{PDF EPUB} the Eudemian Ethics by Aristotle Aristotle Eudemian Ethics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

{PDF EPUB} the Eudemian Ethics by Aristotle Aristotle Eudemian Ethics Read Ebook {PDF EPUB} The Eudemian Ethics by Aristotle Aristotle Eudemian Ethics. Thesis: Alexander at various times exhibited the only form of courage Aristotle outlines in the Eudemian Ethics – the virtue of the balance between rash and cowardice. Analysis of the model of virtue ethics and the doctrine of the Mean described in Eudemian Ethics allow to distinguish between difference forms of courage on the scale between rash and cowardice, with courage being the “golden mean” of human virtue. In his epos about Alexander Plutarch mentions many situations and descriptions of events related to Alexander’s life showing him from many perspectives; however, all of them can be classified as true courage according to Aristotle’s scale. Eudemian ethics of Aristotle is not so popular as his Nicomachean ethics partly because it describes an analytical model of virtue – concept of the Mean. However, this is a key concept in Aristotle’s model of virtue ethics. The virtues of being and ethical approaches to virtues have been considered by philosophers since early times. Courage is one of classical examples in ethical models, and Aristotle used courage as one of the best examples to describe his concept of the Mean. The purpose of this paper is to consider the interconnections between Aristotle’s model of mean, concept of courage and the manifestations of courage in Alexander’s life (according to Plutarch). Aristotle was the most influential teacher in Alexander’s life and had incredible impact to his personality forming. It can thus be assumed that Alexander exhibited the courage Aristotle outlines in his “Eudemian Ethics”. Evidences of this approach can be found throughout the texts of Plutarch. Aristotle’s considered courage to be one of human virtues. Usually, it is common to claim that this philosopher outlined several types of courage, according to reasons which raise it. However, this idea does not reflect the Aristotle’s doctrine of the Mean. According to “Eudemian Ethics”, the definition which might be used to determine the nature of courage is: “Courage is the mean between fear and recklessness” (Aristotle). In other words, courage can be explained as the optimal (virtuous) balance between fear and recklessness. Coward person is not able to act under the influence of fear, reckless person does not feel fear at all. On the other hand, courageous individual feels fear similarly to all other people, but he is still able to act voluntary with the confidence for honor and nobility. This is the core meaning of courage as the virtue for Aristotle (within the context of Eudemian Ethics). However, Aristotle also uses the term “courage” in situational context. Here is the list of the manifestations of courage (expressed differently on the courage scale): civic – the result of punishment cowardice transformed to forced feel of braveness; ignorance – “children and madmen face things rushing on them” (Aristotle); military, based on knowledge “not of what is formidable, but of ways of encountering what is formidable”; boldness, based on previous luck, which motivates one to face danger; passion – leading to heedlessness of the possibility to defeat (Aristotle). It is possible to determine that, according to Aristotle’s view, there can be different manifestations of courage (seen as a scale), but the true courage is the balance between the extreme ends of this scale. Other types of behaviour described above are also related to courage, but they are not achieving the Mean. The work of Plutarch describing events from Alexander’s life is incredibly valuable, since his presentation is clear and unbiased (without extra worship of Alexander, but written with deep respect). Using Aristotle’s ethic, it is possible to develop a totally new perception of Alexander’s true courageousness, and its consequent manifestations. However, in certain situations it is also difficult to judge whether it was true courage or rashness. For example, Alexander’s courage during some of battles can be perceived both as Aristotle’s virtuous balance between fear and recklessness, and as his courage of boldness, generated by too self-confident character. In my opinion, Alexander manifested true courage (according to Aristotle’s model), since he managed to balance between rashness and cowardice. Throughout the text of Plutarch, it is possible to trace the moments when Alexander exhibited the courage, not the cowardice (or similar reactions) and not rashness, but the golden middle between them. Below there are several examples of Alexander’s courageous behaviour, and the analysis of them. The scene with horse, from Alexander’s youth, is a good example of true courage as it was defined by Aristotle. When nobody could subdue recalcitrant stallion, Alexander said then: “What an excellent horse