then no individual researcher possesses only one ‘intelligence’, nor

does a research field determine the ‘intelligence’ used by a researcher in that field. Sir Peter

Medawar observed:

Are scientists a homogeneous body of people in respect of temperament, motivation, and the style of thought? Obviously not … there is no such thing as the scientific mind. Scientists are people of very dissimilar temperaments doing different things in very different ways. Among scientists are collectors, classifiers and compulsive tidiers-up; many are detectives by temperament and many are explorers; some are artists and others artisans. There are poet-scientists and philosopher-scientists and even a few mystics … most people who are in fact scientists could easily have been something else instead.105

Scientific research requires both empirical and symbolic reasoning, and so does humanities

research. And just as there are properties of human existence that can be explained

reductively, so too are there properties of human existence that cannot.

Similarly, though we may prefer to believe that there is something special about human

beings, that desire and belief are proof of nothing other than certain body states. Neither

science nor the humanities can be the primary referent for valid knowledge. Any ‘epistemic’

knowledge model used in research must accommodate the material and the immaterial, the

empirical and the symbolic. It must accommodate the socially constructed nature of

knowledge, but also acknowledge that scientific reasoning gets things ‘right’ about the natural

world of which the symbolizing animal is a product—science ‘works’.

II

104 Howard Gardner, “A Reply to Perry D. Klein’s “Multiplying the Problems of Intelligence by Eight””, Canadian Journal of Education, 23, no. 1 (1998): 96–7. 105 P. B. Medawar, The Art of the Soluble (London: Methuen & Co. Ltd., 1968), 127, 132.

198 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

Just as there is no single disciplinary mind, so there is no single disciplinary knowledge.

There is a continual blurring of the disciplinary boundaries caused by the multifariousness of

research minds and the connectedness of knowledge, however specialist. In 1980, Clifford

Geertz commented that there had been

in recent years … an enormous amount of genre mixing in … intellectual life generally, and such blurring of kinds is continuing apace … It is a phenomenon general enough and distinctive enough to suggest that what we are seeing is not just another redrawing of the cultural map—the moving of a few disputed borders … but an alteration of the principles of mapping. Something is happening to the way we think about the way we think.106

Geertz qualified his observation with the comment that

Of course, to a certain extent this sort of thing has always gone on … But the present jumbling of varieties of discourse has grown to the point where it is becoming difficult either to label authors (What is Foucault—historian, philosopher, political theorist? What Thomas Kuhn—historian, philosopher, sociologist of knowledge?) or to label works.107

But perhaps what is significant here is the implied assumption that authors and discourses

provide discrete knowledge that can be labelled. While neither wholly wrong nor

unreasonable, the view reflects the evolution of the late twentieth-century research university,

rather than some self-evident truth regarding knowledge.

The idea at the centre of the idea of the research university was the intuitive belief,

implicit to German Idealism, in the unity of knowledge. Separate disciplines were only a

reflection of different methods of inquiry into the nature of knowledge, and collectively the

disciplines constituted a single institution whose coherence depended on it vitally embodying

its inherent idea. The perceived cognitive superiority of philosophy and history meant that,

functionally, they were able to provide the fundamental ground by which the specialized

fields within the natural sciences and humanities could be intermeshed. The polemic the

founders directed towards the ‘bread and butter sciences’ and against the ‘derivative quality

106 Clifford Geertz, “Blurred Genres: The Reconfiguration of Social Thought”, American Scholar, 49, no. 2 (1980): 165, 166. 107 Ibid., 166.

199 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

of those faculties which find "their unity not in knowledge directly, but rather in some

external occupation”’ was because they violated that vital ideal.108 Without the idea of ‘pure

basic’ research into knowledge itself—the pursuit of knowledge for its own sake—there

would be no ‘university’, there would be only trade schools.

By contrast, the modern research university, while still notionally embodying the ideal,

actively concentrates on functional specialization within, in Habermas’s words, ‘an ever more

swiftly differentiating system of knowledges’, whose logic can lead them to ‘discard like an

empty shell what once had been called its "idea?"’109 The discarding is epitomized by the late

twentieth-century ‘epistemology wars’ between postmodern relativists and epistemological

objectivists. In the modern academy there is no discipline (or disciplines) that can act as a

synthesizing force. Neither philosophy nor history can. Knowledge is now seen to be

assembled from multiple sources in the sciences, the social sciences, the arts and the

humanities. Research practice reflects the fact that the nature of meaning and the normative

character of intellectual processes are as central to inquiry as the pursuit of knowledge about

things-in-themselves through evidence-based science and logical reasoning (as in physics and

mathematics). There is a constellation of disciplines within a multidisciplinary firmament.

Nevertheless, the underlying disagreement between relativists and objectivists, within

the sciences and the humanities as well as between them, means that ‘scientific’ inquiry, and

hermeneutic inquiry are still seen as polar opposites rather than ‘points on an epistemological

gradient’ as Barbara Herrnstein Smith has recommended.110 Clifford Geertz agrees with the

need for harmonization, but sees opposition differently: ‘Given the dialectical nature of

things, we all need our opponents … What we are most in want of right now is some way of

synthesizing them.’111 Since no single discipline is foundational, synthesis can only be

facilitated, as it is in complex multi-disciplinary technological systems development, by the

108 Habermas, and Habermas quoting Schelling? (unclear from text). See Jürgen Habermas, “The Idea of the University: Learning Processes”, New German Critique, no. 41 (Spring–Summer, 1987): 11. 109 Ibid., 5. 110 Barbara Herrnstein Smith, Scandalous Knowledge: Science, Truth and the Human (Durham: Duke University Press, 2005), 11. 111 Geertz, “Blurred Genres”, 174.

200 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

use of a generic conceptual model that defines relationships between parts.

If we were to use as the basis for a model Smith’s metaphor of ‘epistemological

gradient’, it has the problem that it implies linearity, direction, and hierarchy (higher/lower);

and the problem with Geertz’s specification of a dialectic process is that it reinforces the idea

of binary relations and linear connectedness. To be faithful to the complex and enfolded

nature of human cognition and creativity, any synthesizing model needs to be multi-

dimensional and ‘free-floating’—to represent a cognitive ‘force field’ that expands and

contracts with the pulse of inquiry. No one disciplinary style of reasoning is cognitively

superior to any other. Each have their necessary place in any probing of epistemological and

ontological boundaries. Any model must accommodate both difference and complementarity.

In his discussion of Enlightenment vitalism, Peter Hanns Reill remarked that the

‘refrain of the analogical similarity of the laws governing the physical/organic and

spiritual/moral worlds runs through all of Humboldt’s writings.’112 Reill argues that Wilhelm

von Humboldt’s two foundational essays incorporated a vitalistic vision of nature and

epistemology that

blurred the strict mind/body distinction, emphasizing the mediation between them. The image of mediation between limiting boundaries and the desire to increase the variety between the limits reigned supreme in Humboldt’s logic of ambiguity. Subject and object, form and representation, sign and signified … were locked in an intimate reciprocal relationship.113

‘Enlightenment vitalists’, Reill proposed, ‘were grasping for a new way of organizing reality

built upon the concepts of ambiguity and paradox’.114 They were, he argued, ‘striving to

establish a logic of the ambiguous, enthroning complementarity over unity or

contradiction’.115

112 Peter Hanns Reill, “Science and the Construction of the Cultural Sciences in late Enlightenment Germany: The case of Wilhelm von Humboldt”, History and Theory, 33, no. 3. (Oct., 1994): 356. 113 “Ueber das vergleichende Sprachstudium in Beziehung auf die versheidenen Epochen der Sprachenwicklung” (1820), and “Ueber die Aufgabe des Geschichtschreibers” [On the Historian’s Task] (1821). Reill, ‘”and the Construction of the Cultural Sciences”, 357. 114 Reill, “Science and the Construction of the Cultural Sciences”, 353. 115 Ibid., 354.

201 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

But that impulse is more biological than historical—it is not just the distinctive

character of early nineteenth-century Idealist thought. Reill observed that ‘in many ways this

activity parallels what Bachelard seems to have been striving for in his attempt to evolve a

new way of understanding science’. Bachelard, like Whitehead, was seeking to establish

complementarity rather than dualism in the structure of thought. ‘What was needed’,

Bachelard argued, was ‘an ontology of complementarity less sharply dialectical than the

metaphysics of the contradictory’.116 Ambiguity rather than the discrete difference:

What I am proposing, therefore, is a new way of looking at ambiguity, a view sufficiently supple to comprehend the recent teachings of science. The philosophy of science is, I believe, in need of generally new principles. One such principle is the idea that the characters of things may be essentially complementary, a sharp departure from the tacit (philosophical) belief that being always connotes unity.117

But as well as complementarity within science, there is also the complementarity

between science’s verbally formulated account of scientific reality (however ambiguous that

reality) and the socially malleable reality by which that verbal account is deemed plausible.

Truth is made as well as found. And with inquiry itself, there is a further complementarity.

Inquiry is an attempt to discover how things ‘really are’, but at the same time is a process of

discovering new ways of seeing. Richard Rorty was referring to this duality when he

asserted: ‘Dreyfus tends to read for adequacy, but I usually read for edification’.118

‘Recontextualizers’, Rorty explained, are not people who

reveal the essential nature of anything, but simply tell you how things look when rearranged … I remain deeply suspicious of the claim that some phenomenologists get something right that others have gotten wrong.119

And Peter Burke has suggested that ‘One might … define originality, innovation, invention,

116 Ibid., 354. 117 Gaston Bachelard, The New Scientific Spirit, trans. Arthur Goldhammer (Boston, 1984), 16, quoted in Reill, “Science and the Construction of the Cultural Sciences”, 354. 118 Richard Rorty, “Foreword”, in Heidegger, Authenticity, and Modernity: Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus, vol. 1, ed. Mark A. Wrathall and Jeff Malpas (Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 2000), xii. 119 Ibid., xii. See also Richard Rorty, “Inquiry as Recontextualisation”, reprinted in Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers, vol. 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).

202 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

or creativity in terms of the capacity to recontextualize’.120 Discovery, then, the idea at the

centre of the modern notion of research, can be as much about recontextualizing known

‘things’ as finding new ones. But it remains both.

Contextualization is placing something in context. Clearly, there is an actuality to be

contextualized. Inquiry presupposes understanding and to understand something as

something, presupposes not just context, but awareness of some thing.121 Michael Ermarth

has commented that for Dilthey ‘”understanding” was inseparable from “reshaping” and that

human thought cannot be divorced from the outer world of concrete conditions and actions’.

Dilthey, with his concern for methodological rigour, was never happy with the connotations

of Geist but found alternatives such as ‘social sciences’, ‘moral sciences’, ‘historical

sciences’ unsatisfactory also.122 Dilthey, like Bachelard later, sought complementarity.

Rethinking the way we think of facts, knowledge and their application are integral to

the research and development process, but thought and meaning cannot be solely about

thought and meaning. Mind supplants neither body nor culture, nor biosphere.

III

If a synthesizing model is to be developed, the different ways of reasoning, discovering, and

creating need to be reconciled. The model must provide compatible theoretical and practical

interfaces. Theoretically, it must avoid assigning precedence among knowledge types but

allow the interconnection of different categories of knowledge. Practically, it must

acknowledge the differentiating system of knowledges that arise from the functional

specialization inherent in the modern research university, but enable interconnection of the

different specialist domains.

The primary function of such a model is to provide a common visual schema through

120 Peter Burke, “Context in Context”, Common Knowledge, 8, no. 1 (Winter, 2002): 176. 121 Whitehead describes this as the difference between ‘immediacy-perception’ and ‘meaning- perception’. See Alfred North Whitehead, Symbolism, Its Meaning and Effect (New York: Macmillan Co., 1927). 122 Michael Ermarth, Wilhelm Dilthey: The Critique of Historical Reason (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1978), 354–5, 359.

203 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

which specialist inquiry can be connected and integrated. The rationale for integrated inquiry

is that the notion of separate understanding is worthless if it cannot be combined (at some

point) with other knowledge and understanding to provide the more holistic knowledge that is

ultimately desired and needed. Specialist research will always be the foundation upon which

new knowledge is built, but specialist knowledge can only ever be partial and its natural

trajectory is towards deeper research and further specialization. Ultimately the fusion of the

multiple ‘knowledges’ and ‘intelligences’ intrinsic to ‘normal’ human functioning must be

reflected in both the way knowledge is discovered and created, and the way it is transmitted

and applied. That correlation and fusion cannot be achieved by specialists alone—just as

specialists alone in defence and aerospace cannot produce whole systems. Technological

synthesis is achieved through shared conceptual models and management processes which

ensure integration at a higher level.123

An academic-research knowledge model must accommodate both different categories

of knowledge and different modes of inquiry.124 A consequence is that it should have both

relational and dynamic characteristics. ‘Relational’ in that categories imply difference, but

although there are significant differences in the underlying cognitive ‘stance’ or design focus

associated with different knowledges, no category is foundational, each only has meaning in

relation to the others. ‘Dynamic’ in that individual disciplines nominally align with particular

cognitive modes, thus with particular categories, but there is a blurring of alignments. The

disciplines are more as Barbara Herrnstein Smith envisaged them: concentrations of activity

along inquiry continuums, rather than discrete polarised ‘packages’ fixed to a particular group

or mode.

From our current understanding of neurological and epistemological processes it would

seem that the relationship between experience, creative thought, meaning and understanding

is tetradic. Each depends on the others for its functioning, and all are required equally for the

effective creation and discovery of new knowledge. Consequently, there would seem to be

123 This is discussed in Chapter 5. 124 Here the term ‘categories’ does not mean ontological elements in an ontological category scheme such as Aristotelian or Cartesian or Husserlian category schemes; but refers to inquiry types.

204 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

four principal modes of acquiring knowledge: knowledge through explanation, knowledge

through intuition, knowledge through interpretation, and knowledge through pure reason.

Similarly, just as there are different modes of inquiry, so there are different categories of

knowledge which the modes address. The categories correlate with the ‘design stance’—the

disciplinary orientation—of the inquiry mode and are, in effect, the inquiry meta-subject.

Thus, the explanatory mode could be said to have physical substance (Su), or ‘fact’ (in the

Husserlian sense)125 as its meta-subject. Science and science-based disciplines favour this

mode. The interpretive mode could be said to have meaning (M) as its meta-subject. The

humanities and some social sciences favour this mode, particularly such disciplines as

history, anthropology, sociology, cultural studies, for example. The ‘pure’ reason mode could

be said to have as its meta-subject ‘being’ or ‘essence’ (E). Philosophy and mathematics

practise this mode of inquiry. The intuitive mode could be said to have ‘vitality’ or ‘spirit’

(Sp) as its meta-subject. The disciplines most connected to this category are the aesthetic,

creative and performing arts (including prose and poetry writing), but also any mode of

inquiry where inspiration, instinct, and mysticism are the primary impulses. Spiritual belief

systems such as theism, animism, and pantheism derive from this mode. Vitalism too, but it

also links to explanation, thus to the sciences, and to philosophy.

Together, these categories and modes constitute the elements to be modeled. The table

below provides a summary and a mapping of their generic alignments.

Mode Meta-Subject/Category Disciplinary Domains Explanation Substance Science and some Social Sciences

Interpretation Meaning Humanities and some Social Sciences

Pure Reason Essence Philosophy, Mathematics,

Intuition Spirit Religion, Creative Arts, Performing Arts; Decorative Arts

Table 1: Knowledge Map

125 In the basic Husserlian category scheme ‘fact’ means concrete entities in time or space-time. See David Woodham Smith, Mind World: Essays in Phenomenology and Ontology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 257.

205 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

Thus, the model will be an arrangement of four ‘nodes’ where each node relates to all others

equally (since no node (category, mode, or discipline) is foundational). In other words, the

nodes constitute a tetrad, thus their functional relationship will be tetradic and represented by

the three-dimensional tetrahedron. Figure 1 shows what such a relationship might be:

Spirit: - intuition

Holistic Understandin g Substance: - explanation Meaning: (applied reason) - Interpretation Essence: - ‘pure’ reason

Figure 1: Knowledge Model

The image here is of all modes being bound like a molecular cluster, which as a unity has the

supervenient character of unified knowledge or holistic understanding (just as ‘water’ is the

supervenient character of the hydrogen/oxygen molecule).

This, of course, is purely a conceptual model whose purpose is to aid the visualization

of research effort. It is simply an artificial construct designed to facilitate better correlation

and fusion of that research effort. It only has value to the degree that it is useful. Other quite

different models could be constructed, but this model does, from a theoretical perspective,

begin to capture the interconnected nature of ‘intelligent’ inquiry. Such inquiry must

transcend the wholly positivistic, or wholly relativistic, or wholly intuitive, or wholly rational.

This model can be of practical use.

The distinctive characteristic of the tetrahedron is that each node is connected to all

others. Thus, each knowledge node has three axes which connect it to the other nodes. If we

were to imagine that each axis was an inquiry continuum, then we can see that the model

206 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

encapsulates the main epistemological feature identified as desirable by Barbara Herrnstein

Smith. One way of visualizing this continuum might be to think of the nodes as inquiry

‘constellations’; as shown, for example, in Figure 2:

Figure 2: Inquiry Constellation

Thus, if we consider Figure 1 (and 2), there are six possible axes along which a

researcher or research product could be located. However, if it was accepted that each

researcher has a favoured mode (there will be exceptions), then that researcher, and their

research products, could be represented by ‘values’ along each of the three axes which

associate with that mode/node. A particular research product could be identified by an alpha-

numeric identifier indicating the node and the (three-axis) knowledge ‘mix’. Thus, each

specialist’s research output would have some distinctive mapping profile which would mirror

the distinctive intelligence profile of the individual researcher. For example, assume that a

value along an axis has the range: 1–7, then a particular research product might have the

identifier M 5Sp 2E 1Su; which indicates that the research product is primarily concerned

with meaning (M) but has a strong stylistic leaning towards the intuitive (Sp), some towards

the purely rational (E), but little towards the causal and explanatory (Su). Clearly there are

large differences in style and inclination between researchers, as Medawar and Geertz

commented. Foucault’s profile, for example, would place him, exceptionally, somewhere

around the middle of all six axes. In contrast, Medawar’s ‘tidiers-up’ scientists would be

tightly clustered around the Su node.

The model also allows mapping of disciplinary and sub-disciplinary profiles. For

207 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

example, the M5Sp2E1Su profile discussed above would fit Romantic history. Alternatively,

much local history, for example, might have the profile Su2M1Sp1E. The primary factor,

therefore in determining the research inquiry profile is the question being asked, not the

disciplinary provenance of the researcher. With the blurring of genres, disciplinary

boundaries have increasingly limited value. Trevelyan and Maitland both wrote history, as

Foucault did and Quentin Skinner does: however, each has a very different inquiry ‘profile’.

Alternatively, Proust’s Remembrance of Things Past and Ricoeur’s Meaning, History,

Forgetting, are not unconnected.126

Given that there are six axes and seven locations on each axis, there are a large number

of profiles possible, but very much fewer than there are researchers and research products.

The usefulness of the model’s profiling capability is that it could enable unexpected

similarities and complementarities to be revealed across disciplines rather than just within

disciplinary domains. For example, the M4Sp point is the same point on the M–Sp axis as the

Sp4M point, similarly, M2Sp is the same point as Sp5M, and so on for any axis and any

point. It would seem plausible that matches could reasonably be expected to produce fruitful

collaborations. Although it is likely that a majority of these interdisciplinary matches would

be within the broad nodal groupings, given the vast quantity of research output and numbers

of researchers there would also be many matches across the groups. The matching effectively

facilitates synthesis of research across disciplines, schools, institutions, and countries. Global

profiling is, in the wired automated-search world of the twenty-first century, able to be easily

and comprehensively performed. The tracing of keywords, phrases, styles, references,

citations etc., in varieties of media is today a basic function of most commerce-, research-,

education-, and intelligence-software.

The organization and mechanics of research in the twenty-first century has already

evolved to a stage where that organization and practice is quite different from even twenty

years earlier. The internet, advances in network and computing software, and the ubiquity of

126 Paul Ricouer, Meaning, History, Forgetting (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2004).

208 Ch. 4: Integrated Pure Inquiry

personal access to powerful computing hardware have meant that the virtual and physical

worlds have merged. The scale of collaborative activity—through, ‘wikis’, ‘crowdsourcing’,

and dedicated broadband connections linking universities to test sites (such as the new Large

Hadron Collider)—has risen exponentially. The organization and practice of research in

physics and the biological sciences, for example, has changed dramatically. In biology, gene

data is sourced as much from gene-sequencing synchrotrons as test tubes and detailed reports.

Worlds have merged. In the next few years broadband research-nets will be enhanced to

ultra-broadband—10,000 times faster than the current speed. There is no question that the

nature of research collaboration will change again, and there will be an even greater need to

ensure better integration of the multiple disciplinary, sub-disciplinary, and interdisciplinary

research outputs.

The fundamental building block remains the individual, individualistic, researcher who

reads, thinks, dreams, and discovers, but the ways that researcher connects to sources and the

like-minded will change. A ‘stout pair of boots’ will still be needed from time to time, but as

much to get away from, rather than get to, information. The place of the university in the

research and development process will also change. Organization at a higher level is required

of the synthesized ‘pure basic research’. Management of the research and development

‘loop’—pure to strategic to applied and so on—is still needed if the university is to keep

’moving up the food chain’ and retain its autonomy and independence.127

127 See Chapter 5.

209

210

CHAPTER 5

HISTORY AND RESEARCH MANAGEMENT

The greater our knowledge increases, the greater our ignorance unfolds … the vast stretches of the unknown and the unanswered and the unfinished still far outstrip our collective comprehension … We choose to go to the moon in this decade and do the other things, not because they are easy, but because they are hard, because that goal will serve to organize and measure the best of our energies and skills, because that challenge is one that we are willing to accept, one we are unwilling to postpone. —John Fitzgerald Kennedy1

We now speak of “context-driven” research, meaning “research carried out in a context of application, arising from the very work of problem solving and not governed by the paradigms of traditional disciplines of knowledge.” It involves multidisciplinary teams brought together for short periods of time, often connected only by means of telecommunications. —Gouvernement du Québec, Ministère de l'Éducation2

A Constellation of Disciplines

In their discussion paper on the future of higher education and university research in

Australia, the Vice-Chancellors of eight of the country’s leading research universities noted that the contemporary research university is ‘an adaptive institution evolving in the changing society’, that it ‘cannot live outside the forces of its transformation’, and that ‘its legitimacy depends not on what it has achieved in the past but on what it is becoming and how it can contribute in the future’.3 They identified several principles on which future higher education policy should rest. One principle was that:

Research universities provide the fundamentals of the basic research system that underpins the creation of new knowledge, the application of existing

1 John Fitzgerald Kennedy. Speech at Rice University, 12 September 1962, http://ww1.jsc.nasa.gov/er/seh/ricetalk.htm, [13 June 2006]. 2 Gouvernement du Québec, Ministère de l'Éducation, 1998, Universities and the Future: Government Policy Options Regarding Québec Universities, Consultation Paper, http://www.meq.gouv.qc.ca/REFORME/universi/cons-univ-a.pdf, quoted in Michael Gibbons, ‘What kind of university? Research and teaching in the 21st century’, Victoria University of Technology, 1997 Beanland lecture, Melbourne. 3 Group of Eight, Seizing the Opportunities: A Group of Eight Policy Discussion Paper, 6 June 2007 (Canberra: The Group of Eight, 2007), 14.

211 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

knowledge and the training of highly skilled labour in a global knowledge economy.4

The purpose of higher education, they said, was to ‘enable individuals to learn to the best of

their potential’, but it was basic research that underpinned that function. It was likely that

their use of the term ‘basic research’, rather than simply ‘research’, was deliberate and meant

to distinguish their universities’ research from that in the less prestigious universities.5

The Vice-Chancellors envisaged a ‘top-down’, ‘bottom-up’, process for the

development of research areas. Top-down, the areas would be determined by international

research performance and national economic, strategic, social and environmental priorities.

Bottom-up, areas would be determined by the universities nominating their own areas of

research strength, and research areas they wished to advance. In other words, market-place

processes. They were drawn to this approach through recognizing that ‘both sides’ of politics

at the Federal level were ‘looking more to market mechanisms to shape a responsive and

diverse system of high quality and high standards’.6 The Vice-Chancellor of the University

of Melbourne noted in a later paper that the stability of the American higher education system

was due largely to the ‘unbroken history of … a wide range of institutions within both the

public and private sectors’, allowing market mechanisms to work. ‘Its [the American higher

education system’s] system stability seems worth emulating’, he concluded.7

The future, therefore, for universities, should this vision be embraced, is that they will

be faced with exactly the same strategic business decisions as any other large corporation.

Within the university, the same planning processes would need to be taken regarding product

range (courses) and the range and depth of in-house research needed, first, to support those

4 Ibid., 5. 5 By international standards, research governance and funding in Australia are highly centralized. Unlike some countries, universities receive little research funding from private industry. Research funding to universities is channelled through the Australian Research Council (ARC) and the National Health and Medical Research Council (NHMRC). Funding consists of bulk grants based on institutional research quality and impact, and competitive grants and scholarships for individual researchers. 6 Group of Eight, Seizing the Opportunities, 1. 7 Glyn Davis, “The Search for a Stable Centre”, paper given at the AFR Higher Education Conference, 13 March 2008. http://unimelb.edu.au/speeches/transcripts/davis_AFR_Higher_Ed_20080313.doc, [26/3/08].

212 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

products and, second, to create new product possibilities. For universities, for whom pure

basic research is a core activity, new product possibilities would mean the creation of new

conceptual ‘spaces’. The Vice-Chancellors did not, however, speak in these terms. They did

not explore what pure basic research is or what it might mean in the future. The examples

they provided: agriculture, bio-molecular sciences, health care delivery, mining engineering,

‘engagement with Asia’, and so on, were framed as socially ‘useful’. In other words, they

were more areas of applied research, or development and innovation, than conceptual

exploration. Certainly, there was no direct reference to inquiry concerned primarily with

epistemological and ontological discovery.

The problem is that as universities strive to make their research relate more closely to

social priorities, that desire inevitably means research more related to economic priorities.

The more immediately economically valuable the research is, the greater the rewards in terms

of funding and resources. The effect, however, as Roger L. Geiger has noted, is that

Universities find that insatiable needs and increasing competition constrain their freedom of activity. At times, their involvement with markets appears to threaten the wellspring of knowledge that is the source of their value.8

It is what he calls ‘the paradox of the marketplace’, and it does indeed threaten that

‘wellspring’ of knowledge that is the source of the universities’ value, but only if the

university fails to define and manage the subtle differences in the basic research, applied

research, development and innovation continuum. It is in the ‘product’ end of the continuum

that the marketplace expects performance, not the basic research end. Research at the leading

edge of understanding, outside instrumental concerns, is the universities’ distinctive

competence and the source of their creative value. In the twenty-first century the generation

of advanced, specialized conceptual knowledge remains their distinctive function. It is that

competence which determines the uniqueness of their ‘consumer’ products.

There is a related trend in Australia and internationally for academic research to be

8 Roger L. Geiger, Knowledge and Money: Research Universities and the Paradox of the Marketplace (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), xvii.

213 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

channelled into interdisciplinary research centres and institutes, both to enhance collaboration

between disciplines and to provide a more ‘consumer-oriented’ focus to the research being

undertaken. Centres and institutes provide a more easily understood ‘face’ to sponsors and

other patrons; also, as Roger Geiger notes:

They [the universities] recognize that funding for research has increasingly favoured cross-disciplinary investigations and that departments or schools, left on their own, do little to foster such projects. The general approach has been to encourage the formation of interdisciplinary organizations, particularly by linking them to new appointments.9

The future of single disciplines has become directly connected to their success in cross-

disciplinary investigation. Inevitably, cross-disciplinary investigation will accentuate the

need for the effective integration, at some level, of specialist knowledge. Logically, that can

only be at a pan-disciplinary level—at the institutional level—and this task will itself require

directed research and development.

If a critical future task for the academy is to determine how more unified inquiry might

be accomplished institutionally, then the most pressing task for individual disciplines is to

define their distinctive role in the unified basic research enterprise. To do this they need to

identify what is the distinctive knowledge they pursue, why its pursuit requires their research

skills and what pure basic research means in their field. If this cannot be demonstrated, then

that discipline will have no distinctive leading research role in the research community of the

future university.

For the history discipline, there is significant work to be done to identify what basic

research means for the discipline, and significant work for the university to identify how that

research might integrate with other team-based research in the future research enterprise. It is

likely, however, that many practitioners would not only question whether they might have

any team-based research role to play, but also whether any such thing is possible either

practically or theoretically. Some even argue that fragmentation within the discipline is not

9 Geiger, Knowledge and Money, 172.

214 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

only inevitable but positive.

II

At a forum held by the American Historical Review to discuss Peter Novick's That Noble

Dream: The Objectivity Question and the Future of the Historical Profession,10 a wide range

of views were recorded on the question raised by Novick of the coherence or incoherence of

the discipline. Allan Megill stated that his aim was ‘to point out some broad, and I think little

pondered, implications of the account of the American historical profession that Peter Novick

[had offered in his book]’. Megill’s focus was the fourth and final part of the book, entitled

“Objectivity in Crisis”, in particular, the implications of the chapter titles of that part which

were: : “The Collapse of Comity”; “Every Group Its Own Historian”; “The Centre Does Not

Hold”; and “There Was No King In Israel”. The starting point for Megill’s discussion was his

concern that historians had interpreted Novick’s book ‘as portraying a situation that is

primarily negative’. And from the nature of the wide discussion that followed the book’s

publication, it seemed that that was how it had been interpreted. However, Megill claimed

that ‘a careful reading of Novick’s book, does not suggest that he has an apocalyptic view of

the current fragmented state of historiography, nor does it suggest that he “laments” that

state’.11 It was the view Megill too, held. He declared:

I find that I am profoundly suspicious of attempts to overcome the fragmentation, of attempts to restore (at some higher or more sophisticated level) the synthesis. Belief in the virtue of synthesis and in the badness of fragmentation seems deeply ingrained within our academic culture and within the culture of professional historians in particular … I find no justification—certainly no articulated justification—for taking “fragmentation” as a dispraising term and “synthesis” as a praising one.12

Megill argued that there ‘lies deeply embedded in the professional identity of

historians’ a belief in the possibility of “the full story” which can be told once “further

10 Peter Novick, That Noble Dream: The Objectivity Question and the Future of the Historical Profession (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988). 11 Allan Megill, “Fragmentation and the Future of Historiography”, American Historical Review, 96, no. 3. (Jun., 1991): 693. 12 Ibid., 693–4.

215 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

research” has been done, and that the notion of objectivity was hidden in this idea that there is

a “full story”.13 However, he argued, once it is accepted that there can be no “grand

narrative”, then the only level at which a professional synthesis could be achieved would be

at a reflective level. Unity would come, if at all, ‘through sustained attention to the histories,

sociologies, and rhetorics of historical study—that is, through examining precisely the

diversities that have shadowed historiography from the beginning’. In this respect, works like

Novick’s, and those of such writers as ‘R. G. Collingwood, Hayden White, Paul Veyne, and

Louis Mink’, would assume an important integrative role. Unfortunately, Megill observed,

such work falls ‘into the professionally despised field of historiography or “historiology”’.14

More importantly, he noted, a consequence of integration at this reflective level is that the

character of this integration would be the common recognition by historians of the

impossibility of their union. He concluded, therefore, that ‘the deep teaching of Novick’s

wise and learned book, it seems to me, is that integration, either substantive or

methodological, is impossible, except by force or forgetfulness, and in consequence is not to

be desired’.15

It was a bitter-sweet conclusion. Megill started his article declaring there to be no

problem, but seemed to end by concluding that there was no solution. The cause of this

ambiguity, and the deeper problem, is that Megill failed to define the common

epistemological research function professional historians perform in the academy. He failed

to define at a fundamental level just what type of knowledge historians produce; just what is

behind the questions they are asking. Because he saw only the diverse domains of interest

within the profession, he assumed that sub-disciplinary derived knowledge, let-alone

interdisciplinary knowledge, is incompatible—he implied that diversity is the only common

thread. Consequently, the larger question of how specialist effort might be integrated

becomes irrelevant. As an academic historian, Megill is critically aware of the ‘histories,

sociologies, and rhetorics of historical study’—and has an incisive understanding of the way

13 Ibid., 695. 14 Ibid., 697. 15 Ibid., 698.

216 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

the discipline has been shaped. However, while he acknowledges that conceptually all

disciplinary inquiry has a common epistemological purpose, he seems to assume that

disciplinary boundaries are fixed. Thus, he considers ‘the Peircean appeal to “communities

of the competent”’ to be misguided since ‘there is no single competence’. And he argues that

there is a further problem:

An argument deemed acceptable by the consensus of competent historians may well be deemed unacceptable by the consensus of competent philosophers or economists—and vice versa. Many historians have in fact never entered into serious argumentative relation with economists or philosophers or literary theorists or rhetoricians, for such relations are not in general given professional reward. Hence they do not know how multifarious is competence.16

This may well be a common view. But Megill emphasizes that this is not to argue for

interdisciplinary unification since, he says, his own experience of arguing with practitioners

of other disciplines has indicated that the different modes of argument are too incompatible

‘for any one person to practice them at the same time’.

It is a telling comment and illuminates the underlying assumption that drives his

argument. In this view it is the individual practitioner who must draw together all the threads

and do the synthesizing; which means that even cooperation at an interdisciplinary level is as

impractical as interdisciplinary unification. The assumption he makes comes from accepting

without question the time-honoured notion of the professional historian as lonely craftsman—

that the historian’s output will necessarily be the traditional, individually hand-crafted,

product.

Thus Megill has unfortunately discarded what is now an important consideration for the

discipline going forward, the methodology of interdisciplinary cooperation. Consequently, he

has impeded progress towards removing the two obstacles that face the advancement of

understanding. The first obstacle is philosophical: that there are no foundational or self-

sufficient disciplinary ‘knowledges’, rather, disciplinary endeavour can only be part of an

16 Ibid., 695.

217 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

historically situated human and ‘human’ search for knowledge and meaning. As homo-

sapiens we seek intuitively, and as ‘humans’ we seek culturally, to know our experiential

world as fully as possible. Disciplinary boundaries are markers inside that wider frame. The

second obstacle is practical: given the interconnected nature of knowledge, how can specialist

knowledge meaningfully be integrated so that more unified knowledge can be acquired?

How is that acquisition to be managed? Megill seems to accept the multifariousness of

knowledge but, because he assumes that the individual is the only possible conduit and source

of the final product, sees anything other than discipline-specific knowledge to be impossible.

But even accepting the limiting case that he outlines, Megill would be unlikely to deny that

disciplinary knowledge in the academy is still part of a broader academic dialectic. He would

be unlikely to deny that any exploration at the boundary of disciplinary knowledge—whether

that boundary marks the limits of the discipline’s theoretical frame, or the limits of the

discipline’s traditional domain of interest—will necessarily impinge or encroach into another

discipline’s area, or several disciplines’ areas. Interconnection rather than separation of

disciplinary threads is the norm in any explanation of real events—an observation which, if

not beyond dispute, is close to being so. Thus, again, the real issue is how to integrate

disciplinary research.

III

There is a distinct difference, however, between connected knowledge and integrated

research. Cross-disciplinary discussion stimulates fresh disciplinary research, but the

products of that research remain single-disciplinary. Cross-disciplinary discussion has long

been common in the university, but until recently research has remained distinctly

disciplinary. In the 1960s, (Sir) Michael Postan had described cross-disciplinary activity as

‘usefully invad[ing] each other’s preserves’ in order to ‘enrich their stock of topics and

interests.’ Historians since the early nineteenth century, he argued, had formed themselves

into ‘marauding bands—the so called ‘historical schools’ of jurisprudence, politics and

economics—with the avowed object of annexing the neighbouring fields of political and

social science’. He noted also that the ‘reciprocal incursions from theory to history’ were

218 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

even older; and each time ‘masses of intellectual ammunition’ was left behind which

‘historians still go on firing’.17

Earlier, in 1944, Keith Hancock, like Postan, had remarked on the effect of cross-

disciplinary knowledge on disciplinary output. In his inaugural lecture as Chichele Professor

of Economic History at the , Hancock used as his theme ‘quality of

span’. By ‘quality of span’ he meant the ability to think across disciplinary borders.18 Span,

he later wrote, was ‘an awareness of background … a consciousness of the relation of

things’.19 Hancock in his lecture remarked on his admiration for his predecessor G. N.

Clark’s ‘span of mind which comprehended at the same time the science of a great age and its

technology, its political arithmetic and its philosophy’. Clark, Hancock felt, ‘was well

equipped to lead an attack which surely is long overdue, an attack against the segregation of

minds, which today is the besetting danger of University life in Great Britain’.20 In the

lecture, Hancock spoke approvingly of Alfred Marshall who in order ‘to explain the

economic leadership of England … invoked technology, science, education, politics, morals,

religion (“the Puritan strain”), and national temperament (“the sturdy Norse character” of

Englishmen)’.21 Hancock noted that historians may have felt that Marshall ‘used some of

these categories a trifle indiscriminately’, but observed that they would approve Marshall’s

interpretations less had they been the product of economic theory alone.

Alfred Marshall was one of the most influential economists of his time, but it is not just

the breadth of an explanation which can, as with Marshall, ensure a work’s credibility and

wider relevance. As Maitland’s work has shown, it can also be the depth of a question.

Maitland, a contemporary of Marshall, always wrestled with specific and highly technical

problems related to the history of English law, but the value of his work extended well

17 M. M. Postan, “Fact and Relevance in Historical Study”, Historical Studies, 13, no. 51. (Oct., 1968): 419–20. 18 W. K. Hancock, Politics in Pitcairn and Other Essays (London: Macmillan & Co., 1947), 158. He defines the term more fully in his essay ‘A Note on Mary Kingsley’, in Politics in Pitcairn and Other Essays. 19 W. K. Hancock, Professing History (Sydney: Sydney University Press, 1976), 6. 20 Hancock, Politics in Pitcairn and Other Essays, 157–58. 21 Ibid., 161.

219 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

beyond his narrow technical field of medieval English law. This value was due not so much

to the technical quality of his scholarship, though that was impeccable, but to the

epistemology behind the questions he asked. For Maitland, ‘justice’ is a psychological and

cultural category, not a legal one. For him, to study the history of law was to study the

evolution of social thought—society was defined by its legal concepts.22 Legal history was

the means to this deeper knowledge, since, as he had commented: ‘speaking broadly, we may

say that only in legal documents and under legal forms are the social and economic

arrangements of remote times made visible to us’.23 Michael Bentley notes that Helen Cam,

who had collected some of Maitland’s papers for publication, considered it ‘lamentable’ that

later observers persisted in their view that Maitland was just a ‘constitutional historian’.24

Because the core of Maitland’s research questions was not narrowly technical, the

results of his research, though apparently technical, had much broader relevance and impact.

Eighty years after The History of English Law Before the Time of Edward I was published,25

Alan Macfarlane, a social historian who had also trained as an anthropologist, was struggling

with what he saw as problems with the orthodox picture of the nature of ‘traditional’ English

society up to the fifteenth century. MacFarlane said he was ‘dissatisfied with the general

framework within which I was working, but did not know why, or where I should look for an

alternative model’.26 Significantly, it was a remark of Maitland’s that enabled Macfarlane to

recontextualise English ‘peasant’ society. Maitland had described the highly developed

property rights of women in that early English society, and had remarked that England ‘long

22 ‘The power of seeing’ a murder trial ‘in every age of the history of every race’ was what would be the historian’s greatest facility. Frederic William Maitland, “The Body Politic” in The Collected Papers of Frederic William Maitland, vol. 3, ed. H.A.L. Fisher (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1911), 300. 23 Maitland, “English Legal History”, in Collected Papers, vol. 2, ed. H. A. L. Fisher, 3; quoted in Michael Bentley, Modernizing England’s Past, 124. 24 Helen Cam ed., Historical Essays, ix, quoted in Michael Bentley, Modernizing England’s Past, 124. However, Bentley also notes (126) that R. H. Tawney was ‘relentless in his pursuit of the legal mind as an obstacle to real economic history,’ especially to the ‘entire question of land utilization (as opposed to questions of title).’ But Bentley later notes that other economic historians had emphasized how important, because of the practice of letting and sub-letting, knowledge of title was to questions of tenure and usage. 25 First edition published 1895; second edition published 1898. 26 Alan Macfarlane, The Origins of English Individualism: The Family, Property and Social Transition (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1978), 5.

220 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

ago’ had chosen her ‘individualistic path’.27 That comment was the catalyst. Macfarlane

determined that ‘individualism’ was the point of difference in early English society. It was

that society’s defining element. His hypothesis contradicted the standard picture of peasant

society which historians had long used.28

Macfarlane’s hypothesis was that England had never had a peasantry in the conceptual

sense of the word, that

the majority of ordinary people in England from at least the thirteenth century were rampant individualists, highly mobile both geographically and socially, economically ‘rational’, market-oriented and acquisitive, ego- centred in kinship and social life.29

Thus, he implied, English society has always been different, hence European-inspired social

models could provide little understanding of it. He rejected the idea ‘that at some time

England experienced a period of decisive change, breaking not only with the rest of Europe

but with its own past as well’.30 He continued with the very expansive remark that ‘perhaps

this is no surprise, for it would make them very like their descendants whom we are

beginning to find out were like this three centuries later’.31 But by reasoning in this way,

MacFarlane was ignoring the fluidity of the relationship between agency and structure that

informed Maitland’s work. As Joyce Appleby has observed, apart from severely limiting

interpretive options, there ‘lurks, unexorcized’ beneath MacFarlane’s claim, ‘the sociological

assumption that the form of society dictates events. Instead of seeing men and women [as]

selectively coping with concrete and changing events’. MacFarlane had placed his

individuals in a ‘cultural holding pattern for six hundred years’, Appleby remarked.32

Although her remarks were directed at Macfarlane’s thesis, and written more than

27 Sir F. Pollock and F. W. Maitland, The History of English Law Before the Time of Edward I (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968), 2 vols, 433 (volume reference not given), quoted in Macfarlane, The Origins of English Individualism, 5. 28 Joyce Appleby, “The Origins of English Individualism: The Family, Property and Social Transition”, American Historical Review, 84, no. 4 (Oct., 1979): 1046. 29 Macfarlane, The Origins of English Individualism, 163. 30 Appleby, “The Origins of English Individualism”, 1047. 31 Macfarlane, The Origins of English Individualism, 163. 32 Appleby, “The Origins of English Individualism”, 1047.

221 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

twenty-five years ago, Appleby went on to identify what is still the central problem with

specialist inquiry: ‘Important as they are, Macfarlane’s facts about mobility, marriage,

kinship, and land sales cannot serve as surrogates for the dozens of other relevant variables.

Indeed, the more he argues for the persistence of certain social arrangements, the less they

can explain England’s remarkable economic career’.33 England did indeed undergo a

dramatic economic transformation which MacFarlane’s thesis cannot explain. Nevertheless,

Macfarlane’s research made a valuable contribution to wider cross-disciplinary inquiry and,

as Geoffrey Elton observed, ‘it was Maitland who helped him there’.34 Appleby observed

that despite the ‘major professional donnybrook’ that Macfarlane’s book would cause, she

could imagine ‘dozens of blue pencils quietly excising the word “peasant” from manuscripts

right now’.35

IV

The Macfarlane example reinforces the obvious point that the interrelationship and

interconnections between structure, agency, continuity and change, are so complex and

dynamic that single disciplinary research can never illuminate anything other than limited and

specific disciplinary questions. If wider insight into the physical–psychological–cultural

network are to be achieved, then wider input is needed. However, ‘wider input’ means wider

selection of specialist input since, logically, the knowledge to be aggregated is specialist

knowledge. But the aggregation of specialist knowledge cannot be at the level of the

individual specialist; it can only be at a higher level. Consequently, and contrary to Megill’s

view, if wider explanations are to be achieved then ways must be found to aggregate

knowledge and then synthesize it. Almost from their inception, the humanities in the

academy have developed institutional practices that ensure a certain level of disciplinary

cross-fertilization, but not the synthesis of aggregated knowledge. How this might be

achieved is not a question which the individual disciplines within the humanities consider, nor

do their institutions. The establishment of centres and institutes are a gesture towards

33 Ibid., 1047. 34 Elton, F. W. Maitland (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1985), 101. 35 Appleby, “The Origins of English Individualism”, 1046.

222 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

synthesis, but as Robert Geiger implied, they are more concerned with organizational

questions than theoretical and methodological ones. Co-location, or cross-disciplinary

discussion do not by themselves produce synthesized or aggregated research output.

Conceptual frameworks and methodological processes are required if specialist knowledge is

to be first aggregated and then synthesized. Without them, all that is achieved is the

accumulation of enhanced specialist knowledge; a result which is illustrated by Keith

Hancock’s experience in the formation and operation of the Research School of Social

Sciences, Australian National University.

