Graduate Program in Philosophy Dissertation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Graduate Program in Philosophy Dissertation FEDERAL UNIVERSITY OF PELOTAS Institute of Philosophy, Sociology and Politics Post- Graduate Program in Philosophy Dissertation David Hume's Politics: a distinct reconciliation between Liberalism and Conservatism Celina Alcantara Brod Pelotas, 2020 Celina Alcantara Brod David Hume's Politics: a distinct reconciliation between Liberalism and Conservatism Dissertation presented to the post -graduate program in philosophy of the Federal University of Pelotas, as a partial requirement to obtain the title of Master in Philosophy Advisor: Evandro Barbosa Pelotas,2020 Universidade Federal de Pelotas / Sistema de Bibliotecas Catalogação na Publicação B863d Brod, Celina Alcantara BroDavid hume's politics : a distinct reconciliation between liberalism and conservatism / Celina Alcantara Brod ; Evandro Barbosa, orientador. — Pelotas, 2020. Bro86 f. BroDissertação (Mestrado) — Programa de Pós-Graduação em Filosofia, Instituto de Filosofia, Sociologia e Política, Universidade Federal de Pelotas, 2020. Bro1. Conservatism. 2. Liberalism. 3. Habit. 4. Causality. 5. David hume. I. Barbosa, Evandro, orient. II. Título. CDD : 100 Elaborada por Simone Godinho Maisonave CRB: 10/1733 Celina Alcantara Brod David Hume's Politics: a distinct reconciliation between Liberalism and Conservatism Dissertation presented to the Post-graduate program in philosophy of the Federal University of Pelotas, as a partial requirement to obtain the title of Master in Philosophy Date of Defense: 27.04.2020 Examining Board: . Prof.Dr. Evandro Barbosa – Federal University of Pelotas - UFPEL (Advisor) Prof. Dr. Keberson Bresolin- Federal University of Pelotas - UFPEL Prof.Dr. Spartaco Pupo – University of Calabria - UNICAL To my children, Gabriel and Bruno Acknowledgments Even though writing a dissertation can sometimes be a lonely process, none of this would have been possible without the support and encouragement of some special people. I would like to thank my children for being considerate, they have encouraged me all the way through and patiently waited for my attention. I would like to thank my husband, who has always given me the support and the love I needed to dive into this study, I am conscious of the great debt I owe to him. I would like to thank my father for being supportive and believing in me. I would like to thank my mother who has read all my writings since the beginning, sharing with me her experiences and knowledge, and for not letting me give up. I would like to thank my advisor Evandro Barbosa, for trusting me and my work, and for his friendship and teachings. His support and orientation are key components of this dissertation. I would like to thank professors Spartaco Pupo, Flávia Chagas and Keberson Bresolin for kindly accepting my invitation to be members in the defense committee. I would like to thank all my philosophy professors at Federal University of Pelotas and the Philosophy post-Graduate department. Last, but not least, I would like to thank the taxpayers of this country and Capes for the financial support I received to carry out this research. “I believe in it, I answer for it, for the whole work of man really seems to consist in nothing but proving to himself every minute that he is a man and not a piano- key”. Fyodor Dostoyevsky, Notes from Underground Abstract BROD, Celina A. David Hume's Politics: a distinct Reconciliation between conservatism and Liberalism, 2019.Dissertation – Philosophy, Institute of Philosphy, Sociology and Politics, Federal University of Pelotas, Pelotas, 2020 Abstract: The aim of this dissertation is to argue that Hume's political theory can provide a theoretical procedural configuration that reconciles the skeptical principles of secular Conservatism in its form with the core values of Classical Liberalism in its content, To demonstrate the compatibility of conservative and liberal concepts within this framework, we will demonstrate the connections between Hume's formal principles and his substantive political ideas. This theoretical framework establishes criteria and limits to be considered in the articulation and justification of political arguments Causality and habit are key concepts for understanding Hume's explanation of conventions, his strong defense of moderation, and his critique of political rationalism. We aim to show that it is possible to systematize criteria