The Role of Moral Utility in Decision Making: an Interdisciplinary Framework

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Role of Moral Utility in Decision Making: an Interdisciplinary Framework Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience 2008, 8 (4), 390-401 doi:10.3758/CABN.8.4.390 INTERSECTIONS AMONGG PHILOSOPHY, PSYCHOLOGY, AND NEUROSCIENCE The role of moral utility in decision making: An interdisciplinary framework PHILIPPE N.TOBLER University of Cambridge, Cambridge, England ANNEMARIE KALIS Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands AND TOBIAS KALENSCHER University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands What decisions should we make? Moral values, rules, and virtues provide standards for morally acceptable decisions, without prescribing how we should reach them. However, moral theories do assume that we are, at least in principle, capable of making the right decisions. Consequently, an empirical investigation of the methods and resources we use for making moral decisions becomes relevant. We consider theoretical parallels of economic decision theory and moral utilitarianism and suggest that moral decision making may tap into mechanisms and pro- cesses that have originally evolved for nonmoral decision making. For example, the computation of reward value occurs through the combination of probability and magnitude; similar computation might also be used for deter- mining utilitarian moral value. Both nonmoral and moral decisions may resort to intuitions and heuristics. Learning mechanisms implicated in the assignment of reward value to stimuli, actions, and outcomes may also enable us to determine moral value and assign it to stimuli, actions, and outcomes. In conclusion, we suggest that moral capa- bilities cancan employemploy andand benefitbenefit fromfrom a varietyvariety of nonmoralnonmoral decision-makingdecision-making andand learninglearning mechanisms.mechanisms. Imagine that you are the democratically elected presi- save y people on the ground ( y x)? Or do not only hi- dent of a country and have just been informed that a pas- jackers, but also presidents, have an unconditional duty senger airplane has been hijacked. The hijackers appear not to kill innocent people? to be headed for a city with well-populated skyscrapers. The questions above concern moral decision making, Your air force is in place and ready to shoot the passenger particularly what normative claims should guide us when plane down at your command. You can take many differ- we make moral decisions and how we actually make such ent courses of action: shoot or not, negotiate or not. How moral decisions. In the present review, we attempt to pro- should you decide? Would it make a difference whether vide a road map for the empirical investigation of moral 10 or 500 passengers are on board the airplane, or whether decision making. Our starting point will be the important the passengers have voted for you? Would it make a dif- philosophical distinction between is and ought. This dis- ference if the air force is not in place and the only way to tinction and the need for normative claims sometimes gets stop the hijackers in time is to ask the pilot of a nearby sec- forgotten by politicians and members of the public when ond passenger airplane to crash into the first? Would you they make statements about what should be done, given try to calculate how likely it is that the hijackers actually the facts. Then we will briefly introduce utilitarian and will crash the airplane into a skyscraper and how many deontological moral theories and will review psychologi- innocent people would die if the hijackers were to do so? cal and neuroscientific findings regarding moral decision Assuming that the probability of the hijackers’ heading making. This research will suggest that people may use for a skyscraper appears high, should you have the plane more than one moral theory, as well as moral heuristics, crashed by the other plane with its x additional passengers and that the prefrontal cortex may be particularly impor- beingbeing killedkilled withwith certainty,certainty, inin orderorder to probabilisticallyprobabilistically tant for moral decision making. Finally, we will propose P. N. Tobler, [email protected] Copyright 2008 Psychonomic Society, Inc. 390 MORAL DECISIONS 391 that moral decisions may rely on mental processes and ment (Brandt, 1979), and any other valuable consequences neuronal circuitry that originally evolved to serve non- of actions and rules. For utilitarian theories, something is moral functions, such as reward and punishment process- morally valuable because it promotes nonmoral values ing. We will do so by discussing parallels between moral such as happiness, pleasure, or other kinds of utility. and microeconomic utility theories and by suggesting that Deontological theories argue that certain things are classical learning theory, with its principle of error-driven morally valuable in themselves. Such moral value does not adjustment of reward predictions, can give clues as to derive from the fact that it promotes happiness, pleasure, how people acquire moral behavior. Neuronally, we will or any other utility (Rawls, 1971). The