A Broad Perspective on Embodied Language

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Broad Perspective on Embodied Language Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews 69 (2016) 69–78 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews jou rnal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/neubiorev Grounding meaning in experience: A broad perspective on embodied language a,∗ b c d Giovanni Buccino , Ivan Colagè , Nicola Gobbi , Giorgio Bonaccorso a Dipartimento di Scienze Mediche e Chirurgiche, University “Magna Graecia” of Catanzaro, Viale Salvatore Venuta, 88100, Germaneto, Italy b Faculty of Philosophy, Pontifical University Antonianum, Via Merulana 124/B, 00185, Rome, Italy c Faculty of Philosophy, Pontifical Gregorian University, Piazza della Pilotta 4, 00187, Rome, Italy d Institute for Pastoral Liturgy of Padua, Affiliated to the Pontifical Athenaeum St. Anselmo in Rome, Via G. Ferrari, 2/A, 35123 Padua, Italy a r a t i c l e i n f o b s t r a c t Article history: This work reviews key behavioural, neurophysiological and neuroimaging data on the neural substrates Received 1 March 2016 for processing the meaning of linguistic material, and tries to articulate the picture emerging from those Received in revised form 29 May 2016 findings with the notion of meaning coming from specific approaches in philosophy of language (the Accepted 27 July 2016 “internalist” view) and linguistics (words point at experiential clusters). Available online 28 July 2016 The reviewed findings provide evidence in favour of a causal role of brain neural structures responsible for sensory, motor and even emotional experiences in attributing meaning to words expressing those Keywords: experiences and, consequently, lend substantial support to an embodied and “internalist” conception Embodiment Internalism of linguistic meaning. Key evidence concern verbs, nouns and adjectives with a concrete content, but the challenge that abstract domains pose to the embodied approach to language is also discussed. This Philosophy of language Sensorimotor systems work finally suggests that the most fundamental role of embodiment might be that of establishing com- Mirror neuron system monalities among individual experiences of different members of a linguistic community, and that those Canonical neuron system experiences ground shared linguistic meanings. Semantics © 2016 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Contents 1. Introduction . 69 2. Meaning in philosophy of language . 70 3. Neuroscience, “embodied” language and meaning . 72 3.1. Understanding verbs . 72 3.2. Understanding nouns . 73 3.3. Meaning and experience . 73 4. Possible objections and perspectives . 74 4.1. Abstract linguistic domains . 74 4.2. The problem of solipsism . 75 5. Conclusion . 76 Acknowledgments . 77 References . 77 1. Introduction How do we understand the meaning of words, the basic ele- ments of our linguistic practice? Asking this question might seem ∗ odd, as we live immersed in a linguistic environment. However, Corresponding author. such a question has been extensively investigated since centuries. E-mail addresses: [email protected] (G. Buccino), Philosophy addressed this issue earlier than modern linguistics. [email protected] (I. Colagè), gobbi [email protected] (N. Gobbi), [email protected] (G. Bonaccorso). Nowadays, neuroscience brings key data into this inquiry, and time http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2016.07.033 0149-7634/© 2016 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. 70 G. Buccino et al. / Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews 69 (2016) 69–78 seems ripe for articulating those data with other approaches to sion. The stereotype is a conventional, socially defined notion that language and linguistic meaning. gathers important and typical features of the extension of a word In this review, we will first summarize the main basic trends or expression. The extension is the set of items a word or expres- in philosophy of language about the issue of meaning. We will sion refers to. A speaker must know the socially defined stereotype start by considering how this problem was originally dealt with for acquiring the meaning. Moreover, under this perspective, the in early philosophy of language (Frege, 1892; Russell, 1905, 1910) extension defines the stereotype and, consequently, the meaning and then focusing on some late-twentieth-century developments of a word or expression. In Putnam’s view, this implies that the in philosophy (Putnam, 1975; Searle, 1969, 1979). Namely, we will meaning does not depend on what the speakers think, perceive, assess two fundamental streams in the philosophy of language, the experience etc., but on the “real nature”, the true (physical, chem- so-called “externalist” perspective and the “internalist” approach. ical, genetic, etc.) “hidden structure” of what the expression refers Does understanding the meaning of words resort to “external” to. This is so even when the speaker does not know such nature or (physical or social) entities or to “internal”, embodied experiences? hidden structure (Putnam, 1975 pp. 145-6 and 166). Therefore, the The central section of the review will focus on very recent extension determines the conventional/social stereotype, and the findings in cognitive neuroscience strongly suggesting that the stereotype is what speakers must grasp to understand meanings. meaning of several classes of linguistic items (i.e, verbs, nouns Despite differences between Frege’s and Putnam’s philosophy and adjectives), especially when indicating concrete actions, objects of language, the two positions share a rather “externalist” and dis- and intrinsic features of objects relevant for action, is grounded embodied conception of meaning. According to this conception: (a) in sensorimotor experience and related brain circuitries. The main meanings are supposed to be understood by grasping some kinds idea emerging from these findings, in keeping with the embodied of (physical or social) external entities (like senses or stereotypes), approach to language, is that the speakers understand linguistic and (b) “the psychological state of the individual speaker does not material thanks to a reactivation of those sensorimotor systems determine what he means” (Putnam, 1975 p. 192). involved in the experiences expressed by that linguistic material. Soon after Frege’s proposal, Bertrand Russell (1905, 1910) Thus, we will discuss the aforementioned streams in the philosophy reacted against both the notion of sense and the general idea of language in the light of recent findings coming from neuro- that meanings are unrelated to real and concrete experiences. He science, and show how they offer evidence and arguments in favour claimed that we can understand only those expressions that are of the “internalist” approach. entirely composed of constituents we are acquainted with, where Then, we will briefly consider a recent proposal in linguistics “to be acquainted with . .” essentially means “to have been directly (Dor, 2015) that stresses the experiential ground of linguistic mean- presented with . .”, or simply “to have experienced . .”. It is impor- ing, i.e. the idea that words point at clusters of experiences the tant to note that, in Russell’s view, we are not directly acquainted subject has had with the objects, actions or situations language is with objects, but with “sense-data” coming from our experiences about. with objects (Russell, 1910). Consequently, for example, we can A following section will deal with some implications of the per- understand the word “unicorn”, though we certainly cannot be spective emerging from the previous sections, addressing the issues acquainted with unicorns, if two conditions hold: 1) if we know (or of (i) the meaning in more abstract linguistic domains, and (ii) the are told, or read in, e.g., a dictionary) that a unicorn is a horse with a inter-subjectivity of meaning. horn on the head, and 2) if we have experienced horses, heads and horns. Note that condition 2) should not be understood, from Rus- sell’s standpoint, as meaning that we know the “essence” of such 2. Meaning in philosophy of language objects like horses, heads and horns, but that we are acquainted with certain clusters of sense-data coming from our experiences It may seem obvious that the meaning of a word is its refer- with horses, horns and heads. Moreover, if we learn the word “uni- ence (or “extension”), i.e. the thing, or set of things indicated by corn” because somebody explained it to us verbally (or as we read the word. However, modern philosophy of language – born with its definition on a dictionary), our understanding of “unicorn” also Frege’s (1892) “Sense and Reference” (see also Dummett, 1973; implies that we have learnt to associate the words “horse”, “horn”, Colagè, 2013) – began questioning this point. Frege noted that two and “head” to certain clusters of sense-data. In this way, the defini- expressions with the same reference (e.g. “the morning star” and tion of unicorn as a horse with a horn on the head serves the task of “the evening star”, both denoting Venus) do not necessarily have linking together our past experiences of horses, horns, and heads. the same meaning. Indeed, compare “the morning star is the morn- This opens up a more “internalist” and embodied stance about ing star” with “the morning star is the evening star”: if meaning meaning, according to which the meaning of linguistic expressions were all about reference, these assertions should have the same is fundamentally rooted in our experiences. We will see in Section meaning, which is not the case as the first is a mere tautology 3 that such experiences can be understood
Recommended publications
  • Chapter Five Meaning