do they lose for want of address and boldness to manage him!” (Plutarch). Then, he bravely took control under the horse in few minutes just, risking to get wounds. Was the courage in his actions in fact? Managing very unbridled horse could cause serious harm to his health, thus, the answer is “yes”. Was this courage the manifestation of courageous child’s “ignorance” of character Aristotle wrote about? Obviously, not. Furthermore, Alexander’s skills of horse managing and the ability to tame the wild horse showed he was able to find the true balance – evidence of wisdom which enabled him to become the greatest conqueror. Thereby, the above-mentioned actions of the great General can be considered as the manifestation of true virtue which Aristotle defines in his “Eudemian Ethics”. The events related to Alexander’s entering the ruling of kingdom show another manifestation of true courage. “It seemed to the Macedonians a very critical time; and some would have persuaded Alexander to give up all thought of retaining the Grecians in subjection by force of arms, and rather to apply himself to win back by gentle means the allegiance of the tribes who were designing revolt, and try the effect of indulgence in arresting the first motions towards revolution. But he rejected this counsel as weak and timorous, and looked upon it to be more prudence to secure himself by resolution and magnanimity, than, by seeming to truckle to any, to encourage all to trample on him”(Plutarch). Was his attitude towards kingdom ruling courageous? Definitely! Being a wise and skilled strategist and a leader, Alexander understood potential dangers. However, honor became the reason not to accept compromises he was forced to and not to take side of cowards. Being the closest to real courage according to Aristotle, Alexander managed to go against the prevailing opinion. The scene of battle near the river Granicus also illustrated the courage of Alexander in Aristotle’s sense. Conditions of Alexander’s army and location were absolutely unfavorable. In addition, he had to deal with the common belief that Daesius month is not suitable for successful military performance. The incredible influence of prejudices in ancient times should also be considered. What was the Alexander’s response? Here are some quotes from Plutarch: “It was late, he told him that he should disgrace the Hellespont should he fear the Granicus”. The greatest victory followed the courageous decision of General. It cannot be said that Alexander did not feel fear at all. The quote illustrates that he found strength to get over it for the love of honor, nobility and greatest purpose. In general, the types of Aristotle’s courage do not have clear lines to get the only precise meaning. Multiply treated philosophical statements are even more disputable in the aspect of ancient historical events. However, it is stated that unbelievable courage of greatest conqueror is worth to be recognized the virtue of wisdom (the golden mean) in Aristotle’s ethical model. Numerous examples illustrate the nature of courage of Alexander the Great and it is the doctrine of the Mean and true virtue that enabled him to make an outstanding contribution in the world’s history. Aristotle, Eudemian Ethics. Hide browse bar Your current position in the text is marked in blue. Click anywhere in the line to jump to another position: This text is part of: Search the Perseus Catalog for: View text chunked by: Table of Contents: After this we must take a fresh starting-point and discuss the subjects that follow. Now all goods are either external or within the spirit, and of these two kinds the latter are preferable, as we class them even in the extraneous discourses. 1 For Wisdom and Goodness and Pleasure are in the spirit, and either some or all of these are thought by everybody to be an End. And the contents of the spirit are in two groups, one states or faculties, the other activities and processes. Let these assumptions, then, be made, and let it be assumed as to Goodness that it is the best disposition or state or faculty of each class of things that have some use or work. The Annenberg CPB/Project provided support for entering this text. Purchase a copy of this text (not necessarily the same edition) from Amazon.com. An XML version of this text is available for download, with the additional restriction that you offer Perseus any modifications you make. Perseus provides credit for all accepted changes, storing new additions in a versioning system. Aristotle, Eudemian Ethics. Hide browse bar Your current position in the text is marked in blue. Click anywhere in the line to jump to another position: This text is part of: Search the Perseus Catalog for: View text chunked by: Table of Contents: The man 1 who at Delos set forth in the precinct of the god his own opinion composed an inscription for the forecourt of the temple of Leto in which he distinguished goodness, beauty and pleasantness as not all being properties of the same thing.