moral quality of propose that reward regions, such as the striatum and the actions arises from the fact that the action is done to pro- prefrontal cortex, may contribute to the acquisition and tect such moral values. The consequences and outcomes expression of moral behavior. Our proposal implies that of actions are secondary. Impermissible actions remain so the reward system may have beneficial functions not only irrespective of how good their consequences are. Some for individual survival by computing reward value, but deontological theories claim that all moral values can be also for society and culture by contributing to the compu- traced to one ultimate moral principle. One example of tation of the moral value of decisions and actions. such an ultimate principle is autonomy, conceived as the ability of a person to generate self-binding laws (Kant, The Is–Ought Gap 1797). Another example is the ability to act (Gewirth, When we ponder the morally right course of action, we 1998). Other positions claim that there are several moral always face a problem. Philosophers since Hume (1739) values, which have equal standing. Ross (1930), for ex- have argued that the factual characteristics of the situation ample, proposes seven basic values, which correspond to will themselves never tell us how we ought to act. Knowing seven moral duties: fidelity, reparation, justice, benefi- who the hijackers are, what they are going to do, and what cence, gratitude, self-improvement, and noninjury. Kant’s the consequences of their actions will be is not enough to de- (1797) work on morals is the paradigmatic example of a duce what the president ought to do. To use Hume’s words, deontological theory. The core rule in Kant’s system is the “you cannot derive an ought from an is” (Hume, 1739; for categorical imperative, which requires that we act accord- a related argument, see Moore, 1903; for a comparison, see ing to maxims that could become universal laws. Rules Bruening, 1971; for a dissenting view, see Searle, 1964). In often arise from the rights of those affected by the agent’s order to find out what the president ought to do, we need actions (Kamm, 2007). In Kantian terminology, this is ex- not only information about the facts of the current situation, pressed by the claim that one ought to treat others as ends but also some normative claims about what is valuable. We in themselves, and never only as means to an end. would commit a logical fallacy if we were to deduce moral Virtue ethics focuses on the motives and character conclusions just from descriptive facts. traits of actors. The bearers of moral quality are not ac- In the airplane example, one possible normative claim tions but life, people, and their capabilities (Nussbaum, might be that we are morally obliged to provide happiness 2000; Sen, 1985). Virtues are goods in themselves, and for the largest possible number of people. This would be their continued practice contributes to the good life. Ex- a utilitarian normative claim (e.g., Mill, 1861). Another amples of virtuous dispositions are wisdom, courage, possibility would be to presuppose the moral rule that moderation, justice, kindness, generosity, self-respect, one ought not to kill. This would be a deontological nor- compassion, altruism, forgiveness, and sincerity. Virtues mative claim (e.g., Kant, 1797). Descriptive information may fall in between more extreme character dispositions. about the situation must be combined with such norma- Having too little or too much of the disposition results in tive claims in order to reach a conclusion about what one vices (e.g., cowardice or rashness for courage; Aristotle, ought to do. For example, if one embraces the normative Nicomachean Ethics, 2002 ed.). Virtues should be care- claim that we are morally obliged to save as many people fully cultivated through moral education by role models. as possible, we could determine what to do by combining The development of habits helps to make the expression this claim with factual information about how different of virtuous dispositions more stable and reliable, but vir- possible actions would affect the number of people saved. tuous behavior should nevertheless remain goal directed Thus, normative claims and descriptive information taken and purposeful. Applying and reconciling virtues requires together allow us to make moral decisions. practical wisdom, which helps to discern what is important for a good life. Virtues are associated with an appropriate Moral Theories feeling of the right emotions. Aristotle and, more recently, We derive normative claims from moral theories. The Anscombe (1958), MacIntyre (1985), and Foot (2001) are main classes of moral theories are the utilitarian (conse- some of the prime proponents of virtue ethics. quentialist), deontological, and virtue theories. Utilitarian- ism states that the moral quality of actions is determined Moral Decisions in Theory and Practice by their consequences (utilitas Latin for [public] good, An implication of the is–ought gap is that whereas moral usefulness). This means that we have the duty to maximize theories provide standards for how we should act, they do not the sum or mean utility of all individuals in the society.