Hancock, in the role of academic advisor to the Interim Council formed to implement

the establishment of the Australian National University, had set out his own ideas for more

formalized research-school arrangements that would facilitate the ‘reciprocity’ Postan had

described. But Hancock’s emphasis was on the evolution of shared interests through scholars

working alongside one another in the appropriate intellectual environment, not joint research.

Imposed collaborative research was something he actively opposed—though he was aware, as

he said, that without strong leadership at the institutional level, ‘separate competing

specialisms’ ran the risk of becoming just a ‘rabble of individualists’.36

Hancock’s view was that planning in such situations meant not the imposition of a

design, but a plan which would bring to fruition a design implicit in the ‘healthy growth’ of

intellectual endeavour.37 When outlining his ideas on the structure of the new social sciences

research school to the Interim Council, Hancock specifically avoided the term ‘departments’,

which implied rigidity and segregation, and instead used the term: ‘growing points’. He

identified the ‘growing points’ as: Economics, Statistics, Population and Health Studies, Law,

Political Science, Social Anthropology, Psychology, History and Philosophy, Sociology, and

Geography.38 Philosophy was to have the special role of ‘gadfly work’, by which he meant

36 Quoted in S. G. Foster and Margaret M. Varghese, The Making of the Australian National University (St. Leonards: Allen & Unwin, 1996), 50. The source was not referenced specifically, but was from correspondence with Sir Frederic Eggleston and made after Hancock’s resignation from the advisory committee in April 1949. 37 W. K Hancock, Country and Calling (London: Faber and Faber, 1954), 238, quoted in S. G. Foster and Margaret M. Varghese, The Making of the Australian National University, 39. 38 In a letter to H. C. Coombs (a member of the Interim Council). Hancock to Coombs 31

223 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

that philosophers would force methodological questions to be addressed and perspective to be

maintained. This perhaps indicated that he did not think of philosophy itself as a research

discipline in the sense of discovery of new knowledge. Nevertheless, Hancock considered

philosophical expertise essential input since, as he explained later,

It was almost impossible for our economists, political scientists, demographers and lawyers to see their problems in shallow perspective when almost every day they were exchanging ideas with two such competent philosophers as P. H. Partridge and J. A. Passmore.39

Thus he had concluded that ‘the advancement of knowledge will be achieved in the process of

questioning, answering and debating’.40 The centre of action, however, was the individual;

the individual was made more productive by working within a stimulating and congenial

environment. Outstanding researchers were the foundation. The whole was not larger than

the parts, the parts were the whole; the process was there to make the parts better.

Nor is it clear from his operational description how Hancock saw the advancement of

knowledge as differing from the accumulation of knowledge: whether new knowledge was

always outside current understanding, or whether it was always within established cultural

understanding. He had written how ‘master-craftsmen’ such as Marc Bloch ‘illuminate’ the

meaning of ‘perspective’,41 and had quoted with approval Marc Bloch’s definition of history

as ‘essentially a progressive movement of the human intelligence’,42 but it was more the

refinement of socialised knowledge rather than the exploration of knowledge’s limits which

was Hancock’s goal. Yet it was Bloch’s conceptual originality which was his distinctive

contribution to research, not his craftsmanship. Hancock was ambivalent about the

usefulness of theory to the historian. He felt that ‘sound technique’—by which he meant

‘amongst other things, rigorous precision’—was the essential element for the historian, not

theory. His view was that theory had its place: but only in that it could be ‘useful’ in the

March 1947, quoted in S. G. Foster and Margaret M. Varghese, The Making of the Australian National University, 39. 39 Hancock, Professing History, 43. 40 Ibid., 12. 41 W. K. Hancock, Perspective in History (Canberra: The Australian National University, 1982), vii. 42 Hancock, Professing History, 12.

224 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

quest to ‘combine precision with span’. He conceded that, as a tool, it was needed for certain

data, but in his opinion, to say ‘no theory, no history’ (as he quoted the economic historian

Werner Sombart as saying) was ‘true sometimes, but not always’. Hancock considered a

more appropriate axiom to be: ‘No imagination, no history’.43

But in proposing this alternative, Hancock was either rejecting or avoiding Sombart’s

point that ‘theory’ was, unavoidably, the conceptual framework which determined the form

any interpretation or ordering of data was to take. Hancock, in contrast, was denoting theory

as a tool to aid description, not as a conceptual frame that preceded explanation. For

Sombart, economic history and sociology were simply the means by which social and cultural

phenomena could be probed to establish deeper theoretical insight. The rationale for

Sombart’s work on the history of bourgeois society was to progress questions of social

theory. He successfully advanced theoretical knowledge in his fields of study. For example,

there seems little doubt that his large study, Modern Capitalism (1902), stimulated and

challenged Max Weber;44 (it was probably more important for Weber, some argue, than he

admitted when explaining The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism).45 And

Sombart’s conclusions regarding the importance of the evolution of honouring contracts to

bourgeois morality strongly influenced Max Horkheimer’s thinking on the relationship

between collective interest and individual consciousness. Those ideas shaped Horkheimer’s

later studies, and Horkheimer’s studies were influential in shaping twentieth-century critical

theory.46 The fact that the work of Sombart, Weber and Horkheimer was outside orthodoxy,

was the reason it was so influential.

Hancock’s approach to the organization of research and the role of theory in it—

43 Ibid., 20–21. The Sombart quote was used also in “Machiavelli in Modern Dress: An Inquiry into Historical Method”, in Hancock, Politics in Pitcairn and Other Essays, 22; and in “Ordeal by Thesis”, in Hancock, Perspective in History, 13. 44 Guenther Roth, “Introduction” in Weber’s Protestant Ethic: Origins, Evidence, Contexts, eds Hartmut Lehmann and Guenther Roth (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 11. 45 Friedrich Wilhelm Graf, “The German Theological Sources and Protestant Church Politics”, in Weber’s Protestant Ethic, 32 46 See Peter M. R. Stirk, Max Horkheimer: A New Interpretation (Hemel Hempstead: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1992), 22, 224n. Stirk was referring to Sombart’s Der Bourgeois. Zur Geistesgeschichte der Modernen Wirtschaftsmenschen (Munich and Leipzig: Duncker and Humboldt, 1923).

225 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

research to be personality driven and theory to be peripheral—might have reflected Oxford

history school orthodoxy, and might have produced scholarly material of high academic

quality, but it did not necessarily produce knowledge that was valued by the wider

community. Sir Frederic Eggleston, a member of the Australian National University Interim

Council, was one who was critical both of Hancock’s approach and of the concept of the

humanities as a loose group of independent studies which British universities such as

Hancock’s Oxford encouraged.47 He was concerned that Hancock’s proposal could result in

energies being dissipated and the ‘fundamental problems of the subject [social science]’ being

neglected. Eggleston, like Hancock, wanted the Research School of Social Sciences to

function as an interdisciplinary, cooperative research centre (‘my dream’, he said). But as an

experienced politician and diplomat, and as one deeply concerned with social philosophy,

Eggleston was uninterested in inquiry as simply single-discipline inquiry. He was

unequivocal that the school should be concerned with ‘fundamental social truths’, and with

strengthening understanding of the intrinsic unity of the social sciences. These ideas were

articulated in his book: Search for a Social Philosophy and were stimulated by the ideas of, in

particular, Bergson, Whitehead, Ruth Benedict, and J. C. Smuts. Eggleston was particularly

drawn to Smuts’s rejection (explained in Smuts’s Holism and Evolution) of narrow Cartesian

dualism and its replacement with an ‘holistic’ evolutionary process where physical

phenomena and human personality are part of one indivisible set of interacting force-fields.48

Atoms, cells, mind, and personality were the product of evolutionary continuity. For Smuts,

personality was the supreme ideal of evolution, but for Eggleston the social entity, not

individual personality, was the ideal. In Search for a Social Philosophy, Smuts’s fields of

force are recast as ‘patterns’, but Eggleston remained strongly drawn to Smuts’s vision.

Eggleston had also read Karl Mannheim with great interest and approval; he sent Max

Crawford an early draft of Search for a Social Philosophy for review.49

47 See S. G. Foster and Margaret M. Varghese, The Making of the Australian National University, 49. 48 Holism and Evolution was published in 1926. The title of vol. 2 of Hancock’s biography of Smuts is Smuts: The Fields of Force. Smuts’s philosophy and Holism and Evolution is discussed at some length in W. K. Hancock, Smuts: The Fields of Force 1919–1950 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968), 176–97. 49 Eggleston also acknowledged a debt to Maitland. Eggleston’s book was written around three

226 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

Eggleston sought integrated knowledge. In Search for a Social Philosophy, he had

written: ‘It is a curious and … an anomalous feature in the history of thought, that the social

sciences have developed in separate compartments with little attention to the obvious

relations they bear one to another’.50 He was clear that this was not what he wanted from the

research school:

We want economists who are aware that their main decisions are political in character; political scientists who understand how dependent they are on law, and lawyers who understand how the law must give substance to political concepts; historians capable of showing how institutions work; and a philosophy which shows how knowledge and thought are articulated in institutions and conduct.51

And he was quite clear what, for him, advancement of knowledge meant: ‘I suggest that, in

the social sciences, it is not the extension of knowledge but the intensification of

knowledge—the revelation of meaning—that is needed [italics added]’. In economics, for

example, he said it was the ‘nature of economic thought’ and the ‘springs of economic action’

that were to be understood, if society was to advance, since ‘all of the economic problems

which face us today raise fundamental social issues’.52 Although basic research was in his

view essential, he also held that if the advancement of knowledge was not linked to pragmatic

social action, then it was useless. Hancock, in a letter to Mills, which Eggleston had read,

had described himself ‘more of a social artist than a social scientist—or possibly I should call

myself a craftsman … I venture into all fields, but I am not a master of them … I have shied

way from the “ologies”’.53 Eggleston’s comment on this was:

concepts which he had used as a basis for his theory of society: ‘pattern’, ‘contract’, and ‘psychic’. He had written how ‘the warrant for the use of the word [contract] is Maitland’s description of the evolution of law as being from status to contract.’ F. W. Eggleston, Search for a Social Philosophy (Parkville: Melbourne University Press, 1941), 12. 50 Eggleston, Search for a Social Philosophy, 15. 51 S. G. Foster and Margaret M. Varghese, The Making of the Australian National University, 49. 52 From “Notes on Professor Hancock’s Letter”, 8 September 1947, quoted in Warren G. Osmond, Frederic Eggleston: An Intellectual in Australian Politics (North Sydney: Allen & Unwin, 1985), 268. 53 Letter from Hancock to Mills, 16 July 1947, quoted in Warren G. Osmond, Frederic Eggleston: An Intellectual in Australian Politics, 268.

227 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

The most remarkable feature of present-day thought is the terrific problems we have to face and the fact that we have no answers. Professor Hancock says he disregarded ‘ologies long ago but they did not disregard us, and the air is full of clamant ideologies. The man in the street is not aware of the fact but all his claims touch upon fundamental social principles. What has the academic world done to meet them in the last forty years? 54

Eggleston held Hancock in high regard, but did not consider him indispensable to the

accomplishment of the Council’s goals. He advised Sir Douglas Copland, the first Vice-

Chancellor, accordingly. In 1949 Hancock resigned his position as Academic Advisor.55

The strong view which Eggleston held regarding research—that the purpose of the

advancement of knowledge was not simply the enlargement of knowledge of the world, but

also the improvement of society—was the same philosophy that drove Horkheimer, Adorno

and others in the Institute for Social Research in Frankfurt. The function of a research school

of social sciences in this view was to mediate effectively between practical and theoretical

inquiry. What was missing from Eggleston’s thinking, though, was any clear research model

whereby pure basic research, strategic basic research, applied research, and experimental

development (social improvement in this case) could be separately identified and managed,

but remained connected and interactive. But in this regard, in the humanities and social

sciences, no-one else, either, had thought about such a model. Keith Hancock had a clear

idea of how a research school should be run, but that idea was not based on either an

integrated research model or an integrated knowledge model. Consequently, efforts at

combining specialist research were never particularly successful. Those efforts demonstrated

why models of some form were needed.

In 1957 Hancock accepted the positions of Director of the Research School of Social

Sciences and Professor of History, roles which he was to discharge with distinction until 1961

and 1965 respectively. However, his research management philosophy and his theoretical

approach to disciplinary research remained unchanged from that articulated to the Interim

54 Osmond, Frederic Eggleston: An Intellectual in Australian Politics, 268. 55 Hancock describes in Country and Calling [243] the meeting with Copland, in London, which led to his resignation.

228 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

Council. Find ‘good men’ from whom ‘good work’ could be relied upon to flow, identify

growing points around which this work could be focused, and build a few bridges between

disciplines and between specialists. There is nothing wrong with this philosophy if it is

understood to be subordinate to the accomplishment of, or at least progress towards, defined

objectives and purpose. Some integrating rationale is required, though, if it is to result in

anything more than individual works from a talented collective. Without specific theoretical

guidance or direction to individual research, accumulation of knowledge rather than its

intensification can be the only possible outcome at the institutional level. This is not to say

that the cooperative effort which produced the Australian Dictionary of Biography was of

limited value. The dictionary was and is an invaluable aid to Australian historical

scholarship, but it is not new knowledge in the theoretical sense, in the way that, say, the

critical theory which emerged through cooperative effort from the Institute for Social

Research, was new knowledge. With Hancock, there seemed to be an assumption that

whatever was produced would have value. His Oxonian sense of unassailable legitimacy

seemed to cause him to accept without question the soundness of the view that the scholarship

of ‘good men’ justified itself. In this view, in the hands of a scholar all work is of value. And

as he said:

Even a pedestrian inquiry has value when it is pursued carefully and fair- mindedly; to get the record right, so far as the evidence allows, is not only a mental but also a moral achievement. Precision and honesty, by which our civilization stands or falls, are not to be despised even in small topics of research [since] small topics may reflect large issues.56

But that presupposes that what ‘large’ means is known and agreed. In the context above in

which Hancock used the word, he simply meant issues that were interdisciplinary and not, in

his words, ‘cellular’ (within the discipline). The function of ‘large’ issues, he explained, was

simply to extend the ‘horizon of opportunities’ for the individual researcher. And one method

of ‘extending the horizon’, he said, ‘is the interdisciplinary seminar, in which people whose

techniques are diverse, mobilize them in a combined attack upon some common problem’.

56 Hancock, Perspective in History, 12.

229 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

The ‘common problem’, he said, ‘may be industries (e.g. the wool industry) or regional (e.g.

Buganda) or sociological (e.g. urbanization)’. If the attack was ‘mounted at the post-doctoral

level’, then the ‘clear intention [was to] advance knowledge’.57 Hancock put this theory into

practice in a Wool Seminar which was held in Canberra between 1957 and 1959. The ‘wool

seminar’, he submitted, with its focus the ‘common problem’ of the wool industry, ‘reveal[ed]

the work done’ at this ‘higher level’.58 The seminar resulted in a book—The Simple Fleece—

of ‘40 closely related chapters’ most of which came from the thirty-six papers which had been

presented over the seminar’s two-and-a-half year duration. Hancock claimed that one

positive outcome for the ‘natural scientists’ and social scientists who participated in the

seminar, was that they ‘discovered ways and means of communicating with each other and

they learnt a good deal about each other’s methods of research’.59 He particularly wished to

prevent the seminar ‘becoming merely an aggregate of specialists’.60

But did the seminar advance knowledge? Did it justify its cost? How intellectually

valuable was the result of the very considerable time and effort put into it by the large number

of highly qualified and capable participants? Did learning about ‘each other’s methods of

research’ mean looking into the epistemological and ontological questions regarding the

nature of scientific knowledge versus the nature of social science and humanities knowledge?

If not, what was it that they learnt? None of the individual chapters in The Simple Fleece

indicate any evidence of intellectual synthesis, though this lack of synthesis could be

expected since the chapters comprise what were intended to be special studies for a planned

Volume II. Volume I was to provide an overview, which would illuminate the central theme

which had emerged, to link and enlarge the disciplinary studies. It was never written and thus

the collection of special studies became the complete book.

57 Ibid., 12. 58 Ibid., 12. 59 Ibid., 12. 60 From a paper circulated by Hancock during the planning phase: ‘First very rough proposals for seminar on Wool (from 1850 to the present day)’, Barnard MSS, 250, Box 1, Noel Butlin Archives Centre, Canberra, quoted in Geoffrey Bolton, “Rediscovering Australia: Hancock and the Wool Seminar” in Keith Hancock: The Legacies of an Historian, ed. D. A. Low (Carlton South: Melbourne University Press, 2001), 187.

230 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

After publication, The Simple Fleece quietly sank from view. Historical Studies and

the Journal of the Royal Australian Historical Society ignored its appearance, and the

Australian Journal of Politics and History gave a short notice of five lines. Geoffrey Bolton

noted that a ‘thoughtful review’ by an economic historian, J. W. McCarty, in Business

Archives and History ‘concentrated most on the chapters influenced by “the Butlin

revolution”’.61 However, John La Nauze had commented that ‘If Butlin [an economic

historian] were asked to write about religion in Australia he would produce a column of

figures headed “Churches–Capital Formation”’.62 Certainly, the book provided no cultural

perspectives.63 Another reviewer commended the book as a useful work of reference but

noted that a few sections of the book had already become out of date.64

The Wool Seminar demonstrated quite clearly that the production of synthesized

knowledge requires much more than simple faith in the efficacy of ‘the ‘healthy growth’ of

intellectual endeavour’ within an interdisciplinary environment. The integration and

synthesis of specialist effort into complex wholes requires more than debate amongst

specialists. Hancock had made it clear that he understood that without effective management

‘separate competing specialisms’ ran the risk of becoming just a ‘rabble of individualists’.

But he did not to know what that management required. He argued that it would be ‘almost

impossible’ for the disciplinary specialists to ‘see their problems in shallow perspective when

almost every day they were exchanging ideas with … competent philosophers’. But that was

just what did happen. The problem to be investigated by the multidisciplinary group was

never defined. Rather than identify what was a problem that transcended individual specialist

inquiry and required combined, advanced, research skills, Hancock merely identified an entry

point to a yet-to-be-defined problem. He confused ‘problem’ with signification. The wool

industry was so central to Australian life that it meant something to all Australians. Thus as a

61 Bolton, “Rediscovering Australia: Hancock and the Wool Seminar”, 192–3. 62 Ibid., 195, no reference given. 63 Libby Robin noted the book gave a ‘powerful, rounded portrait of the Australian wool industry in late-1950s Australia’, but observed that it gave ‘surprisingly few cultural insights into the ‘rediscovering Australia’’ process which Hancock sought. Libby Robin, “Woolly Identities”, in Keith Hancock: The Legacies of an Historian, 201. 64 Bolton, ‘Rediscovering Australia: Hancock and the Wool Seminar’, 193.

231 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

theme or signifier it had value, but in itself it was not a ‘problem’. Hancock himself thought

of it semiotically rather than problematically. In his paper framing the seminar, Hancock

identified as the unifying principle: what ‘wool can mean [italics added]’—and then listed the

sorts of things it might mean to economists, scientists, social historians. Thus, such things as

‘the labour force and its organization’ for the economists, ‘land utilization (including

technology)’ for the agricultural economists, geographers, and social historians, ‘ecological

change in general’ for ‘some brands of Natural scientist’.65 Inevitably the product, The

Simple Fleece, simply provided more information within a narrowly scientific and economic

instrumentalist frame. The history that was written was highly competent, but orthodox and

uni-disciplinary; it showed no evidence at all of any altered perspective. The one new

perspective that did result from the seminar was a greater sensitivity to ecology; however, this

occurred more indirectly than directly, more through good luck than good management.66

Sir Frederic Eggleston, talented amateur though he might have been, perceived more

acutely than Hancock that a research school within an institute of advanced study needed to

intensify knowledge, not simply extend information. Eggleston sensed that the intensification

of knowledge involved, among other things, research into the sociology of knowledge and the

identification of fundamental objects of study. He sensed that it was inextricably shaped by

theory—no less in the humanities and the social sciences than in the physical and medical

sciences—and that the need was for more holistic knowledge. But how research was to be

organized to accomplish this ‘whole of knowledge’ inquiry, Eggleston had no idea. Neither

did anyone within the academy. There were no academic models, either in Australia or

overseas, that could be used because research management remained concerned with the

individual and the individually crafted product. How specialist knowledge might be

65 Ibid., 185–6. 66 Hancock would disagree. In his Foreword to the book he states ‘Our discussions covered a range of themes: economists found themselves concerned with animal genetics and nutrition, ecologists and botanists with the historical processes involved in changing patterns of land utilization, and historians with the scientific and economic principles of pasture improvement.’ Hancock, The Simple Fleece, v. It is not obvious in the chapters. For example, A. W. Martin’s chapter: “Pastoralists in the Legislative Assembly of , 1870–1890”, is a standard political history written from a very orthodox perspective. The scientific chapters appear to be completely shaped by scientific questions, and their conclusions exactly directed to those questions.

232 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

aggregated so that a more intensified and complex whole could be achieved had not been

considered because it had not emerged as a requirement.

The requirement had emerged elsewhere. By the end of World War II, governments

everywhere had recognized the direct connection between research and development and

national security and thus, the need to for their effective integration.

Within the military-industrial ‘complex’ that had emerged after World War II,

particularly in America, there was recognized the need to combine effectively the research

and development efforts of the many thousands of government, university, and industry

scientists and engineers into major defense and aerospace projects.67 The intensification of

the during the 1950s, and the successful launch and orbiting of the first Soviet

Sputnik in 1957, provided a further strengthening of that requirement. The space program,

the intercontinental ballistic missile program, the strategic air defence program, and the

Polaris submarine program that followed, all required basic research, applied research,

development, and production to be managed as an integrated whole if those wholly new and

highly complex systems were to perform as intended. By the early 1970s conceptual

frameworks and control and analysis processes had been defined which enabled the

successful acquisition of conceptually unique land, sea, air, and space systems from combined

but disparate research, development, and production groups. Using these frameworks and

processes, the US Department of Defense (US DoD) and the US National Aeronautics and

Space Administration (NASA) were able to combine specialist research with innovative,

multi-disciplinary, engineering development to produce complex, integrated, systems. The

frameworks and processes themselves required new conceptual thinking. Traditional

management approaches were inadequate. A key feature of the framework was that it

maintained a ‘pluralist’ system of institutions and organizations (universities, companies and

government agencies) and enabled productive interaction between ‘frontier’ research and

mission-directed development.68

67 As had been demonstrated in the Manhattan Project. Research and national security were now considered inseparable. 68 See for example, Karl Kreilkamp, “Towards a Theory of Science Policy”, Science Studies, 3,

233 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

Today, the pan-disciplinary solutions that are now being sought by governments and

research authorities in response to new national and global problems, from bio-ethics to

global warming, for example, require the same type of conceptual management that is needed

to acquire solutions for such problems as landing men on Mars, or providing defence in space

against intercontinental ballistic missiles. Significantly, that management does not seek to

manage pure basic research, it seeks only to manage the experimental development of the

engineered systems. The clear differences between undirected research and mission-directed

development are institutionalized in those management processes. It was from the early

military-industrial experience that the different research and development categories were

drawn and formalized in the Frascati Manual.

Integrating Specialist Knowledge

Malcolm Gillies, at the time the president of the Council for the Humanities, Arts and the

Social Sciences (CHASS), noted recently that ‘the world’s problems have scant respect for

disciplines or knowledge sectors’, but observed the inconvenient fact that ‘most people feel

secure within the narrow confines and well-trodden paths of their own upbringing … the

disciplines remain powerful units of organization’. Gillies was introducing a CHASS

occasional paper on the issue of pan-disciplinary collaboration, and went on to say that:

‘Similarly, the broad sectors of knowledge—science, technology, engineering and medicine

(STEM) and the humanities, arts and social sciences (HASS)—provide time-honoured yet

segregated playgrounds for discovery and interpretation’. This situation, he argued, was

unsatisfactory. The Government was also keen to facilitate greater involvement of the

creative industries in STEM research programs.69 Consequently, in December 2005 CHASS

had been commissioned by the Government to examine and report on the relationship

no. 1 (Jan., 1973): 6–7. For limitations, see Karl Kreilkamp, “Hindsight and the Real World of Science Policy”, Science Studies, 1, no. 1 (Jan., 1971): 65–66. 69 For example, PMSEIC (Prime Minister’s Science, Engineering and Innovation Council) Working Group, Imagine Australia: The Role of Creativity in the Innovative Economy (Canberra: PMSEIC, 2005).

234 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

between these sectors. Gillies stated the research focus:

These sectors uphold different economies and promote different methodologies. Our biggest challenge is to find ways in which these sectors can collaborate better and turn their differences of perspective into pan- disciplinary strengths.70

The completed CHASS report called for ‘a ‘whole of knowledge’ approach, embracing both

the humanities, arts and social sciences disciplines and those of science, technology,

engineering and medicine, to address the ‘whole of Government’ research priorities’.71

The report identified what it judged to be the characteristics of successful ‘cross-

sectoral collaborations’ and also examined the reasons why some collaborations fail.

However, the characteristics and reasons that it identified described the environment in which

collaboration should occur. It said nothing about the processes and frameworks by which that

collaboration could be managed. It identified management success factors, but not

management processes. A positive environment is a necessary condition for a collaborative

project to succeed, but it is not a sufficient condition. Effective management of both the

overall collaborative program, as well as the individual collaborative projects themselves, is

required. This was the aspect that NASA and US Defense recognized was conceptually

complex. Yet on this the CHASS paper was silent. It said nothing about how integrated

disciplinary knowledge was to be managed. It did not identify different research and

development categories, nor did it consider how research output can be synthesized into a

product that could be used by Government to solve or ameliorate practical problems. Yet a

research product requires translation if it is to be useful to non-research ends. Research that

cannot be implemented is useless to government: it has no value. Research needs to be

converted through some form of development process before it can used by non-specialists in

actual social, political, and economic environments. Conversely, experience in the defence

and aerospace industries showed that the stimulus for the most interesting basic research is

70 Jenni Metcalfe, et. al., CHASS Occasional Papers; Collaborating Across the Sectors: The Relationships between the Humanities, Arts and Social Sciences (HASS) and Science, Technology, Engineering and Medicine (STEM) Sectors, November 2006 (Canberra: Council for Humanities, Arts and Social Sciences (CHASS), 2006), 3. 71 Ibid., 7.

235 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

the problems associated with the practical application of complex solutions. The relationship

between research and its application is symbiotic.

II

NASA and US Defense had recognized quickly, through failure, that there were two quite

distinct aspects to the successful management of complex acquisitions. The first was the need

for an acquisition management process that enabled effective management decisions to be

made at the program level. The second was the need for a technical problem-solving and

control process—a systems engineering process—that enabled customer requirements to be

translated into desired functionality and that functionality reflected in a system design that

could be broken down into specialist design elements. Research was only incorporated into

the process as a sub-element of the development of new subsystem elements by subsystem

specialists or as commissioned applied research linked to particular program problems. The

agencies had found that mission-directed research was the most cost-effective way to support

basic research even though the lead times were long, but they did not seek to control

research.72

The central feature of the program management process was the definition of the

logical phases of any development program whose purpose was to acquire effective solutions

to new problems. The phases were designated as: ‘concept exploration’,

‘demonstration/validation’, ‘full-scale development’, ‘production’, and ‘operation’. By

separating the program into distinct phases (the conceptual derivation of a solution, the

engineering development of that solution, and the production of the developed prototype),

each phase could be managed separately as distinct projects should the complexity and size of

the program require it. Thus, for example, concept exploration could be undertaken as a

separate project. If considered desirable, several conceptual studies by different groups could

72 During 1967–9, the US DoD undertook a retrospective review (‘Project Hindsight’) of the effectiveness of research funding to the acquisition of weapons systems. The review found that it took approximately nine years for ‘directed basic research’ (sic) to emerge in key weapons systems, and approximately twenty years for ‘undirected basic research’ (sic) to emerge. Office of the Director of Defense Research and Engineering, Project Hindsight: Final Report (Washington: US DoD, 1969), iii– iv.

236 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

be commissioned so that alternative solutions could be explored. Then, say, two of the most

promising concepts might be selected for detailed analysis and validation; then the best one or

two could be selected for full-scale development at the end of which a working prototype—

which could be anything from a new electronic product to a space shuttle or more—would

have been produced and could be evaluated in a full operational environment. If the

operational testing was satisfactory, then approval could be granted for full production of the

required number of operational units. In the case of aircraft or electronic systems, hundreds,

or even thousands, might be produced; in the case of systems like the space shuttle, just a

few. Contractors such as Lockheed Martin or Boeing, for example, would participate in some

or all of the phases of a program.

Since the acquisition management methodology was based on the logic of the

development process rather than specific programs, the life cycle was applicable to an

acquisition of any size. All development acquisitions were managed with this model

regardless of whether the product was the modest electronic system such as a new radar, or a

‘star wars’ air defence system of which the space shuttle might be part.73 Further, it could be

‘scaled’. The principles were applied in exactly the same way to the sub-contractor project

initiated to develop a new subsystem—say, the graphic display for the radar, or the thrusters

for the shuttle—as they were to the overall program to acquire the complete system. An

analogy could be drawn with whole-of-knowledge programs and the government agencies,

universities, research centres and institutes. The location of the customer and the nature of

the question would determine which organization and at what level program management

responsibility would be assumed.

The central feature of the systems engineering management process was that of an

iterative system-design process that ensured that customer needs were matched to system

requirements, requirements were matched to functionality, and functionality was matched to a

physical element in the system design; then that the final system was validated against the

73 They still are. The life-cycle was revised in 2000 to allow greater flexibility for systems that might already exist but which require new or further development.

237 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

agreed system requirements. As the system requirements were a description of the

customer’s needs, the validation demonstrated satisfaction of the intent of the contract, not

simply the delivery of an operating system.

To ensure as far as possible that the logic that converted system requirements to

detailed design requirements was sound, the iterative system-design process consisted of two

iterative conceptual ‘loops’: a requirements to functions loop, and a functions to physical

loop. ‘Synthesis’ was the term used to describe the process by which system functionality

was allocated to the appropriate elements of the physical system. Existing subsystems would

be used to the maximum extent possible; however, since the development program was

initiated because there was no satisfactory existing system, some functionality could only be

allocated to yet-to-be-developed system elements.

The point was that customers did not want a physical system as such; they wanted the

functionality that the physical system provided. Defense customers typically required

systems that detected, classified, evaluated, and engaged particular types of phenomena in the

system’s operating environment. How those functions were achieved was up to the

developer. Usually it was with a land, sea, air or space vehicle equipped with sensors,

command and control computers, and weapons systems. Nevertheless, it was not always

obvious what the actual physical system might be that could best deliver that functionality.

The fact that the system mission was conceptually new was the reason that existing systems

were inadequate, thus new systems had to be acquired through a development process, not

simply through an ‘off-the-shelf’ purchasing process. Again, the analogy with whole-of-

knowledge programs is that ‘customers’—whether governments, agencies or organizations—

do not want research as theory, they want research translated into practice: but what that

practice might be they are unable to determine, as acquiring an answer to that question was

the reason they sought specialist assistance.

The defence and aerospace community found, nevertheless, that systems acquisition

concepts by themselves were not enough. Within the broad program and project conceptual

238 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

framework there was interweaved an extensive management system for classifying and

authorizing. The way work was to be defined, the way requirements were to be classified,

and the way authority, responsibility, and accountability were to be defined and delegated

was carefully specified and closely controlled. The aim was not to mandate how program and

project participants were to do their work, but to establish standards, definitions and criteria

by which that work should be described and reported so that unambiguous communication

amongst disparate, separated, groups could be maintained and management control exercised.

The system for classifying work was through standardized ‘work breakdown structures’,

which ensured that work and systems were ‘decomposed’ into generic elements that were

independent of the organization undertaking the work. This enabled work to be compared

across organizations, across programs, and across time. Without this standardization, neither

synchronic nor diachronic comparison of organizations nor programs was possible.

Regardless of whether it was, say, a ship system or a space system, at the first level of

decomposition the program components would be the same. At the next level, differences

would emerge in the decomposition of those elements, but the elements would be standard for

that type of system.74 When combined with an ‘organization breakdown structure’, a

‘responsibility assignment matrix’ (RAM) could be produced for the program whereby work

scope, budget and responsibility could be assigned to specialist work teams; thus management

control could be achieved.

Authority was separated into two broad groups, then sub-groups within each. Again,

the point was that these were conceptual groupings: thus they were just as applicable to the

small local project as they were to the large international program. The groupings

represented ‘constituencies’ of same-interest groups. Different ‘constituencies’ would have

different priorities and measures of success. The primary interest of the ‘customer’

74 ‘Level 1’ specified the system; there were seven types, thus: Aircraft System, Space System, Missile System, Ship System, Surface Vehicle, Ordnance System, Electronics System. ‘Level 2’ was the actual system, thus Air Vehicle, Ship, Launch Vehicle, etc., along with nine other categories such as Training, Systems Test and Evaluation, System/Project Management, Support Equipment, Industrial Facilities. Level 3 contained system specific elements; for example, under ‘Air Vehicle’ from Level 2, would be the elements ‘Airframe’, ‘Propulsion Unit’, ‘Communications’, etc. Level 4 could be defined by the individual developers.

239 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

constituency was the acquisition of the most cost-effective solution to an identified need. For

customers such as NASA or US Defense, this need inevitably arose through the identification

of a ‘capability gap’: in other words, recognition that additional capability was required in

order for the group to fulfill its operational responsibilities. For the commercial customer, the

need would arise either through the identification of extra capability required to enable the

company to survive, or for extra capability to enable it to reach new performance standards.

Whatever the detail, the principle was that the acquisition would deliver clear ‘business

benefits’. The primary interest of the ‘contractor’ constituency was to ensure that an

unambiguously defined, agreed and measurable bundle of products and services that were

within the contractor group’s competence to deliver was delivered to an agreed price and

schedule, and that the contractor had the necessary authority to determine the best way to

achieve that outcome.

Each constituency had a number of sub-groups within it corresponding to expertise and

type of authority. For example, within the customer constituency the ‘sponsor’ had quite

different authority and accountability than that of the ‘project authority’. So, for the CHASS

project—production of a report on how to achieve ‘whole of knowledge’ research—the

customer was the Department of Education, Science and Training (DEST), the sponsor was

the DEST division that funded the study and to whom the report would be delivered, and the

project authority was the office charged with ensuring on behalf of the customer that the task

was properly defined, contracted and delivered. CHASS, as the representative of the

contractor group would be the ‘prime contractor’ and would be accountable for delivering the

final report—even though the report itself might have been produced by a number of sub-

contractors who were the subject-matter-experts: the specialist researchers. Importantly,

though, the only entity with the authority to warrant that the completed document was capable

of satisfying the contractual requirements was the ‘prime contractor’. Conversely, the only

entity that had the authority to warrant that the content of a particular subject element did

what it was required to do, was the subject matter expert: the specialist researcher. The non-

specialist customer, because they were not the specialist, could not. What they could say was

240 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

that the response did not satisfy their requirements; but that might have been because the

requirement was inaccurate, not because the response was inadequate. Thus rectification of

the problem in this instance would lie initially with the customer and the prime contractor, not

with the specialist researcher.

For NASA and US Defense, this meant that authority was of three types: management

authority, system design authority, and subsystem design authority. Each was distinct and

independent; they could neither be combined nor eliminated, as each had quite different

domains of expertise, responsibility, and accountability. For management authority it was to

ensure that the optimum ‘trade-off’ decisions between cost, schedule, and system cost-

effectiveness had been made; for system design authority, to ensure that the optimum system

configuration and assignment of functional, performance, and interface requirements to sub-

systems had been made; and for subsystem design authority, to ensure that the optimum, most

innovative, design had been developed to satisfy those assigned requirements.

There was accordingly a new understanding that in order to develop complex systems

there was required conceptually an additional layer of analysis, and hence an additional layer

of design and design authority. This meant that a new layer of specialist expertise was

required: that of the systems engineer whose role was to determine the relationships and

information flows between semi-autonomous elements so that a desired system capability was

achieved. This new understanding precipitated new approaches to project organization. The

prime contractor was no longer automatically assumed to be the shipbuilder, or aircraft

manufacturer, or equipment manufacturer. Rather, it now was the organization most capable

technically of defining the system and subsystem requirements, most capable managerially of

coordinating and integrating specialist effort, and most capable financially of guaranteeing

system performance. Research supplemented resolution of design problems but otherwise

remained outside direct program management control.

III

Whole-of-knowledge inquiry involves as many layers of differing interests, authority and

241 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

expertise as the advanced technology development projects. The chain that links basic

research to delivered value is the same.

The implications for whole-of-knowledge inquiry of these new conceptual

understandings are fundamental. A whole-of-knowledge ‘customer’ product is analogous to a

system. It is a particular arrangement of parts that results in synergy not possible simply from

the parts as a collection. The parts of the whole-of-knowledge product—its subsystems—are

HASS and STEM bodies of knowledge. These bodies of knowledge and understandings are

integrated in a such a way as to provide a way of acting, relating, conceptualizing or being—a

‘business’ benefit—that cannot be realized by any of the separate bodies of knowledge

whether scientific, technological, medical, artistic, humanist, psychological, cultural or

critical. Solutions to global problems of water shortage in the twenty-first century, for

example, will not be found through science or technology alone. Just as complex

technological systems exhibit capabilities that are greater than the sum of the capabilities of

their parts, so too do integrated bodies of knowledge products. It is from the relationship

between the subsets not from the subsets themselves that the system capabilities are created.

For the whole-of-knowledge product, ‘system capabilities’ are social processes, facilities and

understandings that transcend single-discipline solutions or interpretations. And as with the

technological system where requirements or attributes that define a ‘whole’ system have no

meaning for the parts, so with the ‘whole of knowledge’ product. The larger problem or need

identified by the ‘customer’ has no direct meaning for the disciplinary components. Each

problem has to have its ‘solution’ requirements defined, those requirements analyzed, and the

epistemological ‘functionality’ implied by them identified.

In the whole-of-knowledge case, the customer requirement needs to be ‘decomposed’

into more detailed inquiry questions and those questions mapped to ‘work’ elements in an

epistemological and ontological work breakdown structure. The ‘functionality’ implied by

the questions would then translate into something such as the knowledge modes in Table 1.

Just as ‘detection’, ‘classification’, and ‘engagement’ are typical technological system

functions, so ‘intuition’, ‘explanation’, and ‘interpretation’ are typical knowledge system

242 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

functions. For the whole-of-knowledge product, the physical system will be the knowledge

transfer mechanisms (media, processes, institutions) appropriate to the customer constituency.

Just as the decomposed physical system in an advanced technology system is a hierarchy of

possibly thousands of hardware and software items, so the decomposed whole-of-knowledge

system will be a hierarchy of possibly thousands of disciplinary developed products. In

complex physical systems, software modules are often distributed and shared throughout the

system. Similarly, in whole-of-knowledge systems, the blurring of genres will mean that

disciplinary products will often be common to a number of areas of specialist inquiry. The

mapping profiles arising from the knowledge tetrahedron would clarify where these

commonalities and complementarities arise.

With technological systems, architectural decisions—arrangements of parts in relation

to functional flow—made at the system level determine the task that the individual subsystem

must perform and the way that it must relate to the other parts.75 This will require either the

adjustment of an existing subsystem to satisfy the new interface requirements, or the research

and development by the subsystem specialist of a compatible new subsystem. Just as a radar

system can be optimized to fit into a particular combat system through manipulation of

existing performance parameters such as power, range, frequency, data rate and physical size,

so knowledge domain specialists can optimize existing knowledge domain elements to match

higher level requirements for variations within particular knowledge categories. The

variations required will depend on the larger question being asked, or from a number of

questions arising from the larger problem being investigated; in other words, derived

questions. A radar optimized for one particular platform and mission, might have to be re-

designed for a different application.

Of particular significance is the fact that, as with technological systems, the questions

might not require new research in order to be answered. New research is only undertaken in

systems development if the existing sub-system cannot be ‘optimized’ to meet the new

75 For whole-of-knowledge ‘system’, the knowledge tetrahedron allows mapping of information flow.

243 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

functional, performance, and interface requirements. The same applies to the whole-of-

knowledge product. New research is only required if the current specialist knowledge is

insufficient to answer the questions allocated to it. In most instances, the task is one of

applying existing specialist knowledge to the new question asked—just as most questions

from the ‘floor’ at a conference can be answered with existing knowledge. Only if they

cannot is new research required. Consequently it is possible that a completely new and

valuable whole-of-knowledge product can be delivered, as with technological systems,

without new research being required. But, as with technological systems, that would be

unusual. By the very nature of them being on completion the most advanced systems

available, somewhere within those systems would be elements that required new research for

their creation.

The notion of layered authority on which the management of these programs is built

means that accountability, authority and expertise are locked together. Responsibility is

matched to expertise, and those given responsibility are also given sufficient authority to

enable them to exercise expert judgement. In technology development projects, a subsystem

designer will be (can only be) accountable for satisfying the requirements that have been

‘accepted’ by them as domain expert. But as domain expert they are the only one with the

authority to warrant the subsystem design—it is the qualification program that will determine

whether that judgement was sound. The accountability for the ‘whole’ system, however, can

only be borne by the system design authority who allocated design requirements to the

subsystem elements. The actual analysis and decisions regarding the allocation of

requirements will be the result of a team effort between the system designers and the

subsystem specialists, but once agreed, accountability and thus authority for warranting the

soundness of the analysis and allocation decisions rests with the system design authority.

Applying this concept to whole-of-knowledge programs means that there is no conflict

between ‘academic self-determination and radical creativity’—academic freedom—and the

management of institutional performance.76 Not only is basic research (the ‘radical-creative

76 The phrase is Simon Marginson’s (Simon Marginson, “Academic Creativity Under New

244 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

imagination’ at work) outside the experimental development category where management is

exercised but, even when it is required, the authority for its efficacy and relevance remains

with the specialist researcher. The funding of basic research remains a strategic decision of

the particular specialist organization and related to its aspirations toward research quality.

Performance management remains in the experimental-development–delivered-product

region of the continuum. Lockheed Martin which undertakes a wide range of government-

funded program conceptual studies and systems developments had self-funded R&D

expenditure for 2006 of US$ 1,139 million; Boeing’s was US$ 3,200 million.77 For a for-

profit company there is no conflict with the notion of pure research and management control

since it is conducted within a business model that ensures that curiosity-driven research—

research for its own sake—ultimately, ‘pays its way’ through enabling innovative product

development, or even, occasionally, the identification of completely ‘new’ business. For-

profit companies also buy basic research. In 2005, thirty-six percent of Nokia employees

were employed in R&D. Currently, that figure is thirty-one percent, but now the company

has joint research facilities with Massachusetts Institute of Technology and with Stanford

University.78

These notions of layered authority, and the notion of multiple constituencies, do have

major ramifications for the identification and organization of specialist knowledge. Just as

the defense and aerospace systems development programs identified the need for a new level

of engineering and management expertise, so for whole-of-knowledge programs a new level

of analysis is needed and thus a new type of expertise is required. The new and distinct

intellectual task to be performed is the analysis of the higher-level question, its breakdown

Public Management: Foundations for an Investigation”, Educational Theory, 58, no. 3 (2008): 269). See also, Simon Marginson, “Steering from a distance: Power Relations in Australian Higher Education”, Higher Education, 34, no. 1 (July, 1997): 63–80; Carole Kayrooz, “The Role of Autonomy in Social Science Research: The View from UK and Australian Universities”, http://portal.unesco.org/education/en/files/51655/11634338925Kayrooz-EN.pdf/Kayrooz-EN.pdf, [10/12/08]; Simon Marginson and Mark Considine, The Enterprise University: Power Governance and Reinvention in Australia (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 133–174. 77 Lockheed Martin Corporation 2006 Annual Report, 17; Boeing; Charting the Course: 2006 The Boeing Company Annual Report, 22. 78 21,453 employees out of a total of 68,483 employees. US SEC Form 20–F 2006 Nokia, Year ended 31 Dec. 2006, 76, 38.

245 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

into lower-level ‘derived’ questions, the mapping of these to the appropriate ‘functional’

categories, then the allocation of that functionality, and lower-level functionality, to the

relevant disciplinary sub-elements. That responsibility is held at system level (program level)

but the complexity of the task will almost certainly mean that the analysis would have to

undertaken by a multi-disciplinary team: nevertheless, the end result would be ‘warranted’ by

the new (higher-level) specialist authority.

Management by the academy of the research process in the academy—if it is to be

effective—must be based on the assumption that the academy as a group-unit represents a

research capability greater than the sum of its parts. The institution has a creative, synthetic,

role. The individual researcher might be capable of developing valuable, ‘finished’, social

products from his or her own basic research, just as the individual NASA engineer might be

capable of bringing a wholly original product to market. But NASA’s purpose and value is

not the provision of a stimulating work environment for talented individuals. NASA (or

Nokia and others) is more than the individual talent of its employees. Management and

technical processes in those organizations ensure that a synthesis of effort occurs such that

institutional output is greater than the sum of the (talented) individual parts. Similarly in the

research university in the twenty-first century, the research output of the university should be

more than the sum of individual academic research output.