Recommended publications
  • Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Version 1.1 (Last Updated : Apr
    - Institute for scientific and technical information - Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Version 1.1 (Last updated : Apr. 05, 2018) This resource contains 4435 entries grouped into 89 collections. Controlled vocabulary used for indexing bibliographical records for the "Philosophy" FRANCIS database (1972-2015, http://pascal-francis.inist.fr/ ). This vocabulary is browsable online at: https://www.loterre.fr Legend • Syn: Synonym. • →: Corresponding Preferred Term. • FR: French Preferred Term. • DE: German Preferred Term. • SC: Semantic Category. • DO: Domain. • URI: Concept's URI (link to the online view). This resource is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International license: LIST OF ENTRIES List of entries English French Page • 10th century Xe siècle 176 • 11th - 13th centuries XIe - XIIIe siècles 176 • 11th century XIe siècle 176 • 12th -13th centuries XIIe - XIIIe siècles 176 • 12th century XIIe siècle 176 • 13th - 14th centuries XIIIe - XIVe siècles 176 • 13th - 15th centuries XIIIe - XVe siècles 176 • 13th century XIIIe siècle 176 • 14th - 15th centuries XIVe - XVe siècles 176 • 14th - 16th centuries XIVe - XVIe siècles 176 • 14th - 17th centuries XIVe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 14th century XIVe siècle 176 • 15th - 17th centuries XVe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 15th century XVe siècle 176 • 1656-1658 1656-1658 176 • 16th - 17th centuries XVIe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 16th - 18th centuries XVIe - XVIIIe siècles 176 • 16th - 20th centuries XVIe - XXe siècles 176 • 16th century XVIe siècle 176 • 1735-1985 1735-1985
    [Show full text]
  • 7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul
    7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul Roger Crisp n the recent revival of interest in Aristotelian ethics, relatively little attention has been paid to the virtue of greatness of soul (megalopsuchia). This is partly Ibecause of the focus on the more structurally central concepts of Aristotle’s theory, in particular happiness (eudaimonia) and virtue (aret¯e). But in fact a study of greatness of soul can reveal important insights into the overall shape of Aristotelian ethics, including the place of external goods and luck in the virtuous life, and the significance of “the noble” (to kalon). Further, Aristotle describes the great-souled person in more detail than any other, and calls greatness of soul a “sort of crown of the virtues” (NE IV.3.1124a1–2). Many have found aspects of the portrait of the great-souled person in the Nicomachean Ethics repellent or absurd, but that is no good reason for the student of Aristotle to shy away from it. In this chapter, I shall elucidate Aristotle’s account of greatness of soul, addressing some puzzles internal to that account and bringing out its place in, and implications for, the ethics of Aristotle and of those modern writers influenced by him. Greatness of Soul as a Virtue To understand greatness of soul as an Aristotelian virtue requires first understand- ing Aristotle’s conception of virtue itself. Aristotle distinguishes virtues into two classes – intellectual virtues and virtues of character – corresponding to distinct aspects of the human soul (NE I.13). Greatness of soul is a virtue of character, though, like all such virtues, it requires its possessor to have the intellectual virtue of practical wisdom (phron¯esis; NE VI.13).
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle and the Value of Tragedy Malcolm Heath
    Aristotle and the Value of Tragedy Malcolm Heath This article explores Aristotle’s understanding of the value of tragedy. The primarily technical analyses of the Poetics are not sufficient for this purpose: they must be read in the context of Aristotle’s philosophical anthropology. An outline of Aristotle’s understanding of the structure of human motivation provides a framework within which to interpret his discussion of the uses of music, and in particular of music’s status as an intrinsically valuable component of cultivated Downloaded from leisure. Applying that model to tragedy requires an explanation of what motivates engagement with drama that evokes distressing affects. Aristotle’s account of musical katharsis, if read with sufficient attention to its structure and interpreted in the light of his analysis of pleasure, provides a solution. If the importance which Aristotle attaches to intrinsically valuable leisure activities is overlooked, it http://bjaesthetics.oxfordjournals.org/ is not possible to understand his conception of a good human life, or his aesthetics. What motivates human beings to invest time and effort in producing and consuming trag- edies? And how does that investment contribute to a characteristically human way of life? That is, what value attaches to the production and consumption of tragedies? Though Aristotle touches briefly on poetry’s roots in human nature at the beginning of Poetics 4, for the most part the existence of poetry and its diverse kinds is treated in the Poetics, not as an explanandum, but as the starting point for technical analyses of how poems, in their various kinds, are best composed.