    1. The Study of Meaning Semantics: The meaning of words: Lexical semantics Chapter Five The meaning of sentences: Propositional meaning, compositional meaning Meaning Linguistic semantics vs. Logical Meaning semantics/philosophical semantics Pragmatics: The meaning of utterances 1 2 2. Semantic Meaning Logicians and philosophers have tended to concentrate on a restricted range of sentences (typically, statements, or ‘propositions’) within Semantics is the study of meaning in language. a single language. Meaning has been studied for thousands of The linguistic approach aims to study the years by philosophers, logicians and linguists. properties of meaning in a systematic and E.g. Plato & Aristotle. objective way, with reference to as wide a range of utterances and languages as possible, ∴ broader in scope. 3 4 3. The meaning of meaning Geoffrey Leech (1974, 1981). Semantics: The 3. The meaning of meaning Study of Meaning. Seven types of meaning: C. K. Ogden & I. A. Richards (1923). The Meaning of Meaning. Conceptual meaning John means to write. Connotative meaning A green light means to go. Social meaning Health means everything. Associative Affective meaning His look was full of meaning. Meaning What is the meaning of life? Reflected and meaning What does ‘capitalist’ mean to you? Collocative meaning What does ‘cornea’ mean? Thematic meaning 5 6 1 3.2 Connotative meaning 3.1 Conceptual meaning The communicative value an expression has by ‘ ’ ‘ ’ Also called ‘denotative’ or ‘cognitive’ meaning. virtue of what it refers to, over and above its Refers to logical, cognitive or denotative purely conceptual content. content. A multitude of additional, non-criterial Concerned with the relationship between a properties, including not only physical word and the thing it denotes, or refers to.
    [Show full text]
  • Minding the Body Interacting Socially Through Embodied Action
    Linköping Studies in Science and Technology Dissertation No. 1112 Minding the Body Interacting socially through embodied action by Jessica Lindblom Department of Computer and Information Science Linköpings universitet SE-581 83 Linköping, Sweden Linköping 2007 © Jessica Lindblom 2007 Cover designed by Christine Olsson ISBN 978-91-85831-48-7 ISSN 0345-7524 Printed by UniTryck, Linköping 2007 Abstract This dissertation clarifies the role and relevance of the body in social interaction and cognition from an embodied cognitive science perspective. Theories of embodied cognition have during the past two decades offered a radical shift in explanations of the human mind, from traditional computationalism which considers cognition in terms of internal symbolic representations and computational processes, to emphasizing the way cognition is shaped by the body and its sensorimotor interaction with the surrounding social and material world. This thesis develops a framework for the embodied nature of social interaction and cognition, which is based on an interdisciplinary approach that ranges historically in time and across different disciplines. It includes work in cognitive science, artificial intelligence, phenomenology, ethology, developmental psychology, neuroscience, social psychology, linguistics, communication, and gesture studies. The theoretical framework presents a thorough and integrated understanding that supports and explains the embodied nature of social interaction and cognition. It is argued that embodiment is the part and parcel of social interaction and cognition in the most general and specific ways, in which dynamically embodied actions themselves have meaning and agency. The framework is illustrated by empirical work that provides some detailed observational fieldwork on embodied actions captured in three different episodes of spontaneous social interaction in situ.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Reference 1. the Phenomenon Of
    1 Reference 1. The phenomenon of reference In a paper evaluating animal communication systems, Hockett and Altmann (1968) presented a list of what they found to be the distinctive characteristics which, collectively, define what it is to be a human language. Among the characteristics is the phenomenon of "aboutness", that is, in using a human language we talk about things that are external to ourselves. This not only includes things that we find in our immediate environment, but also things that are displaced in time and space. For example, at this moment I can just as easily talk about Tahiti or the planet Pluto, neither of which are in my immediate environment nor ever have been, as I can about this telephone before me or the computer I am using at this moment. Temporal displacement is similar: it would seem I can as easily talk about Abraham Lincoln or Julius Caesar, neither a contemporary of mine, as I can of former president Bill Clinton, or my good friend John, who are contemporaries of mine. This notion of aboutness is, intuitively, lacking in some contrasting instances. For example, it is easy to think that animal communication systems lack this characteristic—that the mating call of the male cardinal may be caused by a certain biological urge, and may serve as a signal that attracts mates, but the call itself is (putatively) not about either of those things. Or, consider an example from human behavior. I hit my thumb with a hammer while attempting to drive in a nail. I say, "Ouch!" In so doing I am saying this because of the pain, and I am communicating to anyone within earshot that I am in pain, but the word ouch itself is not about the pain I feel.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Abstract Hermeneutics