IV

The notion that specialist inquiry is inevitably embedded within some larger frame is self

evident and well understood. The CHASS paper quotes remarks made by a representative of

a government science organization, the CSIRO:

In reality, most of our ‘science’ questions do, to various degrees, need to be considered in the broader context … it makes a lot of sense first up to use interdisciplinary measures to frame the research questions or broader research agendas.79

Although that statement might seem to be recognizing the need to integrate science questions

79 Metcalfe, et. al., CHASS Occasional Papers, 28.

246 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

into a holistic knowledge frame, the vision behind it is more limited. The intent is more the

effective enunciation of the science question, than the effective identification and framing of a

‘whole of knowledge’ question where science’s involvement, its lower-level derived question,

is yet to be defined. In regard to the derivation of a science question, the CSIRO itself, as a

government-funded research organization, needs to develop a ‘solutions’ acquisition process

model that accommodates a more comprehensive notion of interest groups and authority.

Government-funded research programs have very long ‘stakeholder’ chains. Many different

interest groups are involved. Each has a different notion of what ‘successful’ means, and thus

each has different views on how success should be measured. The question being researched

by the specialist will almost certainly be quite a different question from that asked by

Government.

Similarly, a more comprehensive management understanding is required at the project

level. The CHASS paper notes that ‘many of the cross-sectoral collaborations reported

benefit from using end users in the projects to ensure greater ownership of the final outcome,

service or product’.80 But the authors give no indication that they understand the complexity

of the management process required to ensure that positive outcome for all projects or

programs. Positive outcomes are quite easily achieved with small, motivated, relatively

homogeneous groups working closely together, but much more difficult with large multi-

sectoral groups and authorities that may be widely dispersed geographically and culturally.

As whole-of-knowledge programs could involve several governments, many institutions, and

very many disciplinary groups and sub-groups, or may involve only one institution such as a

university, a refined approach to the identification and delegation of authority and

responsibility is needed for their effective management. The participants are so numerous,

and their expertise and interests so different, that the integration of that effort is impossible

without refined management processes and structures. And as with technology development,

a ‘scalable’ system acquisition life-cycle needs to be defined for whole-of-knowledge

programs so that structured program milestone decisions can be facilitated and appropriate

80 Ibid., 28.

247 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

system acquisition strategies selected for programs of any size. None of these three

requirements—a new level of analysis, new authority structures, and new development

models—would be difficult, in principle, to satisfy. All that is required is the modification of

existing industry models and definitions. However, the modification of some aspects of those

models would not be simple.

With knowledge programs, the work of modification of the system analysis process

requires an extra level of conceptual subtlety to that required by technology programs. The

definition and agreement of categories for the classification of different types and forms of

knowledge—consequently, how questions are to be classified and thus how ‘functionality’ is

to be comprehended, defined, and decomposed—is complex and difficult. Similarly, the

definition and agreement of a model or principles by which information or knowledge flows

between knowledge elements can be determined, is complex and difficult.81 With knowledge

programs the ‘work’ elements to be defined are phenomenological and ontological in nature.

As many of these programs will have components where research at the limits of knowledge

itself is required, the establishment of conceptually complex and refined elements is an

essential prerequisite for their execution. In the programs we are concerned with—pan-

disciplinary programs that work at the edge of current understanding—events in nature,

events in culture or society, and events in consciousness need to be accommodated.

For categories and hierarchies of knowledge and functionality to be agreed, some form

of agreement would need to be reached on the handling of entrenched conceptual dichotomies

such as causality and intentionality, or structure and agency, or even on how the very

concepts of agency, rationality, knowledge, mind, truth, should be considered. At what level

should those concepts be placed in any ontological or epistemological hierarchy? By

definition, whole-of-knowledge inquiry can assume no foundational epistemic perspective.82

81 Although a model has been proposed in this thesis (Chapter 4, Section 3), that is a preliminary conceptual ‘sketch’ produced in isolation to assist the presentation of an argument. The development of an agreed working model would be a pan-disciplinary project in itself—and requiring detailed collaborative specialist work by a range of large and small academic teams to establish standards for integrated inquiry. 82 Thus the selection of the ‘tetrahedron’ of Chapter 4. There is no HASS/STEM divide.

248 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

Scientific realism can be no more privileged than social realism; structural determinism no

more privileged than autonomous self-fashioning. At some level the very basic categories

concerned with modes-of-being must be defined and agreed. Whether that level should be

‘high’ or ‘low’ is itself not obvious since its selection might seem to privilege one form of

realism—scientific or social—over the other. Many category schemes exist; Aristotle,

Descartes, Husserl, Whitehead, Hartmann and Quine are just some who have attempted to

define basic categories. David Woodruff-Smith, for example, equates basic categories with

modes-of-being and defines them as such things as dependence, intentionality, unity, and

process.83 David Woodruff-Smith is a philosopher. Specialists with different interests would

be likely to have different preferences. What might finally be agreed collectively is to be

determined. However, the identification and classification of agreed categories and structures

is a particularly challenging task. But it must be done if integrated inquiry is to be possible.

For organizations such as NASA and US Defense, conceptual arguments are securely

contained within the boundary of scientific realism. Epistemological doubt is outside that

boundary. Standard templates have long been developed and agreed. But for the academic

research communities, conceptual arguments are unbounded. Epistemological doubt and

ontological doubt are fundamental. No templates exist. Unfortunately, effective management

of whole-of-knowledge inquiry cannot be achieved without them. The search, though, is not

for the absolute ‘truth’ about a single reality, but for a means of assisting unambiguous

communication about perceptions of and within both scientific and social reality.

V

It might be felt that the comparison of the development of whole-of-knowledge systems with

the development of technological systems has been taken too far. However, the similarities

are striking. With the development of technological systems, those involved have learnt

through bitter experience that without a clear understanding of ‘work’ categories, authority

83 David Woodruff Smith, Mind World: Essays in Phenomenology and Ontology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 243. See also, for example, David J. Chalmers, “Ontological Anti- Realism”, http://consc.net/papers/ontology.pdf, [10/12/08]

249 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

boundaries, and structured project and program processes, no complex acquisition can

succeed. How then could the development of self-reflexive and very much more conceptually

complex whole-of-knowledge products be successful when none of these fundamental

management elements are defined? The most obvious answer is that they cannot. And many

projects of this type would be of much higher complexity than those which the CHASS paper

used as examples.84

Research cannot be utilized in any managed sense without program-level management

models and processes. Without them, basic research becomes supplanted by applied research

and development activity. With them, it is the translation to usable products that is managed,

not basic research. The product to be delivered in any program funded by Government will

always, if it is to be acceptable to Government, be directly related to some form of social

action. In most instances, particularly where extensive change is involved, both physical and

psychical change will be involved. For example, in all of the four current Australian national

research priorities the social and the scientific are inextricably joined—the physical, the

psychological, and the cultural are intertwined.85 Investigation into these priority areas

involves not only causal relations in nature, intentional relations in consciousness, social

relations in culture, but also the nature of their interconnection—the information flows—and

the effects on each of this interaction. Thus a management process applied to them that does

not contain a schema that allows the effective separation of research categories, or the

effective integration of scientific realism and social realism, will be ineffective. A process is

needed that allows researchers and developers to deal with those categories and epistemic

structures separately, and combined, and both statically and dynamically—a process, in other

words, that makes the integration and interaction of Naturwissenschaften with

Geisteswissenschaften, and research with development, possible.

84 See Metcalfe, et. al., CHASS Occasional Papers, 100–109. Twelve case studies were described but no distinction was drawn between research categories. Most case studies were mixes of applied research, development and innovation. None were pure basic research. 85 The research priorities are: an environmentally sustainable Australia; promoting and maintaining good health; frontier technologies for building and sustaining Australian industries; and safeguarding Australia. Quoted in CHASS Occasional Papers, 15.

250 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

It is clear that a much more detailed model of the whole-of-knowledge acquisition life-

cycle needs to be developed, promulgated and used. Between the extremes of pure basic

research at one end of the life-cycle to the delivery of a useable product at the other, and

between the ends of the spectrum of possible contributors and roles, there are unlimited

options and combinations. Management of these programs is not possible without adaptable,

scalable, management, nor without ‘inquiry’ templates.

There is a need at the disciplinary level also. By applying the concepts and logic of

technological research and development and systems acquisition process to integrated inquiry

programs, the classification of research in the humanities and social sciences disciplines

becomes more refined. There is as much a distinction between research and development in

that sector as in the science and technology sector. For their effective management, the

distinction between pure basic research, strategic basic research, applied research, and

experimental development is no less important in the humanities and social sciences than in

science and technology.

If a program in either sector does not lead at some point or in some component to

research at a fundamental level, then what is being performed is not research activity in the

sense of discovery, but the organization and application of existing knowledge in new ways—

which, in Frascati Manual terminology, is ‘experimental development’. The radar

manufacturer only commissions new research to be undertaken if the existing system cannot

be adapted to new tasks through manipulation of existing technology and performance

parameters. The radar manufacturer will, however, independent of any contracts it may have,

fund its own research and development program in order to ensure that it has products that

are, for selected parameters, leaders in their competitive fields. If not, it will not win

contracts to participate in larger development programs, nor will it survive as a company in

the longer term. The range and depth of its R&D program are strategic business decisions.

With any external development-program sub-contract it may hold, the extent of program-

required research effort it might expend will be a contractual decision and program funded.

In a like manner, the humanities or social science ‘centre’ should only commission new

251 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

research if the question allocated to it cannot be answered from existing specialist

knowledge. Applying knowledge is not basic research. But again, it is unlikely that basic

research in some part of the whole-of-knowledge program sub-elements would not be

required. Also, quite independent of that particular program, the humanities or social science

centre (and associated departments) will, like the radar manufacturer, undertake ‘corporately’

a full-spectrum research program to ensure that its specialist knowledge is pre-eminent in

those disciplinary areas and disciplinary sub-specialties that it considers its areas of strength.

Universities, Research, and History

If the argument presented above were to be accepted, there would be a number of

consequences for universities, research and individual disciplines. In particular, there would

be ramifications in three aspects: first, the role of universities in whole-of-knowledge

programs; second, the relation of basic research to that role; and third, the relation of bodies

of knowledge to basic research. For the single discipline, the question that arises is: what is

the discipline’s distinctive basic research function? If it does not have a true basic research

role what other distinctive research or development role might it have?

Although there are a number of research categories in the R&D administrative schema,

it is pure basic research and strategic basic research that is the university’s key competitive

strength. Thus the primary question for the individual discipline remains: what is its

distinctive function in basic research. And, if is accepted that academic basic research is

central to whole-of-knowledge programs and that these programs will be the broad shape of

programs in the future, then the question to be answered ultimately for the individual

discipline is what role can it play in the university’s twenty-first-century basic research

programs?

I

If the foundation of basic research activity is discovery, then discovery in academic

252 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

research—that is, intellectual inquiry—means epistemological and ontological discovery.

Scientific discovery supports that ‘mission’, as does discovery in the humanities, arts and

social science. There can be no epistemic dualisms. Neither the interpretive nor the empirical

can be privileged. Cultural frameworks and scientific frameworks are inextricably entwined:

each presupposes the other. Whole-of-knowledge discovery implies discovery at the

boundaries of human understanding. It is not just the comprehension of general relations of

the particular—truth and knowledge claims about observable phenomena—but also how to

contextualize experience to make it intelligible (and bearable). Inquiry at this basic research

level involves both abstract thought and embodied experience. Abstract thought and

embodied experience must ultimately be integrated if research results are to have both validity

and meaning; but that integration can only be achieved through team and program design, and

thus at a level above the specialist. That whole-of-knowledge ‘system design’ function is a

pan-disciplinary university function. Management of team design within basic research, and

management of the research spectrum interconnections, is the university’s primary twenty-

first century research responsibility.

Fortuitously, that function coincides with the university’s unique capability and that

capability is the university’s key competitive strength in the research market. The university

provides the only true unbounded research environment; and that environment, in turn, is the

most attractive research environment for leading researchers. The modern university is the

organization best able to integrate physical and metaphysical research, and that ability should

assure the university of a distinctive future research role. The ‘whole of knowledge’ product

now being sought can only be produced by the integration of leading research in both HASS

and STEM specialist areas. It can only be produced by the integration of specialists in all

fields, and it can only be produced in an atmosphere of complete academic freedom—outside

the bounds of any cultural or epistemological restrictions on either questions or answers.

Very few organizations have that capability, nor do they have that freedom. Research

effort in for-profit organizations has to be more targeted towards products which are more

tangible and whose utility is available in the shorter term. Even many not-for-profit

253 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

organizations bear this restriction. The CSIRO, which has epitomized the notion of a pure

research institution, now directs, through its ‘flagship’ programs, a majority of its government

funding to research directly associated with the National Research Priorities. Only about one

quarter of CSIRO effort is devoted to research not related to the four National Research

Priorities.86 This government-directed research, being politically generated, will always be

concerned with social and economic ‘needs’ framed within ‘normal’ social boundaries, and

hence intellectually constrained. The CSIRO could, through well constructed ‘solutions’

acquisition processes, ensure that Government intellectual constraint does not penetrate down

to the basic research level, but it would still have has no Geisteswissenschaften capability; it

would still be incapable of true integrated inquiry.

One key strategic objective identified by the CSIRO in its recent Strategic Plan was to

‘stimulate breakthroughs by promoting cross-pollination, especially in frontier research’.87

The Strategic Plan identified five ‘emerging science’ themes that cut across traditional

boundaries and would be important for twenty-first century science. The themes were novel

biotechnologies, complex systems science, new information and communication

technologies, nanotechnology, and social and economic integration. It is self-evident that

each of those themes is connected inextricably with the social. For example, the Plan noted

that the central theme of complex systems science was

the exploration of systems whose behaviour cannot be understood or predicted from the characteristics of their component parts. Such systems are inherently nonlinear and are often characterised by ‘fractal scaling laws’ and may exhibit ‘self organisation’. Complex systems are being found and studied over a wide range of time and space scales from those of a single cell to the entire globe and involve processes ranging from mathematical or physical alone to the intersection of biology and socio-economics.88

It would seem, therefore, if the CSIRO is to achieve its objective of breakthroughs in

frontier research, it will need research partners that have capability in more than just the

86 CSIRO, Strategic Plan for 2003–2007: Delivery and Execution (Canberra: CSIRO, 2003), 32. 87 Ibid., 72. 88 Ibid., 72.

254 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

physical sciences. Classical reductive science is not enough. This is the reason

Geisteswissenschaft emerged; and later, postmodernist inquiry. In that vein, Deborah and

Mark Madsen noted that the new scientific interest in chaotic dynamics (which requires the

scientist to dispense with certainty or absolutism in favour of contextuality, and to think

holistically not reductively) marked the arrival of ‘postmodern science’.89 The flow,

however, is in both directions. Postmodernist thought can no more ignore advances in the

biological and neurophysiological sciences than science can ignore the insights postmodernist

thought has brought to inquiry.

If complex systems science involves the intersection of mathematics, physics, biology

and socio-economics, then complex systems science is indistinguishable from whole-of-

knowledge inquiry. Its pursuit involves all domains of knowledge and requires all modes of

inquiry. The CSIRO might have complex learning organisms as its research focus, but so do

the humanities, arts, and social sciences. Their inquiry, in fact, is more advanced in that

direction than the CSIRO’s. Habermas’s communicative action theory, Luhmann’s social

systems theory, and Latour’s actor-network theory,90 for example, are concerned specifically

with agency and self-organization in complex social systems, but have moved beyond the

simple functionalism of science. Researchers in the humanities and social sciences seek, like

scientists, to illuminate the connections between agents and their environments, and to

extrapolate, just as the scientist does. Both seek to provide a sounder basis for future action;

but through advances in both, possibilities for self-fashioning are created which affect what

that action might entail. In the twenty-first century, biotechnology and ecosystems are central

research themes and those themes subsume all knowledge domains. However, the social

imperative framing those themes is action and self-fashioning. ‘Intelligent’ pursuit of those

89 Deborah L. Madsen and Mark S. Madsen, “Fractals, Chaos and Dynamics: The Emergence of Postmodern Science”, in Postmodern Surroundings, ed. Steven Earnshaw (Amsterdam: Editions Rodopi, 1994), 129. 90 Latour is more the leading spokesperson. The theory evolved from work with Steven Woolgar,Michel Callon and others. See Bruno Latour, Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005). See also, Steven C. Ward, Reconfiguring Truth: Postmodernism, Science Studies, and the Search for a New Model of Knowledge (Laham: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996), 95–127.

255 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

ends demands a ‘critical ontology of ourselves’ for which expertise from every discipline is

needed.

On the theme of ‘novel biotechnologies’, the CSIRO stated in its Strategic Plan that

‘biotechnology research will deliver new insights into the molecular make-up of living

organisms, human populations and entire ecosystems’. But as was discussed in the previous

Chapter, biotechnology and genetic technology is not just new technology, as the CSIRO

infers. All technology changes the way society understands itself, but with genetic

engineering, technology is no longer ‘other’. As Jürgen Habermas noted, genetic technology

cannot avoid changing the self-understanding of the species. It uproots the categorical

distinction between ‘the naturally grown’ and the ‘made’, which, up to now, represented a

fundamental distinction.91 The differentiation between what is ‘manufactured’ and what has

‘come to be by nature’ alters familiar modes of action.92 As Hans Jonas has argued,

previously the engineer or technologist was dealing with ‘dead matter’, the activity was

‘building’, but in dealing with organisms,

activity is confronted with the auto-activity of active material, the biological system in its natural functioning into which a new determinant has to be incorporated … The mode of the technological act is intervention, not building.93

Thus, as Jonas concludes, ‘to ‘produce’ here means to commit something to the stream of

evolution in which the producer himself is carried along’.94 ‘Technologically mastered

nature now again includes man who (up to now) had, in technology, set himself against it as

its master.’95 The nature of human action has changed.96

91 Jürgen Habermas, The Future of Human Nature (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003), 42 92 Ibid., 46. 93 H. Jonas, Technik, Medizin und Eugenik. Zur Praxis des Prinzips Verantwortung (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1985), 165, quoted in Jürgen Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, 47. 94 Jonas, Technik, Medizin und Eugenik, 168 95 Jonas, Technik, Medizin und Eugenik, quoted in Jürgen Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, 47, no page reference given. 96 See also Chapter 1 [The Altered Nature of Human Action] in Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1984).

256 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

Novel biotechnologies such as ‘assisted reproductive technologies’—treatment for the

medical condition of infertility—are already pervasive. And as Robyn Ferrell has observed,

these technologies ‘now leach into the more speculative realms of genetic manipulation’. She

notes that any technology produces change, sometimes dramatic change, and observes also,

like Jonas, that ‘its innovation can be seen to exceed the thought that engendered it’. Ferrell

proposes that in its ability to produce something that is the same but different, technology is

‘reproduction’.97 Her conclusion is thus a corollary to Jonas’s observation that

technologically mastered nature includes man. But even technology outside genetics is never

just technology; it cannot be separated from the social and political. Technology is a

social/political agent, as the mobile phone and the internet have shown. Through what it

represents in imagination, technology is profoundly socially constitutive. In her declaration

that she ‘would rather be a cyborg than a goddess’, Donna Haraway assigned social agency to

technology. In Haraway’s polemic, to be a cyborg is a more politically viable mode of social

life than that of a feminized female human.

But even Haraway, in her assumptions, is subordinating ‘new technology’ to normative

discursive frames—in this instance, late twentieth-century radical feminism. Technology in

her argument is still ‘other’, a manufactured product of capitalist society. But as Habermas,

Jonas, and others have warned, technology is no longer ‘other’. The ‘breakthroughs’ the

CSIRO hope to achieve through ‘cross-pollination’ are envisaged by them as breakthroughs

in new technology. They are still thinking of this future technology as ‘other’ and as a

passive product of future science. But in Jonas’s words, ‘the certainty and completeness of

prediction, fall short of the causal pregnancy of our technological deeds’. Thus, ‘an

imaginative “heuristics of fear”’ should replace the former ‘projections of hope’.98 If true

cross-pollination across the HASS-STEM divide occurs, the breakthroughs made are very

likely to be of a different kind than the CSIRO currently imagines.

II

97 Robyn Ferrell, Copula: Sexual Technologies, Reproductive Powers (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2006), 146. 98 Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility, x.

257 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

If, as Gaston Bachelard has claimed, ‘all knowledge is in response to a question’,99 then the

ability to achieve significant ‘breakthroughs’ must require an ability to ask significant

questions—questions that will be larger than single disciplinary frames. Consequently the

ability to frame and address significant questions is at the core of research competence, but

questions that transcend disciplinary sectors cannot be identified and addressed unilaterally by

individual specialists. Even agreement on what, at a meta-level, ‘significant’ means, requires

substantial pan-disciplinary work. Meta-level questions require for their framing and

decomposition management at a pan-disciplinary level; they require management as

university programs. Regardless of where the research ‘need’ is generated—whether from

Government in its pursuit of National priorities, or Government block funding for basic

research, or institutional self-directed research—the ‘need’ has to be decomposed into a

hierarchy of significant questions that can be worked on at the specialist level, and in a way

that enables the results to be integrated. For it to perform this role, the university would need

to alter its own organization so that its intellectual function was enhanced to make it equal to

its administrative function.

As the university is an organization which has the ability to frame ‘big’ questions, and

as it is the organization which is pre-eminent in the ability to pursue ‘big’ questions (because

of the breadth and depth of its specialists and the unbounded inquiry frame in which they

work) so the university is the organization with an indispensable role in the conduct of

significant research programs. The university is the logical entity, through the intellectual

authority delegated by government through the university protocols and its legislation, to be

both the sponsor and the ‘system design authority’ for ‘big’ questions. However in the

university, currently, there are no management structures for whole-of-knowledge inquiry,

nor intellectual structures for system level analysis of the ‘needs’ which drive research

funding.

Research management in the university, as it is currently performed, is sales and

99 Gaston Bachelard, La Formation de l'Esprit Scientifique (1934).

258 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

performance management for the various separate university research clusters.100 It is not

management of integrated research activity for specific research programs arising from higher

level ‘needs’ or requirements. Within the university, the term ‘management’ connotes

corporate management—management of the totality of the learning, knowledge transfer, and

research functions which define the organization as a university. But research program

management is quite different from university corporate management, just as program

management in NASA or Nokia is different from corporate management. The aims,

organization, tasks, budgets and authority for program management are quite different from

the aims, organization, tasks, budget, and authority of corporate management. Program

management is the weft to corporate management’s warp within the fabric which is the

organization. In this ‘matrix management’ model, the actual research or development effort

is performed by the subject matter experts from the functional (disciplinary) departments101

within the corporate entity, however, those specialists are accountable to the specific research

program for the effectiveness of the research or development work they undertake for that

research program. The university needs to adapt its research management processes to reflect

these matrix management principles.

Without some form of arrangement for higher level management of whole-of-

knowledge inquiry, it is hard to see how the academy can ever resolve the problem, which

Novick and Megill discussed, of increasing specialization leading to the increasing

fragmentation of knowledge rather than to the desired synthesis. Or as William J Bouwsma

described it: ‘our proliferating specialization’ which is ‘so devastating for the historical

understanding in the long run, no matter how convenient in the short’.102 But span can only

be achieved through organization, just as deep expertise can ultimately only be achieved

through the individual researcher. No one person can achieve increasing span and increasing

depth unless the hours in a day and the years in a life can be increased without limit.

100 That management imposes only generic expectations on the research function. 101 Equivalent to the, say, engineering, production, finance, business development, sales departments of the commercial company. 102 William J. Bouwsma, “From History of Ideas to History of Meaning”, Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 12, no. 2 (Autumn, 1981): 287.

259 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

Nevertheless, the individual researcher remains the fundamental building block from which

all else is built, thus any more comprehensive synthetic knowledge must result from the

combination of researcher and program process.

Disciplines have not previously had to consider the role of their specialist subjects

within a larger research framework because the organization of knowledge and its validation

followed from disciplinary definitions and practice.103 Research practice followed

disciplinary definitions and unequivocally its aim was the expansion of the disciplinary body

of knowledge. Now, as Gibbons and others have emphasized, the mode of knowledge

production is changing in significant ways—from Mode 1disciplinary knowledge, to context-

driven multidisciplinary research team knowledge (Mode 2).104 Knowledge production is

separating from disciplinary structure, and is being institutionalized in non-disciplinary ways.

Research is being conducted through research centres, institutes and think tanks, with

faculties and departments being the preferred form for carrying out teaching. Mode 2

knowledge, as Gibbons has described it, is produced in the context of particular applications

‘intended to be useful to someone whether in industry or government, or society more

generally and this imperative is present from the beginning’.105 In other words, practical

‘needs’ driven inquiry, such as the Australian Government’s National priorities, US

Defense’s capability requirements, or NASA’s Government directed missions. The

university must understand the research-to-products chain, and manage its basic research

appropriately.

However, when a comparison is made between the management of technological

research and development (as undertaken by NASA or US Defense, say) and HASS/STEM

103 In an interview with Theodore Barker in 1977, Julia Mann reflected: ‘I certainly never asked myself where I was going and I can’t remember anybody ever saying to me where is the subject going to or what is its object or anything like that, any more than one would have asked in those days what is the object of history in general.’ Quoted in Michael Bentley, Modernizing England’s Past: English Historiography in the Age of Modernism, 1870–1970 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 128. 104 See reference footnote 79, Chapter 1. 105 Michael Gibbons, “What kind of university? Research and teaching in the 21st century”, Victoria University of Technology, 1997 Beanland lecture, Melbourne, 4, http://www.griffith.edu.au/vc/ate/pdf/gibbons.pdf, [9 May 2007].

260 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

research and development, a significant anomaly becomes apparent. The management of

defence and aerospace research and development is conceptually much simpler than that of

the management of university and government-funded research and development, yet the

management terminology and models used in the former are very much more accurately

defined and acutely conceptualized than in the latter. University and government have not

understood that it is the management models which need attention, not the direction of the

research. A change of assumptions is required, but that alone is not sufficient, there must be

changes of research structure and process as well.

The changes in research structure and process that are required will not affect the

immediate practice of the individual specialist. What ‘happens’ in the world still needs to be

identified, and, in Donald Kelley’s words, ‘“ideas” must be brought down to a human

level’.106 Meaningful evidence still needs to be drawn from the material of the researcher’s

specialty, but it is the researcher’s specialist understanding of the raw material which enables

new knowledge to be derived from the application of abstract questions. Specialization is the

essence of research conducted by an individual. The broader ‘product’ is acquired as ‘Mode

2 knowledge’ through the specific, directed, research project. That does not mean that the

questions the researcher asks of the specialist material will not change, nor that disciplinary

boundaries will not move. Nor is it to deny the circularity of the link between the specialist

question and the needs-driven applications that indirectly affect specialist questions.

Questions do not arise outside historical contexts. But the expression ‘generalist researcher’

is an oxymoron and ‘holistic’ specialist inquiry is meaningless. The specialist researcher will

remain a narrow specialist.

III

If the pursuit of whole-of-knowledge inquiries were in the future to be managed as research

and development programs, what implications does that have for historical research and the

way that research is performed? Second, as the research edge is always moving, how should

106 Donald R. Kelley, The Descent of Ideas: The History of Intellectual History (Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing, 2002), 3.

261 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

the history discipline’s research focus change in order to adapt to the natural movement of the

basic research frontier?

In a changing research environment, change is required to maintain a relative position.

If history, or any academic discipline, is to maintain its relative significance and value to

intellectual inquiry, then it must evolve as intellectual inquiry evolves. To a large degree this

occurs reactively through the need to provide material of ‘interest’ to either disciplinary

specialists, or general readers. Through the process of staying ‘relevant’, the discipline

maintains its position. But that process cannot be relied on to assure a discipline’s future.

Without active intellectual ‘advance’ a discipline can simply ‘fall off’ the basic research train

and become a derivative ‘product’—such as, for history, ‘history channel’ products, or

national commemoration products, to be consumed along with other social and cultural

products.

Because the discipline of history has a central cultural function, the strong tendency is

to subordinate the basic research task to this cultural function. Jean-Noël Jeanneney recently

called this the historian’s ‘civic responsibility’. History for Jeanneney still operates as an

autonomous discipline with clear ‘applied’ functions. He accepts the observation that each

epoch, in its own way, and with its particular concerns, asks new questions of the past and

rereads it differently—but he subordinates this to cultural, didactic, requirements and argues

that it ‘should not lead to cynical relativism’. On the contrary the historian¹s civic

responsibility becomes the ‘weightier’ because of it. Here Jeanneney is expressing what is a

common view of the historian’s function. For him that function has three parts:

First, contributing to a truth (if not the truth) about humankind—what it has been, and consequently what it is; second, clarifying ideas, in order to serve those who engage in action; third, answering the call to help one¹s country, notably through the education system, in its construction of a national identity which is both worthy of the universal values that must inspire it, and faithful to its unique place on the Earth.107

107 This quote, and earlier attributions, are a précis of a flyer for a lecture entitled “The Civic Responsibility of Historians”, to be delivered by Professor Jeanneney at The University of Melbourne, 29 April 2008.

262 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

But this is just the corporate equivalent of producing mainstream developed-product for a

particular market need. As research, its form and intellectual extent is limited to the horizon

of national and international humanist culture. Research in this sense is applied research

directed towards improving the existing product.

Within a true basic research frame, the only limits are the current epistemological and

ontological frontiers. Not only do the types of questions change, but the motivation behind

the questions change. Bishop Stubbs’s history was of value to intellectual inquiry in his time,

but was of marginal value one hundred years later. Historical inquiry in the twentieth century

was interested in the construction of meaning within historical contexts, not, as for Stubbs,

constitutional ‘progress’ and the historical unfolding of a divinely ordained meaning. The

inquiry dimension or axis had changed, and disciplinary focus changed with it. Intellectual

evolution was manifested by a (cognitive) process of abstraction, not accretion. It was

exactly this process of abstraction which William J. Bouwsma was noting when commenting

on the conceptual changes he observed taking place in his field of intellectual history.108

Intellectual history, Bouwsma said, had long been ‘probably the most interdisciplinary

area of historical study’ and a specialty that ‘until recently, was regarded with particular

respect’. However, during the last two decades, he said, ‘the impression has grown among

historians that the kinds of material likely to be studied by intellectual historians are not very

useful for telling us what we most need to know about the past’. The problem was not that

intellectual history was not useful, but rather that it had outgrown its form as an isolated

specialty. ‘We no longer need intellectual history’, he observed, ‘because we all have

become intellectual historians: some of us, no doubt, unintentionally, reluctantly, and without

fully recognizing what has happened’. Nevertheless, the particular value of the specialty was,

he argued, ‘the liberation—not always welcome—that can result from identifying and laying

bare for inspection our own deepest assumptions about ourselves and the world’.109

Bouwsma noted that the arts have long been recognized as a primary vehicle for the

108 Bouwsma, “From History of Ideas to History of Meaning”. 109 Ibid., 279, 280.

263 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

expression of meaning and that intellectual historians ‘have long sensed (without perhaps

fully understanding) their affinities with art historians’. History had become characterized

‘not (as previously) by the sources that it utilizes but by the questions that it asks’.110 And

intellectual history should be seen as a ‘subset of a larger category of human behaviour’. This

category

consists of all efforts to discover or impose meaning on our experience, although some sense of meaning is both a condition and a product of experience. These efforts are not the work of the “intellect” or of any particular area of the personality. They are rather a function of the human organism as a whole; they are carried on both consciously and unconsciously; and they are presupposed by, and merge with, every more specific human activity.111

Here, Bouwsma was both advocating more holistic understanding and acknowledging

the movement from field of inquiry to mode of inquiry. ‘I do see’, he said,

in the conception of man as an animal who must create or discern meaning in everything that he does, the most promising resource that has yet presented itself for overcoming the consequences … of our proliferating specialization … a shift in emphasis from raw historical experience (i.e., what happens to people) to what human beings have made out of that experience [noting] that the creative interpretation of experience also shapes experience, which is only in the abstract independent of the meaning imposed on it.112

But this was simply acknowledging that all disciplinary inquiry is relevant to human

understanding. In 1981, when he spoke, Bouwsma seemed to be clinging to the hope that

somehow a change of assumptions would eradicate specialization in research. A change of

assumptions is required, but that alone is not sufficient: there must be changes of research

structure and process as well.

The main burden of change and synthesis is borne at a higher level, at the institutional

level, not at the level of the individual discipline. It is borne at the institutional level as part

110 Ibid., 285, 287. 111 Ibid., 283. 112 Ibid., 287–288.

264 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

of the requirement to implement and maintain a management structure for integrated, pan-

disciplinary, academic inquiry programs. The disciplines’ responsibility is the maintenance

of first-tier domain expertise. Their accountability is the warranting of specialist competence.

They are the only entities that can create and train specialists in any organizational sense.

The disciplinary field still identifies the epistemological core of the specialist’s inquiry.

However, the value of the specialist to the program is not their disciplinary field, though

fields are important, but the category of question they ask. The type of question is the most

significant parameter in the determination of the particular role that the specialist researcher

or research group will perform in the program’s integrated research team. The type of

question is both the ‘product’ (as, say, a radar is the product in a combat system) and the

functional category to which derived questions are assigned within the integrated scheme

(just as particular ‘detection’ or ‘classification’ functions, for example, are assigned to the

radar subsystem in the combat system). And as with the radar subsystem, the category and

type of question will determine the nature of the interface with other disciplines. In the

jargon of the systems development model, it will determine the nature of the ‘interface

specification’. For the individual disciplines in the university, their conceptual edge is at the

interdisciplinary interface, in the way that they interrelate, rather than enclosed within the

disciplinary ‘product’. The disciplinary domain and method remain unchanged. It is exactly

analogous to the radar product having to change in order to be able to integrate and perform

effectively within a new system. Change will occur in the disciplinary domain, but it will be

incremental and evolutionary and result from interaction at the interface.

If the question of academic research is considered in this more complex model, then for

the history discipline within the academic enterprise there seems to be two distinct functions

it performs. First a cultural function—a development function—which it has performed

through its hand-crafted historiographical products which provide explanatory cultural

narratives; and second, a cognitive function—a research function—which is required since

historical consciousness and historical knowledge are inseparable from the process of inquiry

reflected in pure research. Problems of understanding are at root historical problems if the

265 Ch. 5: History and Research Management

arguments of Hegel, Marx, Dilthey, Mach, Lukács, Collingwood and others are accepted; and

historical consciousness is inseparable from judgement if the arguments of Vico, Kant,

Duhem, Croce, Merleau-Ponty, Gadamer, Ricoeur, Rorty and others are accepted. There is,

by this reasoning, no space outside history in which any researcher or any research

organization can operate. Consequently there seems to be a clear need for specialist history

research within the logic of pure research. The history discipline, however, cannot claim to

be the only one interested in historicity and historical context. Those sensitivities have

leached into most disciplinary streams. But though the styles of reasoning within those

streams might evolve, that does not mean that the disciplines’ primary interests change to

history and the historical. Nor does it mean that the individual specialist’s span extends. As

knowledge accumulates, specialization proliferates: specialists further refine their fields.

There remains the need for deep history specialists regardless of the way disciplinary modes

and boundaries may change. Historical consciousness (cultivated memory)113 mediates

higher-level cognition and deep history specialists are needed in any multidisciplinary project

where conceptual change is involved.

The need for history basic research specialists in the direct production of cultural

products, however, is less clear. Products are usually developed by development groups, not

by the researchers themselves. Within companies there is a distinction drawn between the

two functions. The considerations affecting product development are quite different from

those affecting research. Similarly, academic research should be an activity distinct from

product development; different logic applies. History research in the academy should be

driven by quite different considerations than public accessibility or commercial success.

113 ‘History is memory cultivated’; Hayden White, “Review Article: Guilty of History: The Longue Durée of Paul Ricoeur”, History and Theory, 46, no. 2 (May, 2007): 235.

266

CONCLUSION

I have often taken comfort from the reply Henry James made to H. G. Wells: ‘Of course for myself I live, live intensely and am fed by life, and my value, whatever it be, is in my own kind of expression of that. Therefore I am pulled up by the fact that for you my kind (my sort of sense of expression and sort of sense of life alike) doesn’t exist’. —C.M.H. Clark: A History of Australia1

Life cannot wait until the sciences may have explained the universe scientifically. We cannot put off living until we are ready … Life is fired at us point-blank. And culture, which is but its interpretation, cannot wait any more than can life itself … From all quarters the need presses upon us for a new integration of knowledge, which today lies in pieces … The need to create sound syntheses and systematizations of knowledge … will call out a kind of scientific genius which hitherto has existed only as an aberration: the genius for integration. Of necessity this means specialization, as all creative effort inevitably does; but this time, the man will be specializing in the construction of the whole. —José Ortega y Gassett 2

In his much criticized, but much misunderstood, inaugural lecture, ‘The Science of History’,

J. B. Bury commented that

There was indeed no historian since the beginning of things who did not profess that his sole aim was to present to his readers untainted and unpainted truth. But the axiom was loosely understood and interpreted, and the notion of truth was elastic.3

Bury had prefaced his remarks by noting that ‘within three generations, three short generations’ history had transformed itself to take ‘no small nor isolated place’ in the ‘far- reaching changes in the geography of thought and in the apparatus of research’.4 Today, within another three generations, there have been even more far-reaching changes in the geography of thought and in the apparatus of research; and even greater looseness and

1 C.M.H. Clark: A History of Australia, vol. 5 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1981), vii. 2 José Ortega y Gassett, Mission of the University, ed. Howard Lee Nostrand (New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1992), 63, 69, 70. 3 J. B. Bury, Selected Essays of J. B. Bury, ed. Harold Temperley (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1930), 6. Lecture delivered 26 January 1903. 4 Ibid., 3.

267 Conclusion

elasticity. And, for the academic historian, the looseness in understanding and the elasticity

in definition now apply to more than just notions of purpose and truth. Today, traditional

notions of the university’s form, missions, and research processes are changing.5 The

academy is no longer elitist, collegial, and cloistered, but open, managed, and ‘virtual’. The,

mass, global, digital, ‘postmodern’ age has wrought comprehensive change to the

organization, content, economics, politics, and sociology of knowledge. Consequently,

traditional notions of the way academic products are produced, and how they reach their

audience, are changing. Changing also is the relationship between academic research,

scholarship, and pedagogy. As one university vice-chancellor has remarked: ‘Once the

gatekeepers to knowledge and authority, universities face a world in which information can

be created and distributed without traditional institutions’.6

The future of the history discipline as an academic profession depends not on the

perennial philosophical question of what historians offer to culture, and the form of that

offering, which was represented in the late 1980s by the debate between ‘new’ and ‘old’

history. Rather, it depends now on what historians offer to the research university;

specifically, what basic research function the discipline can perform.7 If it is accepted that

basic research operates at the limits of epistemic and ontological understanding, then the

function of history within culture, and the form of historiographic products in particular

cultures, are subjects for basic research.8 History as basic research is concerned with

cognition and cognition’s individual and collective construction of normativity and culture. It

seeks to discover the meaning within and the meaning of those constructions. History’s value

to basic research is the fact that the ‘historical’ is a fundamental mode of understanding, thus

a fundamental mode of inquiry. The research field for this specialist research is the record of

the human past.

5 See, for example, Group of Eight, Seizing the Opportunities: A Group of Eight Policy Discussion Paper, 6 June 2007 (Canberra: The Group of Eight, 2007), 19–20 6 Glyn Davis, “From the Vice Chancellor”, The University of Melbourne Voice, 1, no. 18. (12 Nov.–26 Nov., 2007). 7 Given, as this thesis has argued, that a core function of a university is basic research. See also Group of Eight, Seizing the Opportunities, 13–14, 8 But history and historiography continue, nevertheless, to have an important cultural function.

268 Conclusion

Human experience is derived from time-sequenced raw sensation by the formation of

the cognitive categories ‘past’, ‘present’ and ‘future’. Historicity—time’s arrow—is a

fundamental ‘dimension’ of human understanding. Similarly, historical consciousness is a

distinctive cognitive ‘state’. To understand both phenomena and epiphenomena as something

is to know them historically. Mathematics, logic, art, and music can be contemplated

ahistorically, as things in themselves, but as things in themselves, although they are affective,

they do not mean anything. Human understanding can only exist within historical

consciousness. A sense of chronology and genealogy is required if sense is to be made of the

physical, psychological, and cultural world in a way that enables life (both physical and

social) to be sustained. Sustainable ‘life’ depends on individual and collective memory

‘normalised’ within subjectivity and culture by, respectively, personal and collective

‘history’. But history as a mode and a field of inquiry, and as an essential basic research

element, is outside memory and culture. Although it seeks to interpret human experience

which, self-evidently, is within physical and cultivated memory, it does so in order to get to

that meaning, and from that to new current meaning, hence new knowledge.

But if academic historians can be chivvied to look more closely at their basic research

function, then the academy needs to make an appraisal of its underlying organizational and

intellectual conceptions. First, it needs to reflect on how research and its management in the

academy are conceptualized. Second, the university needs to consider how its engagement

with its ‘customers’ (public and government) is conceptualized. Phrases such as ‘the

‘creation of knowledge through significant research’ and ‘knowledge transfer to the wider

community’ have become commonplace descriptions of universities’ function, but

understandings of what is meant by ‘knowledge’, of how knowledge is validated, of what

‘significant’ might mean, and of what practical and theoretical transformations are required

before specialist knowledge can be transferred ‘outside’ to non-specialists, are vague.

‘Discovery’ is not ‘creation’, so what does research discover? Is wisdom discovered? Does

basic research create knowledge, or is that done by ‘downstream’ development processes?

How are the ideas generated from a dialectical process conducted at the extreme end of

269 Conclusion

epistemic and ontological understanding made understandable to the non-specialist ‘public’

which does not have the necessary, highly specific, reference knowledge to begin to

understand even the question at the heart of the idea, let alone the responses? How are those

ideas packaged and delivered? Who packages and delivers them? Or is it some other

‘product’ that is ‘transferred’ to the public; a product developed and ‘packaged’ specifically

to be a desirable public-consumption item? Is it any more feasible to expect (as it is

currently) the academic to research, develop, package, and sell a complex academic product,

than to expect the salesman (or researcher, or developer, or marketer) to do the same for the

complex consumer product?

Outside the universities, for-profit organizations of similar size to universities are, by

comparison, very clear on these questions. They have clear conceptual models which enable

them to locate themselves within a ‘value chain’ and, in their language, convert their inputs to

value-added outputs which have extrinsic value. They also understand clearly that they must

continually move ‘up’ the chain in order to maintain their competitive position and ensure

their survival. Companies such as Nokia, Lockheed Martin, Boeing, and IBM have very clear

understanding of the distinction between research, innovation, production, and ‘business’

processes. It is precisely that understanding that enables them to adapt, evolve, and thrive

within a harsh, unforgiving, environment. Each of those companies has a clear understanding

of the difference between pure basic research, strategic basic research, applied research,

experimental development, product innovation, product development, production, marketing,

sales, and product support, and of the interaction between those processes. Nokia

understands very well the profound conceptual difference between basic research output and

a leading-edge product for the retail market. And yet in Australia the government-controlled

competitive grant process for research funding makes no official distinction between

categories. Basic research is bundled together with other research and development products,

then judged on criteria that include national benefit.9 The basic research proposal (which is

9 The Australian Research Council mission is ‘to deliver policy and programs that advance Australian research and innovation globally and benefit the community’. http://www.arc.gov.au/default.htm; [1 December 2008].

270 Conclusion

not only irrelevant but incomprehensible to non-specialists) competes for funding against the

product proposal (say, ‘transportation needs of marginalized communities’) which connects

more directly to notions of ‘value’ and social utility.10 A greater distinction must be drawn

between pure basic research and other research by funding authorities if research is to be

managed effectively. The deeper problem is that these authorities are providing only tactical

(short-term) research management while proclaiming (and, one must assume, believing) it to

be strategic management.

Universities, with their much more complex customer relationships,11 their much more

complex products, and much more complex product mixes, do not have any appropriate

conceptual models or business models of the kind used by their for-profit corporate peers.

The older tradition of external funding through church, court, state, or other patrons, has

meant that it is only relatively recently in the life of the university as institution that the need

for these models has arisen. Intellectually, the traditions of collegiality, the separation of

disciplines, the emphasis on pedagogy, and the conflation, in the humanities in particular, of

scholarship with research, have entrenched the notion of separate spheres of knowledge and

the notion of the individual scholar as the focus of all research, learning, and knowledge

transfer. In this setting, the notion of integrated knowledge has been the institutional Gordian

knot. The paradox of increasing research specialization leading to increasing awareness of

the interrelatedness of all physical, biological, cultural, and ecological processes has created a

need for institutional processes for knowledge integration that current institutions are

incapable of satisfying.

If an effective conceptual model is not established within the university and between

the universities and their ‘customer’—‘society’ as reflected through Government and the

‘marketplace’—then the capacity for genuine advances in epistemic and ontological

10 The consequence of this is that even ‘discovery’ grant applications, intended to be pure or strategic basic research, are worded in utilitarian, ‘experimental development’ language—which, even if a ploy, distorts their basic research focus. See, for example, the ‘Section 4301 Historical Studies’ descriptions of successful discovery project applications submitted to the Australian Research Council in 2007. http://www.arc.gov.au/pdf/DP08/DP08_RFCD.pdf, 347–358. [23 August 2008]. 11 As public institutions with public obligations but with only partial public funding.