for a prudent activity of governing in a theoretical framework that filters empirically consistent arguments from metaphysical ones. Keywords: Conservatism.Liberalism. Habit. Causality.David Hume Abbreviation for Hume’s Works It is a standard practice to refer to Hume’s texts using abbreviations, though not everyone uses the same abbreviations. I will adopt the single letter abbreviations with paragraph and section number to simplify the location of Hume’s passage. As this dissertation was originally written in English, I used Hume’s originals texts available on Hume Texts Online. Hume Texts Online is a free and open access collection of works by David Hume. The site is developed and maintained by Amyas Merivale, and the texts are edited by Amyas Merivale and Peter Millican. The site consists of every philosophical text that Hume published, in accurate editions that faithfully represent the original 18th century publications. DM Of the Dignity or Meanness of 1. Major works (in chronological order) Human Nature T Treatise of Human Nature CL Of Civil Liberty A Abstract of the Treatise El Of Eloquence L Letter from a Gentleman RP Of the Rise and Progress of the Arts E Enquiry Concerning Human and Sciences Understanding Ep The Epicurean M Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Sto The Stoic Morals Pl The Platonist P Dissertation on the Passions Sc The Sceptic N Natural History of Religion PD Of Polygamy and Divorces D Dialogues Concerning Natural SR Of Simplicity and Refinement in Religion Writing H History of England NC Of National Characters Tr Of Tragedy 2. Essays (as ordered in Miller’s ST Of the Standard of Taste standard edition) Co Of Commerce RA Of Refinement in the Arts DT Of the Delicacy of Taste and Mo Of Money Passion In Of Interest LP Of the Liberty of the Press BT Of the Balance of Trade PR That Politics may be reduced to a JT Of the Jealousy of Trade Science BP Of the Balance of Power FP Of the First Principles of Ta Of Taxes Government PC Of Public Credit OG Of the Origin of Government RC Of some Remarkable Customs IP Of the Independency of Parliament PA Of the Populousness of Ancient BG Whether the British Government Nations inclines more to Absolute OC Of the Original Contract Monarchy, or to a Republic PO Of Passive Obedience PG Of Parties in General CP Of the Coalition of Parties PGB Of the Parties of Great Britain PS Of the Protestant Succession SE Of Superstition and Enthusiasm IPC Idea of a Perfect Commonwealth IM Of Impudence and Modesty MP Of Moral Prejudices LM Of Love and Marriage MS Of the Middle Station of Life SH Of the Study of History CR A Character of Sir Robert Walpole Av Of Avarice Su Of Suicide EW Of Essay-Writing IS Of the Immortality of the Soul SUMMARY 1 INTRODUCTION ........................................................................................................ 8 2 THE CONSERVATIVE FRAMEWORK ................................................................. 16 2.1 Skepticism in politics .................................................................................................... 16 2.2 The Passionate and Inventive Nature of the Political Man ............................................. 27 2.3 Time Conventions and Hume’s Secular conservatism.................................................... 37 3 LIBERAL IDEAS ....................................................................................................... 48 3.1 Private Property: A Miraculous Invention ..................................................................... 48 3.2 Constitutional Governments and Freedom ..................................................................... 54 3.3 Commercial Societies and Civilization .......................................................................... 59 4 HUME'S CONSERVATIVE LIBERALISM ............................................................. 63 4.1 Liberalism and Common Life ........................................................................................ 63 4.2 Applying Moderation: Hume against extremism............................................................ 70 5 FINAL CONSIDERATIONS ..................................................................................... 76 REFERENCES .................................................................................................................. 