Embodiment, Language and Mimesis Zlatev, Jordan
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Embodiment, language and mimesis Zlatev, Jordan Published in: Body, Language, Mind. Vol 1: Embodiment 2007 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Zlatev, J. (2007). Embodiment, language and mimesis. In T. Ziemke, J. Zlatev, & R. Franck (Eds.), Body, Language, Mind. Vol 1: Embodiment (pp. 297-337). Mouton de Gruyter. Total number of authors: 1 General rights Unless other specific re-use rights are stated the following general rights apply: Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Read more about Creative commons licenses: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. LUND UNIVERSITY PO Box 117 221 00 Lund +46 46-222 00 00 Embodiment, Language, and Mimesis Jordan Zlatev For years now, leading representatives of theoretical linguistics have been arguing that humans, being gov- erned by a blind ‘language instinct’, can be exhaus- tively described in physico-biological terms. … [T]his conception has been shown to be fundamentally false. Humans are also, and crucially, social, normative, and conscious beings, occasionally capable of acts of free will. Esa Itkonen, What is Language? Abstract The present focus on embodiment in cognitive science undervalues con- cepts such as convention/norm, representation and consciousness. I argue that these concepts constitute essential properties of language, and this makes it problematic for “embodiment theories” to account for human lan- guage and cognition. These difficulties are illustrated by examining a par- ticular, highly influential approach to embodied cognition, that of Lakoff and Johnson (1999), and exposing the problematic character of the notion of the “cognitive unconscious”. To attempt a reconciliation between em- bodiment and language, I turn to the concept of (bodily) mimesis, and pro- pose the notion of mimetic schema as a mediator between the individual human body and collective language. 1. Introduction The main goal of this chapter is to investigate the relationship between language and the concept of embodiment which has become a central, if ambiguous, notion within cognitive science (e.g. Varela, Thompson & Rosch 1991; Clark 1997; Ziemke 2003), the neuroscience of consciousness (e.g. Edelman 1992; Damasio 1994, 2000), (neuro)phenomenology (e.g. Varela 1996; Thompson 2001; Thompson & Varela 2001; Gallagher 1995, 242 Jordan Zlatev 2005, this volume), cognitive linguistics1 (e.g. Lakoff 1987; Johnson 1987; Zlatev 1997; Svensson 1999; Evans 2003) and to some extent develop- mental psychology (e.g. MacWhinney 1999; Mandler 2004). The notion of embodiment is, indeed, even intended to unite efforts in these different fields into what is often called “second generation cognitive science” (Lindblom & Ziemke this volume) or “embodied cognition” (Johnson & Rohrer this volume). There is much to recommend in this (re)turn to the body in the study of the mind, especially since in many ways it can be seen as a justified reaction to the many shortcomings of “classical” information- processing cognitive science according to which the “mind/brain” works essentially as a computer (e.g. Fodor 1981; Jackendoff 1987; Pinker 1994). There are, however, three major unresolved issues within the current “embodiment turn” in the sciences of the mind. The first was mentioned in passing already: there is not one but many different meanings behind the term “embodiment”, both between and within fields, and the corresponding theories are in general not compatible (Ziemke 2003). In particular, I would claim, there is no uniform concept of representation within “embodied cognition”, and this is a constant source of (misguided) debate, both be- tween proponents of embodiment and between them and representatives of the “algebraic mind” (Marcus 2001). Second, by their nature, embodiment theories have a strong individualist orientation, and despite recurrent at- tempts to connect embodiment to social reality and culture (e.g. Palmer 1996; Zlatev 1997; Sinha 1999), there is still no coherent synthesis. In par- ticular, within the work of those emphasizing the role of the “body in the mind” there is no adequate notion of convention or norm, which is essential for characterizing both human culture and the human mind. Third, there is a dangerous tendency to underestimate the role of consciousness in many – though not all – embodiment theories. There seems to be some sort of fear that in appealing to anything that is irreducible to either biology or behav- ior, one is bound to fall into the clutches of “Cartesian dualism”. The con- sequence is, however, that such “non-dualistic” approaches run the risk of 1. When using small letters, i.e. cognitive linguistics, I will refer to the work