271 Conclusion

understanding to change social action, locally and globally, in wholly new ways outside

current perception, is neutralized. Society will always demand things it wants, but those

wants are defined by things known. Thus, a form of epistemic myopia becomes

institutionalized. What does society want new knowledge for? Know what? Why know? Is

it simply in order to extend life? Or is it to make life easier? If the former, then the question

is why? If the latter, the question is, why live? Alternatively, if the object of new knowledge

is not existential answers but practical action—approaches that enable society to know how to

act in a life that is fired point-blank at it—then what criteria are used to judge ‘intelligent’

from ‘unintelligent’ action?

These are not questions that appeal to Government, nor generally to other funders of

research—such as industry—yet they are important and relevant to decisions regarding

choices society has to make; and the university is better equipped than alternative

‘contractors’ to explore these types of questions. However, without processes and conceptual

models that enable the connection of (apparent) knowledge-for-its-own-sake with (apparent)

useful social products, all that will emerge from the university is separate packages of

incomplete knowledge, each incapable of addressing whole problems.

Because of the ‘double hermeneutic’ that operates in human understanding, there are

neither absolute problems nor absolute answers. Neither the human subject nor culture is a

fixed entity, each is self-fashioning and interactive with the other. The university has a

unique capability both to explore the future possibilities inherent in this self-fashioning, and

to assist with decisions regarding societal self-fashioning. However, more synthesized

knowledge is required if intelligent action is to emerge from this exploration.

II

At the centre of the idea of the research university is the notion of curiosity-driven inquiry,

‘knowledge for its own sake’ —pure basic research—but at the centre of the research

university’s ability to survive is the notion of utility in the form of social value. Unless the

university can connect pure basic research to (perceived) current social need, then it will not

272 Conclusion

survive as a research university. It may survive as an institution whose value is pedagogical

or vocational, but it will not continue to exist as an institution whose value (and distinction) is

founded in ‘leading-edge’ research. Similarly with the history discipline: unless it

understands the difference between its basic research function and its cultural function, it will

not have a place in leading-edge research teams and forums.

It was because pure inquiry and social value were integrated in the philosophy behind

the founding of the University of Berlin that that institution exemplified the idea of a research

university. It was that philosophy which ensured the University’s intellectual authority and

financial security. The University of Berlin’s formation represented the happy coincidence of

intellectual and political power. In the founding partnership of Fichte, Schleiermacher, and

Humboldt there was achieved that fusion of intellectual exploration at its epistemic and

ontological limits, with political conviction that that exploration was the most profound

contribution that could be made to Prussian society’s future. Prussia’s defeat at Jena, and its

subsequent occupation by France, had produced a political resolve to create an existentially

independent Prussian state through the development of its citizen’s ‘highest

[intellectual/aesthetic] possibilities’.12 In the first decades of the University of Berlin’s life

the intellectual engine, regardless of discipline, was the desire to know more profoundly; to

know at the limits of understanding. Whether it was Fichte, Schleiermacher, or Hegel in

philosophy, or Niebuhr and Ranke in history, the disciplinary field was simply the means to

deeper knowledge of knowledge.

The fact that the Prussian academy, particularly history, later came to be subordinated

to culture and national identity was due, in part at least, to the fact that there were no effective

institutional processes whereby basic research could be transformed into useful social

products. Hegel’s unified theory of reality, and Fichte’s comprehensive philosophy of

subjectivity remain today outstanding products of pure (metaphysical) inquiry, and still have

research value; but by 1841 in Berlin, when Schelling returned to the University, Hegelianism

was perceived to have become remote from ‘real’ life and unable to provide the ethical and

12 Wilhelm von Humboldt. See Chapter 2, p. 80.

273 Conclusion

spiritual guidance which had been philosophy’s social raison d’être. History replaced

metaphysics as the vehicle for the achievement of society’s highest possibilities.

Unfortunately, research became subordinated to political utility, and with that change the

understanding of what advance meant in relation to knowledge changed.

It is not a coincidence that with this change Prussian academic history subsequently lost

its international intellectual authority. Prussian history was no longer judged to be concerned

with pure inquiry. The true advance of knowledge, advance in the sense of continuing to

move beyond current limits, could (and can) only occur through multi-directional interaction

between frontier (basic) research and research’s other ‘downstream’ components. It could not

(and cannot) be achieved by a one-way transfer, whichever the direction. In late nineteenth-

century Prussia, the flow was from nation to research. Research’s function was to consolidate

knowledge of the known entity: German culture and nation. The ‘highest possibilities’ were

now manifested in the incorporation into the nation’s citizens of the imagined intrinsic values

of this national culture. By the early twentieth century, the higher level of existential being

was now the fusion of citizen, nation, and state.

In the universities of Oxford and Cambridge in the nineteenth century, historical

inquiry had always been subordinated intellectually to culture and nation. In those

institutions, history’s intellectual engine was the desire to produce history that was useful;

principally, history which provided guidance, not on how to be, but on how to act. The

location of the historian inside or outside the university did not affect the general purpose for

which the history was written: any differences resulted from personality. By knowing the

story of Britain’s evolution, and learning from the lessons of the past, Britons as individuals,

as citizens, and as rulers would be better able to act wisely. History considered moral,

religious, social, and political problems. History showed what had been proven to be

successful, and unsuccessful, action. Historians wrote for the general reader. Written history

was a literary work whose raw materials were the records of the human past. Research

supported writing.

274 Conclusion

The fate of British academic history was the converse of that suffered by history and

philosophy in the German academy. In Britain, there were no effective institutional processes

whereby history’s useful social products could be grounded epistemologically or

ontologically in basic research. Effectively, there was no basic research content, just applied

research and ‘product’ development. The consequence was that by the beginning of the

twentieth century, history’s epistemological and ontological assumptions could no longer be

sustained in the British academy. Historians such as J.B. Bury in Britain and Carl Becker in

the US increasingly questioned history’s philosophical foundations. Whereas in the

nineteenth century historians as philosophically, technically, and stylistically diverse as

Stubbs, Carlyle, Green, and Freeman were all writing quite different, but public-approved,

history, in the twentieth century historians as different as Bury, Trevelyan, Butterfield and

Namier all claimed to be writing proper history, and each argued that the others were not.

In Australia in the mid- and late-twentieth century, history and its writing were even

more problematical. The transportation of ontologically weak Oxbridge models to an

existentially uncertain Australia further aggravated the problem of what history and history

writing was. The uncertainty this caused was reflected in the diversity of approach

represented by historians such as Clark, Crawford and Dening. For Clark, history was

literature, and to be great as history it had to speak to that truth of human reality that was

beyond words; his history’s historical form was that of Carlyle’s, its literary form that of

Dostoevsky’s. Crawford, unsuccessful in his quest to understand how history happened, how

necessity and contingency were manifested in life’s actuality, resigned himself to the notion

of history as a form of enlarged liberal humanism. In his conclusion that history was

‘inevitably and inescapably a training in moral sensitivity’,13 at end Crawford equated history

with a modernized form of Sentimentalism. For Dening, history was cultural action;

historical knowledge was ontological wisdom; historical understanding produced wise action,

it enlarged our understanding of how we live, thus how to live. The three historians

demonstrated that there are many ways of knowing, because there are many ways of seeing.

13 See Chapter 2, p. 103.

275 Conclusion

They wrote about what life moved them to observe.

At the beginning of the twenty-first century, anthropocentricity, which in the previous

two centuries had grounded issues of subjectivity, autonomy, cultural authenticity, and human

understanding, has now been seen to be just an epiphenomenon of a larger physical,

biological, ecological system. Biologically and culturally, not only are individuals and

cultures self-fashioning and ever changing—evolving—but so is the notion of the ‘human’.

Survival of life on the planet, not liberty, equality, fraternity, seems now to be the primary

focus for intelligent thought—once Locke’s ‘social contract’, now Serres’s ‘natural contract’.

Life still has to be lived, it cannot wait until solutions are found, but the datum for measuring

intelligent action has moved.

III

This thesis was concerned, at its inception, with knowing, not acting. It sought only to

explore what the notion of history research meant. An unintended consequence, however, has

been that the inquiry has indicated—should the arguments presented be even partially

accepted—that there are actions which should be taken to better define, and thereby improve,

the management of academic research.

First, there is a need to bring the humanities, arts and social sciences research

(Geisteswissenschaften), meaningfully into the formal research categories used for the science

and technology disciplines. The Government statistical categories by which research is

monitored and measured in its several R&D components are irrelevant currently to HASS

research practice. There is no evidence that those categories have any meaningful theoretical

or practical affect on current HASS research. It is acknowledged that rigid boundaries are

neither possible nor desirable, nor are they easily identified, but there are, in relation to

knowledge, critical epistemological differences between basic research, applied research,

development, innovation and production which need to be identified and understood. The

conduct of research as a common enterprise is not possible without the implications these

276 Conclusion

differences have for specialist research being understood and agreed.14

Second, there is a need for the conceptual model which defines the relationship

between the Australian government, its delegated research management bodies (Australian

Research Council, and National Health and Medical Research Council), and the research

practitioners, to be redefined so that more effective management of the whole basic-research

to mission-accomplishment continuum is accomplished. Better formulation of programs,

identification of desired outcomes, allocation of responsibility and separation of pure basic

research from performance management demands would allow more effective specialization

within and between the different entities, and thus a more productive relationship. The

development of acquisition frameworks for the conceptually complex whole-of-knowledge

programs will require, itself, concentrated multi-disciplinary academic expertise.

Third, there is a need to develop knowledge models that allow fusion of HASS and

STEM pure basic research and integrating processes that enable specialist research to fit

epistemologically into specific whole-of-knowledge projects. A new ‘systems design’

function is required at a level ‘above’ that of the specialist researcher. That function ensures

that the research whole is greater than the parts. More was needed to land a man on the moon

than to allow scientists and engineers to co-locate and mix freely. Whole-of-knowledge

research requires similar expertise. If the university is to pursue those programs, then this

new specialist capability must be, and can only be, developed by the university.

Finally, there is a need within the university to develop a business model which defines

more clearly the place of pure basic research and the relationship between research and the

university’s other functions. Pure basic research—wholly undirected research—is an

14 Recent reviews in Australia of the national innovation system and the cooperative research centres program not only make little if any distinction between basic research, applied research, and experimental development, they also struggle to find ways of including the humanities in their discussion. See for example, Department of Innovation, Industry, Science and Research. Collaborating to a Purpose: Review of the Cooperative Research Centres Program, July 2008. Canberra: DIISR, 2008, VenturousAustralia: Building Strength in Innovation [Review of the National Innovation System Report]. North Melbourne: Cutler & Company, 2008, and Productivity Commission. Public Support for Science and Innovation: Research Report, 9 March 2007. Canberra: Productivity Commission, 2007.

277 Conclusion

essential part of a successful model. Given that whole-of-knowledge research will modify the

way research is organized, so it will modify the relationship between research and teaching.

Logically, they will remain connected, but the process from pure basic research to delivered

form will expand. The model should enable the identification of true academic pure basic

research effort from effort which, though currently called ‘research’, is not basic research, nor

even strategic basic, or applied, research, but some other experimental development or

product development activity. ‘Research’ which does not require specialist academic

expertise and academic collaboration for its accomplishment/evolution should not be

classified, formally, as ‘research’ in the university research management model. Much

history research, undertaken both inside the academy as well as outside, would not satisfy the

current formal definition of ‘basic research’. The model would enable the university to better

envisage, and thus manage, the spectrum of in-house, consortium, contracted, subcontracted,

and individual research which is undertaken either within the university or within ‘virtual

teams’. Again, companies such as Nokia, Lockheed Martin, and Boeing have models that

could be adapted.

IV

History is the air we breathe—we are ‘hemmed in by history’.15 Thus, ‘history’s’ existence is

assured. But academic history is not that history. That history is extrinsic to the function the

academic historian performs in the academy. If the discipline is to adapt successfully to

institutional and social change, then it must be clear on that difference; it must be clear on

what ‘business’ it is in.

Academic history, by ensuring that it identifies how its specialist expertise is needed for

the accomplishment of research at the edge of epistemic and ontological understanding, will

ensure its continual renewal, and future, in whatever form that may take.

15 Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Signs (Evanston Ill: Northwestern University Press, 1964), 109.

278

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Primary Sources

Archives

R. M. Crawford papers, University of Melbourne Archives.

Books and Chapters

Academic Standards Panel, History. Report of the Academic Standards Panel, History. Canberra: Australian Vice-Chancellors' Committee, 1991.

Alexander, Samuel. Philosophical and Literary Pieces. London: Macmillan, 1939.

Atkinson, Alan. The Europeans in Australia: A History. Vol. 1. Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1998.

Babbage, Charles. Reflections on the Decline of Science in England and on Some of its Causes. London: B. Fellowes & J. Booth, 1830.

Bacon, Francis. The Advancement of Learning. Edited by G. W. Kitchin. London: J. M. Dent, 1973.

Barrow, Sir John. Sketches of the Royal Society and Royal Society Club. London: Frank Cass, 1971.

Bryce, James. “Presidential Address at the Opening Meeting of the International Congress of Historical Studies, April 3, 1913. With Introductory and Supplementary Remarks by A. W. Ward.” Proceedings of the British Academy. Vol. 1913–1914. London: Oxford University Press, 1915: 113–128.

Burckhardt, Jacob. The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy: An Essay. London: Phaidon Press, 1960.

Burckhardt, Jakob. Reflections on History. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1943.

Bury, J. B. Selected Essays of J. B. Bury. Edited by Harold Temperley. London: Cambridge University Press, 1930.

Bury, J. B. The Idea of Progress: An Inquiry into its Origin and Growth. London: Macmillan and Co. 1921.

Butterfield, Herbert. The Origins of Modern Science 1300–1800. London: G. Bell and Sons, 1958.

——Man on His Past: The Study of the History of Historical Scholarship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1955.

——History and Human Relations. London: Collins, 1951.

Clark, C. M. H. A History of Australia. Vols. 1–6. Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1962– 1987.

Clark, Manning. Manning Clark: A Discovery of Australia. Crows Nest: Australian Broadcasting Corporation, 1991.

279 Bibliography

——The Quest for Grace. Ringwood: Penguin Books, 1991.

——A Historian's Apprenticeship. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1992.

——Occasional Writings and Speeches. Melbourne: Fontana/Collins, 1980.

Collingwood, R. G. An Autobiography. London: Oxford University Press, 1939.

——The Philosophy of Enchantment: Studies in Folktale, Cultural Criticism, and Anthropology. Edited by David Boucher, Wendy James and Philip Smallgood. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005.

——The Principles of History and Other Writings in the Philosophy of History. Edited by W. H. Dray, and W. J. Van Der Dussen. New York: Oxford University Press, 1999.

——Speculum Mentis or The Map of Knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1924.

Comte, Auguste, Early Political Writings/Auguste Comte. Edited and translated by. H. S. Jones. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

Crawford, R. M. Manning Clark, . Making History. Fitzroy, Ringwood: McPhee Gribble Publishers, Penguin Books, 1985.

Crawford, R. M. The Study of History: a synoptic view. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1939.

——An Australian Perspective. Madison: The University of Wisconsin Press, 1960.

——Australia. Melbourne: Hutchinson, 1970.

Croce, Benedetto. Theory and History of Historiography. London: George G. Harrap, 1921.

Dalberg-Acton, John Emerich Edward. Historical Essays and Studies. Edited by John Neville Figgis, and Reginald Vere Laurence. London: Macmillan and Co. 1907.

——Lectures on Modern History. London: Macmillan and Co. 1926.

Dening, Greg. Islands and Beaches: Discourse on a Silent Land, Marquesas, 1774–1880. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1980.

——Mr Bligh’s Bad Language: Passion, Power and Theatre on the Bounty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.

——The Death of William Gooch: A History's Anthropology. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1995

——Readings/Writings. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1998.

——Performances. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1996.

Eggleston, F. W. Search for a Social Philosophy. Parkville: Melbourne University Press, 1941

Elton, Oliver. Frederick York Powell: A Life and a Selection from his Letters and Occasional Writings. Vol. 1: Memoir and Letters. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1906.

——Frederick York Powell: A Life and a Selection from his Letters and Occasional Writings. Vol. 2: Occasional Writings. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1906.

Essays on the Teaching of History. Edited by F. W. Maitland. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1901.

280 Bibliography

Firth, C. H. “The Study of Modern History in Great Britain Considered in connexion with Education, the Organization of the Archives, and the documentary Publications of the Government.” Proceedings of the British Academy. Vol. 1913–1914. London: Oxford University Press, 1915: 139–149.

Flexner, Abraham. Universities: American, English, German. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1994.

Freeman, Edward A. The Methods of Historical Study: Eight Lectures Read in the University of Oxford in Michaelmas Term 1884, with the Inaugural Lecture on The Office of the Historical Professor. London: Macmillan and Co. 1886.

Gierke, Otto. Political Theories of the Middle Age. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1900.

Gooch, G. P. “The Growth of Historical Science” in The Cambridge Modern History. Vol. 12: The Latest Age. Edited by A. W. Ward, G. W. Prothero and Stanley Leathes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1910.

Hancock, W. K. Smuts: The Fields of Force 1919–1950. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968.

——Australia. Brisbane: The Jacaranda Press, 1961.

——Politics in Pitcairn: and Other Essays. London: Macmillan & Co. 1947.

——Perpective in History. Canberra: Australian National University, 1982.

——Professing History. Sydney: Sydney University Press, 1976.

Harrison, Frederic. The Meaning of History and Other Historical Pieces. London: Macmillan and Co. 1906.

Heisenberg, Werner. Physics and Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1958.

Humanities and Social Sciences Futures: Papers from the National Humanities and Social Sciences Summit. Edited by Malcolm Gillies, Mark Carroll and John Dash. Canberra: Australian National University, 2001.

Krieger, Murray. The Institution of Theory. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994.

Langlois, CH. V. and C. H. Seignobos. Introduction to the Study of History. London: Duckworth & Co. 1898.

Macaulay, Lord. Miscellaneous Essays. London: Collins' Clear-Type Press, n. d.

Mach, Ernst. Knowledge and Error: Sketches on the Psychology of Enquiry. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1976.

Maitland, Frederic William. The Letters of Frederic William Maitland. Edited by C. H. S. Fifoot. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965.

——State, Trust and Corporation. Edited by David Runciman and Magnus Ryan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003.

McTaggart, John, McT. Ellis. Philosophical Studies. Edited by S. V. Keeling. London: Edward Arnold, 1934.

Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism, On Liberty, Essay on Bentham, together with selected writings of Jeremy Bentham and John Austin. Edited by Mary Warnock. London: Collins, 1966.

281 Bibliography

Newman, John Henry. The Idea of a University. Edited by I. T. Ker. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976.

Oman, Sir Charles. On the Writing of History. London: Methuen,1939.

——Memories of Victorian Oxford: and of some early years, (London: Methuen, 1941)

Ortega y Gasset, Jose. Mission of the University. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1992.

Oxford Lectures on University Studies 1906–1921. Edited n.n. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1924.

Pattison, Mark. Isaac Casaubon: 1559–1614. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1892.

——Memoirs. London: Macmillan and Co. 1885.

——The Project Gutenberg EBook of Milton. http://www.gutenberg.org/etext/8770 (accessed 22 July 2007).

Pauli, Wolfgang. Writings on Physics and Philosophy. Edited by Charles P. Enz and Karl Meyen. Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 1994.

Powicke, F. M. Ways of Medieval Life and Thought: Essays and Addresses. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1971.

Royce, Josiah. Lectures on Modern Idealism. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1919.

Schelling, F. W. J. On University Studies. Edited by Norbert Guterman. Athens OH: Ohio University Press, 1966.

Schrodinger, Erwin. Nature and the Greeks-and-Science and Humanism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

Scott, Ernest. History and Historical Problems. Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1925.

Seeley, J. R. The Expansion of England. Edited by John Gross. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1971.

Smuts, Jan Christian. Walt Whitman: A Study in the Evolution of Personality. Edited by Alan L. McLeod. Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 1973.

Solow, Robert M. Francis Oakley, Phyllis Franklin. Making the Humanities Count: The Importance of Data. Cambridge MA: American Academy of Arts & Sciences, 2002.

Stubbs, William. Germany in the Later Middle Ages, 1200–1500. Edited by Arthur Hassall. London: Longmans, Green and Co. 1908.

——Seventeen lectures on the Study of Medieval and Modern History and Kindred Subjects Delivered at Oxford, under statutory obligation in the years 1867–1884. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1887.

Tawney, R. H. Religion and the Rise of Capitalism: A Historical Study. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1975.

The Cambridge Modern History. Vol. XII: The Latest Age. Edited by A. W. Ward, G. W. Prothero and Stanley Leathes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1910.

Barnard, Alan, ed. The Simple Fleece: Studies in the Australian Wool Industry. Parkville: Melbourne University Press, 1962.

Thompson, Joseph. The Owens College: Its Foundation and Growth; and its Connection with the Victoria University, Manchester. Manchester: J. E. Cornish, 1886.

282 Bibliography

Tout, Thomas Frederick. The Collected Papers of Thomas Frederick Tout with A Memoir and Bibliography. Vol. I: Miscellaneous Papers Chiefly on the Study of History and The University of Manchester. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1932.

Trevelyan, George Macaulay. English Literature and Its Readers: Presidential Address to The English Association. n.p.: The English Association, 1951.

——An Autobiography & Other Essays. London: Longmans, Green and Co, 1949.

——Clio, A Muse and Other Essays Literary and Pedestrian. London: Longmans, Green and Co, 1913.

Veblen, Thorstein. The Higher Learning in America. New York: Sagamore Press Inc. 1957.

Ward, A. W. “Closing Remarks.” Proceedings of the British Academy. Vol. 1913–1914. London: Oxford University Press, 1915: 129–138.

Weber, Max. From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. Edited by H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1957.

Wheelwright, E. L. ed. Higher Education in Australia. Melbourne: F. W. Cheshire, 1965.

Whitehead, Alffred North. The Concept of Nature: Tarner Lectures delivered in Trinity College November 1919. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1920.

——Alfred North Whitehead: An Anthology. Edited by F. S. C. Northrop and Mason W Gross. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1953.

——Dialogues of Alfred North Whitehead/as recorded by Lucien Price. Boston: David R. Godine, 2001.

——Science and the Modern World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1926.

Zohn, Harry, ed. In These Great Times: A Karl Kraus Reader. Manchester: Carcanet Press Limited, 1984.

Articles

Acton, John, Emeric, Edward, Dalberg. “German Schools of History.” English Historical Review 1, no. 1 (January, 1886): 7–42.

Alexander, Fred, A. Boyce Gibson, Margaret Gowing, Robin Gollan. “Hancock: Some Reminiscences.” Historical Studies 13, no. 51 (Oct., 1968): 291–306.

Clark, C. M. H. “Hancock’s Australia and Australian Historiography: A Note.” Historical Studies 13, no. 51 (Oct., 1968): 329–332.

—— and A. L. Burns, Hugh Stretton, D. J. Mulvaney, J. S. Gregory, W. McMahon Ball, W. K. Hancock. “R. M. Crawford: Some Reminiscences.” Historical Studies 15, no. 57 (Oct., 1971): 5–21.

Collingwood, R. G. “Human Nature and Human History.” Proceedings of the British Academy. Vol. 22, 1936. London: Oxford University Press, 1937: 97–127.

—— “Are History and Science Different Kinds of Knowledge?” Mind 31, no. 124 (Oct., 1922): 443– 466.

283 Bibliography

Condorcet. “Sketch for a Historical Picture of the Progress of the Human Mind.” Daedalus 133, no. 3 (Summer, 2004): 65–82.

Crawford, R. M. “The School of Prudence or Inaccuracy and Incoherence in Describing Chaos?” Historical Studies 15, no. 57 (Oct., 1971): 27–42.

Davies, Godfrey. “Charles Harding Firth, 1857–1936.” Proceedings of the British Academy. Vol. 22, 1936. London: Oxford University Press, 1937: 380–400.

Dewey, John. “Meaning and existence.” Journal of Philosophy 25, no. 13 (Jun. 21, 1928): 345–353.

Elton, G. R. “Presidential Address: The Historian's Social Function.” Transactions of the 27, no. (1977): 197–211.

—— [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Reformation of Historical Thought by A. G. Dickens, John M. Tonkin, Kenneth Powell.” History and Theory 25, no. 3 (Oct., 1986): 336–342.

Firth, C. H. “Modern History in Oxford, 1724–1841.” English Historical Review 32, no. 125 (January, 1917): 1–21.

Fite, Warner. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Lectures on Modern Idealism by Josiah Royce. Journal of Philosophy 18, no. 18 (Sep., 1921): 497–499.

Hammond, William. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Plato and Platonism by Walter Pater. Philosophical Review 3, no. 1 (Jan., 1894): 77–81.

Humboldt, Wilhelm von. “On the Historian's Task.” History and Theory 6, no. 1 (1967): 57–71.

Joy, Bill. “Why the future doesn't need us.” Wired, Issue 8.04, (April, 2000). http://www.wired.com/wired/archive/8.04/ (accessed 16 October 2007).

Lovejoy, Arthur O. “The Meaning of Vitalism.” Science 33, no. 851 (April, 1911): 610–614.

Maitland, Frederick, W. “A Prologue to a History of English Law.” Law Quarterly Review 14, (1898): 13–33.

——“William Stubbs, Bishop of Oxford.” English Historical Review 16, no. 63 (Jul., 1901): 417–426.

Miller, J. D. B. “Hancock, Mansergh and Commonwealth Surveys.” Historical Studies 13, no. 51 (Oct., 1968): 396–410.

Parsons, Talcott. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): A Critique of Max Weber's Philosophy of Social Science by W. G. Runciman. Political Science Quarterly 88, no. 2 (Jun., 1973): 345–346.

Postan, M. M. “Fact and Relevance in Historical Study.” Historical Studies 13, no. 51 (Oct., 1968): 411–425.

Powicke, F. M. “Thomas Frederick Tout, 1855–1929.” Proceedings of the British Academy. Vol. 15, 1929. London: Oxford University Press, 1936: 379–410.

——“James Tait, 1863–1944.” Proceedings of the British Academy 1944, London: Oxford University Press, 1944: 379–410.

Power, Eileen. “On Medieval History as a Social Study.” Economica 1, no. 1 (Feb., 1934): 13–29.

Sabine, George H. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Die Grenzen der Naturwissenschaftlichen Begriffsbildung. Eine Logische Einleitung in die Historischen Wissenschaften by Heinrich Rickert. Philosophical Review 23, no. 1 (Jan., 1914): 65–70.

284 Bibliography

Schiller, Friedrich von. “The Nature and Value of Universal History: An Inaugural Lecture [1789].” History and Theory 11, no. 3 (1972): 321–334.

Sinclair, Keith. “On Writing Schist.” Historical Studies 13, no. 51 (Oct., 1968): 426–432.

Smith, W. G. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Die Grenzen der Naturwissenschaftlichen Begriffsbildung. Eine Logische Einleitung in die Historischen Wissenschaften by Heinrich Rickert. Philosophical Review 8, no. 1 (Jan., 1899): 58–60.

Tait, James. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Domesday Book and Beyond: Three Essays in the Early History of England, by F. W. Maitland. English Historical Review 12, no. 48 (Oct., 1897): 768–777.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): England in the Age of Wycliffe by G. M. Trevelyan; The Peasants' Rising and the Lollards by E. Powell and G. M. Trevelyan; Les Soulevent des Travailleurs d'Angleterre en 1381 by Andre Reville and C. Petit-Dutaillis. English Historical Review 15, no. 57 (Jan., 1900): 161–165.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): History of England under Henry IV by James Hamilton Wylie. English Historical Review 9, no. 36 (Oct., 1894): 761–765.

Tawney, R. H. “The Study of Economic History.” Economica , no. 39 (Feb., 1933): 1–21.

Tolkien, J. R. R. “Beowulf: The Monsters and the Critics”. Proceedings of the British Academy. Vol. 22, 1936. London: Oxford University Press, 1937: 245–295.

Tout, T. F. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Statutes and Their Interpretation in the First Half of the Fourteenth Century by T. F. T. Plucknett. English Historical Review 38, no. 150 (Apr., 1923): 271–274.

Veblen, Thorstein B. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Der Moderne Kapitalismus by Werner Sombart. Journal of Political Economy 11, no. 2 (Mar., 1903): 300–305.

Zerffi, Gustavus George. “The Science of History: Inaugural Address.” Transactions of the Royal Historical Society 9, (1881): 1–20.

Government and Other Documents

1297.0–Australian Standard Research Classification (ASRC), 1998. http://www.abs.gov.au/Ausstats/[email protected]/0/2D3B6B2B68A6834FCA25697E0018FB2D?opendocume nt (accessed 15 November 2007).

The Allen Consulting Group. A Wealth of Knowledge: The Return on Investment from ARC-funded Research, Report to the Australian Research Council, 4 September 2003. Canberra: The Allen Consulting Group, 2003.

American Association of University Professors. “1940 Statement of Principles on Academic Freedom and Tenure.” http://www.aaup.org/NR/rdonlyres/EBB1B330-33D3-4A51-B534- CEE0C7A90DAB/0/1940StatementofPrinciplesonAcademicFreedomandTenure.pdf (accessed 1 March 2007).

——“On Freedom of Expression and Campus Speech Codes.” http://www.aaup.org/AAUP/pubsres/policydocs/contents/speechcodes.htm (accessed 1 March 2007).

Ang, Ien, Elizabeth Cassity. Attraction of Strangers: Partnerships in Humanities Research. Canberra: Australian Academy of the Humanities, 2004.

285 Bibliography

Australia, Committee on Australian Universities. Report of the Committee on Australian Universities, September, 1957. Canberra: Govt. Printer, 1958.

Australian History Curriculum Reference Group, Australian Government. Guide to the Teaching of Australian History in Years 9 and 10, 11 October 2007.

Australian Research Council. ARC Strategic Plan for 2005 to 2007. Canberra: ARC, 2005.

——Response to the Draft Research Report on Public Support for Science and Innovation, December 2006. Canberra: ARC, 2006.

——Submission to the Productivity Commission: Public Support for Science and Innovation, December 2006. Canberra: ARC, 2006.

——Summary of Discovery Projects Proposals by Primary Class Code for Funding to Commence in 2008. http://www.arc.gov.au/pdf/DP07/DP07_RFCD.pdf (accessed 23 October 2008).

Australian Science and Technology Council. Research and Technology: Future Directions; Perspectives on Industry. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service, 1992.

——Setting Directions For Australian Research: A Report to the Prime Minister by the Australian Science and Technology Council in Association with the Australian Research Council. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service, 1993.

——Bridging the Gap: The Social Sciences, Humanities, science and Technology in Economic Development. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service, 1993.

Australian Society of Accountants and The Institute of Chartered Accountants in Australia. Statement of Accounting Standards AAS 13, March 1983 Accounting for Research and Development Costs. http://www.aasb.com.au/admin/file/content102/c3/AAS13_3-83.pdf (accessed 15 November 2007).

Boeing Corporation. Charting the Course: The Boeing Company Annual Report 2006. Chicago: Boeing Corporation, 2007.

Callaghan, Daniel. “Ch. 1, Introduction: The Research Imperative; and Ch.3, Is Research a Moral Obligation? Plagues, Death and Aging”, The President’ Council on Bioethics, meeting July 2003. http://www.bioethics.gov/background/callahan_paper.html (accessed 23 August 2008).

CCI. ARC Centre of Excellence for Creative Industries and Innovation 2006 Annual Report. Kelvin Grove: CCI, 2006.

CSIRO. Strategic Plan for 2003–2007: Delivery and Execution. Canberra: CSIRO, 2003.

Commission of European Communities. Communication from the Commission: The role of the universities in the Europe of knowledge COM (2003) 58 final. Brussels: European Commission, 2003.

Council for the Humanities, Arts and Social Sciences (CHASS). Measures of Quality and Impact of Publicly Funded Research in the Humanities, Arts and Social Sciences, CHASS Occasional Paper 2. November 2005. Canberra: DEST, 2005.

Council on Competitiveness. Innovate America: National Innovation Initiative Summit and Report, 2007. http://www.innovateamerica.org/files/InnovateAmerica_EXEC%20SUM_WITH%20RECS.pdf (accessed 1 April 2007).

Dale, Shana, Remarks by the Honorable Shana Dale NASA Deputy Administrator Columbus Future Forum, February 21, 2008. http://www.nasa.gov/pdf/214030main_columbus_future_forum_FINAL_2- 22-08.pdf (accessed 23 February 2008).

286 Bibliography

Davis, Glyn. “The Search for a Stable Centre.” AFR Higher Education Conference, 13 March 2008. http://unimelb.edu.au/speeches/transcripts/davis_AFR_Higher_Ed_20080313.doc (accessed 26 March 2008).

——“The end of the gatekeeper.” Age (Melbourne), Australians All series of ‘Essays on the Nation’, 31 October 2007. http://www.theage.com.au/news/opinion/glyn- davis/2007/10/31/1193618930194.html (accessed 29 April 2008).

——“Institutions as Ideas: Change at the University of Melbourne.” 2006 Redmond Barry Lecture, University of Melbourne. www.unimelb.edu.au/speeches/ (accessed 29 April 2008).

——and Geoff Sharrock. Growing Esteem: Choices for the University of Melbourne. Parkville: University of Melbourne, 2005.

Dawkins, J. S. Higher Eucation: a policy discussion paper. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service, 1987.

——Higher Eucation: A Policy Statement. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service, 1988.

Dearing, Sir Ron. Introduction to Higher Education in the Learning Society; Report. http://www.leeds.ac.uk/educol/ncihe/ (accessed 3 June 2008).

Department of Education, Employment and Workplace Relations. Review of Australian Higher Education, Discussion Paper, June 2008. http://www.dest.gov.au/HEreview(accessed 23 June 2008).

[UK] Department for Education and Skills. The Future of Higher Education. London: HMSO, 2003.

Department of Education, Science and Training. Research Quality Framework: Assessing the quality and impact of research in Australia Issues Paper, March 2005. Canberra: DEST, 2005.

——Research Quality Framework: Assessing the Quality and Impact of Research in Australia: The Preferred Model, September 2005. Canberra: DEST, 2005.

——New Knowledge, New Opportunities: A Discussion Paper on Higher Education Research and Research Training, June 1999. Canberra: DEST, 1999.

——Knowledge and Innovation: A policy Statement on Research and Research Training, December 1999. Canberra: DEST, 1999.

——Humanities and Social Sciences Futures Papers from the National Humanities and Social Sciences Summit held in July 2001. Edited by Malcolm Gillies, Mark Carroll and John Dash. Canberra: DEST, 2001.

——National Research Priorities: Report to Government. Canberra: DEST, 2007.

——Emerging Issues for Cross-Disciplinary Research:Conceptual and Empirical Dimensions, May 2003. Canberra: DEST, 2003.

——Evaluation of Knowledge and Innovation Reforms Consultation Report, March 2004. Canberra: DEST, 2004.

——The Final Report of the National Research Infrastructure Taskforce, March 2004. Canberra: DEST, 2004.

——New Knowledge, New Opportunities: A Discussion Paper on Higher Education Research and Research Training. Canberra: Commonwealth of Australia, 1999.

Department of Innovation, Industry, Science and Research. Collaborating to a Purpose: Review of the Cooperative Research Centres Program, July 2008. Canberra: DIISR, 2008.

287 Bibliography

Domestic Policy Council, Office of Science and Technology Policy. American Competitiveness Initiative: Leading the World in Innovation, February 2006. http://www.whitehouse.gov/stateoftheunion/2006/aci/ (accessed 1 April 2007).

Economic and Social Research Council. Postgraduate Training Guidelines. 4th Edition. 2005. http://www.esrcsocietytoday.ac.uk/ESRCInfoCentre/opportunities/postgraduate/pgtrainingpolicy/ (accessed 30 January 2008).

European Commission. The Sixth Framework Programme in brief. December 2002 Edition. Brussels: European Commission, 2002. http://ec.europa.eu/research/fp6/pdf/fp6-in-brief_en.pdf (accessed 21 December 2008).

Gibbons, Michael. “What Kind of University? Research and Teaching in the 21st century.” 1997 Beanland lecture, Victoria University of Technology. http://www.scribd.com/doc/34280/Research-and- teaching-in-the-21st-century (accessed 9 May 2007).

Group of Eight. Seizing the opportunities: A Group of Eight policy discussion paper, 6 June 2007. http://www.go8.edu.au/storage/go8statements/2007/Seizing_the_Opportunities_Full_060607.pdf (accessed 26 March 2008).

Information Futures Commission, University of Melbourne. Scholarly Information in a Digital Age: choices for the University of Melbourne. www.informationfutures.unimelb.edu.au/consultation- paper.html (accessed 3 March 2008).

Jaruzelski, Barry, Kevin Dehoff, and Rakesh Bordia. Smart Spenders: The Global Innovation 1000. New York: Booz Allen Hamilton, 2006. http://www.strategy- business.com/press/article/06405?gko=c3340-1876-20606671 (accessed 20 August 2008).

Knowledge Nation Taskforce. An Agenda for the Knowledge Nation. Canberra: Chifley Research Centre, 2001.

Lockheed Martin Corporation. Lockheed Martin Corporation 2006 Annual Report. Bethesda: Lockheed Martin, 2007.

Metcalfe, Jenni, Michelle Riedlinger, Anne Pisarski and John Gardner. CHASS Occasional Papers; Collaborating Across the Sectors: The Relationships between the humanities, arts and social sciences (HASS) and science, technology, engineering and medicine (STEM) sectors, November 2006. Canberra: Council for Humanities, Arts and Social Sciences, 2006.

NASA Institute for Advanced Concepts. NASA Institute for Advanced Concepts 6th Annual Report, July 2004. Atlanta: NIAC, 2004.

[US] National Academy of Sciences, National Academy of Engineering, Institute of Medicine. Executive Summary; Rising Above the Gathering Storm: Energizing and Employing America for a Brighter Economic Future, (2007). http://sciencedems.house.gov/Media/File/Reports/natacad_compete_exsum_6feb06.pdf (accessed 1 April 2007).

National Board of Employment, Education and Training. Using Basic Research: Assessing Connections between Basic Research and National Socio-economic Objectives, Part 1: Review of Current Theory and International Practices, Commissioned Report No. 36, March 1995. Canberra: AGPS, 1995.

Nerad, Maresi.” From Doctoral Student to World Citizen: the Chance for Innovative Doctoral Education.” Miegunyah Lecture, 16 February 2005, University of Melbourne. http://depts.washington.edu/cirgeweb/c/wp-content/uploads/2008/07/from-doc-citizen-to-world-citizen- miegunyah.pdf (accessed 14 July 2005).

Nokia Corporation. Nokia in 2005: Review by the Board of Directors and Nokia Annual Accounts 2005. Espoo: Nokia Corporation, 2006.

288 Bibliography

——United States Securities and Exchange Commission Form 20F 2007, Nokia. 20 March 2008.

——United States Securities and Exchange Commission Form 20F 2006, Nokia. 12 March 2007.

Office of the Director of Defense Research and Engineering. Project Hindsight: Final Report, October 1969. Washington: US DoD, 1969.

Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development, Eurostat. Oslo Manual: Guidelines for the Collecting and Interpreting Innovation Data. 3rd edition. Paris: OECD and Eurostat, 2005.

Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD). Frascati Manual: Proposed Standard Practice for Surveys on Research and Experimental Development, 2002. http://www.oecdbookshop.org/oecd/display.asp?lang=EN&sf1=identifiers&st1=922002081p1 (accessed 5 January 2007).

Prime Minister’s Science, Engineering and Innovation Council) Working Group, Imagine Australia: The Role of Creativity in the Innovative Economy. Canberra: PMSEIC, 2005.

Productivity Commission. Public Support for Science and Innovation: Research Report, 9 March 2007. Canberra: Productivity Commission, 2007.

The President’ Council on Bioethics. Session 5: Enhancement 1: Therapy vs. Enhancement. Meeting Transcript, April 26, 2002. http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/apr02/apr26session5.html (accessed 23 August 2008).

——Session 3: Human Nature and Its Future. Meeting Transcript, March 6, 2003. http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/march03/session3.html (accessed 23 August 2008).

——Session 1:”Beyond Therapy": Council's Report to the President. Meeting Transcript, October 16, 2003. : http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/oct03/session1.html (accessed 16 September 2008).

——Session 3: Neuroscience, Neuropsychiatry and Neuroethics: An Overview. Meeting Transcript, January 15, 2004. http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/jan04/session3.html (accessed 22 September 2008).

——Being Human: Readings from the President's Council on Bioethics, Chapter 10: Human Dignity, Introduction. http://www.bioethics.gov/bookshelf/reader/chapter10.html (accessed 22 September 2008).

——Being Human: Readings from the President's Council on Bioethics, Chapter 4: Are We Our Bodies? Introduction. http://www.bioethics.gov/bookshelf/reader/chapter4.html#introduction (accessed 22 September 2008).

——Human Dignity and Bioethics: Essays Commissioned by the President’s Council on Bioethics, March 2008. Washington DC: The President’ Council on Bioethics, 2008.

——Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness; A Report of the President’ Council on Bioethics, 15 October 2003. Washington DC: The President’ Council on Bioethics, 2003.

The University of Melbourne. Growing Esteem: The University of Melbourne Strategic Plan 2006. Parkville: The University of Melbourne, 2006.

——Growing Esteem: Choices for the University of Melbourne: A discussion paper, July 2005. Parkville: The University of Melbourne, 2005.

The World Bank. Constructing Knowledge Societies: New Challenges for Tertiary Education. Washington, DC: The World Bank, 2002. http://publications.worldbank.org/ecommerce/catalog/product?item_id=1044791 (accessed 21 December 2008).

289 Bibliography

United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO). The International Standard Classification of Education (ISCED) 1997. Paris: UNESCO, 2006.

Ungaro, Peter. “How Does An Idea Get Off The Ground? The Interplay Between Innovation, Research and Financial Markets”. Presentation to CRC08 Cooperative Research Centres Association Annual Conference 2008, 21-23 May 2008, Sydney. http://www.crca.asn.au/search/node/Peter%20Ungaro (accessed 23 October 2008).

VenturousAustralia: Building Strength in Innovation [Review of the National Innovation System Report]. North Melbourne: Cutler & Company, 2008.

Warwick, Baroness. “Introductory Paper.” The Future of Higher Education: Dilemmas and Opportunities Conference, Cumberland Lodge, Windsor 28 July-3 August 2003. http://www.21stcenturytrust.org/warwick.html (accessed 3 June 2008).

Wilkinson, James. “‘Undergraduate Education: What Good is it? An International Perspective.” Menzies Oration on Higher Education, The University of Melbourne, 11 July 2006. http://www.unimelb.edu.au/speeches/menziesoration.html (accessed 31 July 2006).

Secondary Sources

Monographs

Agamben, Giorgio. Infancy and History: Essays on the Destruction of Experience. Trans. Liz Heron. London: Verso, 1993.

Althusser, Louis. Essays in Self-Criticism. Trans. Grahame Lock. London: NLB; Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press, 1976.

Anderson, Perry. Arguments Within English Marxism. London: NLB, 1980.

——The Origins of Postmodernity. London: Verso, 1998.

Ankersmit, F. R. History and Tropology: The Rise and Fall of Metaphor. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994.

——Sublime Historical Experience. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005.

Arendt, Hannah. The Human Condition. 2nd ed. London: The University of Chicago Press, 1998.

——and Martin Heidegger. Letters: 1925–1975. Edited by Ursula Ludz. Orlando: Harcourt Inc. 2004.

Arnold, Matthew. Selected Poetry and Prose. Edited by Frederick L. Mulhauser. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1962.

Baldi, Pierre. The Shattered Self: The End of Natural Selection. Trans. Andrew Shields. Cambridge: The MIT Press, 2001.

Barnett, Ronald. Realizing the University in an Age of Supercomplexity. Buckingham: The Society for Research into Higher Education & Open University Press, 2000.

Baudrillard, Jean. Jean Baudrillard: Selected Writings. 2nd ed. Edited by Mark Poster. Oxford: Polity Press & Blackwell Publishers, 2001.

290 Bibliography

Becher, Tony and Paul, R. Trowler. Academic Tribes and Territories: Intellectual Enquiry and the Culture of Disciplines. Buckingham: SRHE and Open University Press, 2001.

Beillharz, Peter. Imagining the Antipodes: Culture, Theory and the Visual in the Work of Bernard Smith. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.

Ben-David, Joseph. Centers of Learning: Britain, France, Germany, United States. 2nd ed. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1992.

Bendix, Reinhard. Force, Fate, and Freedom: On Historical Sociology. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984.

Bennett, M. R. and P. M. S. Hacker. Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. Malden MA: Blackwell Publishing, 2003.

Bentley, Michael. Modernizing England's Past: English Historiography in the Age of Modernism, 1870–1970. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005.