79 1 INTRODUCTION Why associate David Hume's political theory with terms that are late to the author himself? What relevance is there in knowing where conservatism and liberalism are placed in his political doctrine? The answer to this question explains, to a great extent, the two main purposes of this work: first, to show that Hume's political thought, a landmark in the British Enlightenment tradition, should not be neglected, because it represents the final union of his epistemological and moral thesis. Secondly, to defend an attractive fitting of these two concepts within the theoretical structure of the Scottish empiricist. While investigating the relationship between these concepts, an underlying question will be considered throughout this study: how, after all, can novelty integrate the past and how does the past remain in the present without one preventing or damaging
Recommended publications
  • Leibniz E O Direito Brasileiro.Pdf
    RENATO EUGENIO DE FREITAS PERES UMA REVISÃO DAS POSSÍVEIS FONTES LEIBNIZIANAS NA FORMAÇÃO DA CIÊNCIA JURÍDICA BRASILEIRA: UM ESTUDO DA OBRA DE AUGUSTO TEIXEIRA DE FREITAS Dissertação apresentada à Banca Examinadora da Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo como exigência parcial para obtenção do título de Mestre em História da Ciência, sob a orientação da Professora Doutora Ana Maria Alfonso-Goldfarb. Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo São Paulo 2005 0 RESUMO O presente trabalho trata da seguinte hipótese: Leibniz pode ter sido uma fonte de influência para o direito brasileiro? Para realizar tal investigação, examinamos com uma visão crítica a obra jurídica de dois autores: Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz e Augusto Teixeira de Freitas. E o fizemos propondo duas situações que normalmente não são encontradas em trabalhos do gênero. Investigamos a obra jurídica de Leibniz porque embora seu nome seja muito conhecido pelo seu legado filosófico, ele foi também jurista citado como influência. Todavia, seus escritos sobre direito são pouco estudados. Em seguida, estudamos a obra de um jurista brasileiro do ponto de vista da história da ciência. Teixeira de Freitas foi muito importante na época de formação da ciência jurídica brasileira porque ele foi o autor da Consolidação das Leis Civis e do Esboço de Código Civil, textos que foram fundamentais para a teoria e para a prática do direito no Brasil no século XIX. Tratamos de apurar o que Leibniz escreveu em matéria de direito, o que há disponível traduzido para o português ou não, e o que pode ser encontrado na Biblioteca da Faculdade de Direito de São Paulo.
    [Show full text]
  • Downloaded from Brill.Com10/07/2021 01:40:02PM This Is an Open Access Chapter Distributed Under the Terms of the CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 License
    chapter 7 Men, Monsters and the History of Mankind in Vattel’s Law of Nations Pärtel Piirimäe 1 Introduction Emer de Vattel has been widely considered a seminal figure in the European tradition of the law of nations. While attaching himself to the earlier tradition of natural jurisprudence, he offered a normative system of the law of nations that was more firmly and explicitly anchored to the political practice of his contemporary Europe than were the doctrines of his predecessors. Vattel pro- moted the practical applicability of his Droit des gens (1758), stressing that it was not so much written for interested ‘private individuals’, i.e. other scholars or the general public, but it was a ‘law of sovereigns’ that was primarily in- tended for ‘them and their ministers’. It would not help much, he explained, if his maxims were studied only by those who had no influence over public affairs; the ‘conductors of states’, on the other hand, if they chose to learn this science and adopt its maxims as the ‘compass’ for their policies, could produce many ‘happy results’.1 Vattel emphasized the easy comprehension and applica- bility of his book, contrasting his approach with that of Christian Wolff, whose treatise on the law of nations could be understood only if one ‘previously stud- ied sixteen or seventeen quarto volumes which precede it’.2 As Vattel famous- ly declared, his original intention was to introduce Wolff’s system to a wider readership, by rendering his rigid and formal work more ‘agreeable and better calculated to ensure it a reception in the polite world’.3 While it is clear that Vattel’s work amounted to much more than a system- atic account of Wolff’s principles,4 it is in the manner of presentation that the differences between the two scholars are the most striking.