    Research in Phenomenology Research in Phenomenology 41 (2011) 45–59 brill.nl/rp Notes on Abstract Hermeneutics Marcia Sá Cavalcante Schuback Södertörn University, Sweden Abstract Using abstract art as a paradigm, this paper attempts to think, in a provisional manner, the parameters of what the author calls ‘abstract hermeneutics’—a way of thinking capable of responding to the withdrawing, or abstracting, movement of Being. Such abstract thinking— which is an abstracting thinking of the abstract—aims to step beyond objectivity precisely in order to return to phenomenological concreteness. Through an engagement with Heidegger’s understanding of the formal indicative role of the human being as sign (Zeichen), the affinity between the abstracting gestures of abstract art, and the absenting characteristic of human exis- tence, is explored. Keywords Heidegger, hermeneutics, formal-indication, abstract art Die Linien des Lebens sind verschieden Wie Wege sind, und wie der Berge Grenzen. Was hier wir sind, kann dort ein Gott ergänzen Mit Harmonien und ewigem Lohn und Frieden. Hölderlin, “An Zimmern” Would it be something of note for philosophy today to address the question of abstract thought and, more specifically, aboutabstract hermeneutics, what- ever such a phrase might mean? When the challenge of our day seems still, and even more, one of stepping back “to the things themselves” to find a philo- sophical path to the concrete, why address such a question of the abstract? For, phenomenology’s call to the things themselves can be interpreted, and rightly so, precisely as a critique of abstraction. This can also be said in regard to the thoughts of Nietzsche, Marx, and Freud, insofar as they all share with phe- nomenology what could be called a desire or search for lost concreteness.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concrete and the Abstract in the Language of Politics
    Edinburgh Research Explorer The concrete and the abstract in the language of politics Citation for published version: Joseph, J 2017, 'The concrete and the abstract in the language of politics', Rivista di psicolinguistica applicata, vol. Anno XVII, no. 2, pp. 97-112. https://doi.org/10.19272/201707702006 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.19272/201707702006 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Peer reviewed version Published In: Rivista di psicolinguistica applicata General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 28. Sep. 2021 The concrete and the abstract in the language of politics John E. Joseph, University of Edinburgh ABSTRACT Until well into the modern period, concrete was used to mean what is now called abstract. The terms originated as grammatical descriptors for related pairs of nouns and adjectives, then came to be reinterpeted as logical categories tied to the presence or absence of a clear mental image. They remain ambiguous, yet are used as though every word fell clearly into one or the other category.
    [Show full text]
  • CUBISM and ABSTRACTION Background
    015_Cubism_Abstraction.doc READINGS: CUBISM AND ABSTRACTION Background: Apollinaire, On Painting Apollinaire, Various Poems Background: Magdalena Dabrowski, "Kandinsky: Compositions" Kandinsky, Concerning the Spiritual in Art Background: Serial Music Background: Eugen Weber, CUBISM, Movements, Currents, Trends, p. 254. As part of the great campaign to break through to reality and express essentials, Paul Cezanne had developed a technique of painting in almost geometrical terms and concluded that the painter "must see in nature the cylinder, the sphere, the cone:" At the same time, the influence of African sculpture on a group of young painters and poets living in Montmartre - Picasso, Braque, Max Jacob, Apollinaire, Derain, and Andre Salmon - suggested the possibilities of simplification or schematization as a means of pointing out essential features at the expense of insignificant ones. Both Cezanne and the Africans indicated the possibility of abstracting certain qualities of the subject, using lines and planes for the purpose of emphasis. But if a subject could be analyzed into a series of significant features, it became possible (and this was the great discovery of Cubist painters) to leave the laws of perspective behind and rearrange these features in order to gain a fuller, more thorough, view of the subject. The painter could view the subject from all sides and attempt to present its various aspects all at the same time, just as they existed-simultaneously. We have here an attempt to capture yet another aspect of reality by fusing time and space in their representation as they are fused in life, but since the medium is still flat the Cubists introduced what they called a new dimension-movement.