    [Show full text]
  • Catalogue of Titles of Works Attributed to Aristotle
    Catalogue of Titles of works attributed by Aristotle 1 To enhance readability of the translations and usability of the catalogues, I have inserted the following bold headings into the lists. These have no authority in any manuscript, but are based on a theory about the composition of the lists described in chapter 3. The text and numbering follows that of O. Gigon, Librorum deperditorum fragmenta. PART ONE: Titles in Diogenes Laertius (D) I. Universal works (ta kathalou) A. The treatises (ta syntagmatika) 1. The dialogues or exoterica (ta dialogika ex terika) 2. The works in propria persona or lectures (ta autopros pa akroamatika) a. Instrumental works (ta organika) b. Practical works (ta praktika) c. Productive Works (ta poi tika) d. Theoretical works (ta the r tika) . Natural philosophy (ta physiologia) . Mathematics (ta math matika) B. Notebooks (ta hypomn matika) II. Intermediate works (ta metaxu) III. Particular works (ta merika) PART TWO: Titles in the Vita Hesychii (H) This list is organized in the same way as D, with two exceptions. First, IA2c “productive works” has dropped out. Second, there is an appendix, organized as follows: IV. Appendix A. Intermediate or Particular works B. Treatises C. Notebooks D. Falsely ascribed works PART THREE: Titles in Ptolemy al-Garib (A) This list is organized in the same way as D, except it contains none of the Intermediate or Particular works. It was written in Arabic, and later translated into Latin, and then reconstructed into Greek, which I here translate. PART FOUR: Titles in the order of Bekker (B) The modern edition contains works only in IA2 (“the works in propria persona”), and replaces the theoretical works before the practical and productive, as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature Melissa Marie Coakley University of South Florida, [email protected]
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 3-20-2014 Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature Melissa Marie Coakley University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Coakley, Melissa Marie, "Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature" (2014). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/4999 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Aeschynē in Aristotle’s Conception of Human Nature by Melissa M. Coakley A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Science University of South Florida Major Professor: Joanne Waugh, Ph.D. Bruce Silver, Ph.D. Roger Ariew, Ph.D. Thomas Williams, Ph.D. Date of Approval: March 20, 2014 Keywords: Shame, Anaeschyntia, Aidōs, Aischynē, Ancient Greek Passions Copyright © 2014, Melissa M. Coakley DEDICATION This manuscript is dedicated to my husband Bill Murray and to my parents: Joan and Richard Coakley. Thank you for your endless support, encouragement, and friendship. To Dr. John P. Anton, I have learned from you the importance of having a “ton of virtue and a shield of nine layers for protection from the abysmal depths of vice.” Thank you for believing in me, my dear friend.
    [Show full text]
  • Luck and Good Fortune in the Eudemian Ethics
    Luck and Good Fortune in the EudemianEthics Kent Johnson Recentlythere has beensome discussion of Aristotle's treatmentof good for- tune(£\m>x;{a) in the penultimatechapter of the EudemianEthics. I Thereare two claims about this chapterI wish to challenge.One maintainsthat the use of the word tUXll (usuallytranslated as 'luck' or 'chance')in the EE is 'quite different' from Aristotle's theoretical discussion of luck, found in the Physics (Woods 1992,67). The other claim is that good fortune is a subspeciesof luck (Kenny 1992,ch. 5, esp.71 and 75). In challengingthese two views,I hopeto developan accountof Aristotle's true intent in this chapter.In the first part of this article I considerthe notion of luck asit is presentedin the Physicsand then argue that the discussionof luck in the EE accordswith this. In the secondpart I arguethat by the end of his discussionof good fortune in the EE, Aristotle doesnot consider good fortune to be any kind of luck at all. I. TuX1lin the Physicsand the EudemianEthics Woods 1992,166 denies that the useof 'luck' (tuX1l)in the EE agreeswith its usein the Physics,because in the PhysicstUX1l is usedin sucha way that 'to say that somethingoccurred by chancewill not be to give an explanation,but to deny that a general explanation is available'. Thus, there is 'no incompatibility betweensomething's occurring by chanceand its being caused',since chance is not a cause distinct from the four real causes(Woods 1992, 167). Instead, 'chanceoccurrences have the featurethat they fall underno law that holds uni- versallyor for the most part under the descriptionunder which theyare correctly said to occur by chance,though they will havesome explanation under another description'(166).
    [Show full text]
  • 117 Aristotle on Focal Meaning and the Unity of Science MICHAEL T
    Aristotle on Focal and the Meaning Unity of Science MICHAEL T. FEREJOHN This study owes its impetus to a group of suggestions put forward by G. E. L. Owen in his 1960 article, "Logic and Metaphysics in Some Earlier Works of Aristotle".' In that work, Owen gives predominantly textual arguments for the chronological scheme represented by the following three theses. (I) In the earliest works of the Corpus (including those treatises which comprise the Organon), Aristotle was convinced that the verb "to be" [E'LvotL]and its cognates were ambiguous expressions, and that this ambiguity foredoomed the Platonic and Academic program of constructing a single, unified, and all-encompassing science of Being. (II) During an intermediate stage of Aristotle's development (represented by the seventh book of the Eudemian Ethics), he regularly noticed and worked with the possibility of systematic, or non-accidental, ambiguity, though he did not view this possibility as having any bearing on his negative claim in (I). (III) In Metaphysics F2, which reports his mature views on this subject, Aristotle finally struck upon the discovery that the verb "to be" itself was a case of systematic ambiguity (of a sort which Owen labels focal meaning ambiguity). Moreover, this discovery influenced him to reverse his previous estimation of the prospects for a universal science, and even to resurrect in the Metaphysicsthe Platonic program that he himself had dismissed as futile in his earlier works. Most of what I have to say concerns (III). What will be at issue, however, is not its truth. That matter is put beyond serious dispute by the relatively plain structure of Metaphysics F2.