    [Show full text]
  • 181 Chapter VII a World of Many
    181 Chapter VII A World of Many: Giving up the Belief in the Possibility of Universal Rule (1648/59 – 1714) A Description of the “State” of the Holy Roman Empire Slightly less than twenty years after the treaties of Munster and Osnabrück, the jurist and historian Samuel von Pufendorf (1632 – 1694) clad his description of the Holy Roman Empire into a fictitious travel report. He took the role of a Veronese citizen named Severinus de Monzambano, explaining to his alleged brother the oddities of the form of government of the Empire. The choice of Veronese identity had not been random, as the city of Verona the lay on Venetian territory and, from the fourteenth century, Venice had no longer been considered part of the Empire,1 from the turn towards the sixteenth century even as the foe of the Emperor. Pufendorf explained the form of government of the Empire in historical terms, described the processes by which the centre of rule had shifted from the Italian Peninsula to areas north of the Alps and, at the very beginning of his report, made it clear that the Empire was known by the wrong official name. Instead of “Holy Roman Empire”, it should, Pufendorf insisted, be called the “new state of the Germans”, because it had nothing to do with the ancient empire of the Romans. It was a grave mistake, he wrote, to believe that this ancient empire of the Romans had continued to be in existence. Quite on the contrary, the empire, whose capital the city of Rome had once been, had been destroyed.
    [Show full text]
  • Republicanism
    ONIVI C C Re PUBLICANISM ANCIENT LESSONS FOR GLOBAL POLITICS EDIT ED BY GEOFFREY C. KELLOW AND NeVEN LeDDY ON CIVIC REPUBLICANISM Ancient Lessons for Global Politics EDITED BY GEOFFREY C. KELLOW AND NEVEN LEDDY On Civic Republicanism Ancient Lessons for Global Politics UNIVERSITY OF ToronTO PRESS Toronto Buffalo London © University of Toronto Press 2016 Toronto Buffalo London www.utppublishing.com Printed in the U.S.A. ISBN 978-1-4426-3749-8 Printed on acid-free, 100% post-consumer recycled paper with vegetable- based inks. Library and Archives Canada Cataloguing in Publication On civic republicanism : ancient lessons for global politics / edited by Geoffrey C. Kellow and Neven Leddy. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 978-1-4426-3749-8 (bound) 1. Republicanism – History. I. Leddy, Neven, editor II.Kellow, Geoffrey C., 1970–, editor JC421.O5 2016 321.8'6 C2015-906926-2 CC-BY-NC-ND This work is published subject to a Creative Commons Attribution Non-commercial No Derivative License. For permission to publish commercial versions please contact University of Toronto Press. University of Toronto Press acknowledges the financial assistance to its publishing program of the Canada Council for the Arts and the Ontario Arts Council, an agency of the Government of Ontario. an Ontario government agency un organisme du gouvernement de l’Ontario Funded by the Financé par le Government gouvernement of Canada du Canada Contents Preface: A Return to Classical Regimes Theory vii david edward tabachnick and toivo koivukoski Introduction 3 geoffrey c. kellow Part One: The Classical Heritage 1 The Problematic Character of Periclean Athens 15 timothy w.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Sovereignty and the State: the American Revolution, the International Press, and the French Political Imagination
    RETHINKING SOVEREIGNTY AND THE STATE: THE AMERICAN REVOLUTION, THE INTERNATIONAL PRESS, AND THE FRENCH POLITICAL IMAGINATION Steven Weber A thesis submitted to the faculty at the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the Department of History in the College of Arts and Sciences. Chapel Hill 2018 Approved by: Jay Smith Lloyd Kramer Kathleen DuVal © 2018 Steven Weber ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii ABSTRACT Steven Weber: Rethinking Sovereignty and the State: The American Revolution, the International Press, and the French Political Imagination (Under the direction of Jay Smith) This paper examines the ideological content and implications of texts from Britain and North America translated and published in France during the American Revolution and situates them in political dialogues already underway in the French