Recommended publications
  • Product Differentiation
    Product differentiation Industrial Organization Bernard Caillaud Master APE - Paris School of Economics September 22, 2016 Bernard Caillaud Product differentiation Motivation The Bertrand paradox relies on the fact buyers choose the cheap- est firm, even for very small price differences. In practice, some buyers may continue to buy from the most expensive firms because they have an intrinsic preference for the product sold by that firm: Notion of differentiation. Indeed, assuming an homogeneous product is not realistic: rarely exist two identical goods in this sense For objective reasons: products differ in their physical char- acteristics, in their design, ... For subjective reasons: even when physical differences are hard to see for consumers, branding may well make two prod- ucts appear differently in the consumers' eyes Bernard Caillaud Product differentiation Motivation Differentiation among products is above all a property of con- sumers' preferences: Taste for diversity Heterogeneity of consumers' taste But it has major consequences in terms of imperfectly competi- tive behavior: so, the analysis of differentiation allows for a richer discussion and comparison of price competition models vs quan- tity competition models. Also related to the practical question (for competition authori- ties) of market definition: set of goods highly substitutable among themselves and poorly substitutable with goods outside this set Bernard Caillaud Product differentiation Motivation Firms have in general an incentive to affect the degree of differ- entiation of their products compared to rivals'. Hence, differen- tiation is related to other aspects of firms’ strategies. Choice of products: firms choose how to differentiate from rivals, this impacts the type of products that they choose to offer and the diversity of products that consumers face.
    [Show full text]
  • I. Externalities
    Economics 1410 Fall 2017 Harvard University SECTION 8 I. Externalities 1. Consider a factory that emits pollution. The inverse demand for the good is Pd = 24 − Q and the inverse supply curve is Ps = 4 + Q. The marginal cost of the pollution is given by MC = 0:5Q. (a) What are the equilibrium price and quantity when there is no government intervention? (b) How much should the factory produce at the social optimum? (c) How large is the deadweight loss from the externality? (d) How large of a per-unit tax should the government impose to achieve the social optimum? 2. In Karro, Kansas, population 1,001, the only source of entertainment available is driving around in your car. The 1,001 Karraokers are all identical. They all like to drive, but hate congestion and pollution, resulting in the following utility function: Ui(f; d; t) = f + 16d − d2 − 6t=1000, where f is consumption of all goods but driving, d is the number of hours of driving Karraoker i does per day, and t is the total number of hours of driving all other Karraokers do per day. Assume that driving is free, that the unit price of food is $1, and that daily income is $40. (a) If an individual believes that the amount of driving he does wont affect the amount that others drive, how many hours per day will he choose to drive? (b) If everybody chooses this number of hours, then what is the total amount t of driving by other persons? (c) What will the utility of each resident be? (d) If everybody drives 6 hours a day, what will the utility level of each Karraoker be? (e) Suppose that the residents decided to pass a law restricting the total number of hours that anyone is allowed to drive.
    [Show full text]
  • Utility with Decreasing Risk Aversion
    144 UTILITY WITH DECREASING RISK AVERSION GARY G. VENTER Abstract Utility theory is discussed as a basis for premium calculation. Desirable features of utility functions are enumerated, including decreasing absolute risk aversion. Examples are given of functions meeting this requirement. Calculating premiums for simplified risk situations is advanced as a step towards selecting a specific utility function. An example of a more typical portfolio pricing problem is included. “The large rattling dice exhilarate me as torrents borne on a precipice flowing in a desert. To the winning player they are tipped with honey, slaying hirri in return by taking away the gambler’s all. Giving serious attention to my advice, play not with dice: pursue agriculture: delight in wealth so acquired.” KAVASHA Rig Veda X.3:5 Avoidance of risk situations has been regarded as prudent throughout history, but individuals with a preference for risk are also known. For many decision makers, the value of different potential levels of wealth is apparently not strictly proportional to the wealth level itself. A mathematical device to treat this is the utility function, which assigns a value to each wealth level. Thus, a 50-50 chance at double or nothing on your wealth level may or may not be felt equivalent to maintaining your present level; however, a 50-50 chance at nothing or the value of wealth that would double your utility (if such a value existed) would be equivalent to maintaining the present level, assuming that the utility of zero wealth is zero. This is more or less by definition, as the utility function is set up to make such comparisons possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Economic Evaluation Glossary of Terms