Berg, Maxine. A Woman in History: Eileen Power, 1889–1940. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

Berkhofer, Robert F. Jnr. Beyond the Great Story: History as Text and Discourse. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1995.

Berlin, Isaiah. Against the Current: Essays in the History of Ideas. Edited by Hardy, Henry. London: Pimlico, 1979.

——Vico and Herder: Two Studies in the History of Ideas. London: Chatto & Windus, 1980.

——Three Critics of the Enlightenement: Vico, Hamann, Herder. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000.

——The Roots of Romanticism. London: Chatto & Windus, 1999.

——Isaiah Berlin: The Power of Ideas. Edited by Henry Hardy. London: Chatto & Windus, 2000.

Bernstein, Richard J. The New Constellation: The Ehical–Political Horizons of Modernity/Postmodernity. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991.

——Philosophical Profiles: Essays in a Pragmatic Mode. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1986.

——Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983.

Blumenberg, Hans. Work on Myth. Trans. Robert M. Wallace. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 1990.

——The Legitimacy of the Modern Age. Trans. Robert M. Wallace. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 1983.

Borradori, Giovanna. Philosophy in a Time of Terror: Dialogues with Jürgen Habermas and Jacques Derrida. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2003.

Bousma, William J. A Usable Past: Essays in European Cultural History. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990.

Bowers, C. A. Elements of a Post-Liberal Theory of Education. New York: Teachers College Press, 1987.

Bowker, Geoffrey C. and Susan Leigh Star. Sorting Things Out: Classification and Its Consequences. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 1999.

291 Bibliography

Braudel, Fernand. On History. Trans. Sarah Matthews. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1980.

Bredeck, Elizabeth. Metaphors of Knowledge: Language and Thought in Mauthner's Critique. Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 1992.

Briggs, Asa. The Map of Learning:. Canberra: The Australian National University, 1961.

——Victorian Cities. London: Penguin Books, 1990.

Brock, Dan W. Life and Death: Philosophical Essays in Biomedical Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.

Buchanan, Allen. Ethics, Efficiency, and the Market. Totowa: Rowman & Allanheld, 1985.

Burke, Peter. History and Social Theory. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1994.

Cairns-Smith, A. G. Evolving Mind: On the Nature of Matter and Origin of Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

Cannadine, David. G. M. Trevelyan: A Life in History. London: HarperCollinsPublishers, 1992.

Cannon, Susan Faye. Science in Culture: The Early Victorian Period. New York: Science History Publications, 1978.

Carre, Meyrick H. Phases of Thought in England. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949.

Cassirer, Ernst. An Essay on Man: An Introduction to a Philosophy of Human Culture. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1945.

Chakrabarty, Dipesh. Habitations of Modernity: Essays in the Wake of Subaltern Studies. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2002.

Chandler, James. England in 1819: The Politics of Literary Culture and the Case of Romanticism. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1998.

Changeux, Jean-Pierre and Paul Ricoeur. What Makes Us Think: A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain. Trans. M. B. DeBevoise. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000.

Clark, Elizabeth A. History, Theory, Text: Historians and the Linguistic Turn. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 2004.

Cohen, L. Jonathan. An Essay on Belief and Acceptance. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992.

Colley, Linda. Lewis Namier. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1989.

Collini, Stefan, Donald Winch and John Burrow. That Noble Science: A Study in Nineteenth-Century Intellectual history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983.

Connolly, William, E. Political Theory and Modernity. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1988.

——The Ethos of Pluralization. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996.

——Neuropolitics: Thinking, Culture, Speed. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2002.

Corngold, Stanley. Complex Pleasure: Forms of Feeling in German Literature. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998.

292 Bibliography

Crawford, R. M. 'A Bit of a Rebel': The Life and Work of George Arnold Wood. Sydney: Sydney University Press, 1975.

Culler, A. Dwight. The Imperial Intellect: A Study of Newman's Educational Ideal. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1955.

Culler, Jonathan. Framing the Sign: Criticism and its Institutions. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1988.

Currie, George and John Graham. The Origins of the CSIRO: Science and the Commonwealth Government 1901–1926. Melbourne: Commonwealth Scientific and Industrial Research Organization, 1966.

Dale, Leigh. The English Men: Professing Literature in Australian Universities. Toowoomba: Association for the Study of , 1997.

Dallmayr, Fred. Life-world, Modernity and Critique: Paths Between Heidegger and the Frankfurt School. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991.

Damasio, Antonio, R. Descartes' Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. London: Picador, 1994.

——The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. New York: Harcourt, 2000.

——Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain. Orlando: Harcourt Inc. 2003.

D'Amico, Robert. Historicism and Knowledge. New York: Routledge, 1989.

——Contemporary Continental Philosophy. Boulder: Westview Press, 1999.

Davison, Graeme. Australia: The First Postmodern Republic. Edited by Tom Griffiths and David Lowe. London: University of London, 1995.

——The Use and Abuse of Australian History. St. Leonards: Allen & Unwin, 2000.

DeLaura, David. Hebrew and Hellene in Victorian England: Newman, Arnold, and Pater. Austin & London: University of Texas Press, 1969.

Deleuze, Gilles, Guattari, Felix. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota Press, 1987.

Deleuze, Gilles. Pure Immanence: Essays on A Life. Trans. Anne Boyman. New York: Zone Books, 2001.

Dennett, Daniel C. Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 1981.

——Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1995.

Denton, Derek. The Pinnacle of Life: Consciousness and Self-awareness in Humans and Animals. St. Leonards: Allen & Unwin, 1993.

Derrida, Jacques. Positions. 2nd ed. Trans. Alan Bass. London: Continuum, 2002.

Donagan, Alan. The Later Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962.

Dretske, Fred. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 1995.

293 Bibliography

Dupre, Louis. The Enlightenment and the Intellectual Foundations of Modern Culture. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004.

During, Simon. Modern Enchantments: The Cultural Power of Secular Magic. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 2002.

Eagleton, Terry. The Illusions of Postmodernism. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1996.

Edwards, J. G. William Stubbs. London: The Historical Association, 1952.

Elton, G. R. F. W. Maitland. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1985.

England, J. Merton. A Patron for Pure Science: The National Science Foundation's Formative Years, 1945–57. Washington, D.C.: National Science Foundation, 1982.

Ermarth, Michael. Wilhelm Dilthey: The Critique of Historical Reason. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1978.

Fasolt, Constantin. The Limits of History. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2004.

Ferrell, Robyn. Copula: Sexual Technologies, Reproductive Powers. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2006.

Feyerabend, Paul. Farewell to Reason. London: Verso, 1993.

Flax, Jane. Disputed Subjects: Essays on Psychoanalysis, politics and philosophy. New York: Routledge, 1993.

Fogel, Robert William and G. R. Elton. Which Road to the Past? Two Views of History. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1983.

Foster, S. G. and Margaret M. Varghese. The Making of The Australian National University. St. Leonards: Allen & Unwin, 1996.

Frederick, Ferre. Living and Value: Toward a Constructive Postmodern Ethics. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2001.

Freeman, Derek. Dilthey's Dream: Essays on Human Nature and Culture. Canberra: Pandanus Books, 2001.

Friedman, Michael. Reconsidering Logical Positivism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.

Fuchs, Stephan. Against Essentialism: A Theory of Culture and Society. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 2001.

Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Truth and Method. 2nd, Revised Edition. London, New York: Contimuum, 2004.

Galbally, Ann. Redmond Barry. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1995.

Gallagher, Catherine and Stephen Greenblatt. Practicing New Historicism. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2000.

Gallie, W. B. Philosophy and Historical Understanding. London: Chatto & Windus, 1964.

Gardner, Howard. The Mind's New Science: A History of the Cognitive Revolution. New York: Basic Books, 1987.

——Multiple Intelligences: The Theory in Practice. New York: Basic Books, 1993.

294 Bibliography

——Extraordinary Minds: Portraits of Exceptional Individuals and an Examination of Our Extraordinariness. New York: Basic Books, 1997.

——Intelligence Reframed: Multiple Intelligences for the 21st Century. New York: Basic Books, 1999.

Garrett-Jones, Sam, Tim Turpin, Joan Bellavista and Steven Hill. Using Basic Research: Commissioned Report No. 36. : National Board of Employment, Education and Training, 1995.

Geertz, Clifford. The Interpretation of Cultures. London: Hutchinson & Co. 1975.

——After the Fact: Two Countries, Four Decades, One Anthropologist. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1995.

Geiger, Roger L. Knowledge and money: Research Universities and the Paradox of the Marketplace. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004.

Gibbons, Michael, Camille Limoges, Helga Nowotny, Simon Schwartzman, Peter Scott and Martin Trow. The New Production of Knowledge: The Dynamics of Science and Research in Contemporary Societies. London: Sage Publications, 1994.

Goehr, Lydia. The Quest for Voice: On Music, Politics, and the Limits of Philosophy. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998.

Goldmann, Lucien. The Philosophy of the Enlightenment: The Christian Burgess and the Enlightenment. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1973.

Gossman, Lionel. Between History and Literature. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1990.

——Basel in the Age of Burckhardt: A Study in Unseasonable Ideas. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2000.

Gray, John. Heresies. London: Granta Books, 2004.

Grumley, John, E. History and Totality: Radical historicism from Hegel to Foucault. London: Routledge, 1989.

Habermas, Jürgen. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures. Trans. Frederick Lawrence. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1987.

——Autonomy and Solidarity: Interviews with Jürgen Habermas. 2nd ed. Edited by Dews, Peter. London: Verso, 1992.

——Postmetaphysical Thinking: Philosophical Essays. Trans. William Mark Hohengarten. Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1994.

——The Liberating Power of Symbols: Philosophical Essays. Trans. Peter Drew. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2001.

——Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God, and Modernity. Edited by Mendieta, Eduardo. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002.

——The Future of Human Nature. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003.

Hacking, Ian. Historical Ontology. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 2002.

Hagberg, G. L. Meaning & Interpretation: Wittgenstein, Henry James, and Literary Knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994.

Halsey, A. H. Decline of Donnish Dominion: The British Academic Professions in the Twentieth Century. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992.

295 Bibliography

Haraway, Donna. Primate Visions: Gender, Race, and Nature in the World of Modern Science. New York: Verso, 1992.

Hayek, F. A. New studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1978.

Hayles, N. Katherine. How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature, and Informatics. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1999.

Helgeby, Stein. Action as History: The Historical Thought of R. G. Collingwood. Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2004.

Heyck, T. W. The Transformation of Intellectual Life in Victorian England. London: Croon Helm, 1982.

Hobsbawm, Eric. On History. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1997.

Hofstadter, Richard. Anti-intellectualism in American life. London: Jonathon Cape, 1964.

Holbrook, David. Evolution and the Humanities. Aldershot: Gower Publishing Company, 1987.

Holme, E. R. The American University: An Australian View. Sydney: Angus & Robertson, 1920.

Hooley, Graham, John Saunders and Nigel Piercy. Marketing Strategy and Competitive Positioning. 3rd ed. Harlow: Peason Education Limited, 2004.

Horkheimer, Max and Theodor W Adorno. Dialectic of Enlightenment. Trans. John Cumming. New York: Continuum, 1993.

Hughes, H. Stuart. Consciousness and Society: The Reorientation of European Thought 1890–1930. London: Macgibbon & Kee, 1959.

Hunter, Ian, Denise Meredyth, Bruce Smith and Geoff Stokes. Accounting for the Humanities: The Language of Culture and the Logic of Government. Brisbane: Institute for Cultural Policy Studies, 1991.

Hunter, Ian. Rival Enlightenments: Civil and Metaphysical Philosophy in Early Modern Germany. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.

Iggers, Georg, G. The German Conception of History: The National Tradition of Historical Thought from Herder to the Present. Revised ed. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press, 1983.

International Conference on the Unity of Science. The Search for Absolute Values: Harmony Among the Science. Vol I.: Proceedings of the Fifth International Conference on the Unity of the Sciences, November 26–28, 1976; Washington, D. C. New York: The International Cultural Foundation Press, 1977.

Israel, Jonathan. Enlightenment Contested: Philosophy, Modernity, and the Emancipation of Man 1670–1752. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.

Jameson, Frederic. Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism. New York: Verso, 1992.

Jann, Rosemary. The Art and Science of Victorian History. Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1985.

Jay, Martin. The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social research 1923–1950. Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1973.

296 Bibliography

——Marxism and Totality: The Adventures of a Concept from Lukacs to Habermas. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984.

——Force Fields: Between Intellectual History and Cultural Critique. New York: Routledge, 1993.

——Songs of Experience: Modern American and European Variations on a Universal Theme. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2005.

Johnson, Mark. The Meaning of the Body: Aesthetics of Human Understanding. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2007.

Jonas, Hans. The Gnostic Religion: The Message of an Alien God and the Beginnings of Christianity. Beacon Hill: Beacon Press, 1963.

——Philosophical Essays: From Ancient Creed to Technological Man. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1974.

——The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age. Trans. Hans Jonas with the collaboration of David Herr. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1984.

Kargon, Robert H. Science in Victorian Manchester: Enterprise and Expertise. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1977.

Kelley, Donald R. The Human Measure: Social Thought in the Western Legal Tradition. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1990.

——The Descent of Ideas: The History of Intellectual History. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing, 2002.

Kellner Douglas. Jean Baudrillard: From Marxism to Postmodernism and Beyond. Oxford: Polity Press, 1989.

Kenyon, John. The History Men: The Historical Profession in England since the Renaissance. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1983.

Kerr, Clark. The Uses of the University. 4th ed. Cambridge MA.: Harvard University Press, 1995.

Kloppenberg, James, T. Uncertain Victory: and Progressivism in European and American Thought, 1870–1920. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Koselleck, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Trans. Keith Tribe. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 1985.

——The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing Concepts. Trans. Todd Samuel Presner and Others. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002.

Krieger, Leonard. Ranke: The Meaning of History. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1977.

——Time's Reasons: Philophies of History Old and New. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1989.

Kuhn, Thomas S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1970.

La Nauze, John. Walter Murdoch: A Biographical Memoir. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1977.

——: Two Lectures. Brisbane: Press, 1960.

LaCapra, Dominick. Rethinking Intellectual History: Texts, Contents, Language. London: Cornell University Press, 1983.

297 Bibliography

——History in Transit: Experience, Identity, Critical Theory. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2004.

Lang, Berel. Heidegger's Silence. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996.

Latour, Bruno. Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.

Lepenies, Wolf. Between Literature and Science: The Rise of Sociology. Trans. R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.

Levine, Philippa. The Amateur and the Professional: Antiquarians, Historians and Archaeologists in Victorian England, 1838–1886. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986.

Levi-Strauss, Claude. Structural Anthropology. London: Penguin Books, 1993.

Levy, David J. Hans Jonas: The Integrity of Thinking. Columbia: University of Missouri Press, 2002.

——Political Order: Philosophical Anthropology, Modernity, and the Challenge of Ideology. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State university Press, 1987.

Lodge, David. Consciousness and the Novel: Connected Essays. London: Secker & Warburg, 2002.

Loesberg, Jonathan. Aestheticism and Deconstruction. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1991.

Lowith, Karl. Martin Heidegger and European Nihilism. Edited by Richard Wolin. Trans. Gary Steiner. New York: Columbia University Press, 1995.

Lucy, Niall. Debating Derrida. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1995.

Luft, Sandra Rudnick. Vico's Uncanny Humanism: Reading the New Science between Modern and Postmodern. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2003.

Luhmann, Niklas. Essays on Self-Reference. New York: Columbia University Press, 1990.

——Social Systems. Trans. John Bednarz, Jr. with Dirk Baecker. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1995.

——Observations on Modernity. Trans. William Whobrey. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998.

——Theories of Distinction: Redescribing the Descriptions of Modernity. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002.

Lukacs, Georg. History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics. Trans. Rodney Livingstone. London: Merlin Press, 1971.

——Soul and Form. Trans. Anna Bostock. London: Merlin Press, 1974.

——The Destruction of Reason. Trans. Peter Palmer. London: The Merlin Press, 1980.

Lukacs, John. Historical Consciousness: Or the Remembered Past. New York: Schocken Books, 1985.

Lyotard, Jean-Francois. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989.

Macfarlane, Alan. The Origins of English Individualism: The Family, Property and Social Transition. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1978.

——F. W. Maitland and the Making of the Modern World. www.alanmacfarlane.com/TEXTS/Maitland_final.pdf (accessed 19 July 2008).

298 Bibliography

Macgregor, Duncan, Andrew Leigh, David Madden, and Peter Tynan. Imagining Australia: Ideas for Our Future. Crows Nest: Allen & Unwin, 2004.

Macintyre, Alasdair. After Virtue. London: Duckworth, 1981.

Macintyre, Stuart. Colonial Liberalism: The Lost World of Three Victorian Visionaries. Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1991.

——A History for a Nation: Ernest Scott and the Making of Australian History. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1994.

——and Anna Clark. The . Carlton: Melbourne University Publishing, 2003.

——and R. J. W. Selleck. A Short History of the University of Melbourne. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 2003.

Makkreel, Rudolph, A. Dilthey: Philosopher of the Human Studies. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975.

Mannheim, Karl. Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge. London: Routledge, 1991.

——Essays on the Sociology of Culture. Edited by Ernest Manheim and Paul Kecskemeti. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1971.

Marchand, Suzanne L. Down from Olympus: Archaeology and Philhellenism in Germany, 1750–1970. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996.

Marginson, Simon. Education and Public Policy in Australia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.

——Remaking the University: Monash. St. Leonards: Allen & Unwin, 2000.

——and Mark Considine. The Enterprise University: Power, Governance and Reinvention in Australia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.

Markus, Julia. J. Anthony Froude: The Last Undiscovered Great Victorian. New York: Scribner, 2005.

Mathews, Freya. The Ecological Self. London: Routledge, 1991.

McClelland, Charles, E. The German Historians and England: A Study in Nineteenth-Century Views. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971.

McIntire, C. T. Herbert Butterfield: Historian as Dissenter. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004.

McNeill, William H. Mythistory and Other Essays. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1986.

McPhee, Peter. 'Pansy': A Life of Roy Douglas Wright. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1999.

Mead, George, H. Movements in Thought in the Nineteenth Century. 6th ed. Edited by Merritt H. Moore. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1956.

Medawar, P. B. The Art of the Soluble. London: Methuen, 1968.

——Induction and Intuition in Scientific Thought. London: Methuen, 1969.

Megill, Allan. Prophets of Extremity: Nietzsche, Heidegger, Foucault, Derrida. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985.

Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Signs. Evanston Ill: Northwestern University Press, 1964.

299 Bibliography

——The Structure of Behaviour. Boston: Beacon Press, 1967.

Metz, Rudolph. A Hundred Years of British Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1938.

Meyer, Leonard B. Music, The Arts, and Ideas: Patterns and Predictions in Twentieth-Century Culture. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1994.

Mink, Louis, O. Historical Understanding. Edited by Brian Fay, Eugene O. Golob, Richard T. Van. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1987.

Mintzberg, Henry, Bruce Ahlstrand, and Joseph Lampel. Strategy safari: A guided Tour through the Wilds of Strategic Management. Hemel Hempstead: Prentice Hall Europe, 1998.

Moore, Walter. Schrodinger: Life and Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989.

Muirhead, John, H. Coleridge as Philosopher. Bristol: Thoemmes Press, 1992.

Neuhouser, Frederick. Fichte's Theory of Subjectivity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.

Norton, Andrew. The Unchained University. St. Leonards: The Centre for Independent Studies, 2002.

Novick, Peter. That Noble Dream: The”Objectivity Question”and the American Historical Profession. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.

Nowotny, Helga, Peter Scott and Michael Gibbons. Re-Thinking Science: Knowledge and the Public in an Age of Uncertainty. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2001.

Nussbaum, Martha C. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.

Oakeshott, Michael. Experience and Its Modes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1966.

——On History and Other Essays. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1983.

O'Flaherty, James C. Johann Georg Hamann. Boston: Twayne Publishers, 1979.

Ogden, C. K. and I. A. Richards. The Meaning of Meaning: A Study of The Influence of Language upon Thought and of The Science of Symbolism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969.

Olsen, Stein Haugom. The End of Literary Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987.

Omnes, Roland. Quantum Philosophy: Understanding and Interpreting Contemporary Science. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999.

——Converging Realities: Toward a Common Philosophy of Physics and Mathematics. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005.

Orsini, G. N. G. Coleridge and German Idealism: A Study in the History of Philosophy with Unpublished Materials from Coleridge's Manuscripts. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1969.

Osmond, Warren G. Frederic Eggleston: An Intellectual in Australian Politics. North Sydney: Allen & Unwin, 1985.

Owen, David. Maturity and Modernity: Nietzsche, Weber, Foucault and the Ambivalence of Reason. London: Routledge, 1994.

Parsons, Talcott and Gerald M. Platt. The American University. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1973.

300 Bibliography

Pascoe, Rob. The Manufacture of Australian History. Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1979.

Passmore, John. A Hundred Years of Philosophy. Middlesex: Penguin Books, 1986.

——Recent Philosophers. London: Gerald Duckwort, 1988.

——Serious Art: A Study of the Concept in All the Major Arts. London: Duckworth, 1991.

Pater, Walter. The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry; The 1893 Text. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980.

Pippin, Robert B. The Persistence of Subjectivity: On the Kantian Aftermath. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005.

——Idealism as Modernism: Hegelian Variations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.

——Modernism as a Philosophical Problem: On the Dissatisfactions of European High Culture. Cambridge MA: Basil Blackwell, 1991.

Plumb, J. H. Crisis in the Humanities. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1964.

Poynter, John and Carolyn Rasmussen. A Place Apart: The University of Melbourne: Decades of Challenge. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1996.

Price, Huw. Time's Arrow & Archimedes Point: New Directions in the Physics of Time. New York: Oxford University Press, 1996.

Quine, W. V. Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press, 1969.

Readings, Bill. The University in Ruins. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1996.

Redford, Arthur. Manchester Merchants and Foreign Trade 1850–1939. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1956.

Reill, Peter Hanns. The German Enlightenment and the Rise of Historicism. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1975.

——Vitalizing Nature in the Enlightenment. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2005.

Reuben, Julie A. The Making of the Modern University: Intellectual Transformation and the Marginalization of Morality. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1996.

Rich, David Z. The Dynamics of Knowledge: A Contemporary View. New York: Greenwood Press, 1988.

Richardson, Alan W. Carnap's Construction of the World: The Aufbau and the Emergence of Logical Empiricism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

Richter, Melvin. The Politics of Conscience: T. H. Greeen and His Age. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1964.

——The History of Political and Social Concepts: A Critical Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press, 1995.

Rickman, H. P. Dilthey Today: A Critical Appraisal of the Contemporary Relevance of His Work. Westport: Greenwood Press, 1988.

Ricoeur, Paul. Oneself as Another. Trans. Kathleen Blamey. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1992.

301 Bibliography

Robbins, Bruce. Secular Vocations: Intellectuals, Professionalism, Culture. London: Verso, 1993.

Roberts, David D. Nothing but History: Reconstruction and Extremity after Metaphysics. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995.

Rorty, Richard. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979.

——Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989.

——Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.

——Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers. Vol. 3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

——Philosophy and Social Hope. London: Penguin Books, 1999.

——and Gianni Vattimo. The Future of Religion. Edited by Santiago Zabala. New York: Columbia University Press, 2005.

Rose, Philip. On Whitehead. Belmont: Wadsworth, 2002.

Rosenberg, Jay F. Thinking About Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.

Roszak, Theodore. The Making of a Counter Culture: Reflections on the Technochratic Society and its Youthful Opposition. London: Faber and Faber, 1968.

Rothblatt, Sheldon. The Revolution of the Dons: Cambridge and Society in Victorian England. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968.

——Tradition and Change in English Liberal Education: An Essay in History and Culture. London: Faber and Faber, 1976.

——The Idea of the Idea of a University and its Antithesis. Bundoora: La Trobe University, 1989.

Rowlands, Mark. The Nature of Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.

Russell, Bertrand. History of Western Philosophy and Its Connection with Political and Social Circumstances from Earliest Times to the Present Day. 2nd ed. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1969.

Sandys, John Edwin. A History of Classical Scholarship. Vol. 3. New York: Hafner Publishing Company, 1967.

Schluchter, Wolfgang. Paradoxes of Modernity: Culture and Conduct in the Theory of Max Weber. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1996.

Schnadelbach, Herbert. Philosophy in Germany, 1831–1933. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984.

Schneewind, J. B. The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Moral Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

Schneider, Mark, A. Culture and Enchantment. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1993.

Scott, Peter. The Crisis of the University. Beckinham: Croon Helm, 1984.

Seager, William. Metaphysics and Consciousness. London: Routledge, 1991.

Searle, John R. The Construction of Social Reality. New York: The Free Press, 1995.

302 Bibliography

——Consciousness and Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.

Seigel, Jerrold. The Idea of the Self: Thought and Experience in Western Europe since the Seventeenth Century. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005.

Selleck, R. J. W. The Shop: The University of Melbourne 1850–1939. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 2003.

Sengoopta, Chandak. Otto Weininger: Sex, Science, and Self in Imperial Vienna. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2000.

Serres, Michel. Hermes: Literature, Science, Philosophy. Edited by Josue V. Harari, David F. Bell. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1982.

——The Natural Contract. Trans. Elizabeth MacArthur and William Paulson. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 1995.

——and Bruno Latour. Conversations on Science, Culture, and Time. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 1995.

Slee, Peter, R. H. Learning and a Liberal Education: The Study of Modern History in the Universities of Oxford, Cambridge, and Manchester, 1800–1914. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1986.

Smith, Barbara Herrnstein. Belief and Resistance: Dynamics of Contemporary Intellectual Controversy. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1997.

——Scandalous Knowledge: Science, Truth and the Human. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2005.

Smith, Bernard. The Antipodean Manifesto: Essays in Art and History. Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1976.

Smith, David Woodruff. Mind World: Essays in Phenomenology and Ontology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.

Smith, Roger. Inhibition: History and Meaning in the Sciences of the Mind and Brain. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992.

Soffer, Reba N. Discipline and Power: The University, History, and Making of an English Elite, 1870– 1930. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1994.

Southard, Robert. Droysen and The Prussian School of History. Lexington: The University of Kentucky Press, 1995.

Southern, R. W. History and Historians: Selected Papers of R. W. Southern. Edited by R. J. Bartlett. Malden MA: Blackwell Publishing, 2004.

Stirk, Peter M. R. Max Horkheimer: A New Interpretation. Hemel Hempstead: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1992.

Symonds, Richard. Oxford and Empire: The Last Lost Cause. Houndmills: The Macmillan Press, 1986.

Taylor, Charles. Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers. Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.

——Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1989.

——Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1995.

303 Bibliography

Thomasson, Amie L. Fiction and Metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.

Thompson, E. P. The Poverty of Theory and Other Essays. London: Merlin Press, 1978.

Thompson, John B. Critical Hermeneutics: A Study in the Thought of Paul Ricoeur and Jürgen Habermas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.

Tiles, Mary. Bachelard: Science and Objectivity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984.

——and Jim Tiles. An Introduction to Historical Epistemology: The Authority of Knowledge. Cambridge MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1993.

Toews, John Edward. Hegelianism: The Path Toward Dialectical Humanism, 1805–1841. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980.

——Becoming Historical: Cultural Reformation and Public Memory in Early Nineteenth-Century Berlin. London: Cambridge University Press, 2004.

Torfing, Jacob. New Theories of Discourse: Laclau, Mouffe and Zizek. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1999.

Toulmin, Stephen. Human Understanding. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972.

Touraine, Alain. Critique of Modernity. Trans. David Macey. Cambridge MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1995.

Trevor-Roper, H. R. Historical Essays. London: Macmillan & Co. 1963.

Truscot, Bruce. Redbrick University. London: Faber and Faber, 1943.

Tuttle, Howard N. The Dawn of Historical Reason: The Historicality of Human Existence in the thought of Dilthey, Heidegger and Ortega y Gasset. New York: Peter Lang Publishing, 1994.

Varela, Francisco J. Ethical Know-How: Action, Wisdom, and Cognition. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1999.

Vattimo, Gianni. The Adventure of Difference: Philosophy After Nietzsche and Heidegger. Trans. Cyprian Blamires. Oxford: Polity Press, 1993.

Veysey, Laurence R. The Emergence of the American University. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1965.

Vovelle, Michel. Ideologies and Mentalities. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1990.

Weber, Max. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Captialism. Trans. Talcott Parsons. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1976.

Wellek, Rene. Confrontations: Studies in the Intellectual and Literary Relations between Germany, England, and the United States during the nineteenth century. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1965.

Wellmer, Albrecht. Endgames: The Irreconcilable Nature of Modernity, Essays and Lectures. Trans. David Midgley. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 1998.

White, Hayden. The Content of the Form: Narrative Discourse and Historical Representation. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1990.

——and Frank E. Manuel. Theories of History. Los Angeles: The William Andrews Clark Memorial Library University of California, 1978.

304 Bibliography

Williams, Bernard. Making Sense of Humanity: and other Philosophical Papers 1982–1993. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.

Williams, Raymond. Communications. 3rd Edition. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1976.

——Culture and Society: 1780–1950. New York: Columbia University Press, 1983.

——Keywords: A vocabulary of Culture and Society. London: Fontana/Croon Helm, 1976.

Wilson, Edward O. Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1998.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations. 3rd Edition. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1968.

Woolf, Daniel. The Social Circulation of the Past: English Historical Culture 1500–1730. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003.

Zammito, John H. Kant, Herder, and the Birth of Anthropology. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2002.

——A Nice Derangement of Epistemes: Post-Positivism in the Study of Science from Quine to Latour. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2004.

Edited Books and Chapters

Abelove, Henry, Betsy Blackmar and Peter Dimock, eds. Visions of History. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1983.

Ameriks, Karl and Dieter Sturma, eds. The Modern Subject: Conceptions of the Self in Classical German Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1995.

Anderson, Faye and Stuart Macintyre, eds. The Life of the Past: The Discipline of History at the University of Melbourne. Melbourne: The Department of History, University of Melbourne, 2006.

Attridge, Derek, Geoff Bennington and Robert Young, eds. Post-structuralism and the Question of History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.

Australian Academy of the Humanities. Knowing Ourselves and Others: The Humanities in Australia into the 21st Century. Canberra: Australian Academy of the Humanities, 1998.

Badmington, Neil, ed. Posthumanism. Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2000.

Beilharz, Peter, ed. Social Theory: A Guide to Central Thinkers. North Sydney: Allen & Unwin, 1991.

Benhabib, Seyla and Nancy Fraser, eds. Pragmatism, Critique, Judgement: Essays for Richard J. Bernstein. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 2004.

Berger, Stefan, Mark Donovan and Kevin Passmore, eds. Writng National Histories: Western Europe Since 1800. London: Routledge, 1999.

Bernstein, Richard J. ed. Habermas and Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1985.

Berube, Michael and Carey Nelson, eds. Higher Education Under Fire: Politics, Economics, and the Crisis of the Humanities. New York: Routledge, 1995.

Bloch, R. Howard, ed. Medievalism and the Modernist Temper. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1996.

305 Bibliography

Bolitho, Harold and Chris Wallace-Crabbe, eds. Approaching Australia: Papers from the Harvard Australian Studes Symposium. Harvard: Harvard University Committee on Australian Studies, 1998.

Boucher, David, James Connelly and Tariq Modood, eds. Philosophy, History and Civilization: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on R. G. Collingwood. Cardiff: University of Wales Press, 1995.

Bourne, K. and D. C. Watt, eds. Studies in International History. London: Longmans, Green and Co, 1967.

Brake, Laurel and Ian Small, eds. Pater in the 1990s. Greensboro: ELT Press, 1991.

Bridge, Carl, ed. Manning Clark: Essays on his Place in History. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1994.

Brown, Richard Harvey and J. Daniel Schubert, eds. Knowledge and Power in Higher Education: A Reader. New York: Teachers College Press, 2000.

Coady, Tony, ed. Why Universities Matter: A Conversation about Values, Means and Directions. St. Leonards: Allen & Unwin, 2000.

Coffield, Frank and Bill Williamson, eds. Repositioning Higher Education. Buckingham: SRHE and Open University Press, 1997.

Cooper, Simon, John Hinkson and Geoff Sharp, eds. Scholars and Entrepreneurs: The Universities in Crisis. North Carlton: Arena Publications, 2002.

Culler, Jonathan, ed. Deconstruction: Critical Concepts in Literary and Cultural Studies. Vol. 1. London and New York: Routledge, 2003.

——Deconstruction: Critical Concepts in Literary and Cultural Studies. Vol. 2. London and New York: Routledge, 2003.

Dahlbom, Bo, ed. Dennett and his Critics. Cambridge MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1993.

Dauenhauer, Bernard P., ed. At the Nexus of Philosophy and History. Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1987.

Dayton, Gene and Warwick Mules, eds. Humanities: New Horizons. Rockhampton: School of Humanities, Central Queensland University, 1998.

Debbins, William, ed. Essays in the Philosophy of History: By R. G. Collinwood. Austin: University of Texas Press, 1965.

Earnshaw, Steven, ed. Postmodern Surroundings. Amsterdam: Editions Rodopi, 1994.

Ewer, Peter, ed. For the Common Good: CSIRO and Public Sector Research and Development. Leichhardt: Pluto Press, 1995.

Fairchild, Henry Pratt, ed. The Obligation of Universities to the Social Order. New York: New York University Press, 1933.

Festenstein, Matthew and Simon Thompson, eds. Richard Rorty: Critical Dialogues. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2001.

Fulford, Tim, ed. Romanticism and Science 1773–1833. London: Routledge, 2002.

Gardiner, Patrick, ed. The Philosophy of History. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982.

306 Bibliography

Gildenhard, Ingo and Martin Ruehl, eds. Out of Arcadia: Classics and Politics in Germany in the Age of Burckhardt, Nietzsche and Wilamowitz. London: Institute of Classical Studies, School of Advanced Studies, University of London, 2003.

Glatt, Evelyn and Maynard W. Shelley, eds. The Research Society. New York: Gordon and Breach, 1968.

Goody, Esther N., ed. Social Intelligence and Interaction: Expressions and Implications of the Social Bias in Human Intelligence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.

Gotschl, Johann, ed. Erwin Shrödingers World View: The Dynamics of Knowledge and Reality. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992.

Grumley, John, Paul Crittenden and Pauline Johnson, eds. Culture and Enlightenment: Essays for Gyorgy Markus. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing, 2002.

Guignon, Charles and David R. Riley, eds. Richard Rorty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003.

Hale, J. R., ed. The Evolution of British Historiography: From Bacon to Namier. London: Macmillan, 1967.

Hall, John and A. I. C. Jarvie, eds. Transition to Modernity: Essays on Power, Wealth and Belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.

Heaney, Seamus, ed. Beowulf. London: Faber and Faber, 1999.

Hiley, David R., James F. Bohman and Richard Shusterman, eds. The Interpretive Turn: Philosophy, Science Culture. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991.

Hoy, David Couzens, ed. Foucault: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1994.

Hughes, Agatha C. and Thomas P. Hughes, eds. Systems, Experts, and Computers: The Systems Approach in Management and Engineering. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 2000.

Huhn, Tom, ed. The Cambridge Companion to Adorno. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.

Iggers, George and James M. Powell, eds. Leopold von Ranke and the Shaping of the Historical Discipline. New York: Syracuse University Press, 1990.

Ihde, Don, ed. Paul Ricoeur: The Conflict of Interpretations: Essays in Hermeneutics. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1974.

Jacob, Merle and Tomas Hellstrom, eds. The Future of Knowledge Production in the Academy. Buckingham: SRHE and Open University Press, 2000.

Jasper, David, ed. The Interpretation of Belief: Coleridge, Schleiermacher and Romanticism. Houndmills: The Macmillan Press, 1986.

Karooz, Carole, Gerlese Åkerlind and Malcolm Tight, eds. Autonomy in Social Science Research : The View from United Kingdom and Australian Universities. Oxford: Elsevier, 2007.

Kennington, Richard, ed. The Philosophy of Baruch Spinoza. Washington D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1980.

Kenway, Jane, Elizabeth Bullen and Simon Robb, eds. Innovation & Tradition: The Arts, Humanities and the Knowledge Economy. New York: Peter Lang Publishing, 2004.

Klahr, David and Kenneth Kotovsky, eds. Complex Information Processing: The Impact of Herbert A. Simon. Hillsdale N.J. : Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1989.

307 Bibliography

Klemm, David E. and Gunter Zoller, eds. Figuring the Self: Subject, Absolute, and Others in Classical German Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997.

Klibansky, Raymond and H. J. Paton, eds. Philosophy and History: Essays presented to Ernst Cassirer. 2nd ed. New York: Harper & Row, 1963.

Kors, Alan Charles and Paul J. Korshin, eds. Anticipations of the Enlightenment in England, France, and Germany. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1987.

Kramer, Lloyd and Sarah Maza, eds. A Companion to Western Historical Thought. Malden MA: Blackwell Publishers, 2002.

Krausz, Michael, ed. Critical Essays on the Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972.

Lehmann, Hartmut and Guenther Roth, eds. Webers Protestant Ethic: Origins, Evidence, Contexts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.

Low, D. A., ed. Keith Hancock: The Legacies of an Historian. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 2001.

Macintyre, Stuart, ed. The Historian’s Conscience: Australian Historians on the Ethics of History. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 2004

——and Julian Thomas, eds. The Discovery of Australian History 1890–1939. Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1995.

——and Peter McPhee, eds. Max Crawford’s School of History: Proceedings of a Symposium held at the University of Melbourne 14 December 1998. Parkville: History Department The University of Melbourne, 2000.

Marchand, Suzanne and David Lindenfield, eds. Germany at the Fin De Siecle: Culture, Politics, and Ideas. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University, 2004.

Marois, Maurice, ed. Documents for History: Life and Human Destiny. Paris: Editions Rive Droite, 1997.

McKinnon, Susan and Sydel Silverman, eds. Complexities: Beyond Nature & Nurture. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2005.

Mullarkey, John, ed. The New Bergson. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1999.

Nonaka, Ikujiro and Toshihiro Nishiguchi, eds. Knowledge Emergence: Social, Technical, and Evolutionaty Dimensions of Knowledge Creation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.

Oleson, Alexandra and John Voss, eds. The Organization of Knowledge in Modern America, 1860– 1920. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1976.

Ormiston, Gayle L. and Alan D. Schrift, eds. The Hermeneutic Tradition: From Ast to Ricoeur. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1990.

Owensby, Jacob, ed. Dilthey and the Narrative of History. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994.

Parker, Sue Taylor, Robert W. Mitchell and Maria L. Boccia, eds. Self-Awareness in Animals and Humans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.

Passerin d’Entrèves, Maurizio and M. Seyla Benhabib, eds. Habermas and the Unfinished Project of Modernity: Critical Essays on The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1996.

308 Bibliography

Patton, Paul, ed. Deleuze: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1996.

Pines, David, ed. Emerging Syntheses in Science: Proceedings of the Founding Workshops of the Sante Fe Institute Santa Fe, New Mexico. Redwood City: Addison-Wesley, 1988.

RaJan., Tilottama and Michael, J. O’Driscoll, eds. After Poststructuralism: Writing the Intellectual History of Theory. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2002.

Reason, Peter and Hilary Bradbury, eds. Handbook of Action Research: Participative Inquiry and Practice. London: Sage Publications, 2001.

Rickard, John and Peter Spearritt, eds. Packaging the Past? Public Histories. Carlton: MUP and Australian Historical Studies, 1991.

Roberts, David, ed. Reconstructing Theory: Gadamer, Habermas, Luhmann. Carlton South: Melbourne University Press, 1995.

Rockmore, Tom and Joseph Margolis, eds. History, Historicity, and Science. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing, 2006.

Rorty, Richard, J. B. Schneewind and Quentin Skinner, eds. Philosophy in History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.

Rothblatt, Sheldon and Björn Wittrock, eds. The European and American university, since 1800: Historical and sociological essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.

Ruegg, Walter, ed. A History of the University in Europe: Volume 3, Universities in the Nineteenth and Early Twentieth Centuries (1800–1945). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.

Salmon, Wesley and Gereon Wolters, eds. Logic, Language, and the Structure of Scientific Theories. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1994.

Sarkar, Sahotra, ed. Science and Philosophy in the The Legacy of the Vienna Circle: Modern Reappraisals. New York: Garland Publishing, 1996.

Schmitt, Frederick F., ed. Socializing Epistemology: The Social Dimensions of Knowledge. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc. 1994.

Schreuder, Deryck M., ed. The Humanities and a Creative Nation: Jubilee Essays. Canberra: The Australian Academy of the Humanities, 1995.

Scott, Peter, ed. Higher Education Re-formed. London: Falmer Press, 2000.

Seidman, Steven, ed. The Postmodern Turn: New Perspectives on Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.

Sheehan, Paul, ed. Becoming human: New Perspectives on the Inhuman Condition. Westport: Praeger Publishers, 2003.

Shusterman, Richard, ed. Bourdieu: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1999.

Silverman, Hugh J. and Donn Welton, eds. Postmodernism and Continental Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1988.

Sixty Years of the National Health and Medical Research Council 1936–1996. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service, 1996.

Smith, Anthony and Frank Webster, eds. The Postmodern University?. Buckingham: SRHE and Open University Press, 1997.

309 Bibliography

Stone, Lawrence, ed. The University in Society. Vol. 1: Oxford and Cambridge from the 14th to the Early 19th Century. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974.

——The University in Society. Vol. 2: Europe, Scotland, and the United States from the 16th to the 20th Century. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974.

Stephens, Michael D. ed. Culture, Education and the State. London: Routledge, Chapman and Hall, 1988.

Stern, David G. and Bela Szabados, eds. Wittgenstein Reads Weininger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.

Stern, Fritz, ed. The Varieties of History from Voltaire to the Present. New York: Vintage Books, 1973.

Stokes, Geoffrey, ed. The Politics of Identity in Australia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.

Stuchtey, Benedikt and Peter Wende, eds. British and German Historiography 1750–1950: Traditions, Perceptions, and Transfers. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.

Sykes Davies, Hugh and George Watson, eds. The English Mind: Studies in the English Moralists Presented to Basil Willey. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1964.

Tagliacozzo, Giorgio and Hayden V. White, eds. Giambattista Vico: An International Symposium. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1969.

Taylor, Mark C. ed. Deconstruction in Context. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1986.

Teich, Mikulas and Robert Young, eds. Changing Perspectives in the History of Science: Essays in Honour of Joseph Needham. London: Heinemann, 1973.

Tully, James and Daniel M. Weinstock, eds. Philosophy in an Age of Pluralism: The Philosophy of Charles Taylor in Question. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.

Tully, James, ed. Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and His Critics. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1988.

Turner, Bryan, S., ed. Theories of Modernity and Postmodernity. London: Sage Publications, 1990.

Welton, Donn, ed. The Essential Husserl: Basic Writings in Transcendental Phenomenology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999.

White, Stephen K., ed. Life-world and Politics: Between Modernity and Postmodernity: Essays in Honor of Fred Dallmayr. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1989.

——The Cambridge Companion to Habermas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.

Wrathall, Mark A. and Jeff Malpas, eds. Heidegger, Authenticity, and Modernity: Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus. Vol. 1. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 2000.

Zahorski, Kenneth, J. ed. Scholarship in the Postmodern Era: New Venues, New Values, New Visions. San Franscisco: Wiley, 2002.

Zika, Charles. No Gods Except Me: Orthodoxy and Religious Practice in Europe, 1200–1600. Parkville: The History Department, University of Melbourne, 1991.

Zylinska, Joanna, ed. The Cyborg Experiments: The Extensions of the Body in the Media Age. London: Continuum, 2002.

310 Bibliography

Law, John and John Hazzard, ed. Actor Network Theory and After. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1999.

Articles

Adams, David. “Metaphors for Mankind: The Development of Hans Blumenberg's Anthroplogical Metaphorology.” Journal of the History of Ideas 52, no. 1 (Jan.–Mar. 1991): 152–166.

Allen, Barry. “Turning Back to the Linguistic Turn in the Theory of Knowledge.” Thesis Eleven , no. 89 (May, 2007): 6–22.

Anderson, Melissa S. “The Complex Relations Between The Academy and Industry.” Journal of Higher Education 72, no. 2 (Mar.–Apr., 2001): 226–246.

Anderson, Pamela Sue. “Agnosticism and Attestation concerning the Other in Ricoeur's ‘Oneself as Another’.” Journal of Religion 74, no. 1 (Jun., 1994): 65–76.

Anderson, Wilda C. “Dispensing with the Fixed Point: Scientific Law as Historical Event.” History and Theory 22, no. 3 (Oct., 1983): 264–277.

Ankersmit, F. R. “Reply to Professor Iggers.” History and Theory 34, no. 3 (Oct., 1995): 168–173.

——“Historicism: An Attempt at Synthesis.” History and Theory 34, no. 3 (Oct., 1995): 143–161.

——“The Sublime Dissociation of the Past: Or How to Be(come) What One is No Longer.” History and Theory 40, no. 3 (Oct., 2001): 295–323.