of linguists who regard language and cognition as intimately connected (e.g. It- konen, Levinson and Jackendoff). When used with capital letters, Cognitive Linguistics refers to the school of linguistics departing from the work of La- koff, Langacker and Talmy. The borders are admittedly fuzzy, but in general, Cognitive Linguistics is a hyponym (extensionally speaking a subset) of cogni- tive linguistics. Embodiment, Language, and Mimesis 243 one form or another of physico-biological reductionism, which as pointed out by Itkonen in the motto to this chapter is deeply misguided. To substantiate these claims in detail would require an extensive review of the literature, which the allotted space of a book chapter does not permit me. My strategy will therefore be to single out one of the above mentioned fields, cognitive linguistics, and even more narrowly, focus on a single exposition of “embodiment theory”: Philosophy in the Flesh (PitF) by George Lakoff and Mark Johnson (1999). This choice is motivated by the following reasons: (a) Lakoff and Johnson are two of the foremost propo- nents of “embodied cognition” not only in (cognitive) linguistics, but in general, (b) PitF is their most recent extensive joint publication, and it is often mentioned as one of the three major reference works on embodiment up to date, along with Varela et al. (1991) and Damasio (1994), and (c) while philosophically oriented, the work deals with implications from lin- guistic research, and it is precisely in relation to language that the difficul- ties of “embodiment theory” are most clearly accentuated.2 The problem reveals itself when we ask the seemingly simple question: In what sense can (knowledge of) language be said to be “embodied”? Prior to answering this question, however, we need to step back and ad- dress, if briefly, the fundamental question: What is language? In the mono- graph with this title, from which the opening quotation was taken, Esa It- konen persuasively argues that the nature of language has been commonly misunderstood in modern “theoretical linguistics” (including both the gen- erative and the cognitive/functional paradigms). Instead of “instincts”, “cognitive modules”, “neural mechanisms” or “usage”, Itkonen (1978, 1983, 1991, 2003) offers a very clear and intuitive answer: Language is a social institution for communicating meanings, a conception with sound roots in the tradition, e.g. Saussure (1916), Trubetzkoy (1939) and Wittgen- stein (1953). As such, language exists primarily between people rather than (only) within people. It is “shared” by the members of the community who speak it – in the strong sense in which people can “share a secret”: they all know it, and they know that they know it, rather than in the weak sense of “sharing a bottle of wine”. But what is it that people share when they know 2. I should point out that my own previous work on language and embodiment (Zlatev 1997) suffers from the same three drawbacks listed above, i.e. it lacks coherent concepts of representation and convention and, in addition, disregards their dependence on consciousness. My criticism of “embodiment theory” in the first part of this chapter is therefore also a form of (former-)self-criticism. 244 Jordan Zlatev a language? Above all: linguistically encoded concepts, i.e. lexical mean- ings, and rules for their combination. In Section 2 of this chapter I will elaborate on this, and argue that it is impossible to account for linguistic meaning without the concept of representation. Nearly as obviously, the conventionality of language, as well as the fact that we follow rules (which we are free to break) rather than mechanical deterministic procedures shows that our knowledge of language is (in principle) accessible to con- sciousness. This also implies that linguistic knowledge involves declarative, and not only procedural knowledge.3 This characterization of language in terms of conventionality, represen- tation and accessibility to consciousness appears to be on a collision course with attempts to explain language in terms of “embodiment”, since as pointed out above, it is precisely these three concepts that are at best under- developed, and at worse rejected by proponents of embodied cognition. In the recent work of cognitive linguists such as Johnson and Lakoff,4 and especially in PitF, this dissonance turns into an outright contradiction. In Section 3 I analyse the concept of embodiment as explicated within PitF (with some references to other Cognitive Linguistic work to show that PitF is by no means an exception), in order to make this contradiction as clear as possible. In brief: if language has the properties that I claim, and if em- bodiment has the properties that Lakoff and Johnson claim, then language can not be embodied.