    Economic Evaluation Glossary of Terms A Attributable fraction: indirect health expenditures associated with a given diagnosis through other diseases or conditions (Prevented fraction: indicates the proportion of an outcome averted by the presence of an exposure that decreases the likelihood of the outcome; indicates the number or proportion of an outcome prevented by the “exposure”) Average cost: total resource cost, including all support and overhead costs, divided by the total units of output B Benefit-cost analysis (BCA): (or cost-benefit analysis) a type of economic analysis in which all costs and benefits are converted into monetary (dollar) values and results are expressed as either the net present value or the dollars of benefits per dollars expended Benefit-cost ratio: a mathematical comparison of the benefits divided by the costs of a project or intervention. When the benefit-cost ratio is greater than 1, benefits exceed costs C Comorbidity: presence of one or more serious conditions in addition to the primary disease or disorder Cost analysis: the process of estimating the cost of prevention activities; also called cost identification, programmatic cost analysis, cost outcome analysis, cost minimization analysis, or cost consequence analysis Cost effectiveness analysis (CEA): an economic analysis in which all costs are related to a single, common effect. Results are usually stated as additional cost expended per additional health outcome achieved. Results can be categorized as average cost-effectiveness, marginal cost-effectiveness,
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 4 4 Utility
    Chapter 4 Utility Preferences - A Reminder x y: x is preferred strictly to y. x y: x and y are equally preferred. x ~ y: x is preferred at least as much as is y. Preferences - A Reminder Completeness: For any two bundles x and y it is always possible to state either that xyx ~ y or that y ~ x. Preferences - A Reminder Reflexivity: Any bundle x is always at least as preferred as itself; iei.e. xxx ~ x. Preferences - A Reminder Transitivity: If x is at least as preferred as y, and y is at least as preferred as z, then x is at least as preferred as z; iei.e. x ~ y and y ~ z x ~ z. Utility Functions A preference relation that is complete, reflexive, transitive and continuous can be represented by a continuous utility function . Continuityyg means that small changes to a consumption bundle cause only small changes to the preference level. Utility Functions A utility function U(x) represents a preference relation ~ if and only if: x’ x” U(x’)>U(x) > U(x”) x’ x” U(x’) < U(x”) x’ x” U(x’) = U(x”). Utility Functions Utility is an ordinal (i.e. ordering) concept. E.g. if U(x) = 6 and U(y) = 2 then bdlibundle x is stri ilctly pref erred to bundle y. But x is not preferred three times as much as is y. Utility Functions & Indiff. Curves Consider the bundles (4,1), (2,3) and (2,2). Suppose (23)(2,3) (41)(4,1) (2, 2). Assiggyn to these bundles any numbers that preserve the preference ordering; e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Negative Externality: Reduces Utility Or Profit Externalities Defined
    Chapter 7 Externalities Reading • Essential reading – Hindriks, J and G.D. Myles Intermediate Public Economics. (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2006) Chapter 7. • Further reading – Bator, F.M. (1958) ‘The anatomy of market failure’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 72, 351—378. – Buchanan, J.M. and C. Stubblebine (1962) ‘Externality’, Economica, 29, 371—384. – Coase, R.H. (1960) ‘The problem of social cost’, Journal of Law and Economics, 3, 1—44. – Lin, S. (ed.) Theory and Measurement of Economic Externalities. (New York: Academic Press, 1976) [ISBN 0124504507 hbk]. – Meade, J.E. (1952) ‘External economies and diseconomies in a competitive situation’, Economic Journal, 62, 54—76. Reading – Pigou, A.C. The Economics of Welfare. (London: Macmillan, 1918). • Challenging reading – Muthoo, A. Bargaining Theory with Applications. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999) [ISBN 0521576474 pbk]. – Starrett, D. (1972) ‘Fundamental non-convexities in the theory of externalities’, Journal of Economic Theory, 4, 180—199. – Weitzman, M.L. (1974) ‘Prices vs. quantities’, Review of Economic Studies, 41, 477—491. Introduction • An externality is a link between economic agents that lies outside the price system – Pollution from a factory – Envy of a neighbor • Externalities are not under the control of the affected agent – Efficiency theorems do not apply – Competitive equilibrium unlikely to be efficient • Externalities are of practical importance – Global warming – Damage to ozone layer Externalities Defined •An externality is present whenever some economic
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Economics