Asdal, Kristin. “The Problematic Nature of Nature: The Post-constructivist Challenge to Environmental History.” History and Theory 42, no. 4 (Dec., 2003): 60–74.

Ashkenazi, Guy. “Metaphors in Science and Art: Enhancing Human Awareness and Perception.” Electronic Journal of Science Education 11, no. 1 (2006): 1–7.

Askling, Berit, Mary Henkel and Barbara Kehn. “Concepts of Knowledge and their Organization in Universities.” European Journal of Education 36, no. 3 (2001): 341–350.

Badmington, Neil. “Theorizing Posthumanism.” Cultrual Critique , no. 53 (Winter, 2003): 10–27.

Baker, Keith Michael. “On Condorcet's”Sketch".” Daedalus 133, no. 3 (Summer, 2004): 56–64.

Baltimore, David. “Limiting Science: A Biological Perspective.” Daedalus 134, no. 4 (Fall, 2005): 7– 15.

Bammer, Gabriele. “Integration and Implementation Sciences: Building a New Specialization.” Ecology and Society 10, no. 2 (2005): 1–25.

Bates, David. “Idols and Insight: An Enlightenment Topography of Knowledge.” Representations 73, no. (Winter, 2001): 1–23.

Bateson, Patrick. “The Origin of Human Differences.” Daedalus 134, no. 4 (Fall, 2005): 36–46.

Battaglia, Debbora. “Multiplicities: An Anthropologist's Thoughts on Replicants and Clones in Popular Film.” Critical Inquiry 27, no. 3 (Spring, 2001): 493–514.

Becher, Tony. “Historians on History.” Studies in Higher Education 14, no. 3 (1989): 263–278.

Bender, Thomas. “Wholes and Parts: The Need for Synthesis in American History.” Journal of American History 73, no. 1 (Jun., 1986): 120–136.

311 Bibliography

——“A Round-table: Synthesis in American History-Wholes and Parts: A Continuing Conversation.” Journal of American History 74, no. 1 (Jun., 1987): 123–130.

Bendix, Reinhard. “Max Weber and Jakob Burckhardt.” American Sociological Review 30, no. 2 (Apr., 1965): 176–184.

Benhabib, Seyla. “Epistemologies of Postmodernism: A Rejoinder to Jean-Francois Lyotard.” New German Critique , no. 33 (Autumn, 1984): 103–126.

——“In Defense of Universalism. Yet Again! A Response to Critics of Situating the Self.” New German Critique , no. 62 (Spring–Summer, 1994): 173–189.

Bentley, Michael. “Past and”Presence": Revisiting Historical Ontology.” History and Theory 45, no. 3 (Oct., 2006): 349–361.

Berger, Stefan. “Historians and Nation Building in Germany After Reunification.” Past and Present , no. 148 (Aug., 1995): 187–222.

Bernstein, Richard J. “Rethinking Responsibility.” Hastings Center Report 25, no. 7 (1995): 13–20.

Bess, Michael D. “Icarus 2.0: A Historian's Perspective on Human Biological Enhancement.” Technology and Culture 49, no. 1 (January, 2008): 114–126.

Bevir, Mark. “Sidney Webb: Utilitarianism, Positivism, and Social Democracy.” Journal of Modern History 74, no. 2 (Jun., 2002): 217–252.

Bitbol, Michel and Pierre Luigi Luisi . “Autopoiesis With or Without Cognition: Defining Life at its Edge.” Journal of the Royal Society Interface 1, no. 1 (Nov., 2004): 99–107.

Black, Donald. “Dreams of Pure Sociology.” Sociological Theory 18, no. 3 (Nov., 2000): 343–367.

Blair, Ann. “Reading Strategies for Coping with Information Overload ca. 1550–1700.” Journal of the History of Ideas 64, no. 1 (Jan., 2003): 11–28.

Bleiklie, Ivar and Haldor Byrkjeflot. “Changing Knowledge Regimes: Universities in a New Resarch Environment.” Higher Education 44, no. 3/4 (Oct–Dec., 2002): 519–532.

Blokland, Hans. “Unhappily Trapped in the Emancipation-Dilemma.” The Good Society 12, no. 2 (2003): 58–62.

Bloland, Harland G. “Whatever Happened to Postmodernism in Higher Education: No Requiem in the New Millenium.” Journal of Higher Education 76, no. 2 (Mar.–Apr., 2005): 121–150.

Boutcher, Warren. “The Analysis of Culture Revisited: Pure Texts, Applied Texts, Literary Historicisms, Cultural Histories.” Journal of the History of Ideas 64, no. 3 (Jul.–Sep., 2003): 489–510.

Bouwsma, William J. “The Renaissance and the Drama of Western History.” American Historical Review 84, no. 1 (Feb., 1979): 1–15.

——“Intellectual History in the 1980s: From History of Ideas to History of Meaning.” Journal of Interdisciplinary History 12, no. 2 (Autumn, 1981): 279–281.

Bowie, Andrew. “Schleiermacher and Post-Metaphysical Thinking.” Critical Horizons 5, no. 1 (Apr., 2004): 165–200.

Brint, Steven, Mark Riddle, Lori Turk-Bicakci and Charles S. Levy. “From the Literal to the Practical Arts in American Colleges and Universities: Organizational Analysis and Curricular Change.” Journal of Higher Education 76, no. 2 (Mar.–Apr., 2005): 151–180.

312 Bibliography

Brobjer, Thomas H. “Nietzsche's Relation to Historical Methods and Nineteenth-Century German Historiography.” History and Theory 46, no. 2 (May, 2007): 155–179.

Brown, Donald E. “Human Universals, Human Nature, and Human Culture.” Daedalus 134, no. 4 (Fall, 2005): 47–54.

Brown, Richard Harvey. “Positivism, Relativism, and Narrative in the Logic of the Historical Sciences.” American Historical Review 92, no. 4 (Oct., 1987): 908–920.

Bubbio, Paolo Diego. “Mimetic Theory and Hermeneutics.” Colloquy 9 (2005): http://www.arts.monash.edu.au/others/colloquy/issue9/bubbio.pdf.

Burger, Thomas. “Droysen's Defense of Historiography: A Note.” History and Theory 16, no. 2 (May, 1977): 168–173.

Burke, Peter. “Context in Context.” Common Knowledge 8, no. 1 (Winter, 2002): 152–177.

——“Images as Evidence in Seventeenth-century Europe.” Journal of the History of Ideas , no. (2003): 273–296.

Burroughs, Peter. “John Robert Seeley and British Imperial History.” Journal of Imperial and Commonwealth History 1, no. 2 (January, 1973):191–211.

Cameron, Evan. “From Plato to Socrates: Wittgenstein's Journey on Collingwood's Map.” Canadian Aesthetics Journal 10, no. (Fall, 2004): http://www.uqtr.uquebec.ca/AE/.

Carey, Susan. “Bootstrapping and the Origin of Concepts.” Daedalus 133, no. 1 (Winter, 2004): 59–68.

Carignan, Michael I. “Fiction as History or History as Fiction? George Eliot, Hayden White, and Nineteenth Century Historicism.” Clio 29, no. 4 (Summer, 2000): 395–414.

——“Analogical Reasoning in Victorian Historical Epistemology.” Journal of the History of Ideas , no. (2003): 445–464.

Carlin, Laurence. “Selecting a Phenomenalism: Leibniz, Berkeley, and the Science of Happiness.” Journal of the History of Ideas 68, no. 1 (Jan., 2007): 58–78.

Chandler, James. “Critical Disciplinarity.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 355–360.

Child, Arthur. “Thoughts on the Historiology of Neo-Positivism.” Journal of Philosophy 57, no. 20/21 (Sep. 29–Oct. 13, 1960): 665–674.

Chodat, Robert. “Naturalism and Narrative, Or, What Computers and Human Beings Can't Do.” New Literary History 37, no. 4 (Autumn, 2006): 685–706.

Chow, Rey. “An Addiction from Which We can Never Get Free.” New Literary History 36, no. 1 (Winter, 2005): 47–55.

Clark, G. Kitson. “A Hundred Years of the Teaching of History at Cambridge, 1873–1973.” Historical Journal 16, no. 3 (Sep., 1973): 535–553.

Clendinnen, Inga. “Who Owns the Past?.” Quarterly Essay 23, no. (2006): 1–72.

Cmiel, Kenneth. “After Objectivity: What Comes Next in History?.” American Literary History 2, no. 1 (Spring, 1990): 170–181.

Colletti, Lucio. “A Political and Philosophical Interview.” New Left Review 86, no. (Jul.–Aug., 1974): 3–28.

313 Bibliography

Connolly, William E. “The Uncertain Condition of the Critical Intellectual: A Response.” Political Theory 23, no. 4 (Nov., 1995): 653–657.

——“Speed, Concentric Cultures, and Cosmopolitanism.” Political Theory 28, no. 5 (Oct., 2000): 596– 618.

——“Experience and Experiment.” Daedalus 135, no. 3 (Summer, 2006): 67–75.

Cooke, Maeve. “Between 'Objectivism' and 'Contextualism': The Normative Foundations of Social Philosophy.” Critical Horizons 1, no. 2 (Sep., 2000): 193–227.

Cowley, W. H. “The Higher Learning versus the Higher Education.” Journal of Higher Education 25, no. 8 (Nov., 1954): 401–410.

Crocker, Lester, G. “Interpreting the Enlightenment: A Political Approach.” Journal of the History of Ideas 46, no. 2 (Apr.–Jun., 1985): 211–230.

Culler, Jonathan. “In Need of a Name? A Response to Geoffrey Harpham.” New Literary History 36, no. 1 (Winter, 2005): 37–42.

Cunliffe, Leslie. “A Wittgensteinian Approach to Discerning the Meaning of Works of Art in the Practice of critical and Contextual Studies in Secondary Art Education.” Journal of Aesthetic Education 40, no. 1 (Spring, 2006): 65–78.

Damasio, Antonio and Hanna Damasio. “Minding the Body.” Daedalus 135, no. 3 (Summer, 2006): 15–22.

Daston, Lorraine . “Objectivity and the Escape from Perspective.” Social Studies of Science 22, no. 4 (Nov , 1992): 597–618.

——“Whither Critical Inquiry?.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 361–364.

——“Fear and Loathing of the Imagination in Science.” Daedalus 134, no. 4 (Fall, 2005): 16–30.

——and Peter Galison. “The Image of Objectivity.” Representations , no. 40 (Autumn, 1992): 81–128.

Davis, Glyn. “The Rising Phoenix of Competition: What Future for Australia's Public Universities?” Griffith Review 11, no. (2006): http://www3.griffith.edu.au/01/griffithreview/.

Davis, Natalie Zemon. “History's Two Bodies.” American Historical Review 93, no. 1 (Feb., 1988): 1– 30.

——“Towards Mixtures and Margins.” American Historical Review 97, no. 5 (Dec., 1992): 1409– 1416.

——“Religion and Capitalism Once Again? Jewish Merchant Culture in the Seventeenth Century.” Representations 59, no. (Summer, 1997): 56–84.

Dawson, Andrew C. “The Intellectual Commons: A Rationale for Regulation.” Prometheus 16, no. 3 (1998): 275–289.

Dawson, Doyne. “The Marriage of Marx and Darwin.” History and Theory 41, no. 2 (Feb., 2002): 43– 59.

Delanty, Gerard. “The Governance of Universities: What Is the Role of the University in the Knowledge Society? .” Canadian Journal of Sociology 27, no. 2 (Spring, 2002): 185–198.

DeLaura, David J. “Arnold and Carlyle.” PMLA 79, no. 1 (Mar., 1964): 104–129.

De Lauretis, Teresa. “Statement Due.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 365–368.

314 Bibliography

Demeritt, David. “What is the ‘Social Construction of Nature’? A Typology and Sympathetic Critique.” Progress in Human Geography 26, no. 6 (2002): 767–790.

Deranty, Jean-Philippe. “Injustice, Violence and Social Struggle. The Critical Potential of Axel Honneth's Theory of Recognition.” Critical Horizons 5, no. 1 (Apr., 2004): 297–322.

DeVries, Wilhelm, A. “Meaning and Interpretation in History.” History and Theory 22, no. 3 (Oct. 1993): 253–263.

Dickey, Laurence. “Blumenberg and Secularization:”Self-Assertion”and the Problem of Self-Realizing Teleology in History.” New German Critique , no. 41 (Spring–Summer, 1987): 151–165.

Diggins, John, Patrick. “The Oyster and the Pearl: The Problem of Contextualism in Intellectual History.” History and Theory 23, no. 2 (May, 1984): 151–169.

Dinerstein, Joel. “Technology and Its Discontents: On the Verge of the Posthuman.” American Quarterly 58, no. 3 (2006): 569–595.

Doja, Albert. “The Shoulder of Our Giant: Claude Levi-Strauss and his Legacy in Current Anthropology.” Social Science Information 45, no. 1 (2006): 79–107.

Dolan, Ray. “The Body in the Brain.” Daedalus 135, no. 3 (Summer, 2006): 78–85.

Donnelley, Strachan. “Bioethical Troubles: Animal Individuals and Human Organisms.” Hastings Center Report 25, no. 7 (1995): 21–29.

Dreyfus, Hubert L. “A Merleau-Pontyian Critique of Husserl's and Searle's Representationalist Accounts of Action.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100, no. (2000): 287–302.

Duffy, Simon. “The Difference Between Science and Philosophy: The Spinoza–Boyle Controversy Revisited.” Paragraph 29, no. 2 (2006): 115–138.

Dunne, Joseph. “Newman Now: Re-examining the Concepts of 'Philosophical' and 'Liberal' in The Idea of the University.” British Journal of Educational Studies 54, no. 4 (Dec., 2006): 412–428.

During, Simon. “Socialist Ends: The British New Left, Cultural Studies, and the Emergence of Academic Theory.” Postcolonial Studies 10, no. 1 (2007): 23–39.

Edel, Abraham. “Levels of Meaning and the History of Ideas.” Journal of the History of Ideas 7, no. 3 (Jul.–Sep. 1946): 355–360.

Edelman, Gerald M. “The Embodiment of Mind.” Daedalus 135, no. 3 (Summer, 2006): 23–32.

Edwards, Anne, Sharyn Roach Anleu, Bryan Turner and Anna Yeatman. “The Future of Sociology: the 20th anniversary of Sociology at Flinders University.” The Flinders Journal of History and Politics 21, no. 2000 (2000): 1–30.

Ehrmann, Jacques. “Introduction to Gaston Bachelard.” MLN 81, no. 5 (Dec., 1966): 572–578.

Eichner, Hans. “The Rise of Modern Science and the Genesis of Romanticism.” PMLA 97, no. 1 (Jan., 1982): 8–30.

Eisenmann, Linda. “Integrating Disciplinary Perspectives into Higher Education Research: the Example of History.” Journal of Higher Education 75, no. 1 (January/February, 2004): 7–22.

Epstein, Mikhail. “Between Humanity and Human Beings.” Common Knowledge 13, no. 1 (Winter, 2007): 18–32.

315 Bibliography

Erlin, Matt. “Reluctant Modernism: Moses Mendelssohn's Philosophy of History.” Journal of the History of Ideas , no. (2002): 83–104.

Ermarth, H. Michael. “Mindful Matters: The Empire's New Codes and the Plight of Modern European History.” Journal of Modern History 57, no. 3 (Sep., 1985): 506–527.

Escobar, Arturo. “Welcome to Cyberia: Notes on the Anthropology of Cyberculture.” Current Anthropology 35, no. 3 (Jun., 1994): 211–231.

Falk, Janet. “Electronic Communication and Changing Organizational forms.” Organization Science 6, no. 4 (Jul.–Aug., 1995): 337–349.

Feenberg, Andrew. “Will the Real Post-human Please Stand Up!: A Response to Elichirigoity.” Social Studies of Science 30, no. 1 (Feb., 2000): 151–157.

Feinberg, Todd E. “Our Brains, Our Selves.” Daedalus 135, no. 4 (Fall, 2006): 72–80.

Ferrell, Robyn. “Hume Reads Freud: Empiricism as Rhetorical Event.” Critical Horizons 4, no. 2 (Sep., 2003): 265–280.

Fish, Stanley. “Theory's Hope.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 374–378.

Flax, Jane. “What is the Subject? Review Essay on Psychoanalysis and Feminism in Postcolonial Times.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 29, no. 3 (2004): 905–923.

Fludernik, Monika. “Threatening the University - The Liberal Arts and the Economization of Culture.” New Literary History 36, no. 1 (Winter, 2005): 57–70.

Fodor, Jerry. “How the Mind Works: What We still don't Know.” Daedalus 135, no. 3 (Summer, 2006): 86–96.

Follesdal, Dagfin and Michael Friedman. “American Philosophy in the Twentieth Century.” Daedalus 135, no. 2 (Spring, 2006): 116–126.

Foote, George A. “Science and Its Function in Early Nineteenth-Century England.” Osiris 11, no. (1954): 438–454.

Forland, Tor Egil. “The Ideal Explanatory Text in History: A Plea for Ecumenism.” History and Theory 43, no. 3 (Oct., 2004): 321–340.

Franke, William. “Metaphor and the Making of Sense: The Contemporary Metaphor Renaissance.” Philosophy and Rhetoric 33, no. 2 (2000): 137–153.

Freundlieb, Dieter. “Why Subjectivity Matters: Critical Theory and the Philosophy of Subject.” Critical Horizons 1, no. 2 (Sep., 2000): 229–245.

Friedman, Michael. “Carnap's Aufbau Reconsidered.” Nous 21, no. 4 (Dec., 1987): 521–545.

——“The Re-evaluation of Logical Positivism.” Journal of Philosophy 88, no. 10 (Oct., 1991): 505– 519.

Fromm, Harold. “Muses, Spooks, Neurons, and the Rhetoric of”Freedom".” New Literary History 36, no. 2 (Spring, 2005): 147–159.

Frow, John. “Recovering Memory.” Australian Humanities Review , (Dec., 1996): http:// www.lib.latrobe.edu.au/AHR/.

——“Australian Cultural Studies: Theory, Story, History.” Postcolonial Studies 10, no. 1 (2007): 59– 75.

316 Bibliography

Fuchs, Stephan. “Beyond Agency.” Sociological Theory 19, no. 1 (Mar., 2001): 24–40.

Fuller, Steve. “Intelligent Design Theory: A Site for Contemporary Sociology of Knowledge .” Canadian Journal of Sociology 31, no. 3 (2006): 277–289.

Gabardi, Wayne. “Contemporary Models of Democracy.” Polity 33, no. 4 (Summer, 2001): 547–568.

Galbraith, V. H. “James Tait.” English Historical Review 60, no. 237 (May, 1945): 129–135.

Galison, Peter. “Specific Theory.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 379–383.

Gardner, Howard. “A Reply to Perry D. Klein's 'Multiplying the Problems of Intelligence by Eight'.” Canadian Journal of Education 23, no. 1 (Winter, 1998): 96–102.

Geertz, Clifford. “Blurred Genres: The Refiguration of Social Thought.” American Scholar 49, no. 2 (1980): 165–179.

——“History and Anthropology.” New Literary History 21, no. 2 (Winter, 1990): 321–335.

Gelder, Ken. “Notes on the Research Future of Australian Literary Studies.” Australian Humanities Review , no. 37 (Dec., 2005): http://www.lib.latrobe.edu.au/AHR/.

Ghosh, P. “Max Weber's Idea of 'Puritanism': A Case Study in the Empirical Construction of the Protestant Ethic.” History of European Ideas 29, no. 2 (Jun., 2003): 367–407.

Ghosh, P. R. “Macaulay and the Heritage of the Enlightenment.” English Historical Review 112, no. 446 (Apr., 1997): 358–395.

Gilbert, Felix. “The New Edition of Johann Droysen's Historik.” Journal of the History of Ideas 44, no. 2 (Apr.–Jun., 1983): 327–336.

Gilligan, Carol. “When the Mind Leaves the Body … and Returns.” Daedalus 135, no. 3 (Summer, 2006): 55–66.

Gilman, Sander L. “Collaboration, the Economy, and the Future of the Humanities.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 384–390.

Giustiniani, Vito, R. “Homo, Humanus, and the Meanings of 'Humanism'.” Journal of the History of Ideas 46, no. 2 (Apr.–Jun., 1985): 167–195.

Glymour, Clark. “The Automation of Discovery.” Daedalus 133, no. 1 (Winter, 2004): 69–77.

Goehr, Lydia. “Writing Music History.” History and Theory 31, no. 2 (May, 1992): 182–189.

——“Political Music and the Politics of Music.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52, no. 1 (Winter, 1994): 99–112.

——“The Institutionalization of a Discipline: A Retrospective of Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism and the American Society of Aesthetics, 1939–1992.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51, no. 2 (Spring, 1993): 99–121.

——“Adorno, Schoenberg, and the”Totenanz der Prinzipen" in Thirteen Steps.” Journal of the American Musicological Society 56, no. 3 (Autumn, 2003): 595–636.

Goldstein, Doris S. “J. B. Bury's Philosophy of History: A Reappraisal.” American Historical Review 82, no. 4 (Oct., 1977): 896–919.

Goodman, David. “’There is No-one to Whom I Can Talk’-Norman Harper and American History in Australia.” Unpublished paper for ANZASA , (2004)

317 Bibliography

Gopnik, Alison. “Finding Our Inner Scientist.” Daedalus 133, no. 1 (Winter, 2004): 21–28.

Gordijn, Bert. “Converging NBIC Technologies for Improving Human Performance: A Critical Assessment of the Novelty and the Prospects of the Project.” Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics , no. (Winter, 2006): 726–732.

Gossman, Lionel. “Jacob Burkhardt as Art Historian.” Oxford Art Journal 11, no. 1 (1988): 25–32.

——“Philhellenism and Antisemitism II: The Rise of Eurocentrism.” Comparative Literature 46, no. 4 (Autumn, 1994): 372–389.

——“The Boundaries of the City: A Nineteenth Century Essay on”The Limits of Historical Knowledge".” History and Theory 25, no. 1 (Feb., 1986): 33–51.

——“Philhellenism and Antisemitism: Matthew Arnold and His German Models.” Comparative Literature 46, no. 1 (Winter, 1994): 1–39.

——“The Existenzbild in Burkhardt's Art Historical Writing.” MLN 114, no. 5 (Dec., 1999): 879–928.

——and Wilhelm Vischer . “The Boundaries of the City: A Nineteenth-Century Essay on “The Limits if Historical Knowledge".” History and Theory 25, no. 1 (Feb., 1986): 33–51.

Gottschall, Jonathan. “The Tree of Knowledge and Darwinian Literary Study.” Philosophy and Literature 27, no. (2003): 1–14.

——“Literary Universals and the Sciences of Mind.” Philosophy and Literature 28, no. (2004): 202– 217.

——and Marcus Nordland. “Romantic Love: A Literary Universal.” Philosophy and Literature 30, no. (2006): 432–452.

Grafton, Anthony. “History's Postmodern Fates.” Daedalus 135, no. 2 (Spring, 2006): 54–69.

——“The History of Ideas: Precept and Practice, 1950–2000 and Beyond.” Journal of the History of Ideas 67, no. 1 (Jan., 2006): 1–32.

Gray, John. “An Illusion with a Future.” Daedalus 133, no. 3 (Summer, 2004): 10–17.

Gregorian, Vartan. “Education and Our Divided Knowledge.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 137, no. 4 (Dec., 1993): 605–611.

Grubb, W. Norton and Marvin Lazerson. “Vocationalism in Higher Education: The Triumph of the Education Gospel.” Journal of Higher Education 76, no. 1 (Jan.–Feb., 2005): 1–25.

Guignon, Charles. “Philosophy after Wittgenstein and Heidegger.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50, no. 4 (Jun., 1990): 649–672.

Gumbrecht, Hans Ulrich. “Slow and Brilliant: Reactions to Geoffrey Galt Harpham's Diagnosis of the Humanities Today.” New Literary History 36, no. 1 (Winter, 2005): 131–139.

Habermas, Jürgen. “The Idea of the University: Learning Processes.” New German Critique , no. 41 (Spring–Summer, 1987): 3–22.

Haigh, Gideon. “The Nelson Touch: The New Censorship”. The Monthly, (May 2006).

Harlan, David. “Intellectual History and the Return of Literature.” American Historical Review 94, no. 3 (Jun., 1989): 581–609.

Harootunian, Harry. “Theory's Empire: Reflections on a Vocation for Critical Inquiry.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 396–402.

318 Bibliography

Harpham, Geoffrey Galt. “Beneath and Beyond the”Crisis in the Humanities".” New Literary History 36, no. 1 (Winter, 2005): 21–36.

Harris, Wendell V. “Interpretive Historicism:”Signs of the Times”and Culture and Anarchy in their Contexts.” Nineteenth-Century Literature 44, no. 4 (March, 1990): 441–464.

Harrison, Peter. “Curiosity, Forbidden Knowledge, and the Reformation of Natural Philosophy in Early Modern England.” Isis 92, no. 2 (Jun., 2001): 265–290.

Hart, Keith. “Marcel Mauss: In Pursuit of the Whole. A Review Essay.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 49, no. 2 (2007): 1–13.

Harte, N. B. “Trends in Publications on the Economic and Social History of Great Britain and Ireland, 1925–1974.” The Economic History Review 30, no. 1 (Feb., 1977): 20–41.

Hartmann, Nicolai. “German Philosophy in the Last Ten Years.” Mind 58, no. 232 (Oct., 1949): 413– 433.

Haskell, Thomas L. “Objectivity is not Neutrality: Rhetoric vs Practice in Peter Novick's That Noble Dream.” History and Theory 29, no. 2 (May, 1990): 129–157.

Hatcher, John. [Review] The Origins of English Individualism. Reviewed Work(s): The Origins of English Individualism: The Family, Property and Social Transition by Alan Macfarlane.” Historical Journal 22, no. 3 (Sep., 1979): 765–768.

Hayles, N. Katherine. “Afterword: The Human in the Posthuman.” Cultrual Critique , no. 53 (Winter, 2003): 134–137.

——“Commentary: The Search for the Human.” New Literary History 36, no. 2 (Spring, 2005): 327– 333.

——“Desiring Agency: Limiting Metaphors and Enabling Constraints in Dawkins and Deleuze/Guattari.” SubStance 30, no. 1/2; Issue 94/95 (2001): 144–159.

——“The Materiality of Informatics.” Configurations 1, no. 1 (Winter, 1993): 147–170.

Healy, Philip. “The Cardinal and the Samurai: Reflections on the Purpose of Education in the Works of J. H. Newman and Fukuzawa Yukichi.” Studies in Higher Education 14, no. 3 (1989): 247–262.

Heffernan, Teresa. “Bovine Anxieties, Virgin Births, and the Secret of Life.” Cultural Critique , no. 53 (Winter, 2003): 116–133.

Heller, Agnes. “The Unmasking of the Metaphysicians or the Deconstructing of Metaphysics.” Critical Horizons 5, no. 1 (Apr., 2004): 401–418.

Helsinger, Elizabeth. “Reflections on Reflections; or Moving On.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 463–467.

Hempel, Carl G. “The Function of General Laws in History.” Journal of Philosophy 39, no. 2 (Jan., 1942): 35–48.

Henrich, Dieter. “Subjectivity as Philosophical Principle.” Critical Horizons 4, no. 1 (Apr., 2003): 7– 27.

Herkless, John, L. “Economic Change and the Idealist Revival at the Turn of the Century .” History and Theory 26, no. 2 (May, 1987): 166–179.

Hermanowicz, Joseph C. “Classifying Universities and Their Departments: A Social World Perspective.” Journal of Higher Education 76, no. 1 (January/February, 2005): 26–55.

319 Bibliography

Hernon, Joseph M. “The Last Whig Historian and Consensus History: George Macaulay Trevelyan, 1876–1962.” American Historical Review 81, no. 1 (February, 1976): 66–97.

Hexter, J. H. “The Rhetoric of History.” History and Theory 6, no. 1 (1967): 3–13.

——“Carl Becker, Professor Novick, and Me: Or, Cheer Up, Professor N.” American Historical Review 96, no. 3 (Jun., 1991): 675–682.

Hildebrand, David L. “Genuine Doubt and the Community in Peirce’s Theory of Inquiry.” Southern Philosophy Review 12, no. 1 (1996): 33–43.

Hindess, Barry. “Uneven Development in the Moment of Theory.” Postcolonial Studies 10, no. 1 (2007): 41–58.

Hirsch, Eric; Charles Stewart. “Introduction: Ethnographies of Historicity.” History and Anthropology 16, no. 3 (Sep., 2005): 261–274.

Hollinger, David A. “The Return of the Prodigal: The Persistence of Historical Knowing.” American Historical Review 94, no. 3 (Jun., 1989): 610–621.

——“Postmodernist Theory and Wissenschaftliche Practice.” American Historical Review 96, no. 3 (Jun., 1991): 688–692.

——“The Disciplines and the Identity Debates, 1970–1995.” Daedalus 126, no. 1 (Winter, 1997): 333– 351.

——“Texts, Contexts, and Contingency.” Occasional Paper No. 10, American Council of Learned Societies. (2004).

Honneth, Axel and Avashai Margalit. “Recognition.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 75, no. (2001): 111–139.

Hovigimyan, G. H. “Art in the Age of the Spiritual Machines (with apologies to Ray Kurzweil).” Leonardo 34, no. 5 (2001): 453–458.

Howard, Thomas Albert. “Jacob Burckhardt, Religion and the Historiography of “Crisis” and “Transition".” Journal of the History of Ideas 60, no. 1 (Jan., 1999): 149–164.

Howarth, Janet. “Science Education in Late-Victorian Oxford: A Curious Case of Failure?” English Historical Review 102, no. 403 (April, 1987): 334–371.

Hoyningen-Huehne, Paul. “The Interrelations between the Philosophy, History and Sociology of Science in Thomas Kuhn's Theory of Scientific Development.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43, no. 4 (Dec., 1992): 487–501.

Huber, Ludwig; Gisela Shaw. “Editorial.” European Journal of Education 27, no. 3 (1992): 193–199.

Huber, Ludwig; Gisela Shaw. “Towards a New Studium Generale: Some Conclusions.” European Journal of Education 27, no. 3 (1992): 193–199.

Hume, Robert D. “Kant and Coleridge on Imagination.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 28, no. 4 (Summer, 1970): 485–496.

Hunter, Ian. “Christian Thomasius and the Desacralization of Philosophy.” Journal of the History of Ideas 61, no. 4 (Oct., 2000): 595–616.

——“The History of Theory.” Critical Inquiry 33, no. 1 (Autumn, 2006): 78–112.

——“The Time of Theory.” Postcolonial Studies 10, no. 1 (2007): 5–22.

320 Bibliography

Hutcheon, Linda and Michael Hutcheon. “A Convenience of Marriage:Collaboration and Interdisciplinarity.” PMLA 116, no. 5 (Oct., 2001): 1364–1376.

Iggers, Georg G. “The Image of Ranke in American and German Historical Thought.” History and Theory 2, no. 1 (1962): 17–40.

——“Comments on F. R. Ankersmit's Paper. “Historicism: An Attempt at Synthesis.” History and Theory 34, no. 3 (Oct., 1995): 162–167.

——“Historicism: The History and Meaning of the Term.” Journal of the History of Ideas 56, no. 1 (Jan., 1995): 129–152.

Ingram, David. “Blumenberg and the Philosphical Grounds of Historiography.” History and Theory 29, no. 1 (Feb., 1990): 1–15.

Jacoby, Russell. “A New Intellectual History.” American Historical Review 97, no. 2 (Apr. 1992): 405– 424.

Jameson, Frederic. “Morality Versus Ethical Substance.” Social Text , no. 8 (Winter, 1983): 151–154.

——“Postmodernism, or The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism.” New Left Review 146, (Jul.–Aug., 1984): 53–92.

——“Symptoms of Theory and Symptoms for Theory.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 43– 408.

Jay, Martin. “Fieldwork and Theorizing in Intellectual History: A Reply to Fritz Ringer .” Theory and Society 19, no. 3 (Jun. 1990): 311–321.

——“For Theory.” Theory and Society 25, no. 2 (Apr., 1996): 167–183.

Jensen, Casper Bruun. “A Nonhumanist Disposition: On Performativity, Practical Ontology, and Intervention.” Configurations 12, no. 2 (Spring, 2004): 229–261.

Johnson, James William. “Chronological Writing: Its Conceptual Development.” History and Theory 2, no. 2 (1962): 124–145.

Johnson, Mark. “Mind Incarnate: From Dewey to Damasio.” Daedalus 135, no. 3 (Summer, 2006): 46– 54.

Jonas, Hans. “Freedom of Scientific Inquiry and the Public Interest.” Hastings Center Report 6, no. 4 (Aug., 1976): 15–17.

——“Towards a Philosophy of Technology.” Hastings Center Report 9, no. 1 (Feb., 1979): 34–43.

——“The Burden and Blessing of Mortality.” Hastings Center Report 22, no. 1 (Jan.–Feb., 1992): 34– 40.

——“Wissenschaft as Personal Experience.” Hastings Center Report 32, no. 4 (Jul.–Aug., 2002): 27– 35.

Jones, Gareth Stedman. “The Pathology of English History.” New Left Review , no. 46 (Nov.–Dec., 1967): 29–43.

——“Class Struggle and the Industrial Revolution.” New Left Review , no. 90 (Mar.–Apr., 1975): 35– 69.

——“From Historical Sociology to Theoretical History.” British Journal of Sociology 27, no. 3 (Sep., 1976): 295–305.

321 Bibliography

Joshua, Essaka. “Wordsworth amongst the Aristotelians.” Journal of the History of Ideas 67, no. 3 (Jul., 2006): 511–522.

Joyce, Patrick. “The Return of History: Postmodernism and the Politics of Academic History in Britain.” Past and Present , no. 158 (Feb., 1998): 207–235.

Kagan, Jerome. “The Uniquely Human in Nature.” Daedalus 134, no. 4 (Fall, 2005): 77–88.

Karmel, Peter. “Occasional Paper 2/2000 Reforming Higher Education.” Academy of the Social Sciences , (2000):

Kass, Leon R. “Appreciating the Phenomenon of Life.” Hastings Center Report 25, no. 7 (1995): 3–12.

Kayrooz, Carole. “The Role of Autonomy in Social Science Research: The View from UK and Australian Universities.” http://portal.unesco.org/education/en/files/51655/11634338925Kayrooz- EN.pdf/Kayrooz-EN.pdf.

Kearnes, Matthew. “Chaos and Control: Nanotechnology and the Politics of Emergence.” Paragraph 29, no. 2 (2006): 57–80.

Kelley, Donald R. “The Metaphysics of Law: An Essay on the Very Young Marx .” American Historical Review 83, no. 2 (Apr., 1978): 350–367.

——“Horizons of Intellectual History: Retrospect, Circumspect, Prospect.” Journal of the History of Ideas 48, no. 1 (Jan.–Mar. 1987): 143–169.

——“Intellectual History in a Global Age.” Journal of the History of Ideas 66, no. 2 (Apr.–Jun. 2005): 155–167.

Kerr, Anne and Sarah Cunningham-Burley. “On Ambivalences and Risk: Reflexive Modernity and the New Human Genetics.” Sociology 34, no. 2 (2000): 283–304.

Kezar, Adrianna and Susan Talburt, . “Questions of Research and Methodology.” Journal of Higher Education 75, no. 1 (Jan.–Feb., 2004): 1–6.

Kirby, Davis A. and Laura A. Gaither. “Genetic Coming of Age: Genomics, Enhancement, and Identity in Film.” New Literary History 36, no. 2 (Spring, 2005): 263–282.

Kivy, Peter. “Is Music Art?.” Journal of Philosophy 88, no. 10 (Oct., 1991): 544–554.

Klein, Julie Thompson. “Interdisciplinary Needs: The Current Context.” Library Trends 44, no. 2 (Fall, 1996): 134–164.

Kloppenberg, James T. “Objectivity and Historicism: A Century of American Historical Writing.” American Historical Review 94, no. 4 (Oct., 1989): 1011–1030.

——“Pragmatism: An Old Name for Some New Ways of Thinking.” Journal of American History 83, no. 1 (Jun., 1996): 100–138.

Kompridis, Nikolas. “From Reason to Self-Realization? Axel Honneth and the”Ethical Turn”in Critical Theory .” Critical Horizons 5, no. 1 (Apr., 2004): 323–360.

Koselleck, Reinhart. “Crisis.” Journal of the History of Ideas 67, no. 2 (Apr., 2006): 357–400.

Krause, Sharon R. “Desiring Justice: Motivation and Justification in Rawls and Habermas.” Contemporary Political Theory 4, no. 4 (Nov., 2005): 363–385.

Kreiger, Leonard. “The Autonomy of Intellectual History.” Journal of the History of Ideas 34, no. 4 (Oct.–Dec. 1973): 499–516.

322 Bibliography

Kreiger, Murray. “The School of Criticism and Theory: An Allegorical History.” New Literary History 25, no. 4 (Autumn, 1994): 881–892.

Kreilkamp, Karl. “Hindsight and the Real World of Science Policy.” Science Studies 1, no. 1 (Jan., 1971): 43–66.

——“Towards a Theory of Science Policy.” Science Studies 3, no. 1 (Jan., 1973): 3–29.

LaCapra, Dominick. “Intellectual History and Its Ways.” American Historical Review 97, no. 2 (Apr. 1992): 425–439.

Lane, Robert. “The Limited Triumph of Functioanl Rationality.” The Good Society 12, no. 2 (2003): 63–68.

Larmore, Charles. “History and Truth.” Daedalus 133, no. 3 (Summer, 2004): 46–55.

Latour, Bruno. “Why has Critique Run Out of Steam? From Matter of Fact to Matter of Concern.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 225–248.

Lazier, Benjamin. “Overcoming Gnosticism: Hans Jonas, Hans Blumenberg, and the Legitimacy of the Natural World.” Journal of the History of Ideas 64, no. 4 (Oct., 2003): 619–637.

Lee, Orville. “Social Theory across Disciplinary Boundaries: Cultural Studies and Sociology.” Sociological Forum 14, no. 4 (Dec., 1999): 547–581.

Lemert, Charles. “The Habits of Intellectuals: Response to Ringer.” Theory and Society 19, no. 3 (Jun. 1990): 295–310.

Lenneberg, Hans. “The Myth of the Unappreciated (Musical) Genius.” Music Quarterly 66, no. 2 (Apr., 1980): 219–231.

——“Speculating about Sociology and Social History.” Journal of Musicology 6, no. 4 (Autumn, 1988): 409–420.

——“Classic and Romantic: The First Usage of the Terms.” Music Quarterly 78, no. 3 (Autumn, 1994): 610–625.

Levine, Joseph M. “Intellectual History as History.” Journal of the History of Ideas 66, no. 2 (Apr.– Jun. 2005): 155–167.

Levitt, Theodore. “Marketing Myopia.” Harvard Business Review 38, no. 4 (Jul.–Aug., 1960): 24–47.

——“Marketing Myopia—Retrospective Commentary.” Harvard Business Review 53, no. 5 (Sep.– Oct., 1975): 177–181.

Levy, Neil and Tim Bayne. “A Will of One's Own: Consciousness, Control, and Character.” International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 27, no. 5 (2004): 459–470.

Longford, Graham. “Sensitive Killers, Cruel Aesthetes, and Pitiless Poets: Foucault, Rorty, and the Ethics of Self-Fashioning.” Polity 33, no. 4 (Summer, 2001): 569–592.

Lovejoy, Arthur O. “Present Standpoints and Past History.” Journal of Philosophy 36, no. 18 (Aug., 1939): 477–489.

Luhmann, Niklas. “System as Difference.” Organization 13, no. 1 (Jan., 2006): 37–57.

Macintyre, Stuart. “History, Politics and the Philosophy of History.” Australian Historical Studies , no. 123 (2004): 130–136.

323 Bibliography

Mack, Mary Peter. “The Fabians and Utilitarianism.” Journal of the History of Ideas 16, no. 1 (Jan., 1955): 76–88.

MacKenzie, Ian. “Gadamer's Hermeneutics and the Use of Forgery.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 45, no. 1 (Autumn, 1986): 41–48.

——“Improvisation, Creativity, and Formulaic Language.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 58, no. 2 (Spring, 2000): 173–179.

Macklin, Ruth. “The New Conservatives in Bioethics: Who are They and What Do They Seek? .” Hastings Center Report 36, no. 1 (Jan.–Feb., 2006): 34–43.

Maclean, Michael, J. “Johann Droysen and the Development of Historical Hermeneutics.” History and Theory 21, no. 3 (Oct., 1983): 347–365.

Makkreel, Rudolf A. “Toward a Concept of Style: An Interpretation of Wilhelm Dilthey's Psycho- Historical Account of the Imagination.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 27, no. 2 (Winter, 1968): 171–182.

Mandelbaum, Maurice. “The History of Ideas, Intellectual History, and the History of Philosophy.” History and Theory 5, no. 5 (1965): 33–66.

Maniates, Maria Rika. “The Reception of New Music Today: A Response.” New Literary History 17, no. 2 (Winter, 1986): 381–390.

Mara, Gerald M. “After Virtue, Autonomy: Jürgen Habermas and Greek Political Theory.” The Journal of Politics 47, no. 4 (Nov., 1985): 1036–1061.

Marcus, Steven. “Humanities from Classics to Cultural Studies.” Daedalus 135, no. 2 (Spring, 2006): 15–21.

Marginson, Simon. “Steering from a Distance: Power relations in Australian Higher Education.” Higher Education 34, no. 1 (Jul., 1997): 63–80.

——“Academic Creativity Under New Public Management: Foundations for an Investigation.” Educational Theory 58, no. 3 (Aug., 2008): 269–287.

Martinson, Steven, D. “Filling the Gaps: “The Problem of World Order” in Friedrich Schiller's essay on Universal History.” Eighteenth-Century Studies 22, no. 1 (Autumn, 1988): 24–46.

Mauss, Marcel. “Une Categorie de L'Esprit Humain: La Notion de Personne Celle de”Moi".” Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland 68, no. (Jul.–Dec., 1938): 263–281.

Mazzeo, Joseph, Anthony. “Some Interpretations of the History of Ideas [Fetschrift for Philip P. Wiener].” Journal of the History of Ideas 33, no. 3 (Jul.–Sep. 1972): 379–394.

McCarthy, Thomas. “History and Evolution: On the Changing Relation of Theory to Practice in the Work of Jürgen Habermas.” Philosophy of Science , no. (1978): 397–423.

——“Complexity and Democracy, or the Seducements of Systems Theory.” New German Critique 35, no. Special Issue (Spring–Summer, 1985): 27–53.

McCollow, J. and R. Lingard. “Changing Discourses and Practices of Academic Work.” Australian Universities Review , no. 2 (1986): 11–19.

McGann, Jerome. “A Note on the Current State of Humanities Scholarship.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 409–413.

——“Culture and Technology: The Way We Live Now, What is to be Done?.” New Literary History 36, no. 1 (Winter, 2005): 71–82.

324 Bibliography

McKusick, James C. “A New Poem by Samuel Taylor Coleridge.” Modern Philology 84, no. 4 (May, 1987): 407–415.

McLean, Ian. “Hegel of Darwin? The Role of Tendencies in Bernard Smith's Historiography.” Thesis Eleven , no. 82 (August, 2005): 54–61.

McNeill, William H. “History and Scientific Worldview.” History and Theory 37, no. 1 (Feb., 1998): 1–13.

Megill, Allan. “Fragmentation and the Future of Historiography.” American Historical Review 96, no. 3 (Jun., 1991): 693–698.

——“Globalization and the History of Ideas.” Journal of the History of Ideas 66, no. 2 (Apr.–Jun. 2005): 155–167.

Meltzer, Francoise. “Future? What Future.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 468–471.

Milburn, Colin. “Nano/Splatter: Disintegrating the Postbiological Body.” New Literary History 36, no. 2 (Spring, 2005): 283–311.

Milsom, S. F. C. “F. W. Maitland” in Proceedings of the British Academy. Vol. 66, 1980. London: Oxford University Press, 1982: 265–281.

——“Maitland.” Cambridge Law Journal 60, no. 2 (Jul., 2001): 265–270.

Mink, Louis O. “History and Fiction as Modes of Comprehension.” New Literary History 1, no. 3 (Spring, 1970): 541–558.

Molt, Andreas. “Adorno and the Myth of Subjectivity.” Contretemps 3, no. (Apr., 2002): 109–121.

Moon, J. Donald. “Understanding and Explanation in Social Science: On Runciman's Critique of Weber.” Political Theory 5, no. 2 (May, 1977): 183–198.

——“Values and Political Theory: A Modest Defense of a Qualified Cognitivism.” The Journal of Politics 39, no. 4 (Nov., 1977): 877–903.

Moravia, Sergio. “From Homme Machine to Homme Sensible: Changing Eighteenth-Century Models of Man's Image.” Journal of the History of Ideas 39, no. 1 (Jan.–Mar. 1978): 45–60.

Morgan, Peter. “Bloom, Frye, and the Academic Aspiration after the Unity of Knowledge.” Interchange 22, no. 12 (1991): 29–38.