    [Show full text]
  • Reference and Reinterpretation
    Reference and Reinterpretation by Anthony Kulic A thesis presented to the University of Waterloo in fulfilment of the thesis requirement for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy Waterloo, Ontario, Canada, 2007 ©Anthony Kulic, 2007 Author’s Declaration I hereby declare that I am the sole author of this thesis. This is a true copy of the thesis, including any required final revisions, as accepted by my examiners. I understand that my thesis may be made electronically available to the public. ii Abstract Reference is the relation held to obtain between an expression and what a speaker or thinker intends the expression to represent. Reference is a component of interpretation, the process of giving terms, sentences, and thoughts semantic content. An example of reference in a formal context involves the natural numbers, where each one can be taken to have a corresponding set‐theoretic counterpart as its referent. In an informal context reference is exemplified by the relation between a name and the specific name‐bearer when a speaker or thinker utters or has the name in mind. Recent debates over reference have concerned the mechanism of reference: How is it that we can refer? In informal contexts, externalists see the reference relation as explicable in terms of the salient causal relations involved in the naming of a thing, or a class of things, and the ensuing causal chains leading to a term’s use. Opponents of this view— internalists—see the reference relation as being conceptually direct, and they take the external approach to rely on untenable metaphysical assumptions about the world’s structure.
    [Show full text]
  • The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition
    THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF EMBODIED COGNITION Embodied cognition is one of the foremost areas of study and research in philosophy of mind, philosophy of psychology and cognitive science. The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition is an outstanding guide and reference source to the key philosophers, topics and debates in this exciting subject and essential reading for any student and scholar of philosophy of mind and cognitive science. Comprising over thirty chapters by a team of international contributors, the Handbook is divided into six parts: Historical underpinnings Perspectives on embodied cognition Applied embodied cognition: perception, language, and reasoning Applied embodied cognition: social and moral cognition and emotion Applied embodied cognition: memory, attention, and group cognition Meta-topics. The early chapters of the Handbook cover empirical and philosophical foundations of embodied cognition, focusing on Gibsonian and phenomenological approaches. Subsequent chapters cover additional, important themes common to work in embodied cognition, including embedded, extended and enactive cognition as well as chapters on embodied cognition and empirical research in perception, language, reasoning, social and moral cognition, emotion, consciousness, memory, and learning and development. Lawrence Shapiro is a professor in the Department of Philosophy, University of Wisconsin – Madison, USA. He has authored many articles spanning the range of philosophy of psychology. His most recent book, Embodied Cognition (Routledge, 2011), won the American Philosophical Association’s Joseph B. Gittler award in 2013. Routledge Handbooks in Philosophy Routledge Handbooks in Philosophy are state-of-the-art surveys of emerging, newly refreshed, and important fields in philosophy, providing accessible yet thorough assessments of key problems, themes, thinkers, and recent developments in research.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Cite Complete Issue More Information About This Article
    THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia ISSN: 0495-4548 ISSN: 2171-679X [email protected] Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea España Plebani, Matteo The indispensability argument and the nature of mathematical objects* THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, vol. 33, no. 2, 2018, pp. 249-263 Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea España DOI: https://doi.org/10.1387/theoria.17613 Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=339755528007 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System Redalyc More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America and the Caribbean, Spain and Journal's webpage in redalyc.org Portugal Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative THEORIA ESTABLISH E D IN 1952 BY MIGU E L SÁNCH E Z -MAZAS Vol. 33/2 • May 2018 Second Series An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science CALIJ Centro de Análisis, Lógica e Informática Jurídica (CALIJ) http://www.ehu.eus/theoria T H E O R I A REVISTA DE TEORÍA, HISTORIA Y FUNDAMENTOS DE LA CIENCIA AN INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL FOR THEORY, HISTORY AND FOUNDATIONS OF SCIENCE ESTABLISH E D in 1952 by MIGUEL SÁNCHEZ-MAZAS Second Series EDITORIAL BOARD Editor-in-chief: Andoni IBARRA (University of the Basque Country, UPV/EHU) Editors: Cristina CORREDOR (Universidad de Valladolid), Antonio DIÉGUEZ (Universidad de Málaga) Logic and philosophy of logic and mathematics: José Luis ZALABARDO (University College
    [Show full text]
  • 233 Meaning and the Second Language Learner Jane Nkechi
    Meaning and the Second Language Learner Jane Nkechi Ifechelobi* Abstract Meaning is about the most elusive and controversial phenomenon in the study of language .The ambiguous nature of meaning is manifest in the fact that in almost any language, one expression can be subject to a number of interpretations depending on the speaker, the hearer and the situation where the expression is used. Meanings are ultimately determined not by words but by people [Hybels and Weaver26]. Most often the second language learner seeks to interpret word meaning without reference to the person who uses it and the community in which it is used. The concern of this paper is to bring out the complexity between meaning and the second language learner, because meaning lies on the interpreter and not on the user of the language. http://dx.doi.org/10.4314/ujah.v13i1.13 Introduction Language is a means of communication but what is normally conveyed in language use is not words and sentences but a message. The implication is that language cannot stand on its own apart from the function of conveying messages. This suggests that meaning exists elsewhere than in language. In any language use, the more important and more valuable object is the message; language is only secondary. In the study of language one is concerned more with the expression of meanings than with meaning itself. However the analysis of meaning is the message enveloped in the linguistic form. It is obvious that there is an intrinsic connection between meaning and communication such that it is impossible to account for the former except in terms of the latter.