    Mathematical Economics Dr Wioletta Nowak, room 205 C [email protected] http://prawo.uni.wroc.pl/user/12141/students-resources Syllabus Mathematical Theory of Demand Utility Maximization Problem Expenditure Minimization Problem Mathematical Theory of Production Profit Maximization Problem Cost Minimization Problem General Equilibrium Theory Neoclassical Growth Models Models of Endogenous Growth Theory Dynamic Optimization Syllabus Mathematical Theory of Demand • Budget Constraint • Consumer Preferences • Utility Function • Utility Maximization Problem • Optimal Choice • Properties of Demand Function • Indirect Utility Function and its Properties • Roy’s Identity Syllabus Mathematical Theory of Demand • Expenditure Minimization Problem • Expenditure Function and its Properties • Shephard's Lemma • Properties of Hicksian Demand Function • The Compensated Law of Demand • Relationship between Utility Maximization and Expenditure Minimization Problem Syllabus Mathematical Theory of Production • Production Functions and Their Properties • Perfectly Competitive Firms • Profit Function and Profit Maximization Problem • Properties of Input Demand and Output Supply Syllabus Mathematical Theory of Production • Cost Minimization Problem • Definition and Properties of Conditional Factor Demand and Cost Function • Profit Maximization with Cost Function • Long and Short Run Equilibrium • Total Costs, Average Costs, Marginal Costs, Long-run Costs, Short-run Costs, Cost Curves, Long-run and Short-run Cost Curves Syllabus Mathematical Theory of Production Monopoly Oligopoly • Cournot Equilibrium • Quantity Leadership – Slackelberg Model Syllabus General Equilibrium Theory • Exchange • Market Equilibrium Syllabus Neoclassical Growth Model • The Solow Growth Model • Introduction to Dynamic Optimization • The Ramsey-Cass-Koopmans Growth Model Models of Endogenous Growth Theory Convergence to the Balance Growth Path Recommended Reading • Chiang A.C., Wainwright K., Fundamental Methods of Mathematical Economics, McGraw-Hill/Irwin, Boston, Mass., (4th edition) 2005.
    [Show full text]
  • The Governance of Energy Displacement Network Oligopolies
    THE GOVERNANCE OF ENERGY DISPLACEMENT NETWORK OLIGOPOLIES Discussion Paper 96-08 Federal Energy Regulatory Commission Office of Economic Policy October 1996 Revised, May 1997 DISCUSSION PAPER THE GOVERNANCE OF ENERGY DISPLACEMENT NETWORK OLIGOPOLIES Richard P. O'Neill Charles S. Whitmore and Michelle Veloso Office of Economic Policy Federal Energy Regulatory Commission Washington, D.C. Olin Foundation Conference on Gas Policy Issues Yale University School of Management New Haven, Connecticut October 4, 1996 Revised May 1997 The analyses and conclusions expressed in this paper are those of the authors and do not necessarily represent the views of other members of the Federal Energy Regulatory Commission, any individual Commissioner, or the Commission itself. Contents Page Executive Summary ..........................................................v I. Introduction .............................................................1 II. Historical Background: The Inertial Baggage ...................................3 A. Introduction .......................................................3 Early Public Utility Regulation ......................................3 Modern Public Utility Regulation ....................................4 B. The Mathematical School: The Quest for Efficiency .........................5 The Quest for Perfect Rates ........................................5 Dynamic Efficiency and Auctions ....................................8 Unanswered Questions ............................................9 C. The Political School: the Quest
    [Show full text]
  • Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility Author(S): John C
    Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility Author(s): John C. Harsanyi Source: Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 63, No. 4 (Aug., 1955), pp. 309-321 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1827128 Accessed: 18-07-2015 00:34 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of Political Economy. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 128.135.12.127 on Sat, 18 Jul 2015 00:34:52 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CARDINAL W ELFARE, INDIVIDUALISTIC ETHICS, AND INTERPERSONAL COMPARISONS OF UTILITY' JOHN C. HARSANY1 Universityof Queensland I uals prefersY to X, thenX should be re- T HE naive conceptof social welfare garded as sociallypreferable to Y. But no as a sum of intuitivelymeasurable other restrictionis to be imposed on the and comparable individual cardi- mathematical form of a social welfare nal utilities has been found unable to function. withstand the methodological
    [Show full text]
  • Hazards of Neoliberalism: Delayed Electric Power Restoration After Hurricane Ike.” Under Revision at the British Journal of Sociology