public sphere by the 1770s. Focused on popular sovereignty, representation in government, and public control of state finances, the paper shows how documents from America and Britain reinforced radical political arguments in France that would ultimately undermine the absolutist old regime. These texts, circulated legally in newspapers and the state-run periodical Affaires de l’Angleterre et de l’Amérique, communicated numerous arguments in favor of populism and public action to French readers. This thesis places those texts into the cannon of subversive writings that circulated in the French public sphere in the years before the revolution, and thus places
    [Show full text]
  • Gabriel Bonnot De Mably and the “Philosophie Économique”: Connections and Disconnections
    Gabriel Bonnot de Mably and the “philosophie économique”: connections and disconnections Julie Ferrand PHARE ***** Preliminary version Introduction Of the opponents to physiocracy, Gabriel Bonnot de Mably’s name is one of the most quoted. As pointed out by J.K. Wright, his Doutes proposés aux philosophes économistes sur l’ordre naturel et essentiel des sociétés politiques (1768) and Du commerce des grains (1775) are unique among his works. They provide the only opportunity we have of seeing Mably arguing against an opposing system of thought (Wright 1997, 109). However, the Abbé says that he is the follower of the Economists regarding taxation, agricultural and commerce issues (Mably 1794-5 [1768], 2). This statement is often either quote without analysis or is considered as a reminiscence of an agricultural model in ancient Greece (see Wright 1997). Yet Mably is far from arguing against modern commercial society as a whole. In a previous works, we demonstrated that throughout his life, he stresses the necessity to develop the agricultural sector based on free circulation of goods inside the Kingdom and an export control system (see Ferrand and Orain 2017). And when he attacks the liberalization of grain trade promoted by the ministry of Turgot, it is to denounce the nefarious consequences of the continual rise in corn prices for the lower classes that followed the two liberalizations (1764 and 1774). Nevertheless, Mably does not for this reason question the primacy of agricultural trade, and not totally even the liberalization of the grain market (see Ferrand 2013). On the other hand, the opposition is more evident with regard to the political theory advocated by Lemercier de la Rivière.
    [Show full text]
  • Innovation After the French Revolution, Or, Innovation Transformed: from Word to Concept
    Innovation after the French Revolution, or, Innovation Transformed: From Word to Concept Benoît Godin 385 rue Sherbrooke Est Montreal, Quebec Canada H2X 1E3 [email protected] Project on the Intellectual History of Innovation Working Paper No. 14 2013 Previous Papers in the Series: 1. B. Godin, Innovation: The History of a Category. 2. B. Godin, In the Shadow of Schumpeter: W. Rupert Maclaurin and the Study of Technological Innovation. 3. B. Godin, The Linear Model of Innovation (II): Maurice Holland and the Research Cycle. 4. B. Godin, National Innovation System (II): Industrialists and the Origins of an Idea. 5. B. Godin, Innovation without the Word: William F. Ogburn’s Contribution to Technological Innovation Studies. 6. B. Godin, ‘Meddle Not with Them that Are Given to Change’: Innovation as Evil. 7. B. Godin, Innovation Studies: the Invention of a Specialty (Part I). 8. B. Godin, Innovation Studies: the Invention of a Specialty (Part II). 9. B. Godin, καινοτομία: An Old Word for a New World, or the De-Contestation of a Political and Contested Concept. 10. B. Godin, Republicanism and Innovation in Seventeenth Century England. 11. B. Godin, Social Innovation: Utopias of Innovation from c.1830 to the Present. 12. B. Godin and P. Lucier, Innovation and Conceptual Innovation in Ancient Greece. 13. B. Godin and J. Lane, ‘Pushes and Pulls’: The Hi(S)tory of the Demand-Pull Model of Innovation. Project on the Intellectual History of Innovation 385 rue Sherbrooke Est, Montreal, Quebec H2X 1E3 Telephone: (514) 499-4074 Facsimile: (514) 499-4065 www.csiic.ca Abstract For centuries, innovation has been a pejorative concept, and there has been no study of what innovation is.