Morris, Meaghan. “Humanities for Taxpayers: Some Problems.” New Literary History 36, no. 1 (Winter, 2005): 111–129.

Moyn, Samuel. “Amos Funkenstein on the Theological Origins of Historicism.” Journal of the History of Ideas 64, no. 4 (Oct.–Dec. 2003): 639–657.

Muller, Johan and George Subotzky. “What Knowledge is Needed in the New Millennium?.” Organization 8, no. 2 (2001): 163–182.

Newton, Tim. “Crossing the Great Divide: Time, Nature, and the Social.” Sociology 37, no. 3 (Aug., 2003): 433–457.

Noiriel, Gerard. “Foucault and History: The Lessons of Disillusion.” Journal of Modern History 66, no. 3 (Sep. 1994): 547–568.

Nonaka, Ijujiro and Noboru Konno. “The Concept of”Ba": Building a Foundation for Knowledge Creation.” California Management Review 40, no. 3 (Spring, 1998): 40–54.

325 Bibliography

Novick, Peter. “My Correct Views on Everything.” American Historical Review 96, no. 3 (Jun., 1991): 699–703.

Nowotny, Helga, Peter Scott and Michael Gibbons . “Introduction: ‘Mode 2’ Revisited: The New Production of Knowledge.” Minerva 41, no. 3 (Sep., 2003): 179–194.

Nybom, Thorsten. “The Humboldt Legacy: Reflections on the Past, Present, and Future of the European University.” Higher Education Policy , no. 16 (2003): 141–159.

Ohman, Arne. “Making Sense of Emotion: Evolution, Reason, and the Brain.” Daedalus 135, no. 3 (Summer, 2006): 33–45.

O'Leary, Timothy. “Foucault, Dewey, and the Experience of Literature.” New Literary History 36, no. 4 (Autumn, 2005): 543–557.

Orr, Linda. “The Revenge of Literature: A History of History.” New Literary History 18, no. 1 (Autumn, 1986): 1–22.

Owen, Tim. “Genetic Social Science and the Study of Human Biotechnology.” Current Sociology 54, no. 6 (Nov., 2006): 897–917.

Palti, Elias. “In Memoriam: Hans Blumenberg (1920–1996), An Unended Quest.” Journal of the History of Ideas 58, no. 3 (Jul.–Sep. 1997): 503–524.

——“The ‘Return of the Subject’ as a Historico-intellectual Problem.” History and Theory 43, no. 1 (Feb., 2004): 57–82.

Pantin, W. A. “Frederick Maurice Powicke.” English Historical Review 80, no. 314 (January, 1965): 1– 9.

Paz, Octavio. “In Search of the Present.” The New Republic 204, no. 2 (Jan., 7, 1991): 33–37.

Pena, Alonso, . “On the Role of Mathematical Biology in Contemporary Historiography.” History and Theory 38, no. 4 (Dec., 1999): 101–120.

Pensky, Max. “Natural History: the Life and Afterlife of a Concept in Adorno.” Critical Horizons 5, no. 1 (Apr., 2004): 228–258.

Peschl, M. F. “Modes of Knowing and Modes of Coming to Know. Knowledge Creation and Knowledge Co-Construction as Socio-epistemological Engineering in Educational Processes.” Constructivist Foundations 1, no. 3 (2006): 111–123.

Peters, Edward. “The Desire to Know the Secrets of the World.” Journal of the History of Ideas , no. (2001): 593–610.

Pethes, Nicholas. “Terminal Man: Biotechnological Experimentation and the Reshaping of ‘the Human’ in Medical Thrillers.” New Literary History 36, no. 2 (Spring, 2005): 161–185.

Phillips, Mark, Salber. “Reconsideration on History and Antiquarianism: Arnaldo Momigliano and the Historiography of Eighteenth-Century Britain.” Journal of the History of Ideas 57, no. 2 (Apr.–Jun. 1996): 297–316.

Pike, Rhana. “Plenary Presentation: To Sail beyond the Sunset: Navigating the Uncharted Waters of Bioethics”. Science Editor 27, no. 5, (Sep.–Oct. 2004).

Pinker, Steven. “Why Nature and Nurture Won't Go Away.” Daedalus 134, no. 4 (Fall, 2005): 5–17.

Pippin, Robert B. “Idealism and Agency in Kant and Hegel.” Journal of Philosophy 88, no. 10 (Oct., 1991): 532–541.

326 Bibliography

——“Critical Inquiry and Critical Theory.” Critical Inquiry 30, no. 2 (Winter, 2004): 424–428.

Poe, Marshall. “Butterfield's Sociology of Whig History: A Contribution to the Study of Anachronism in Modern Historical Thought.” Clio 25, no. 4 (Summer, 1996): 345–363.

Poole, Millicent. “Re-framing Higher Education: Mind the Market.” Dialogue 18, no. 1 (1999): 27–43.

Price, William J. and Lawrence W. Bass. “Scientific Research and the Innovative Process.” Science 164, no. 3881 (May, 1969): 802–806.

Protevi, John. “Deleuze, Guattari and Emergence.” Paragraph 29, no. 2 (2006): 19–39.

Quillen, Carol E. “Crossing the Line: Limits and Desire in Historical Interpretation.” History and Theory 37, no. 1 (Feb., 1998): 40–68.

Quine, W. V. “Main Trends in Recent Philosophy: Two Dogmas of Empiricism.” Philosophical Review 60, no. 1 (Jan., 1951): 20–43.

Reill, Peter Hanns. “Narration and Structure in Late Eighteenth-Century Historical Thought.” History and Theory 25, no. 3 (Oct., 1986): 286–298.

——“Science and the Construction of the Cultural Sciences in Late Enlightenment Germany: The Case of Wilhelm von Humboldt.” History and Theory 33, no. 3 (Oct., 1994): 345–366.

Richter, Melvin. “Begriffsgeschichte and the History of Ideas.” Journal of the History of Ideas 48, no. 2 (Apr.–Jun. 1987): 247–263.

——“Understanding Begriffsgeschichte. A rejoinder.” Political Theory 17, no. 2 (May, 1989): 296– 301.

——“Reconstructing the History of Political Languages: Pocock, Skinner, and the Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe.” History and Theory 29, no. 1 (Feb., 1990): 38–70.

Ridley, Glynis . “Losing America and Finding Australia: Continental Shift in an Enlightenment Paradigm.” Eighteenth-Century Life 26, no. 3 (2002): 202–224.

Ringer, Fritz, K. “Counter comment [to 'Problems in the History of Higher Education': A Review Article].” Comparative Studies in Society and History 19, no. 2 (Apr. 1977): 258–258.

——“The Intellectual Field, Intellectual History, and the Sociology of Knowledge.” Theory and Society 19, no. 3 (Jun., 1990): 269–294.

——“Max Weber on Causal Analysis, Interpretation, and Comparison.” History and Theory 41, no. 2 (May, 2002): 163–178.

——“Max Weber's Liberalism.” Central European History 35, no. 3 (2002): 379–395.

Rip, Arie. “Constructing Expertise: In a Third Wave of Science Studies.” Social Studies of Science 33, no. 3 (Jun., 2003): 419–434.

Roberts, Robert C. “What an Emotion Is: A Sketch.” Philosophical Review 97, no. 2 (Apr., 1988): 183–209.

Rorty, Richard. “Philosophy-Envy.” Daedalus 134, no. 4 (Fall, 2005): 18–24.

Ross, Dorothy. “Afterword.” American Historical Review 96, no. 3 (Jun., 1991): 704–708.

Roth, Michael S. “Introduction.” New Literary History 21, no. 2 (Winter, 1990): 239–251.

327 Bibliography

——“The 'Ironist's Cage'.” Political Theory 19, no. 3 (August, 1991): 419–432.

——“Performing History: Modernist Contextualisation in Carl Schorske's Fin-de-siecle Vienna.” American Historical Review 99, no. 3 (Jun., 1994): 729–745.

Runciman, W. G. “Weber's Understanding: A Reply to J. Donald Moon.” Political Theory 5, no. 2 (May, 1977): 199–204.

——“Culture Does Evolve.” History and Theory 44, no. 2 (Feb., 2005): 1–13.

Rundell, John, et. al. “Issues and Debates in Contemporary Critical and Social Philosophy.” Critical Horizons 5, no. 1 (Apr., 2004): 1–25.

Sachs, Aaron. “The Ultimate ‘Other’: Post-colonialism and Alexander Von Humboldt's Ecological Relationship with Nature.” History and Theory 42, no. 4 (Dec., 2003): 111–135.

Sahlins, Marshall. “What is Anthropological Enlightenment? Some Lessons of the Twentieth Century.” Annual Review of Anthropology 28, no. (1999): i–xxiii.

Saint-Amand, Pierre and Sophia Hawkes. “Contingency and the Enlightenment.” SubStance 26, no. 2 (1997): 96–109.

Saler, Michael. “Modernity and Enchantment: A Historiographic Review.” American Historical Review 111, no. 3 (Jun., 2006): 692–716.

Salter, Ammon J. and Ben J. Martin. “The Economic Benefits of Publicly Funded Basic Research: A Critical Review.” Research Policy 30, no. 3 (2001): 509–532.

Sass, Louis, A. “Introspection, Schizophrenia, and the Fragmentation of the Self.” Representations , no. 19 (Summer, 1987): 1–34.

——“Pathogenesis, Common-Sense, and the Cultural Framework: A Commentary on Stanghelli.” Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 8, no. 2&3 (June/September, 2001): 219–224.

——“Incomprehensibility and Understanding.” Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 10, no. 2 (June, 2003): 125–132.

——“Some Reflections on the (Analytic) Philosophical Approach to Delusion.” Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 11, no. 1 (March, 2004): 71–80.

Saunders, David. “The Critical Jurist and the Moment of Theory.” Postcolonial Studies 10, no. 1 (2007): 77–92.

Sawyer, R. Keith. “Emergence in Sociology: Contemporary Philosophy of Mind and Some Implications for Sociological Theory.” American Journal of Sociology 107, no. 3 (Nov., 2001): 551– 585.

Schatzki, Theodore R. “Nature and Technology in History.” History and Theory 42, no. 4 (Dec., 2003): 82–93.

Schütze, Christian. “The Political and Intellectual Influence of Hans Jonas.” Hastings Center Report 25, no. 7 (1995): 40–43.

Scott, Joan, W. “The Evidence of Experience.” Critical Inquiry 17, no. 4 (Summer, 1991): 773–797.

Searle, John R. “Free Will as a Problem in Neurobiology.” Philosophy 76, no. 298 (Oct., 2001): 491– 514.

Serres, Michel. “Response: to”What are the Questions that Fascinate You?”"What Do You Want to Know?”.” SubStance 32, no. 1 (Issue 100, 2003): 56–59.

328 Bibliography

——and Felicia McCarren. “The Natural Contract.” Critical Inquiry 19, no. 1 (Autumn, 1992): 1–21.

——and Roxanne Lapidus. “Knowing and Believing: A Dialogue.” SubStance 23, no. 2 (Issue 74, 1994): 49–55.

——and Roxanne Lapidus. “Anaximander: A Founding Name in History.” SubStance 22, no. 1& 2 (Issue 71/72, 1993): 266–273.

——and Roxanne Lapidus. “Literature and the Exact Sciences.” SubStance 18, no. 2 (Issue 59, 1989): 3–34.

Sewell, Keith C. “The 'Herbert Butterfield Problem’ and its Resolution.” Journal of the History of Ideas 64, no. 4 (Oct., 2003): 599–618.

Shaw, David Gary, . “The Return of Science.” History and Theory 38, no. 4 (Dec., 1999): 1–9.

Sheehan, Donal. “The Manchester Literary and Philosophical Society.” Isis 33, no. 4 (Dec., 1941): 519–523.

Simon, Bart. “Introduction: Toward a Critique of Posthuman Futures.” Cultrual Critique , no. 53 (Winter, 2003): 2–9.

Simon, Herbert A. “The Architecture of Complexity.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 106, no. 6 (Dec., 1962): 467–482.

Singer, Irving. “The Morality of Sex: Contra Kant.” Critical Horizons 1, no. 2 (Sep., 2000): 175–191.

Skinner, Quentin. “Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas.” History and Theory 8, no. 1 (1968): 3–53.

——“Hermeneutics and the Role of History.” New Literary History 7, no. 1 (Autumn, 1975): 209–232.

——“Sir Geoffrey Elton and the Practice of History.” Transactions of the Royal Historical Society 7, (1997): 301–316.

Smith, Barbara Herrnstein. “Belief and Resistance: A Symmetrical Account.” Critical Inquiry 18, no. 1 (Autumn, 1991): 125–139.

——“Relativism, Today and Yesterday.” Common Knowledge 13, no. 2,3 (Spring–Fall, 2007): 227– 249.

Soffer, Reba N. “The Revolution in English Social Thought, 1818–1914.” American Historical Review 75, no. 7 (Dec., 1970): 1938–1964.

——“Nation, Duty, Character and Confidence: History at Oxford, 1850–1914.” Historical Journal 30, no. 1 (March, 1987): 77–104.

Soll, Jacob. “Introduction: The Uses of Historical Evidence in Early Modern Europe.” Journal of the History of Ideas 64, no. 2 (Apr., 2003): 149–157.

——“Empirical History and the Transformation of Political Criticism in France from Bodin to Bayle.” Journal of the History of Ideas64 , no. 2 (Apr., 2003): 297–316.

Sorkin, David. “Wilhelm Von Humboldt: The Theory and Practice of Self-formation (Bildung).” Journal of the History of Ideas 44, no. 1 (Jan.–Mar. 1983): 55–73.

Spacks, Patricia Meyer. “Revolution in the Humanities.” Daedalus 135, no. 2 (Spring, 2006): 11–14.

329 Bibliography

Spiegel, Gabrielle, . “History, Historicism and the Social Logic of the Text in the Middle Ages.” Speculum 65, no. 1 (January, 1990): 59–86.

Starn, Randolph. “Historians and”crisis".” Past and Present , no. 52 (Aug., 1971): 3–22.

Stern, David G. “Models of Memory: Wittgenstein and Cognitive Science.” Philosophical Psychology 4, no. 2 (1991): 203–218.

——“The 'Middle Wittgenstein': from Logical Atomism to Practical Holism.” Synthese 87, no. 2 (1991): 203–226.

Stewart, Susan. “Thoughts on the Role of the Humanities in Contemporary Life.” New Literary History 36, no. 1 (Winter, 2005): 97–103.

Stone, Lawrence and Gabrielle, M. Spiegel. “History and Post-Modernism.” Past and Present , no. 135 (May, 1992): 189–208.

Stout, G. F. “S. Alexander (1859–1938): Personal Reminiscences.” Mind 49, no. 193 (January, 1940): 126–129.

——“The Philosophy of Samuel Alexander (I.).” Mind 49, no. 193 (January, 1940): 1–18.

Strong, E. W. “William Whewell and John Stuart Mill: Their Controversy about Scientific Knowledge.” Journal of the History of Ideas 16, no. 2 (Apr.–Jun. 1955): 209–231.

Struever, Nancy S. “Historical Priorities.” Journal of the History of Ideas 66, no. 4 (Oct., 2005): 541– 556.

Stuart-Fox, Martin, . “Evolutionary Theory of History.” History and Theory 38, no. 4 (Dec., 1999): 33– 51.

Sweet, Paul R. “Young Wilhelm von Humboldt's Writings Reconsidered.” Journal of the History of Ideas 34, no. 3 (Jul.–Sep. 1973): 469–482.

Szabados, Bela. “What is the Role of the Arts and Aesthetics in Wittgenstein's Philosophy?.” Canadian Aesthetics Journal 10, no. (Fall, 2004): http://www.uqtr.uquebec.ca/AE/.

Thacker, Eugene. “Data Made Flesh: Biotechnology and the Discourse of the Posthuman.” Cultrual Critique , no. 53 (Winter, 2003): 72–97.

——“What is Biomedia?.” Configurations 11, no. 1 (Winter, 2003): 47–79.

Therborn, Goran. “Dialectics of Modernity:On Critical Theory and the Legacy of Twentieth-Century Marxism.” New Left Review I/215, no. (Jan.–Feb., 1996): 59–81.

——“After Dialectics: Radical Social Theory in a Post-Communist World .” New Left Review 43, no. (Jan.–Feb., 2007): 63–119.

Thomas, Keith. “History and Anthropology.” Past and Present , no. 24 (Apr., 1963): 3–24.

Tierney, William G. “Academic Freedom and Tenure - Between Fiction and Reality.” Journal of Higher Education 75, no. 2 (March/April, 2004): 161–177.

Tiles, Mary. “The Normal and Pathological: The Concept of Scientific Medicine.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44, no. 4 (Dec., 1993): 729–742.

Toews, John E. “Intellectual History after the Linguistic Turn: The Autonomy of Meaning and the Irreducibility of Experience.” American Historical Review 92, no. 4 (Oct., 1987): 879–907.

330 Bibliography

——“Refashioning the Masculine Subject in Early Modernism: Narratives of Self-Dissolution and Self-Construction in Psychoanalysis and Literature, 1900–1914.” Modernism/Modernity 4, no. 1 (1997): 31–67.

Toulmin, Stephen. “The Plausibility of Theories.” Journal of Philosophy 63, no. 20 (Oct., 1966): 624– 627.

Tsao, J. Y. et. al. “Galileo's Stream: A framework for Understanding Knowledge Production.” Research Policy 37, no. (2008): 330–352.

Uebel, Thomas E. “Anti-Foundationalism and the Vienna Circle's Revolution in Philosophy.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47, no. 3 (Sep., 1996): 415–440.

——“Logical Empiricism and the Sociology of Knowledge: The Case of Neurath and Frank.” Philosophy of Science 67, no. (Sep., 2000): s138–s150.

Unger, Rudolph. “The Problem of Historical Objectivity: A Sketch of its Development to the Time of Hegel [1923].” History and Theory Beiheft 11, no. (1971): 60–86.

Velimirovic, Milos. “Changing Interpretations of Music.” New Literary History 17, no. 2 (Winter, 1986): 365–380.

Vilar, Pierre. “Marxist History, A History in the Making: Towards a Dialogue with Althusser.” New Left Review 80, no. (Jul.–Aug., 1973): 65–106.

Vogel, Lawrence. “Does Environmental Ethics Need a Metaphysical Grounding?.” Hastings Center Report 25, no. 7 (1995): 30–39.

Weikart, Richard. “Darwinism and Death: Devaluing Human Life in Germany 1859–1920.” Journal of the History of Ideas , no. (2002): 323–344.

Weinberg, Steven. “Physics and History.” Daedalus 134, no. 4 (Fall, 2005): 31–39.

Weingart, Peter. “Close Encounters of the Third Kind: Science and the Context of Relevance.” Poetics Today 9, no. 1 (1988): 43–60.

Wilkens, Matthew. “Toward a Benjaminian Theory of Dialectical Allegory.” New Literary History 37, no. 2 (Spring, 2006): 285–298.

Wilkins, Burleigh Taylor. “Frederick York Powell and Charles A. Beard: A Study in Anglo-American Historiography and Social Thought.” American Quarterly 11, no. 1 (Spring, 1959): 21–39.

Wilson, Patrick. “Interdisciplinary Research and Information Overload.” Library Trends 44, no. 2 (Fall, 1996): 192–203.

Wolfle, Dael. “Changing Research Emphasis.” Science 164, no. 3881 (May, 1969): 773–773.

Wrangham, Richard. “Killer Species.” Daedalus 134, no. 4 (Fall, 2005): 25–35.

Zagorin, Perez. “History, the Referent and Narrative: Reflections on Postmodernism Now.” History and Theory 38, no. 1 (Feb., 1999): 1–24.

Zammito, John H. “Are We Being Theoretical Yet? The New Historicism, the New Philosophy of History, and Practicing Historians.” Journal of Modern History 65, no. 4 (Dec., 1993): 783 – 814.

——“Ankersmit and Historical Representation.” History and Theory 44, no. 2 (May, 2005): 155–181.

331 Bibliography

Review Articles

Aaron, Richard I. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Function of Reason by A. N. Whitehead. Mind 39, no. 156 (Oct., 1930): 488–492.

Abelove, Henry. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Poverty of Theory by E. P. Thompson. History and Theory 21, no. 1 (Feb., 1982): 132–142.

Acton, H. B. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Faith and History: A Comparison of Christian and Modern Views of History, by Reinhold Niebuhr. Ethics 60, no. 3 (Apr., 1950): 218–221.

——[Review] “Religion, Culture, and Class.” Reviewed Work(s): Notes Towards the Definition of Culture by T. S. Eliot. Ethics 60, no. 2 (Jan., 1950): 120–130.

Allen, Barry. [Review] “The Soul of Knowledge.” Reviewed Works: Reviewing the Soul: Multiple Personality and the Sciences of Memory by Ian Hacking. History and Theory 36, no. 1 (Feb., 1997): 63–82.

Audetat, Marc. [Review] “Re-Thinking Science, Re-Thinking Society.” Reviewed Work(s): Re- Thinking Science: Knowledge and the Public in an Age of Uncertainty by Helga Nowotny, Peter Scott, Michael Gibbons. Social Studies of Science 31, no. 6 (Dec., 2001): 950–956.

Bereiter, Carl. [Review] “Follow the Money to Real Science.” Reviewed Work(s): Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge by Edward O. Wilson; Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meaning of Life by Daniel C. Dennett. The Journal of the Learning Sciences 9, no. 2 (2000): 205–208.

Bevir, Mark. [Review] “Begriffsgeschichte.” Reviewed Work(s): The History of Political and Social Concepts: A Critical Introduction by Melvin Richter; History of Concepts: Comparative Perspectives by Iain Hampsher-Monk, Karin Tilmans, Frank van Vree. History and Theory 39, no. 2 (May, 2000): 273–284.

Block, Ned. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Consciousness Explained, by Daniel Dennett. Journal of Philosophy 90, no. 4 (Apr., 1993): 181–193.

Bloor, David. [Review] “A Civil Skepticism.” Reviewed Work(s): Belief and Resistance: Dynamics of Contemporary Intellectual Controversy by Barbara Herrnstein Smith. Social Studies of Science 28, no. 4 (Aug., 1998): 655–665.

Bouwsma, William J. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The Legitimacy of the Modern Age, by Hans Blumenberg. Journal of Modern History 56, no. 4 (Dec., 1984): 698–701.

——[Review] “Work on Blumenberg.” Reviewed Work(s): Work on Myth by Hans Blumenberg, trans. Robert M. Wallace. Journal of the History of Ideas 48, no. 2 (Apr.–Jun. 1987): 347–354.

Bredo, Eric. [Review] “Unifying Biological and Cultural Psychology” Reviewed Work(s): Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge by Edward O. Wilson; Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meaning of Life by Daniel C. Dennett. The Journal of the Learning Sciences 9, no. 2 (2000): 221–232.

Burger, Thomas. [Review] “Concepts and Reality, Values and Validity.” Reviewed Work(s): The Limits of Concept Formation in Natural Science: A Logical Introduction to the Historical Sciences by Heinrich Rickert; Guy Oakes. American Journal of Sociology 93, no. 4 (Jan., 1988): 959–966.

Campbell, Gregor. [Review] “Work on Reason.” Reviewed Work(s): Work on Myth by Hans Blumenberg; The Legitimacy of the Modern Age by Hans Blumenberg; The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity by Jürgen Habermas. Diacritics 21, no. 4 (Winter, 1991): 53–68.

Caporael, Linnda R. [Review] “The Hybrid Science.” Reviewed Work(s): Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge by Edward O. Wilson; Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meaning of Life by Daniel C. Dennett. The Journal of the Learning Sciences 9, no. 2 (2000): 209–220.

332 Bibliography

Carr, David. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Times by Reinhart Koselleck; Keith Tribe. History and Theory 26, no. 2 (May, 1987): 197–204.

Casey, John. [Review] “After Virtue.” Reviewed Work(s): After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory by Alasdair Macintyre. Philosophical Quarterly 33, no. 132 (Jul., 1983): 296–300.

Chakrabarty, Dipesh. [Review] “A Global and Multicultural”Discipline”of History?” Reviewed Work(s): Western Historical Thinking: An Intellectual Intercultural Debate, by Jorn Rusen . History and Theory 45, no. 1 (Feb., 2006): 101–109.

Cheney, C. R. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Historical Essays in Honour of James Tait by J. G. Edwards, V. H. Galbraith and E. F. Jacob, eds. English Historical Review 50, no. 197 (January, 1935): 128–131.

Christian, David. [Review] “History in the Landscapes of Modern Knowledge.” Reviewed Work(s): The Landscape of History: How Historians Map the Past by John Lewis Gaddis. History and Theory 43, no. 3 (Oct., 2004): 360–371.

Chytry, Josef. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Modernism as a Philosophical Problem: On the Dissatisfactions of European High Culture by Robert B. Pippin. History and Theory 34, no. 1 (Feb., 1995): 106–121.

Clark, Stephen R. L. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues, by Alasdair Macintyre. Philosophical Quarterly 51, no. 203 (Apr., 2001): 266–269.

Coles, Romand. [Review] “Of Democracy, Discourse, and Dirt Virtue: Developments in Recent Critical Theory.” Reviewed work(s): Endgames: The Irreconcilable Nature of Modernity. Essays and Lectures by Albrecht Wellmer; David Midgley, Habermas on Law and Democracy: Critical Exchanges by Michel Rosenfeld; Andrew Arato, The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory by Jürgen Habermas; Ciaran Cronin; Pablo De Greiff, On the Pragmatics of Communication by Jürgen Habermas, trans. Maeve Cooke. Political Theory 28, no. 4 (Aug., 2000): 540–564.

Collins, Randall. [Review] “Is the History of Ideas a Principled Eclecticism?” Reviewed Work(s): The Descent of Ideas:The History of Intellectual History by Donald R. Kelley. History and Theory 43, no. 2 (Feb., 2004): 136–145.

Connelly, James. [Review] “A Time for Progress?” Reviewed Work(s): A Study of the Idea of Progress in Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Critical Theory by Guiseppe Tassone. History and Theory 43, no. 3 (Oct., 2004): 410–422.

Connolly, William E. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory by Alasdair Macintyre. Political Theory 10, no. 2 (May, 1982): 315–319.

——[Review] “Spinoza and Us.” Reviewed Work(s): Bodies, Masses, Power: Spinoza and His Contemporaries by Warren Montag, Collective Imaginings: Spinoza Past and Present by Moira Gatens and Genevieve Lloyd, The New Spinoza (Theory Out of Bounds) by Warren Montag and Ted Stolze . Political Theory 29, no. 4 (Aug., 2001): 583–594.

Creighton, J. F. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Lectures on Modern Idealism by Josiah Royce. Philosophical Review 30, no. 3 (May, 1921): 309–312.

Crowell, Steven Galt. [Review] “Rationalism in History.” Reviewed Work(s): Logic of the History of Ideas by Mark Bevir. Diacritics 33, no. 1 (Spring, 2003): 3–22.

Dallmayr, Fred R. and DianeRubenstein. [Review] “Four Discourses and Four Volumes.” Reviewed Work(s): The Augustinian Imperative. Vol. 1, Modernity and Political Thought by William E. Connolly; Thomas Hobbes: Skepticism, Individuality and Chastened Politics. Vol. 2, Modernity and Political Thought by Richard E. Flatham; G. W. F. Hegel: Modernity and Politics. Vol. 3, Modernity

333 Bibliography

and Political Thought by Fred R. Dallmayr; Desire, History, and Value. Vol. 4, Modernity and Political Thought by Michael J. Shapiro. The Journal of Politics 56, no. 4 (Nov., 1994): 1119–1132.

DeLaura, David J. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Idea of a University Defined and Illustrated by John Henry Newman by Ian Ker. Modern Language Review 74, no. 2 (Apr., 1979): 427– 430.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Letters and Diaries of John Henry Newman. Volume II. Tutor of Oriel, January 1827 to December 1831 by Ian Ker: Thomas Gornall: John Henry Newman; The Letters and Diaries of John Henry Newman. Volume III. TNew Bearings, January 1832 to June 1833 by Ian Ker: Thomas Gornall: John Henry Newman. Modern Language Review 76, no. 3 (Jul., 1981): 682–686.

Dennett, Daniel. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience by Francisco J. Varela, Evan Thompson and Eleanor Rosch . American Journal of Psychology 106, no. 1 (Spring, 1993): 121–126.

deVries, Jacqueline R. [Review] “Why History? Ethics and Postmodernity and What Happens to History: The Renewal of Ethics in Contemporary Thought.” Reviewed Work(s): Why History? Ethics and Postmodernity by Keith Jenkins. What Happens to History: The Renewal of Ethics in Contemporary Thought. Edited by Howard Marchitello . Clio 32, no. 2 (Winter, 2003): 209–217.

Dreyfus, Hubert L. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience by Francisco J. Varela, Evan Thompson and Eleanor Rosch . Mind 102, no. 407 (Jul., 1993): 542–546.

Duda, John. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Archaeologies of the Future: The Desire Called Utopia and Other Science Fictions by Fredric Jameson . MLN 120, no. 5 (Dec., 2005): 1245–1249.

Dunn, Susan. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Romanticism and the Rise of History by Stephen Bann. History and Theory 35, no. 3 (Oct., 1996): 384–390.

Eldridge, Richard. [Review] “History vs. (Epistemological) Theory.” Reviewed Work(s): Interpretive Reasoning, by Laurent Stern. History and Theory 45, no. 3 (Oct., 2006): 448–454.

Elton, Oliver. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Biographia Literaria by by S. T. Coleridge: J. Shawcross; Coleridge's Literary Criticism: The Indebtedness of Samuel Taylor Coleridge to August Wilhelm von Schlegel by Anne A. Helmholtz. Modern Language Review 4, no. 1 (Oct., 1908): 119– 125.

Feinberg, Walter. [Review] “On ‘After Virtue’." Reviewed Work(s): After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory by Alasdair Macintyre. Theory and Society 13, no. 2 (Mar., 1984): 249-262.

Fennell, Francis L. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): John Henry Newman Sermons 1824–1843: Vol. 1. Sermons on the Liturgy and Sacraments and on Christ the Mediator by Placid Murray; John Henry Newman after a Hundred Years by Ian Ker; Alan Hill; John Henry Newman and the Liberal Heresy by Robert Pattison. Victorian Studies 37, no. 1 (Autumn, 1993): 144–147.

Fesmire, Steven. [Review] “Philosophy Disrobed: Lakoff and Johnson’s Call for Empirically Responsible Philosophy.” Reviewed Work(s): Philosophy In the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought, by George Lakoff and Mark Johnson . The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 14, no. 4 (2001): 300–305.

Foster, Thomas. [Review] “The Reappearing Body in Postmodern Technoculture.” Reviewed Work(s): How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature, and Informatics by N. Katherine Hayles. Contemporary Literature 42, no. 3 (Autumn, 2001): 617–631.

Fournier, Marcel. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Against Essentialism: A Theory of Culture and Society by Stephan Fuchs. Canadian Journal of Sociology 28, no. 3 (Summer, 2003): 433–436.

334 Bibliography

Friedman, Michael. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Philosophical Papers by Moritz Schlick; H. L. Mulder, B. F. B. van de Velde-Schlick, eds. Philosophy of Science 50, no. 3 (Sep., 1983): 498– 514.

Fromm, Harold. [Review] “A Crucifix for Dracula: Wendell Berry Meets Edward O. Wilson.” Reviewed Work(s): Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge by Edward O. Wilson; Life is A Miracle: An Essay Against Modern Superstition by Wendell Berry. The Hudson Review 53, no. 4 (Winter, 2001): 657–664.

——[Review] “Science Wars and Beyond.” Reviewed Work(s): Scandalous Knowledge: Science, Truth, and the Human by Barbara Herrnstein Smith; Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism, by Paul Boghossian. Philosophy and Literature 30, no. 2 (Oct., 2006): 580–589.

Gabardi, Wayne. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Working Class in Weimar Germany: A Psychological and Sociological Study by Erich Fromm ; Barbara Weinberger ; Wolfgang Bonss. New German Critique, no. 41 (Spring–Summer, 1987): 166–178.

——[Review] “The Philosophical Politics of the Modern–Postmodern Debate.” Reviewed Work(s): Between Freiburg and Frankfurt: Toward a Critical Ontology by Fred Dallmayr; Political Theory and Postmodernism by Stephen K. White; The New Constellation: The Ethical–Political Horizons of Modernity/Postmodernity by Richard J. Bernstein. Political Research Quarterly 47, no. 3 (Sep., 1994): 769–778.

Ghosh, Peter. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Basel in the Age of BurckhardtA Study in Unseasonable Ideas by Lionel Gossman. History of European Ideas 28, no. 4 (Dec., 2002): 295–315.

Godin, Benoit. [Review] “Writing Performative History: The New Atlantis.” Reviewed Work(s): The New Production of Knowledge: The Dynamics of Science and Research in Contemporary Societies by Michael Gibbons, Camille Limoges, Helga Nowotny, Simon Schwartzman, Peter Scott and Martin Trow . Social Studies of Science 28, no. 3 (Jun., 1998): 465–483.

Gordon, Peter E. [Review] “Self-Authorizing Modernity: Problems of Interpretation in the History of German Idealism.” Reviewed Work(s): German Idealism: The Struggle Against Subjectivism, by Frederick Beiser; German Philosophy 1760–1860, by Terry Pinkard. History and Theory 44, no. 2 (Feb., 2005): 121–137.

Gorman, J. L. [Review] “Philosophical Fascination with Whole Historical Texts.” Reviewed Work(s): History and Tropology by F. R. Ankersmit, . History and Theory 36, no. 3 (Oct., 1997): 406–415.

Gossman, Lionel. [Review] “Voices of Silence.” Reviewed Work(s): Imperfect Histories: the Elusive Past and the Legacy of Romantic Historicism by Anne Rigney. History and Theory 43, no. 2 (May, 2004): 272–277.

Gray, Charles, M. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Origins of English Individualism: The Family, Property and Social Transition by Alan Macfarlane; Land, Labour and Economic Discourse by Keith Tribe. Journal of Modern History 52, no. 2 (Jun., 1980): 312–315.

Hacking, Ian. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s):The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change by Thomas S. Kuhn. History and Theory 18, no. 2 (May, 1979): 223– 236.

Hagberg, Gary L. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The Quest for Voice: Music, Politics, and the Limits of Philosophy, by Lydia Goehr. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 58, no. 1 (Winter, 2000): 85–88.

Hansen, David T. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Educating for an Ecological Sustainable Culture by C. A. Bowers. American Journal of Education 97, no. 1 (Nov., 1988): 115–120.

Harrison, Brian. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Witness Against the Beast, William Blake and the Moral Law by E. P. Thompson. English Historical Review 86, no. 340 (Jul., 1971): 574–587.

335 Bibliography

Haskell, Thomas L. [Review] “Farewell to Fallibilism: Robert Berkhofer's Beyond the Great Story and the Allure of the Postmodern.” Reviewed Work(s): Beyond the Great Story: History as Text and Discourse by Robert F. Berkhofer, Jr. History and Theory 37, no. 3 (Oct., 1998): 347–369.

——[Review] “Perspective as a Problem and Solution.” Reviewed Work(s): Historians and Social Values by Joep Leerssen and Anne Rigney (eds.). History and Theory 43, no. 3 (Oct., 2004): 341–359.

Hill, Christopher, S. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Mysterious Flame: Conscious Minds in a Material World by Colin McGinn. Philosophical Review 110, no. 2 (Apr., 2001): 300–303.

Hoffheimer, Michael H. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Philosophy without Foundations: Rethinking Hegel by William Maker. Clio 25, no. 2 (Winter, 1996): 219–224.

Hunter, Ian. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy, by J. B. Schneewind. Philosophical Review 109, no. 3 (Jul., 2000): 444–447.

Iggers, Georg G. [Review] “Historiography in the Twentieth Century.” Reviewed Work(s): Geschichtswissenschaft Im Zeitalter Der Extreme: Theorien; Methoden; Tendenzen Von 1900 Bis Zur Gegenwart, by Luft Raphael . History and Theory 44, no. 3 (Oct., 2005): 469–476.

Jay, Martin. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The Legitmacy of the Modern Age, by Hans Blumenberg. History and Theory 24, no. 2 (May, 1985): 183–196.

——and Jane Flax. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Postmodernism, or, the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, by Frederic Jameson. History and Theory 32, no. 3 (Oct., 1993): 296–310.

Jed, Stephanie. [Review] “Proof and Transnational Rhetorics: Opening Up the Conversation.” Reviewed Work(s): History, Rhetoric, and Proof: The Menahem Stern Jerusalem Lectures, by . History and Theory 40, no. 3 (Oct., 2001): 372–384.

Jonas, Hans. [Review] “A Review Article.” Reviewed Work(s): Visual Thinking, by Rudolph Arnheim. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 30, no. 1 (Autumn, 1971): 111–117.

Jones, Paul Dafydd. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Protestant Theology and the Making of the Modern German University by Thomas Albert Howard. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 75, no. 4 (Dec., 2007): 1006–1009.

Kampf, Louis. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Confrontations: Studies in the Intellectual and Literary Relations between Germany, England, and the United States during the Nineteenth-Century by Rene Wellek; Literary History and Literary Criticism: ACTA of the Ninth Congress International Federation for Modern Languages and Literature, Kenneth McPhee and William M. Gibson (eds.); The Third Dimension: Studies in Literary History by Robert E. Spiller. History and Theory 6, no. 1 (1967): 72–88.

Kelley, Theresa M. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): England in 1819: The Politics of Literary Culture and the Case of Romantic Historicism by James Chandler. Nineteenth-Century Literature 54, no. 4 (Mar., 2000): 534–538.

Kirkland, John. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Prophets of Extremity: Nietzsche, Heidegger, Foucault, Derrida by Allan Megill. History and Theory 26, no. 2 (May, 1987): 204–213.

Klein, Kerwin Lee. [Review] “Anti-history: The Meaning of ‘Historical Culture’." Reviewed Work(s):Historical Culture by Sande Cohen. Clio 25, no. 2 (Winter, 1996): 125–143.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Nothing but History: Reconstruction and Extremity after Metaphysics by David D. Roberts. Theory and Society 27, no. 3 (Jun., 1998): 430–435.

336 Bibliography

——[Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Encounters: Philosophy of History after Postmodernism by Ewa Domanska; Passive Nihilism: Cultural Historiography and the Rhetorics of Scholarship by Sande Cohen . Clio 30, no. 1 (Fall, 2000): 79–90.

Knoper, Randall. [Review] “Fresh Networks: Science, Literature, Feminism, and Cultural Studies.” Reviewed Work(s): Scandalous Knowledge: Science, Truth, and the Human by Barbara Herrnstein Smith; Darwin LovesYou: Natural Selection and the Re-Enchantment of the World by George Levine; The Nick of Time: Politics, Evolution, and the Untimely by Elizabeth Grosz; TimeTravels: Feminism, Nature, Power by Elizabeth Grosz; Psychosomatic: Feminism and the Neurological Body by Elizabeth Wilson; Between Science and Literature: An Introduction to Autopoetics by Ira Livingston. College Literature 35, no. 4 (Fall, 2008): 199–213.

Kramer, Lloyd. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Cultural Semantics: Keywords of Our Time, by Martin Jay. Theory and Society 29, no. 2 (Apr., 2000): 253–261.

Kurtz, Lester R. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Origins of English Individualism: The Family, Property and Social Transition by Alan Macfarlane. American Journal of Sociology 86, no. 2 (Sep., 1980): 403–407.

LaCapra, Dominick. [Review] “Reading Exemplars:Wittgenstein's Vienna and Wittgenstein's Tractatus.” Reviewed Work(s): Wittgentein's Vienna by Allan Janik and Stephen Toulmin. Diacritics 9, no. 2 (Summer, 1979): 65–82.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Empire Unpossess'd: An Essay on Gibbon's Decline and Fall by Lionel Gossman. Comparative Literature 34, no. 1 (Winter, 1982): 78–83.

Lacewing, Michael. [Review] “Emotion and Cognition: Recent Developments and Therapeutic Practice.” Reviewed Work(s): Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions by Martha C. Nussbaum . Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 11, no. 2 (Jun., 2004): 175–186.

Ladd, John. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): New Ways of Ontology by Nicolai Hartmann. Journal of Philosophy 51, no. 3 (Feb., 1954): 108–112.

Laird, John. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Speculum Mentis or the Map of Knowledge, by R. G. Collingwood. Mind 34, no. 134 (Apr., 1925): 235–241.

Levine, Andrew. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts, by Axel Honneth. Ethics 108, no. 3 (Apr., 1998): 619–622.

Levine, David. [Review] “The ‘Correct’ Principles of Social Organisation.” Reviewed Work(s): The Origins of English Individualism: The Family, Property and Social Transition by Alan Macfarlane. Journal of Interdisciplinary History 11, no. 4 (Spring, 1981): 669–676.

Levine, Donald N. [Review] “Sociology After MacIntyre.” Reviewed Work(s): After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory by Alasdair Macintyre. American Journal of Sociology 89, no. 3 (Nov., 1983): 700–707.

Loone, Eero. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Making History: Agency, Structure and Change in Social Theory by Alex Callinocos. History and Theory 29, no. 3 (Oct., 1990): 331–339.

Luft, Sandra Rudnick. [Review] “Secular Theology: in the Modern Age.” Reviewed Work(s): Theology and Scientific Imagination by Amos Funkenstein. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 56, no. 4 (Winter, 1988): 741–750.

Macintyre, Alasdair. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Legitimation of Belief, by Ernst Gellner. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29, no. 1 (Mar., 1978): 105–110.

Makkreel, Rudolf. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Wilhelm Dilthey: The Critique of Historical Reason by Michael Ermarth. History and Theory 19, no. 3 (Oct., 1980): 353–362.

337 Bibliography

May, Todd. [Review] “France's Heidegger: History and Philosophy in the Early Years.” Reviewed Work(s): Generation Existential: Heidegger's Philosophy in France 1927–1961, by Ethan Kleinberg. History and Theory 46, no. 2 (May, 2007): 264–271.

Mazlish, Bruce. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Between Literature and Science: The Rise of Sociology by Wolf Lepenies. Social Forces 69, no. 4 (Jun., 1991): 1249–1256.

McCabe, David . [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Liberals and Cannibals: The Implications of Diversity by Steven Lukes. Ethics 115, no. 2 (Jan., 2005): 427–430.

McCarthy, Thomas. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The New Constellation: The Ethical– Political Horizons of Modernity/Postmodernity by Richard J. Bernstein. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55, no. 4 (Dec., 1995): 977–981.

McKusick, James C. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): German Aesthetic and Literary Criticism Vol. 1: Winckelmann, Lessing, Hamann, Herder, Schiller and Goethe by H. R. Nisbet; German Aesthetic and Literary Criticism Vol. 2: Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Schopenhauer, Hegel by David Simpson; German Aesthetic and Literary Criticism Vol. 3: The Romantic Ironists and Goethe by Kathleen Wheeler. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 45, no. 3 (Spring, 1987): 301–305.

Megill, Allan. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Aesthetic State: A Quest in Modern German Thought by Josef Chytry. History and Theory 30, no. 1 (Feb., 1991): 70–79.

Miers, Paul. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Godel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid by Douglas R. Hofstadter. MLN 94, no. 5 (Dec., 1979): 1214–1218.

Mink, Louis O. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Ideology and Modern Culture, by John B. Thompson. History and Theory 17, no. 2 (May, 1978): 211–223.

Misgeld, Dieter. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Critique, Norm and Utopia: A Study of the Foundations of Critical Theory by Seyla Benhabib. New German Critique, no. 41 (Spring–Summer, 1987): 178–186.

Mitcham, Carl; Roberrt Frodeman. [Review] “Extending Science, Technology, and Society Interdisciplinarity.” Reviewed Work(s): Transdisciplinarity: Joint Problem Solving Among Science, Technology and Society by Julie Thompson Klein, et. al. Science, Technology & Human Values 28, no. 1 (Winter, 2003): 180–183.

Mokyr, Joel. [Review] “The Ambiguity of Technology.” Reviewed Work(s): Human-Built World: How to Think about Technology and Culture, by Thomas P. Hughes . History and Theory 46, no. 1 (Feb., 2007): 59–65.

Monter, William. [Review] “Re-contextualizing British Witchcraft.” Reviewed Work(s): English Witchcraft 1560–1736, 6 Vols. by James Sharpe. Journal of Interdisciplinary History 35, no. 1 (Summer, 2004): 105–111.

Moon, J. Donald. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Restructuring of Social and Political Theory by Richard J. Bernstein. Political Theory 5, no. 2 (May, 1977): 265–268.

Moyn, Samuel. [Review] “Empathy in History, Empathizing with Humanity.” Reviewed Work(s): The Fragility of Empathy After the Holocaust, by Carolyn J. Dean; and History in Transit: Experience, Identity, and Critical Theory, by Dominick La Capra. History and Theory 45, no. 3 (Oct., 2006): 397– 415.

Nagel, Thomas. [Review] “Libertarianism without Foundations.” Reviewed Work(s): Anarchy, State, and Utopia by Robert Nozick. The Yale Law Review Journal 85, no. 1 (Nov., 1975): 136–149.