    [Show full text]
  • Remains of a Self Solitudes and Responsibilities Michaelsen, Cathrine Bjørnholt
    Remains of a Self Solitudes and Responsibilities Michaelsen, Cathrine Bjørnholt Publication date: 2017 Document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Document license: CC BY-NC-ND Citation for published version (APA): Michaelsen, C. B. (2017). Remains of a Self: Solitudes and Responsibilities. Publikationer fra Det teologiske Fakultet. Publikationer fra Det Teologiske Fakultet Vol. 72 Download date: 29. Sep. 2021 CATHRINE BJØRNHOLT MICHAELSEN BJØRNHOLT CATHRINE ISBN 978-87-93361-32-4 CATHRINE BJØRNHOLT MICHAELSEN Remains of a Self Solitudes and Responsibilities Solitudes and Responsibilities Remains of a Self CATHRINE BJØRNHOLT MICHAELSEN Remains of a Self Solitudes and Responsibilities Publikationer fra Det Teologiske Fakultet 72 CATHRINE BJØRNHOLT MICHAELSEN BJØRNHOLT CATHRINE ISBN 978-87-93361-32-4 CATHRINE BJØRNHOLT MICHAELSEN Remains of a Self Solitudes and Responsibilities Solitudes and Responsibilities Remains of a Self CATHRINE BJØRNHOLT MICHAELSEN Remains of a Self Solitudes and Responsibilities Publikationer fra Det Teologiske Fakultet 72 REMAINS OF A SELF SOLITUDES AND RESPONSIBILITIES REMAINS OF A SELF SOLITUDES AND RESPONSIBILITIES Cathrine Bjørnholt Michaelsen PhD Thesis The Faculty of Theology Department of Systematic Theology ‘Self-understanding and Self-alienation’ University of Copenhagen February 2017 Remains of a Self. Solitudes and Responsibilities Publikationer fra Det Teologiske Fakultet 72 Licensed under CreativeCommons Cathrine Bjørnholt Michaelsen ISBN: 978-87-93361-32-4 (print) ISBN: 978-87-93361-35-5 (pdf) Published by The Faculty of Theology, Copenhagen University Karen Blixens Plads 16 2300 København S. www.teol.ku.dk Cover Art: ‘Le coupeur de gorge’ by Carl Fredrik Hill with permission from Malmö Konstmuseum. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I wish to acknowledge and express my gratitude to the Velux Foundations and the Faculty of Theology, University of Copenhagen, for making possible the research project “Self-understanding and Self-alienation” of which this thesis is a part.