    [Show full text]
  • 201 Subcapítulo 2.3 Valores Diversos Como Justificações De Diferentes
    Subcapítulo 2.3 Valores Diversos como Justificações de Diferentes Ordens Sociais 2.3.1. O Político e o social como esferas autónomas Com as transformações sociais, económicas e religiosas iniciadas no século XVI, e sobretudo desde a revolução liderada por Cromwell em 1640, os fundamentos da ordem social e política vigentes havia séculos foram fortemente abalados , o que deu origem a uma série de obras em que se discutiam esses fundamentos e procurava alternativas e que constituem a moderna filosofia política. Desde a revolução em Inglaterra que a nova ordem social e política, vinha sendo teorizada por autores como, Hobbes (1642, 1651), Locke (1690), Vico em Principi di una scienza nuova (1721), Mandeville em A Fábula das Abelhas (1723), Pascal e outros jansenistas, como Nicole (1733), Hume no Tratado da Natureza Humana (1739) e “Acerca do Comércio” (publicado em Discursos Políticos) , Hutcheson, no Inquiry Concerning Virtue , Montesquieu em Esprit des lois (1748), Quesnay, o Abade Gabriel Bonnot de Mably, Steuart em Inquiry into the Principles of Political Oeconomnie (1767), Adam Smith no Tratado dos Sentimentos Morais (1759), Pudendorf em Direito da Natureza e das Gentes (1771). Mas foi noutra obra de A. Smith, Inquérito sobre a Natureza e Causas da Riqueza das Nações (publicada pela primeira vez em 1776), que foram tratadas de forma mais sistemática as questões relativas ao que ficou conhecido como economia política, pelas relações estreitas que a teorização da actividade económica tinha com a filosofia política e a ética 1. A economia política, tal como estes filósofos a teorizaram, desenvolveu-se a partir do quadro da filosofia política.
    [Show full text]
  • The 'Ignominious Fall of the European Commonwealth': Gentz
    The ‘Ignominious Fall of the European Commonwealth’ : Gentz, Hauterive, and the Armed Neutrality of 1800 Isaac Nakhimovsky Introduction The status of neutral commerce during times of war was one of the questions addressed by a major Anglo-French debate about the character of the European state system that took place around 1800.1 These debates took place in anticipation of a general peace settlement, which became particularly acute following Napoleon’s success in driving the Habsburgs out of Italy and Russia’s growing estrangement from its allies in the Second Coalition against France. In debating the shape of this coming settlement, both sides presented competing accounts of what had happened to the previous European states system, or, in eighteenth-century terms, the European Republic. The question on the surface of this debate was how to assign responsibility for what one of the chief participants, Friedrich von Gentz, later called “the ignominious fall of the European Commonwealth” in the wake of the French Revolution.2 This was inevitably a rather polemical discussion, but as this article aims to show, underlying it was a clash between important models of the European states system. Moreover, each of these models had a well-developed historiographical dimension. At the core of the contest was the question of how the development of the European states system had been impacted by the rise of 1 Important discussions of these debates include F.H. Hinsley, Power and the Pursuit of Peace: Theory and Practice in the History of Relations Between States (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1963), pp. 186–94; Murray Forsyth, “The Old European States-System: Gentz vs.
    [Show full text]
  • Sans-Culottes and the Part That They Played in Tthe French Revolution.1 It Is Also a Book About Rousseau, And, No Less Centrally, a Book About Salons
    �1� INTRODUCTION: “ONE OF THE MOST INTERESTING PAIRS OF BREECHES RECORDED IN MODERN HISTORY” HIS is a book about the sans-culottes and the part that they played in Tthe French Revolution.1 It is also a book about Rousseau, and, no less centrally, a book about salons. Its aim is to try to show how the three subjects were connected, and by doing so, to begin to piece together the historical and intellectual setting in which the republican politics of the French Revolution first acquired their content and shape. This, in the first instance, entails going back quite a long way into the eighteenth century. It also involves trying to get behind many of the events and images now associated with what the sans-culottes became. These centre mainly on the crowds who stormed the Bastille in Paris in July 1789 and, more specifically, on the mixture of direct democracy and physical force that, according to an established range of historical interpretations, either was orchestrated deliberately or erupted spontaneously among the artisans and small shop­ keepers of urban France during the violent period of political conflict that occurred after the Parisian insurrection of 10 August 1792, and the trial and execution of Louis XVI in January 1793. By then, France had become a republic and, again according to the same range of established historical interpretations, the sans-culottes are usually described either as its social and political vanguard, or as the largely unwitting instruments of its Jacobin­ dominated politics.2 In one guise or another, however, the sans-culottes 1 It is also an attempt to correct some of the gaps or mistakes in Michael Sonenscher, “The Sans-Culottes of the Year II: Rethinking the Language of Labour in Revolutionary France,” Social History 9 (1984): 301–28; Work and Wages: Politics, Natural Law and the Eighteenth- Century French Trades (Cambridge, CUP, 1989), ch.