Nowotny, Helga. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Human Understanding, Vol. 1, General Introduction and Part 1 by Stephen Toulmin. Theory and Society 1, no. 3 (Autumn, 1974): 382–385.

338 Bibliography

Orr, Linda. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Clothing of Clio: A Study of the Representation of History in Nineteenth-Century Britain and France by Stephen Bann. History and Theory 24, no. 3 (Oct., 1985): 307–325.

Outhwaite, William. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The Anatomy of Historical Knowledge, by Maurice Mandelbaum. History and Theory 26, no. 1 (Feb., 1987): 121–127.

Paczkowska-Lagowska, Elzbieta. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Historical Understanding in the Thought of Wilhelm Dilthey by Theodore Plantinga. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 43, no. 1 (Sep., 1982): 116–119.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Wilhelm Dilthey: Pioneer of Human Studies by H. P. Rickman. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 42, no. 3 (Mar., 1982): 454–458.

Palti, Elias. [Review] “Historicism as an Idea and as a Language.” Reviewed Work(s): Politiques De L’histoire: L’historisme Comme Promesse et Comme Mythe. by Jeffrey Andrew Barash. History and Theory 44, no. 3 (Oct., 2005): 431–440.

Pocock, J. G. A. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Origins of English Individualism: The Family, Property and Social Transition by Alan Macfarlane. History and Theory 19, no. 1 (Feb., 1980): 100–105.

Putnam, Ruth Anna. [Review] “Democracy without Foundations.” Reviewed Work(s): Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 3 by Richard Rorty. Ethics 110, no. 2 (January, 2000): 388–404.

Randall, D. W. [Review] “A New Unity or Bad Science?” Reviewed Work(s): Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge by Edward O. Wilson; Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meaning of Life by Daniel C. Dennett. The Journal of the Learning Sciences 9, no. 2 (2000): 233–242.

Ringer, Fritz, K. [Review] “Problems in the History of Higher Education: A Review Article.” Reviewed Work(s): The University in Society, Vol. I: Oxford and Cambridge from the 14th to the Early 19th Century; Vol. II: Europe, Scotland and the United States from the 16th to the 20th Century, by Lawrence Stone. Comparative Studies in Society and History 19, no. 2 (Apr., 1977): 239–255.

Roberts, David D. [Review] “Postmdernism and History: Missing the Missed Connections.” Reviewed Work(s): On the Future of History: The Postmodernist Challenge and Its Aftermath, by Ernst Breisach. History and Theory 44, no. 2 (May, 2005): 240–252.

Roberts, Geofrey. [Review] “Postmodernism versus the Standpoint of Action.” Reviewed Work(s): What is History? From Carr and Elton to Rorty and White by Keith Jenkins. History and Theory 36, no. 2 (May, 1997): 249–260.

Rorty, Richard. [Review] “Putnam on Truth.” Reviewed Work(s): Representation and Reality by Hilary Putnam. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52, no. 2 (Jun., 1992): 415–418.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Idealism as Modernism: Hegelian Variations by Robert Pippin. Ethics 111, no. 2 (Jan., 2001): 438–441.

Rossi, Ino. [Review] “Structural Anthroplogy II (Review Article).” Reviewed Work(s): Structural Anthroplogy. Volume II by Claude Levi-Strauss . Man 15, no. 1 (Mar., 1980): 188–194.

Roth, Guenther. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Force, Fate and Freedom: On Historical Sociology, by Reinhard Bendix. History and Theory 24, no. 2 (May, 1985): 196–208.

Roth, Michael S. [Review] “Classic Post-Modernism.” Reviewed Work(s): Refiguring History: New Thoughts on an Old Discipline by Keith Jenkins. History and Theory 43, no. 3 (Oct., 2004): 372–378.

——[Review] “Ebb Tide.” Reviewed Work(s): Sublime Historical Experience, by F. R. Ankersmitt. History and Theory 46, no. 1 (Feb., 2007): 66–73.

339 Bibliography

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity by Richard Rorty. History and Theory 29, no. 3 (Oct., 1990): 339–357.

Rothblatt, Sheldon. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Victorian Mirror of History by A. Dwight Culler; The Art and Science of Victorian History by Rosemary Jann. Albion: A Quarterly Journal Concerned with British Studies 18, no. 4 (Winter, 1986): 684–687.

Roubach, Michael. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger by Michael Friedman. Philosophical Review 111, no. 1 (Jan., 2002): 119–122.

Scheffler, Samuel. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory by Alasdair Macintyre. Philosophical Review 92, no. 3 (Jul., 1983): 443–447.

Schneck, Stephen. [Review] “Connolly's Postmodern Liberalism.” Reviewed Works: Politics and Ambiguity by William E. Connolly; Political Theory and Modernity by William E. Connolly, . The Review of Politics 51, no. 2 (Spring, 1989): 281–290.

Schneider, Ulrich Johannes. [Review] “Sartre and Foucault Matching Each Other: What History Meant for Both of Them.” Reviewed Work(s): Sartre, Foucault, and Historical Reason, by Thomas R. Flynn. History and Theory 46, no. 2 (May, 2007): 272–280.

Seigel, Jerrold. [Review] “Mysticism and Epistemology: The Historical and Cultural Theory of Michel De Certeau.” Reviewed Works: Michel De Certeau: Les Chemins D'Histoire by (eds.) Christian Delacroix, Francois Dosse, Patrick Garcia, and Michael Trebitsch. History and Theory 43, no. 3 (Oct., 2004): 400–409.

Sica, Alan. [Review] “Does PoMo Matter?” Reviewed Work(s): The New Constellation: The Ethical– Political Horizons of Modernity/Postmodernity by Richard J. Bernstein; Crossing the Postmodern Divide by Albert Borgmann. Contemporary Sociology 22, no. 1 (Jan., 1993): 16–19.

Sluga, Hans. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Philosophy in Germany, 1831–1933 by Herbert Schnadelbach . The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36, no. 4 (Dec., 1985): 469–473.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger by Michael Friedman. Journal of Philosophy 98, no. 11 (Nov., 2001): 601–611.

Smelser, Neil J. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Making of the English Working Class by E. P. Thompson. History and Theory 5, no. 2 (1966): 213–217.

Steen, Francis F. [Review] “Grasping Philosophy by the Roots.” Reviewed Work(s): Philosophy In the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought, by George Lakoff and Mark Johnson . Philosophy and Literature 24, no. 1 (Apr., 2000): 197–203.

Svaglic, Martin J. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Imperial Intellect: A Study of Cardinal Newman's Educational Ideal by A. Dwight Culler. Modern Philology 55, no. 1 (Aug., 1957): 66–70.

Thiele, Leslie Paul. [Review] “Heidegger, History, and Hermeneutics.” Reviewed Work(s): Heidegger, Dilthey, and The Crisis of Historicism by Charles R. Bambach; Martin Heidegger and the Problem of Historical Meaning by Jeffrey Andrew Barash; Heidegger et son Siecle: Temps de l'Etre, Temps de l'Histoire by Jeffrey Andrew Barash; Martin Heidegger and European Nihilism by Karl Lowith; Heidegger's Crisis: Philosophy and Politics in by Hans Sluga. Journal of Modern History 69, no. 3 (Sep., 1997): 534–556.

Thompson, E. P. [Review] “On History, Sociology and Historical Relevance.” Reviewed Work(s): Pit- Men, Preachers and Politics; The Effects of Methodism on a Durham Mining Community by Robert Moore. British Journal of Sociology 27, no. 3 (Sep., 1976): 387–402.

Tiles, Mary. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): How the Laws of Physics Lie by Nancy Cartwright; Representing and Intervening by Ian Hacking. Philosophy 60, no. 231 (Jan., 1985): 133– 136.

340 Bibliography

Tillman, Mary Katherine. [Review] “The Human Sciences.” Reviewed Work(s): Wilhelm Dilthey: The Critique of Historical Reason by Michael Ermarth. The Review of Politics 41, no. 4 (Oct., 1979): 598– 601.

Tilly, Charles. [Review] “Three Visions of History and Theory.” Reviewed Work(s): History and Social Theory, by Peter Burke; Remaking Modernity: Politics, History, and Society by Julia Adams; The Oxford Handbook of Contextual Political Analysis by Robert E. Goodwin and Charles Tilly . History and Theory 46, no. 2 (May, 2007): 299–307.

Tirkey, Manoj. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Future of Knowledge Production in the Academy by Merle Jacob: Tomas Heustrom. Science, Technology & Society 8, no. 1 (Mar., 2003): 131– 136.

Toews, John E. [Review] “A New Philosophy of History? Reflections on Postmodern Historicizing.” Reviewed work(s): A New Philosophy of History by Frank Ankersmit ; Hans Kellner. History and Theory 36, no. 2 (May, 1997): 235–248.

——[Review] “Salvaging Truth and Ethical Obligation from the Historicist Tide: Thomas Haskell's Moderate Historicism.” Reviewed Work(s): Objectivity is Not Neutrality: Explanatory Schemes in History by Thomas Haskell. History and Theory 38, no. 3 (Oct., 1999): 348–364.

Turner, Stephen. [Review] “The New Collectivism.” Reviewed Work(s): Practical Reasoning in a Social World: How We Act Together by Keith Graham.” History and Theory 43, no. 3 (Oct., 2004): 386–399.

Uebel, Thomas E. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Philosophy of Science in the Twentieth Century: Four Central Themes by Donald Gillies. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45, no. 4 (Dec., 1994): 1066–1069.

——[Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Carnap's Construction of the World: The Aufbau and the Emergenceof Lgical Empiricism, by Alan. W. Richardson. Philosophical Review 109, no. 3 (Jul., 2000): 447–450.

Vann, Richard T. [Review] “Historian's Words and Things.” Reviewed Work(s): Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Times by Reinhart Koselleck; The Past is a Foreign Country by David Lowenthal . Journal of Interdisciplinary History 18, no. 3 (Winter, 1988): 465–470.

Varela, Francisco. [Review] “Consciousness Explained.” Reviewed Work(s): Consciousness Explained by Daniel Dennett. American Journal of Psychology 106, no. 1 (Spring, 1993): 126–129.

Walicki, Andrzej. [Review] “Hegel's Historical Context: A Review Article.” Reviewed Work(s): Hegelianism. The Path toward Dialectical Humanism, 1805–1841 by John Edward Toews, Hegel by M. J. Inwood. Comparative Studies in Society and History 29, no. 3 (Jul., 1987): 608–614.

Wallace, R. Jay. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory by Alasdair Macintyre; Whose Justice? Which Rationality? by Alasdair MacIntyre. History and Theory 28, no. 3 (Oct., 1989): 326–348.

Wechselblatt, Marty. [Review] “The End(s) of the University in the Information Society.” Reviewed Work(s):Scholars and Entrepreneurs: The Universities in Crisis by Simon Cooper, John Hinkson, Geoff Sharp, (eds.). Antipodes 16, no. 2 (Dec., 2002): 185–191.

White, Hayden. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Vico in the Tradition of Rhetoric by Michael Mooney. Eighteenth-Century Studies 22, no. 2 (Winter, 1988–89): 219–222.

——“Guilty of History? The Longue Duree of Paul Ricoeur.” Reviewed Work(s): Meaning, History, Forgetting, by Paul Ricoeur. History and Theory 46, no. 2 (May, 2007): 233–251.

341 Bibliography

Yack, Bernard. [Review] “Myth and Modernity: Hans Blumenberg's Reconstruction of Modern Theory.” Reviewed Work(s): Work on Myth by Hans Blumenberg; The Legitimacy of the Modern Age by Hans Blumenberg. Political Theory 15, no. 2 (May, 1987): 244–261.

Yengoyan, Aram A. [Review] “Simmel, Modernity, and Germanismus: A Review Essay.” Reviewed Work(s): Simmel on Culture: Selected Writings by David Frisby: Michael Featherstone (eds.); Down from Olympus: Archaeology and Philhellenism in Germany 1750–1970 by Suzanne Marchand . Comparative Studies in Society and History 44, no. 3 (Jul., 2002): 620–625.

Zammito, John H. [Review] “Koselleck's Philosophy of Historical Time(s) and the Practice of History.” Reviewed work(s): Zeitschichten: Studien zur Historik (Mit Einem Beitrag Von Hans-Georg Gadamer) by Reinhart Koselleck. History and Theory 43, no. 1 (Feb., 2004): 124–135.

——[Review] “Reconstructing German Idealism and Romanticism: Historicism and Presentism.” Reviewed work(s): German Idealism: The Struggle Against Subjectivism, 1781–1801 by Frederick Beiser; The Romantic Conception of Life: Science and Philosophy in the Age of Goethe by Robert Richards . Modern Intellectual History 1, no. 3 (2004): 427–438.

Reviews

Allen, Barry. [Review] “What It's All About.” Reviewed Works: The Social Construction of What by Ian Hacking.” Science 285, no. 5425 (Jul., 1999): 205–206.

Allott, Kenneth. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Hebrew and Hellene in Victorian England: Newman, Arnold and Pater by David DeLaura.” The Yearbook of English Studies 1, no. (1971): 299– 300.

Appleby, Joyce. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Origins of English Individualism: The Family, Property and Social Transition by Alan Macfarlane.” American Historical Review 84, no. 4 (Oct., 1979): 1046–1047.

Armytage, W. H. G. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Imperial Intellect: A Study of Cardinal Newman's Educational Ideal by A. Dwight Culler.” Modern Language Review 52, no. 1 (Jan., 1957): 107–108.

Aya, Rod. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Apologies to Thucydides: Understanding History as Culture and Vice-Versa by Marshall Sahlins.” American Anthropologist 108, no. 2 (Jun., 2006): 433–434.

Azzarello, Robert. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Scandalous Knowledge: Science, Truth, and the Human by Barbara Herrnstein Smith.” Cultrual Critique, no. 68 (Winter, 2008): 255–257.

Baber, Zaheer. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The New Production of Knowledge: The Dynamics of Science and Research in Contemporary Societies by Michael Gibbons: Camille Limoges: Helga Nowotny, Simon Schwartzman: Peter Scott: Martin Trow.” Contemporary Sociology 24, no. 6 (Nov., 1995): 751–752.

Bassett, Sharon. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Rhymers Club: Poets of the Tragic Generation by Norman Alford. The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry by Walter Pater: Donald Hill. Pater's Art of Autobiography by Gerald Monsman. Decadence in the !890s by Ian Fletcher.” Victorian Studies 25, no. 4 (Summer, 1982): 497–499.

Bauman, Zygmunt. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Observations on Modernity by Niklas Luhmann.” The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 6, no. 3 (Sep., 2000): 554–554.

Beales, A. C. F. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Imperial Intellect: A Study of Cardinal Newman's Educational Ideal by A. Dwight Culler; John Henry Newman: Autobiographical Writings

342 Bibliography

by Henry Tristram, John Henry Newman.” British Journal of Educational Studies 5, no. 2 (May, 1957): 181–182.

Bednarz, John Jr. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Soziale Systems by Niklas Luhmann.” Contemporary Sociology 16, no. 3 (May, 1987): 443–444.

Berger, Stefan. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Religion and the Rise of Historicism: W. M. L. de Wette, Jacob Burckhardt, and the Theological Origins of Nineteenth-Century Historical Consciousness by Thomas Albert Howard.” English Historical Review 115, no. 464 (Nov., 2000): 1330–1331.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing Concepts by Reinhart Koselleck.” Journal of Social History 38, no. 1 (2004): 211–213.

Blustein, Bonnie, Ellen. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Nineteenth-Century Origins of Neuroscientific Concepts by Edwin Clarke, L. S. Jacyna.” Isis 79, no. 4 (Dec., 1988): 709–710.

——[Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Inhibition: History and Meaning in the Science of Mind and Brain by Roger Smith.” Journal of Interdisciplinary History 25, no. 4 (Spring, 1995): 646–647.

Botterill, George. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The Enigma of the Mind-Body Problem in Contemporary Thought by Sergio Moravia.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47, no. 2 (Jun., 1996): 328–330.

Bryan, Kathy Scales. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Crossing Boundaries: Knowledge, Disciplinarities, and Interdisciplinarities by Julie Thompson Klein.” History of Education Quarterly 38, no. 2 (Summer, 1998): 225–227.

Burke, Peter. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The Waning of the Renaissance, 1550–1640, by William J. Bouwsma.” American Historical Review 106, no. 4 (Oct., 2001): 1442–1443.

——[Review] [Untitled] Reviewed work(s): Basel in the Age of Burckhardt: A Study in Unseasonable Ideas by Lionel Gossman; Jacob Burckhardt and the Crisis of Modernity by John R. Hinde.” Journal of Modern History 74, no. 3 (Sep., 2002): 670–672.

Calhoun, Craig. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Limits of Concept Formation in Natural Science: A Logical Introduction to the Historical Sciences by Heinrich Rickert; Guy Oakes.” Contemporary Sociology 17, no. 2 (Mar., 1988): 232–233.

Campbell, Oscar James. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): German Influence in the English Romantic Period 1788–1818, with Special Reference to Scott, Coleridge, Shelley and Byron. by F. W. Stokoe.” Modern Language Notes 43, no. 4 (Apr., 1928): 262–263.

Chambers, R. W. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Beowulf: The Monsters and the Critics by J. R. R. Tolkien.” Modern Language Review 33, no. 2 (Apr., 1938): 272–273.

Churchland, Patricia Smith. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Mind and Brain: The Many- Faceted problems. Selected readings from the Proceedings of Intrernational Conferences on the Unity of the Sciences, Sir John Eccles (ed) .” The Quarterly Review of Biology 59, no. 1 (March, 1984): 55– 56.

Chytry, Josef. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Down from Olympus: Archaeology and Philhellenism in Germany 1750–1970 by Suzanne Marchand.” American Historical Review 104, no. 3 (Jun., 1999): 1019–1021.

Cockshut, A. O. J. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Hebrew and Hellene in Victorian England: Newman, Arnold and Pater by David DeLaura.” The Review of English Studies 22, no. 86 (May, 1971): 250–251.

343 Bibliography

Coleman, William. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): On University Studies by F. W. J. Schelling: Ellis S. Morgan: Norbert Guterman.” Isis 60, no. 4 (Winter, 1969): 587–588.

Connolly, William E. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Philosophy in an Age of Pluralism: The Philosophy of Charles Taylor in Question by James Tully.” The American Political Science Review 90, no. 1 (Mar., 1996): 181–182.

——[Review] “The Radical Enlightenment: Faith, Power, Theory.” Reviewed Work(s): Radical Enlightenement: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity by ; Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow and the Feeling Brain by Antonio Damasio.” Theory & Event 7, no. 3 (2004), http://muse.jhu.edu/login?uri=/journals/theory_and_event/v007/7.3connolly.html.

de Vries, Willem A. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Wilfrid Sellars: Naturalism with a Normative Turn by James R. O'Shea.” The Review of Metaphysics 61, no. 4 (Jun., 2008): 854–855.

DeLaura, David J. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Newman: The Contemplation of Mind by Thomas Vargish; Newman and the Common Tradition: A Study in the Language of Church and Society by John Coulson.” Victorian Studies 15, no. 3 (Mar., 1972): 371–373.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Letters and Diaries of John Henry Newman. Volume IV. The Oxford Movement, July 1833 to December 1834 by Ian Ker: Thomas Gornall: John Henry Newman.” Modern Language Review 77, no. 1 (Jan., 1982): 179–181.

Dewsbury, Donald, A. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Inhibition: History and Meaning in the Science of Mind and Brain by Roger Smith.” Isis 85, no. 1 (Mar. 1994): 169–170.

Doty, Robert W. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Mere Machine to Trancendent Mind by Hans Moravec.” The Quarterly Review of Biology 75, no. 1 (Mar., 2000): 80–80.

Drozdow-St. Christian. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Imagining the Antipodes: Culture, Theory and the Visual in the Work of Bernard Smith by Peter Beilharz.” Pacific Affairs 72, no. 2 (Summer, 1999): 314–315. 552.

Dunbar, Robin. “Perspectives on Time.” Anthropology Today 8, no. 5 (Oct., 1992): 26–27.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Sociobiological Imagination by Mary Maxwell (ed.).” Man 28, no. 2 (Jun., 1993): 372–373.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Self-Awareness in Animals and Humans: Developmental Perspectives by Sue Taylor Parker, Robert W. Mitchell and Maria I. Bocca (eds).” The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 2, no. 3 (Sep., 1996): 544–545.

——[Review] “Social Intelligence and Interaction: Expressions and Implications of the Social Bias in Human Intelligence.” The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 2, no. 3 (Sep., 1996): 551– 552.

Dykhuis, Michele J. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Force, Fate, and Freedom: On Historical Sociology by Reinhard Bendix .” Social Forces 67, no. 2 (Dec., 1988): 538–539.

Ermarth, H. Michael. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Gesellschaft, Kultur, Theorie: Gesammelte Ausfatze zur neueren Geschichte by Thomas Nipperdey.” American Historical Review 82, no. 3 (Jun., 1977): 665–666.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Aesthetic State: A Quest in Modern German Thought by Josef Chytry.” Journal of Modern History 63, no. 2 (Jun., 1991): 419–421.

Ewing, A. C. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Knowing and the Function of Reason by Richard I. Aaron.” Philosophy 47, no. 182 (Oct., 1972): 379–380.

344 Bibliography

Feiler, Anthony. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Intelligence Reframed by Howard Gardner.” British Journal of Educational Studies 48, no. 4 (Dec., 2000): 453–454.

Flax, Jane. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Levinas, the Frankfurt School and Psychoanalysis, by C. Fred Alford.” Perspectives on Politics 1, no. 4 (Dec., 2003): 757–757.

Forbes, D. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Bentham, Coleridge and the Science of History by Robert Preyer.” Journal of Modern History 32, no. 1 (Mar., 1960): 49–50.

Freeden, Michael. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Equal Freedom and Utility: Herbert Spencer's Liberal Utilitarianism by David Weinstein.” English Historical Review 115, no. 463 (Sep., 2000): 1006–1007.

Fromm, Harold. [Review] “Arguing for Embodied Consciousness.” Reviewed Work(s): What Science Offers the Humanities: Integrating Body and Culture by Edward Slingerland.” Science 322, no. (10 Oct., 2008): 195–196.

Fuchs, Stephan. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Social Systems by Niklas Luhmann.” Contemporary Sociology 26, no. 1 (Jan., 1997): 117–118.

Fuchs, Stephan. “Niklas Luhmann.” Sociological Theory 17, no. 1 (Mar., 1999): 117–119.

Gartman, David. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Rise of Western Rationalism: Max Weber's Developmental History by Wolfgang Schluchter; Guenther Roth.” American Journal of Sociology 88, no. 6 (May, 1983): 1294–1296.

Ghosh, Peter. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Narratives of Enlightenment: Cosmopolitan History from Voltaire to Gibbon by Karen O'Brien.” English Historical Review 115, no. 462 (Jun., 2000): 740–741.

Gibbons, Marc, et. al. “Value of Curiosity-oriented Research.” Nature 225, no. (Mar., 1970): 1005– 1006.

Gibson, Kathleen R. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Origin of the Human Brain by J. P. Changeux.” American Anthropologist 100, no. 1 (Mar., 1998): 213–214.

Gillis, John R. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Category of the Person: Anthropology, Philosophy, History by Michael Carrithers; Steven Collins;Stephen Lukes, (eds.).” American Journal of Sociology 93, no. 3 (Nov., 1987): 709–710.

Goehr, Lydia. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Conventional Wisdom: The Content of Musical Form, by Susan McClary.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 60, no. 1 (Winter, 2002): 87–89.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Interpretation and Overinterpretation, by Umberto Eco, Richard Rorty, Jonathan Culler, Chrisitine Brooke-Rose, Stefan Collini.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51, no. 4 (Autumn, 1993): 632–634.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Aesthetic State: A Quest in Modern German Thought by Josef Chytry.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50, no. 3 (Summer, 1992): 260–262.

Goldstein, Doris S. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Victorian Mirror of History by A. Dwight Culler; The Art and Science of Victorian History by Rosemary Jann.” American Historical Review 92, no. 1 (Feb., 1987): 130–131.

Gooch, G. P. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Bentham, Coleridge and the Science of History by Robert Preyer.” English Historical Review 75, no. 295 (Apr., 1960): 360–361.

Gould, Mark. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Observations on Modernity by Niklas Luhmann.” American Journal of Sociology 106, no. 1 (Jul., 2000): 252–254.

345 Bibliography

Hannan, Barbara. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The Enigma of the Mind-Body Problem in Contemporary Thought by Sergio Moravia.” Philosophical Quarterly 46, no. 184 (Jul., 1996): 411– 413.

Hanson, Russell L. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Logic of the History of Ideas by Mark Bevir; History of Concepts: Comparative Perspectives by Iain Hampsher-Monk, Karin Tilmans, Frank van Vree; The History of Political and Social Concepts: A Critical Introduction by Melvin Richter.” The American Political Science Review 96, no. 4 (Dec., 2002): 795–797.

Hardin, Garrett. [Review] “When Technology Alters Nature: Two Kinds of Responsibility.” Reviewed Work(s): The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age, by Hans Jonas.” Hastings Center Report 14, no. 6 (Dec., 1984): 45–47.

Haroutunian-Gordon, Sophie. [Review] “Mind over Machine: A plea for the Intuitive Conception of Mind.” Reviewed Work(s): Mind over Machine: The Power of Human Intuition and Expertise in the Era of the Computer by Hubert L. Dreyfus, Stuart E. Dreyfus.” Educational Researcher 17, no. 3 (Apr., 1988): 50–52.

Hauptmann, Emily. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Claims of Culture: Equality and Diversity in the Global Era by Seyla Banhabib.” Perspectives on Politics 1, no. 3 (Sep., 2003): 579– 580.

Hazelton, Roger. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Wilhelm Dilthey's Grundlegung Einer Wissenschaftlichen Lebensphilosophie by Carl Theodor Glock.” Philosophical Review 49, no. 5 (Sep., 1940): 586–587.

Healy, Kieran. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Against Essentialism: A Theory of Culture and Society by Stephan Fuchs.” Contemporary Sociology 32, no. 2 (Mar., 2003): 252–254.

Hoffmaster, Barry. [Review] “Fear of Feeling.” Reviewed Work(s): Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions by Martha C. Nussbaum.” Hastings Center Report 33, no. 1 (Jan–Feb., 2003): 45–47.

Hollander, Paul. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Force, Fate, and Freedom: On Historical Sociology by Reinhard Bendix .” American Journal of Sociology 91, no. 6 (May, 1986): 1458–1459.

Hollinger, David A. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Objectivity is Not Neutrality: Explanatory Schemes in History, by Thomas L. Haskell.” Journal of American History 85, no. 4 (Mar., 1999): 1556–1557.

Hollinger, David A. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): A Nice Derangement of Epistemes: Post- positivism in the Study of Science from Quine to Latour by John H. Zammito.” Journal of Modern History 78, no. 2 (Jun., 2006): 458–460.

Holloway, John. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Imperial Intellect: A Study of Cardinal Newman's Educational Ideal by A. Dwight Culler.” The Review of English Studies 9, no. 34 (May, 1958): 225–227.

Holmes, Oliver W. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Time and Mind: The History of a Philosophical Problem by J. J. A. Mooij.” American Historical Review 111, no. 4 (Oct., 2006): 1130– 1130.

Honneth, Axel. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Foucault, Marxism and Critique, by Barry Smart.” American Journal of Sociology 91, no. 5 (Mar., 1986): 1242–1244.

Howard, Thomas Albert. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Jacob Burckhardt and the Crisis of Modernity by John R. Hinde.” American Historical Review 106, no. 4 (Oct., 2001): 1489–1490.

346 Bibliography

Hughes, Winifred. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Victorian Mirror of History by A. Dwight Culler; The Art and Science of Victorian History by Rosemary Jann.” Journal of Modern History 60, no. 2 (Jun., 1988): 374–376.

Hyams, Paul R. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Origins of English Individualism: The Family, Property and Social Transition by Alan Macfarlane.” English Historical Review 96, no. 380 (Jul., 1981): 605–607.

Iggers, Georg G. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Burgerliche Modernisierungskrise und Historiche Sinnbildung: Kulturgeshichte bei Droysen, Burkhardt und Max Weber by Friedrich Jaeger.” American Historical Review 100, no. 3 (Jun., 1995): 915–916.

Inwood, M. J. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Reality and Reason: Dialectic and The Theory of Knowledge, by Sean Sayers.” Mind 1, no. 95 (Apr., 1986): 265–266.

Jann, Rosemary. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Fact and Feeling: Baconian Science and the Nineteenth-Century Literary Imagination by Jonathan Smith.” Nineteenth-Century Literature 52, no. 1 (Jun., 1997): 125–127.

Johnson, Daniel. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Leopold von Ranke und die Moderne Gessichtswissenschaft by Wolfgang Mommsen.” English Historical Review 106, no. 420 (Jul., 1991): 731–731.

Kalberg, Stephen. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Paradoxes of Modernity: Culture and Conduct in the Theory of Max Weber by Wolfgang Schluchter; Neil Solomon.” American Journal of Sociology 102, no. 6 (May, 1997): 1735–1737.

Kelley, Donald R. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The Waning of the Renaissance, 1550– 1640, by William J. Bouwsma.” Isis 92, no. 4 (Dec., 2001): 777–778.

Knight, Kelvin. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues, by Alasdair Macintyre.” Ethics 111, no. 1 (Oct., 2000): 177–179.

Kogler, Hans Herbert. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Social Systems by Niklas Luhmann.” American Journal of Sociology 103, no. 1 (Jul., 1997): 271–273.

Kraft, Julius. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Neue Wege der Ontologie by Nicolai Hartmann.” Philosophical Review 60, no. 1 (Jan., 1951): 129–131.

Krause, Sharon R. [Review] “Brain, Citizens, and Democracy's New Nobility.” Reviewed Work(s): Neuropolitics: Thinking, Culture, Speed by William E. Connolly.” Theory & Event 9, no. 1 (2006): http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory_&_event.

L. E. L. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Neue Wege der Ontologie by Nicolai Hartmann.” Journal of Philosophy 47, no. 14 (Jul., 1950): 417–419.

Lindenfeld, David. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Religion and the Rise of Historicism: W. M. L. de Wette, Jacob Burckhardt, and the Theological Origins of Nineteenth-Century Historical Consciousness by Thomas Albert Howard.” German Studies Review 24, no. 1 (Feb., 2001): 181–182.

Lloyd, Christopher. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Force, Fate and Freedom: On Historical Sociology, by Reinhard Bendix.” American Historical Review 93, no. 5 (Dec., 1988): 1291–1292.

Lukes, Steven. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Durkheim's Philosophy Lectures: Notes from the Lycée de Sens Course, 1883–1884 by Neil Gross; Robert Alun Jones.” American Journal of Sociology 111, no. 4 (Jan., 2006): 1230–1231.

Mayr, Ernst. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Evolutionary Theory: The Unfinished Synthesis by Robert G. B. Reid.” Isis 77, no. 2 (June, 1986): 358–359.

347 Bibliography

McCarthy, Thomas. “Reconstruction and Deconstruction in Contemporary Philosophy: Variations on a Kantian Theme.” Nous 25, no. 2 (1991): 193–194.

McGowen, Randall. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): England in 1819: The Politics of Literary Culture and the Case of Romantic Historicism by James Chandler.” Comparative Literature 51, no. 4 (Autumn, 1999): 352–354.

McKaughan, Larry. [Review] “Reasoning in the Causal Gap.” Reviewed Work(s): Rationality in Action by John Searle.” The American Journal of Psychology, 116, no. 2 (Summer, 2003): 328–330.

Megill, Allan. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Poetics of the New History: French Historical Discourse from Braudel to Chartier by Philippe Carrard.” American Historical Review 98, no. 5 (Dec., 1993): 1556–1557.

Miers, Paul. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): American Literary Realism, Critical Theory and Intellectual Prestige by Phillip Barrish.” MLN 116, no. 5 (Dec., 2001): 1095–1097.

Mokyr, Joel. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Fourth Discontinuity: The Co-Evolution of Human and Machines by Bruce Mazlish.” Journal of Interdisciplinary History 25, no. 4 (Spring, 1995): 644–646.

Monsman, Gerald. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Letters of Walter Pater by Lawrence Evans: Walter Pater. Walter Pater Humanist by Richmond Crinkley.” Victorian Studies 14, no. 4 (Jun., 1971): 468–470.

Moon, J. Donald. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Liberalism and Value Pluralism by George Crowder.” Perspectives on Politics 1, no. 4 (Dec., 2003): 759–760.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Why I am Not a Secularist by William E. Connolly.” American Political Science Review 94, no. 2 (Jun., 2000): 444–445.

Moore, Barrington Jr. [Review] “Reflections on Comparative History.” Reviewed Work(s): Force, Fate, and Freedom: On Historical Sociology by Reinhard Bendix.” Contemporary Sociology 14, no. 1 (Jan., 1985): 14–15.

Moore, Kelly. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Reconfiguring Truth: Post-modernism, Science Studies, and the Search for a New Model of Knowledge, by Steven C. Ward.” Contemporary Sociology 27, no. 2 (Mar., 1998): 211–212.

Morawski, Jill G. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Inhibition: History and Meaning in the Sciences of the Mind and Brain by Roger Smith.” American Historical Review 98, no. 2 (April, 1993): 451–452.

O. F. K. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Wilhelm Dilthey's Grundlegung Einer Wissenschaftlichen Lebensphilosophie by Carl Theodor Glock.” Journal of Philosophy 37, no. 5 (Feb., 1940): 138–139.

O'Connor, Brian. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Kant and the Historical Turn by Karl Ameriks.” Review of Metaphysics 61, no. 4 (Jun., 2008): 827–829.

Oliver, W. Donald. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): New Ways of Ontology by Nicolai Hartmann.” Philosophical Review 63, no. 2 (Apr., 1954): 274–276.

Olson, Richard. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Kant, Herder, and the Birth of Anthroplogy by John H. Zammito.” Isis 93, no. 4 (Dec., 2002): 709–710.

Park, Peter. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Critical Theory and Public Life by John Forester.” American Journal of Sociology 94, no. 5 (Mar., 1989): 1249–1251.

348 Bibliography

Parkinson, G. H. R. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Kant and the Transcendental Object. A Hermeneutic Study by J. N. Findlay.” Mind 92, no. 367 (Jul., 1983): 438–440.

Patch, Howard R. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Beowulf: The Monsters and the Critics by J. R. R. Tolkien.” MLN 54, no. 3 (Mar., 1939): 217–218.

Pierce, J. R. “When is Research the Answer?” Science 159, no. 3819 (Mar., 1968): 1079–1080.

Proudfoot, Diane. [Review] “How Human Can They Get?” Reviewed Work(s): The Age of Spiritual Machines: When Computers Exceed Human Intelligence by Ray Kurzweil.” Science 284, no. 5415 (Apr. 30, 1999): 745–745.

Purdie, Edna. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): German Influence in the English Romantic Period 1788–1818, with Special Reference to Scott, Coleridge, Shelley and Byron. by F. W. Stokoe.” Modern Language Review 23, no. 1 (Jan., 1928): 80–82.

Rader, Melvin. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Dilthey. Philosopher of the Human Studies by Rudolf A. Makkreel.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 36, no. 2 (Winter, 1977): 222–223.

Rainer, Ulrike. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Complex Pleasures: Forms and Feeling in German Literature, by Stanley Corngold.” German Quarterly 73, no. 4 (Autumn, 2000): 433–434.

Reed, Michael C. [Review] “Follow the Money to Real Science.” Reviewed Work(s): Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge by Edward O. Wilson.” Cultural Anthroplogy 40, no. 3 (Jun., 1999): 403–404.

Reiss, Hans. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The German Tradition of Self- Cultivation:”Bildung”from Humboldt to Thomas Mann by W. H. Bruford.” Modern Language Review 71, no. 4 (Oct., 1976): 965–966.

Rheubottom, D. B. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Origins of English Individualism: The Family, Property and Social Transition by Alan Macfarlane.” Man 15, no. 3 (Sep., 1980): 574–575.

Rhodes, James M. [Review] “Recovery of Order: Scheler to Voegelin.” Reviewed Work(s): Political Order: Philosophical Anthroplogy, Modernity, and the Challenge of Ideology by David J. Levy.” The Review of Politics 52, no. 2 (Spring, 1990): 331–333.

Ringer, Fritz, K. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Mind and the Market: Capitalism in Modern European Thought by Jerry Z. Meiller.” Journal of Interdisciplinary History 35, no. 2 (Fall, 2004): 291–292.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): History, Historians,and the Dynamics of Change by William A. Green.” Journal of Interdisciplinary History 26, no. 2 (Autumn, 1995): 269–271.

Robinson, Richard. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Knowing and the Function of Reason by Richard I. Aaron.” Philosophical Review 82, no. 1 (Jan., 1973): 124–126.

Rockmore, Tom. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Bachelard: Science and Objectivity by Mary Tiles.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37, no. 4 (Dec., 1986): 529–531.

Rorty, Richard. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Pragmatism: An Open Question by Hilary Putnam.” Philosophical Review 105, no. 4 (Oct., 1996): 560–561.

——[Review] “Studied Ambiguity.” Reviewed Work(s): Shaping Science with Rhetoric: The Cases of Dobzhansky, Schrodinger, and Wilson by Leah Ceccarelli .” Science: New Series 293, no. 5539 (Sep. 28, 2001): 2399–2400.

Rose William. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): German Influence in the English Romantic Period 1788–1818, with Special Reference to Scott, Coleridge, Shelley and Byron. by F. W. Stokoe.” Review of English Studies 3, no. 10 (Apr., 1927): 245–246.

349 Bibliography

Sass, Louis, A. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): From Freud's Consulting Room: The Unconscious in a Scientific Age by Judith M. Hughes.” Journal of Modern History 69, no. 1 (March, 1997): 125–127.

Schaper, Eva. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Kleinere Schriften by Nicolai Hartmann.” Philosophical Quarterly 7, no. 28 (Jul., 1957): 287–288.

Schmidt, Claudia M. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Kant, Herder, and the Birth of Anthroplogy by John H. Zammito.” German Quarterly 76, no. 2 (Spring, 2003): 221–222.

Schmidt, Gustav. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Wilhelm Dilthey: The Critique of Historical Reason by Michael Ermarth.” Journal of Modern History 53, no. 1 (Mar., 1981): 90–91.

Scott, Eugenie C. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Trouble with Science by Robin Dunbar.” Isis 89, no. 3 (Sep., 1998): 585–586.

Sica, Alan. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Against Essentialism: A Theory of Culture and Society by Stephan Fuchs.” American Journal of Sociology 107, no. 5 (Mar., 2002): 1383–1385.

Sikela, James M. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Shattered Self: The End of Natural Evolution by Pierre Baldi.” Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 46, no. 3 (Summer, 2003): 463–465.

Sisomondo, Sergio. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Reconfiguring Truth: Post-modernism, Science Studies, and the Search for a New Model of Knowledge, by Steven C. Ward.” Isis 91, no. 4 (Dec., 2000): 837–838.

Smith, Roger. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Regions of the Mind: Brain Research and the Quest for Scientific Certainty by Susan Leigh Star.” English Historical Review 108, no. 428 (Jul. 1993): 749–749.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Simians, Cyborgs and Women: Reinvention of Nature by Donna J. Haraway.” Isis 83, no. 2 (Jun. 1992): 350–351.

Stark, David . [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Actor Network Theory and After, by John Law and John Hazzard (eds).” Contemporary Sociology 30, no. 1 (Jan., 2001): 96–97.

Stehr, Nico. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Reconfiguring Truth: Post-modernism, Science Studies, and the Search for a New Model of Knowledge, by Steven C. Ward.” American Journal of Sociology 103, no. 3 (Nov., 1997): 772–774.

Stoianovich, Traian. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The French Historical Revolution: the Annales school 1929–89 by Peter Burke.” American Historical Review 97, no. 3 (Jun., 1992): 862–863.

Stone, Lawrence. “Comment: [on “Problems in the History of Higher Education: A Review Article"].” Comparative Studies in Society and History 19, no. 2 (Apr., 1977): 256–257.

Struever, Nancy S. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory by Alasdair Macintyre.” MLN 96, no. 5 (Dec., 1981): 1193–1195.

Stump, David J. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): A Nice Derangement of Epistemes: Post- positivism in the Study of Science from Quine to Latour by John H. Zammito.” Isis 96, no. 1 (Mar., 2005): 159–160.

Swales, Martin. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The German Tradition of Self- Cultivation:”Bildung”from Humboldt to Thomas Mann by W. H. Bruford; The German Enlightenment and the Rise of Historicism by Peter Hanns Reill.” Journal of Modern History 50, no. 2 (Jun., 1978): 372–374.

Thompson, Kenneth. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Studies in the Theory of Ideology, by John B. Thompson.” British Journal of Sociology 43, no. 4 (Dec., 1992): 682–683.

350 Bibliography

Thorp, Thomas R. [Review] [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): The Critique of Power: Reflective Stages in a Critical Social Theory, by Axel Honneth.” Ethics 104, no. 2 (Jan., 1994): 412–413.

Tiryakian, Edward A. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Observations on Modernity by Niklas Luhmann.” Contemporary Sociology 29, no. 6 (Nov., 2000): 866–868.

Toews, John E. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Terms of Cultural Criticism: The Frankfurt School, Existentialism, Poststructuralism by Richard Wolin.” American Historical Review 98, no. 4 (Oct., 1993): 1207–1208.

——[Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Crisis of Reason: European Thought, 1848–1914 by J. W. Burrow.” Journal of Modern History 74, no. 4 (Dec., 2002): 822–824.

Toulmin, Stephen. [Review] “A Question of Character.” Reviewed Work(s): Schrödinger: Life and Thought by Walter Moore.” New York Review of Books 37, no. 11 (Jun., 1990): http://www.nybooks.com/.

Trommler, Frank. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Search for Normality: National Identity and Historical Consciousness in Germany Since 1800, by Stefan Berger.” German Quarterly 73, no. 4 (Autumn, 2000): 432–433.

Vicedo, Marga. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Shattered Self: The End of Natural Evolution by Pierre Baldi.” Quarterly Review of Biology 77, no. 2 (Jun., 2002): 192–192.

Wechselblatt, Marty. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Eighteenth-Century Hermeneutics: Philosophy of interpretation in England from Locke to Burke by Joel C. Weinscheimer.” Albion: A Quarterly Journal Concerned with British Studies 26, no. 1 (Spring, 1994): 159–161.

Weissman, David. “Logical Positivism: A Retrospective.” Journal of Philosophy 88, no. 10 (Oct., 1991): 520–521.

Wesling, Donald. [Review] “Fear of Feeling.” Reviewed Work(s): Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions by Martha C. Nussbaum.” Common Knowledge 9, no. 2 (Spring, 2003): 348– 349.

White, Alan R. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Knowing and the Function of Reason by Richard I. Aaron.” Philosophical Quarterly 22, no. 86 (Jan., 1972): 73–73.

White, Hayden. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Times by Reinhart Koselleck; Keith Tribe.” American Historical Review 92, no. 5 (Dec., 1987): 1175– 1176.

White, Stephen K. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Neuropolitics: Thinking, Culture, Speed by William E. Connolly.” Perspectives on Politics 1, no. 4 (Dec., 2003): 758–759.

Willey, Thomas E. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Wilhelm Dilthey: The Critique of Historical Reason by Michael Ermarth.” American Historical Review 86, no. 1 (Feb., 1981): 110–111.

Williams, Phillip. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Category of the Person: Anthropology, Philosophy, History by Michael Carrithers; Steven Collins; Stephen Lukes, (eds.).” Journal of Religion 67, no. 1 (Oct., 1987): 578–580.

Williamson, George S. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): Religion and the Rise of Historicism: W. M. L. de Wette, Jacob Burckhardt, and the Theological Origins of Nineteenth-Century Historical Consciousness by Thomas Albert Howard.” Journal of Modern History 73, no. 2 (Jun., 2001): 393– 394.

Wilson, David. [Review] [Untitled]. Reviewed Work(s): The Mysterious Flame: Conscious Minds in a Material World by Colin McGinn.” Quarterly Review of Biology 75, no. 1 (Mar., 2000): 80–81.

351 Bibliography

352

Minerva Access is the Institutional Repository of The University of Melbourne

Author/s: Sulman, R. A.

Title: Does history have a future? An inquiry into history as research

Date: 2008

Citation: Sulman, R. A. (2008). Does history have a future? An inquiry into history as research. PhD thesis, Arts - School of Historical Studies, The University of Melbourne.

Persistent Link: http://hdl.handle.net/11343/35111

File Description: Does history have a future? An inquiry into history as research

Terms and Conditions: Terms and Conditions: Copyright in works deposited in Minerva Access is retained by the copyright owner. The work may not be altered without permission from the copyright owner. Readers may only download, print and save electronic copies of whole works for their own personal non-commercial use. Any use that exceeds these limits requires permission from the copyright owner. Attribution is essential when quoting or paraphrasing from these works.