    Miller, Lee M., Robert J. Antonio and Alessandro Bonanno. “Hazards of Neoliberalism: Delayed Electric Power Restoration after Hurricane Ike.” Under revision at The British Journal of Sociology. HAZARDS OF NEOLIBERALISM: DELAYED ELECTRIC POWER RESTORATION AFTER HURRICANE IKE ABSTRACT This case study explores how neoliberal policies shape the impacts of a natural disaster. We investigate the reactions to major damages to the electric power system and the restoration of power in the wake of Hurricane Ike, which devastated the Houston, Texas, metropolitan area in September 2008. We argue that the neoliberal policy agenda insured a minimalist approach to the crisis and generated dissatisfaction among many residents. The short-term profitability imperative shifted reconstruction costs to consumers, and failed to upgrade the electric power system‟s infrastructure to prepare for future disasters. We illustrate the serious obstacles for disaster mitigation and recovery posed by neoliberal policies that privatize public goods and socialize private costs. Neoliberalism does not address the needs of a highly stratified public, nor does it act on behalf of the public‟s long-term interests and safety. Introduction This article analyses the actions of the electric companies serving the Houston, Texas area1 as they and other relevant actors attempted to restore power and repair the electric infrastructure for several weeks after Hurricane Ike devastated the Houston metropolitan area in September 2008. The details of delayed power restoration after the hurricane show that neoliberalism‟s free market approach hinders efficient response, undermines mitigation efforts, exacerbates the impacts of disasters, and magnifies the inequalities in coping resources and suffering between privileged and less privileged communities.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Utility Treatment of Environmental Externalities
    NRRI 94-10 PUBLIC UTILITY COMMISSION TREATMENT OF ENVIRONMENTAL EXTERNALITIES Kenneth Rose, Ph.D. Senior Institute Economist Paul A. Centolella, Esq. Senior Economist Science Applications International Corporation Benjamin F. Hobbs, Ph.D. Institute Associate and Professor Case Western Reserve University June 1994 This report was prepared by The National Regulatory Research Institute (NRRI) with funding provided by participating member commissions of the National Association of Regulatory Utility Commissioners (NARUC). The views and opinions of the authors do not necessarily state or reflect the views, opinions, or policies of the NRRI, the NARUC, or NARUC member commissions. EXECUTIVE SUMMARY Many public utility commissions in the United States are considering the environmental consequences or externalities from the generation and distribution of electric power. These environmental externalities are the costs to society that are not reflected either in the cost of the resources that produce electricity or in the price of the electricity paid by consumers. Commissions have adopted various methods to internalize these costs in an attempt to have utility costs reflect the actual cost of electricity production and distribution to society. These considerations are in addition to existing environmental standards prescribed by state and federal legislation. The consideration of environmental externalities by state commissions has occurred through least-cost or integrated resource planning processes. Externalities are dealt with on a qualitative basis only, explicitly quantified, or on both a qualitative and quantitative basis. The states that quantify externalities use a percentage "adder" to resource costs, apply a scoring system in a competitive bidding process, or monetize specific pollutants. Traditionally, environmental externalities have been addressed though command-and- control environmental legislation at the state and federal levels and implemented by state and federal environmental regulators.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Consumerism As a Neoliberal Response to Youth Political Disengagement
    societies Article Political Consumerism as a Neoliberal Response to Youth Political Disengagement Georgios Kyroglou and Matt Henn * ID Department of Politics and International Relations, Nottingham Trent University, Nottingham NG1 4FQ, UK; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 27 September 2017; Accepted: 8 December 2017; Published: 11 December 2017 Abstract: Recent trends indicate diminishing public engagement with formal electoral politics in many advanced liberal democracies, especially among the younger generations. However, evidence also suggests that there has been a simultaneous interest by many young citizens in political consumerism. In large part, this interest is shaped as a response to the individualisation and strict ‘economism’ driven by the underlying forces of neoliberalism. Disenfranchised and disillusioned by the seeming incapacity of the purely political sphere to respond to their individualised claims, and having internalised the neoliberal critique of democracy,these young empowered citizen-consumers often search for the ‘political’ within the bounds of the marketplace and are increasingly attracted to consumerist methods of political participation, such as boycotting and buycotting. Given the susceptibility of political consumerism to a neoliberal modus operandi, the lack of available literature problematising its emergence as a response to neoliberal principles is somewhat surprising. The present article will address this gap by connecting the declining levels of electoral participation among younger generations in post-crisis Europe to the rise of political consumerism within the neoliberal ideological hegemony of the ‘marketopoly’. We distinguish between two antithetical, but complimentary effects. Firstly, the internalised neoliberal critique of democracy emphasises the ‘push’ out of the public into the commercial sphere.
    [Show full text]