    [Show full text]
  • The Law of Nations and Natural Law 1625–​1800
    chapter 6 The International Political Thought of Johann Jacob Schmauss and Johann Gottlieb Heineccius: Natural Law, Interest, History and the Balance of Power Peter Schröder 1 Introduction Hugo Grotius had been fairly optimistic that his natural law doctrine would be able to regulate the antagonistic relations between sovereign states. By looking at the arguments of Johann Jacob Schmauss (1690– 1757) and Johann Gottlieb Heineccius (1681– 1741), this chapter scrutinizes the limits of natural law regard- ing interstate relations. They used classical political or juridical concepts of international political thought – such as interest, balance of power, natural law and history – in their political and philosophical writings. Schmauss and Heineccius were both taught by Christian Thomasius1 and were part of the circle of Thomasius’s disciples at the newly founded University of Halle who shaped and continued the early Enlightenment and natural law project. But they pursued their writings and teaching in different directions. Schmauss belonged to the great eighteenth- century jurists. And yet he is almost entirely forgotten, despite the fact that some specialists have empha- sized his importance.2 Schmauss provides one of the crucial links between the University of Halle and the natural law tradition which is so closely associated with Thomasius, and the up and coming University of Göttingen, where he 1 In contrast to Schmauss and Heineccius, Thomasius has been well researched. See in particu- lar the English contributions by Ian Hunter, The Secularisation of the Confessional State: The Political Thought of Christian Thomasius (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007); Thomas Ahnert, Religion and the Origins of the German Enlightenment: Faith and the Reform of Learning in the Thought of Christian Thomasius (Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press, 2006); and Timothy Hochstrasser, Natural Law Theories in the Early Enlightenment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Mably Et L'ordre International À La Fin Du Xviiie Siècle1 Les Révolutionnaires Américains, Puis Les Partisans De La Cons
    Mably et l’ordre international à la fin du XVIIIe siècle1 Les révolutionnaires américains, puis les partisans de la construction d’un gouvernement fédéral dans la crise des années 1783-1787, se référaient à un certain nombre d’auteurs canoniques dans leur appréciation de l’ordre international de leur époque. Ces philosophes, juristes, "publicistes" des XVIIe et XVIIIe siècle étaient lus, connus, cités, utilisés par les auteurs de Federalist Papers et par leurs adversaires anti-fédéralistes. Parmi ces théoriciens de ce que l’on appelle alors le "droit des gens" (le terme de droit international est inventé en 1789 par Jeremy Bentham, mais ne devient d’un usage courant que dans la deuxième moitié du XIXe siècle), on peut citer les fondateurs de l’école du droit naturel le Hollandais Grotius, l’Allemand Samuel Pufendorf, le Neuchâtelois Emer de Vattel auteur du Droit des gens en 1758, le Genevois Jean-Jacques Burlamaqui et le philosophe français Gabriel Bonnot de Mably. Mably est né à Grenoble le 14 mars 1709 dans une famille de noblesse de robe. Gabriel est le deuxième frère de la famille Bonnot, son frère cadet est le philosophe Étienne de Condillac. Mably suit des études chez les Jésuites de Lyon, puis au séminaire de Saint-Sulpice. Protégé par Mme de Tencin, il est reçu dans son célèbre salon parisien où il peut rencontrer Montesquieu, Bolingbroke, Fontenelle, l’abbé de Saint-Pierre, et bien d’autres représentants de la première génération des Lumières. En 1742, Mably est engagé comme secrétaire du cardinal de Tencin (frère de la précédente), nouvellement ministre des Affaires étrangères dans le gouvernement de Fleury.
    [Show full text]