    [Show full text]
  • Ogden and Richards' the Meaning of Meaning and Early Analytic
    Ogden and Richards’ The Meaning of Meaning and early analytic philosophy. James McElvenny [email protected] This is the green open access copy of my paper in Language Sciences (2014, 41.212-221). http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.langsci.2013.10.001 This version silently corrects a few small errors in the published paper. Abstract C.K. Ogden (1889–1957) and I.A. Richards’ (1893–1979) The Meaning of Meaning is widely recognised as a classic text of early twentieth-century linguistic semantics and semiotics, but less well known are its links to the ‘logical atomism’ of Bertrand Russell (1872–1970), one of the foundational doctrines of analytic philosophy. In this paper a detailed comparison of The Meaning of Meaning and logical atomism is made, in which several key similarities between the two theories in subject matter and approach are identified: both attempt to describe meaning in terms of the latest psychological doctrines and both pursue a normative program aimed at rectifying the perceived deficiencies of language. But there are also a number of differences between the theories. Ogden and Richards – most probably inspired by Victoria Lady Welby (1837–1912) – offered a pragmatically oriented account of ordinary language, while Russell sought a ‘logically perfect language’ beyond interpretation, and rejected the work of Welby and her allies. These differences contributed significantly to Russell’s largely negative opinion of The Meaning of Meaning. Despite this, several ideas pioneered in The Meaning of Meaning re-appear in Russell’s later writings. The Meaning of Meaning, it would seem, not only drew inspiration from Russell’s philosophy but may have also contributed to its further development.
    [Show full text]
  • FACING the PROBLEM of ETHICAL SOLIPSISM Sami Pihlström
    Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 GUILT: FACING THE PROBLEM OF ETHICAL SOLIPSISM Sami Pihlström ABSTRACT: This article deals with the constitutive role played by the emotion of guilt, or the capacity of experiencing such emotions, in our moral life. The deeply personal nature of moral guilt (or remorse) leads to the problem of ethical solipsism: it seems that guilt can in the end concern only me, not anyone else, in a morally profound sense. Echoing Dostoevsky, the truly ethical thinker ought to acknowledge that everyone is guilty in front of the entire mankind, “and I more than anyone else”. This problematic feature of our moral perspectives on the world is examined through comments on a number of authors, including Kant, Wittgenstein, Levinas, Gaita, and Todorov. While we do need to avoid solipsism, there is a “truth” hidden in it: morality is something that we are individually and personally deeply responsible for. 1 Immanuel Kant remarks, in a famous footnote to the First Critique, that [t]he real morality of actions (their merit and guilt), even that of our own conduct […] remains entirely hidden from us. Our imputations can be referred only to the empirical character. How much of it is to be ascribed to mere nature […] no one can discover, and hence no one can judge it with complete justice.1 Although commentators have drawn attention to this important passage,2 its full significance still deserves substantial consideration. So does the significance of another famous Kantian remark, according to which, for each one of us, “the depths of his own heart (the subjective first grounds of his maxims) are to him inscrutable”.3 1 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans.
    [Show full text]