    [Show full text]
  • Nature and Moral Excellence in the Aristotelian Ethics
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1976 Nature and Moral Excellence in the Aristotelian Ethics Robert Geis Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Geis, Robert, "Nature and Moral Excellence in the Aristotelian Ethics" (1976). Master's Theses. 2840. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/2840 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1976 Robert Geis NATURE AND MORAL EXCELLENCE IN THE ARISTOTELIAN ETHICS by Robert Geis A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Loyola University of Chicago in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of master of Arts February 1976 PREFACE The past three decades have seen an appreciable growth of interest in ethics both here and in Europe, with discus­ sion equally fruitful in both the classical and modern po­ sitions. The topics discussed, varied and wide-ranging as the.problems they consider, continue to provide appreciat­ ion for the complexities that ethics must treat, whether the views set forth have been one's own or that of a major fig- ure. This thesis is of the latter kind. It centers direct­ ly on one theme in Aristotle's ethics, viz., the relation there of Nature and moral excellence.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Criticism of the Platonic Idea of the Good In
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Peitho. Examina Antiqua PEITHO / EXAMINA ANTIQUA 1 ( 8 ) / 2017 Aristotle’s Criticism of the Platonic Idea of the Good in Nicomachean Ethics 1.6* MELINA G. MOUZALA / University of Patras / In Nicomachean Ethics 1.6 Aristotle sets out to examine the notion of a universal Good and discuss thoroughly what is meant by it. In the introduction to this chapter, he alludes to Plato and uses as the starting point for this discussion the confession that such an inquiry is made an uphill task by the fact that the Forms have been introduced by his own friends.1 Still, his decision as a philosopher or lover of wisdom is to sacrifice even his clos- * An earlier version of this paper was presented at the World Congress, The Philosophy of Aristotle, Athens, 10–15 July 2016. 1 We must recall the passage in the Republic (R. 595b9–c3), which is notoriously recognized as a parallel, because Plato refers to Homer in a way similar to Aristotle’s allusion in EN 1.6. Flashar (1988: 219, n. 26 [1965: 241]) asserts that Aristotle has borrowed the word ὅσιον (EN 1096a16) from the Platonic words: ἀλλὰ γὰρ τὸ δοκοῦν ἀληθὲς οὐχ ὅσιον προδιδόναι (R. 607c7–8), which belong to another passage that refers to Homer within the frame of Plato’s criticism of his poetry. Cf. Smp. 201c6–9; Phd. 91c1 f.; Sph. 246d8–9; Phlb. 14b5–7. In all my references to Flashar, the translation is my own.
    [Show full text]
  • Seminar on Aristotle's Ethics
    Aristotle’s Ethics Philosophy 207z Fall 2013 Chris Korsgaard 205 Emerson Hall 495-3916 [email protected] Office Hours: Thursdays, 2:00-4:00, and by appointment I. Required Texts Aristotle. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Volumes 1 and 2. ed. Jonathan Barnes. Princeton, 1984. (ordered at the Coop) Korsgaard, Christine M. “Two Kinds of Matter in Aristotle’s Metaphysics” (1982) “Aristotle on Function and Virtue” (1986) “Aristotle and Kant on the Source of Value” (1986) “From Duty and for the Sake of the Noble: Kant and Aristotle on Morally Good Action” (1996) “Acting for a Reason” (2004) “The Origin of the Good and Our Animal Nature” (2007) “Aristotle’s Function Argument” (2008) Selections from The Natural History of the Good, the Pufendorf Lectures, 2013 (on the course web site) II. Recommended Books Books containing Recommended Readings on the syllabus: Broadie, Sarah. Ethics with Aristotle. Oxford, 1995. Kraut, Richard (ed). The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Ethics. Blackwell, 2006. Plato. Complete Works. ed. John M. Cooper and D. S. Hutchinson. Hackett, 1997. Rorty, Amélie. Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. University of California, 1981. Other Recommended Books ordered at the Coop: Aquinas, St. Thomas. Commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Trans. C. I. Litzinger. Dumb Ox Books, 1993. Engstrom, Stephen, and Whiting, Jennifer. Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Virtue. Cambridge, 1998. Korsgaard, Christine M. The Constitution of Agency. Oxford, 2008. Miller, Jon (ed). Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, 2011. Pakaluk, Michael, and Pearson, Giles (eds.) Moral Psychology and Human Action in Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Philosophy Applied to Interactive Virtual Media
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Oxford Brookes University: RADAR Aristotelian philosophy applied to interactive virtual media: On the effects of transportation on the player and the practical applications of Virtual Realities. By Joshua Patterson Oxford Brookes University Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the award MA in Philosophy by research Supervisory team – Helen de Cruz and Stephen Boulter September 2017 Abstract Virtual reality is a new technology that blurs the line between what a person feels is real and knows is fake; putting the audience ‘inside’ a piece of art, a new ‘world’ that we can experience (like real life) in a first-person perspective. This technology has come about through the development of interactive virtual media, the product of ‘the evolution of poetry’ that Aristotle discovered and explained. Poetry is something that can hold and transfer meaning, specifically it is anything that can offer or represent the ‘what it is likeness’ of a particular concept or truth, this is what I refer to when I use the term ‘Poetry’. The concept of blurring the line between reality and fiction, gives rise to ‘the paradox of fiction’ and has been a component of art from its conception. We lose ourselves in a myth, a book, a song or a play, and we have emotions about imitations of (fictional) events (even though they are fictional), this losing oneself into poetry is what I will term ‘Transportation’. Virtual realities achieve this and can make us feel like we are inside a piece of art, by fully taking control of our perspective (our experiences), by putting the control of the art’s direction in our hands, and importantly, by captivating our full attention.
    [Show full text]